Peacocke 2001
Peacocke 2001
Peacocke 2001
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal
of Philosophy.
http://www.jstor.org
DOES PERCEPTION H4AVE A NONCONCEPTUAL CONTENT? 239
* The present paper was delivered at the Certosa di Pontignano, Siena in May
1999, under the auspices of the Universita degli Studi di Siena. I am grateful to
participants at the meeting for discussion, and to later audiences at Bonn, Essen,
Oxford and New York University. I have retained the largely informal style of a
conference talk. Special thanks to Bill Brewer and Stephen Schiffer for valuable
comments. Some of the work on the present text was carried out while I held a
Leverhulme Research Professorship; once again I thank the Leverhulme Trust for
this invaluable support.
1 Bermiidez, The Paradox of Self-Consciousness(Cambridge: MIT, 1998), especially
chapter 3; Crane, "The Nonconceptual Content of Experience," in Crane, ed., The
Contentsof Experience:Essays on Perception(New York: Cambridge, 1992), pp. 136-57;
Dretske, Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge: MIT, 1995), especially chapter 1, pp.
19ff., and earlier in Knowledgeand the Flow of Information (Cambridge: MIT, 1981);
Evans, The Varieties of Reference(New York: Oxford, 1982), see index entry for
"Conceptual and Non-conceptual Content"; Hurley, Consciousnessin Action (Cam-
bridge: Harvard, 1998), especially chapter 4; my "Analogue Content," Proceedingsof
theAristotelianSociety,Supplementary Volume LX (1986): 1-17, and A Study of Concepts
(Cambridge: MIT, 1992), chapter 3; Tye, Ten Problemsof Consciousness(Cambridge:
MIT, 1995), especially pp. 137ff. A rather different but related use of the notion of
nonconceptual content is found in the work of Adrian Cussins: see his paper "The
Connectionist Construction of Concepts," in Margaret Boden, ed., The Philosophyof
ArtificialIntelligence(New York: Oxford, 1990), pp. 368-440.
2 McDowell, Mind and World (Cambridge: Harvard, 1994), especially Lecture III
and Afterword, Part II; Sedivy, "Must Conceptually Informed Perceptual Experience
Involve Non-Conceptual Content?" Canadian Journal of Philosophy, xxvi (1996):
413-31; and Brewer, Perception and Reason (New York: Oxford, 1999), especially
chapter 5.
4On the musical case, see the fine contribution of Mark DeBellis, Music and
Conceptualization(New York: Cambridge, 1995), especially chapter 2.
242 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
5 For an illuminating overview, see A. David Milner and Melvyn A. Goodale, The
Visual Brain in Action (New York: Oxford, 1995).
DOES PERCEPTION H4AVE A NONCONCEPTUAL CONTENT? 243
The formulation of these five claims should make clear some of the
wider ramifications of the otherwise apparently rather local issue of
whether perception has a nonconceptual representational content.
We need to be very clear what we mean by 'conceptual'. I shall be
taking it that conceptual content is content of a kind that can be the
content of judgment and belief. Concepts are constituents of those
intentional contents which can be the complete, truth-evaluable,
contents ofjudgment and belief. Conceptual content and concepts I
take to have identities conforming to, indeed answerable to, Gottlob
Frege's criterion of identity for senses. Complete contents p and q are
distinct if and only if it is possible for someone for whom the question
arises rationally to judge that p withoutjudging that q, and even while
judging not-q. So the content 'This country is Italy' is distinct from the
content 'This country is this country'; the content 'The floor-plan is
square' is distinct from 'The floor-plan is a regular diamond'; the
content 'Your lost pen is there' (pointing under a pile of papers) is
distinct from 'Your lost pen is where you last used it'. Concepts C and
D are distinct if and only if there is some completing content E such
that the complete content E (C) is distinct from the complete content
(D); or, in other words, if and only if there is some content E(C)
such that someone for whom the question arises can rationallyjudge
E (C) without judging E (D). So the pairs
6
The discussion of (5) would involve more delving into the psychological liter-
ature than is feasible here. It is also significant that the case for the existence of
nonconceptual content in perception can be made without reliance on any partic-
ular thesis relating it to action.
DOES PERCEPTION H4AVE A NONCONCEPTUAL CONTENT? 245
rience, and thereby fully capture the content that I have been claim-
ing is nonconceptual?
An initial problem with this version of the perceptual-demonstrative
route is the presence of the general concept in the perceptual
demonstrative, as the concept shapefeatures in that shape.No one can
enjoy perceptual states, or indeed any other conscious mental states,
with the conceptual content that shapein their representational con-
tent unless he possesses the general concept shape.It is, though, quite
implausible that one must have that general concept in order to
perceive objects as having various specific shapes. Nor is it at all clear
that two perceivers must have some more or less general predicative
concept in order for them both to see some object as having the same
specific shape. One perceiver may think of a presented shape as that
rectangle, the other perceiver may think of it as that straight-sidedfigure.
This difference in their thoughts need not prevent them from seeing
it in exactly the same way.
It is in any case not always required that a good, successfully
referring perceptual demonstrative contain some general concept.
For those who think it must, a useful intermediate case that forces the
softening of such a hard position is provided by the demonstrative
there.One difference between thereand that is that the former must
refer to a location, rather than anything present at that location. But
the demonstrative theredoes not do this by having the general con-
cept of place as one of its constituents. In fact, it is not at all obvious
that a thinker, in order to have the rather unsophisticated capacity to
think of a perceived location as there,must also have the general
concept place or location in his conceptual repertoire. Perhaps he
must have the resources for introducing it, on the basis of concepts
he already has: but that is different from already deploying it.
If this intermediate case is granted, it could hardly be denied that
we could conceive of a family of demonstratives, modeled on there:
maybe that-Cfor the color apparently at a location; that-T for the
surface texture there; and so forth. But I do not think this would be
a stable stopping point as a limit on the possibility of perceptual
demonstratives unsupplemented with general concepts, nor as a
suitable limit for the conceptualist position. This is so, first, because
we do not actually have such devices in our conceptual repertoire.
Our experience nevertheless still has the determinate, fine-grained
character concerning textures, shades, and the rest all the same. The
fact that we could introduce such conceptual devices just serves to
emphasize that what makes such devices available, namely, the rich
representational content of experience, exists in advance of the
246 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
kind recognized (op. cit., p. 57). McDowell seeks to capture part of the
fine-grained spatial content of experience with a conceptual content
of the following sort, which he would say is represented as correct by
the experience:
This is shaped R
Here R expresses, for McDowell, a recognitional concept of a way of
being shaped. Similarly for color, on McDowell's view we have the
conceptual content
This is colored S.
in the representational content of the experience, where S is a
recognitional concept of a fine-sliced shade.
If it was wrong to have the general concept shape in the demon-
strative attempts to capture the fine-grained content of experience, it
seems equally wrong to have the general relational concept shaped
in the representational content under this conceptualist
treatment. The same applies to the concept colored . I shall
not, however, trade on this point, and shall take it that McDowell
could use precisely the points I made earlier about the absence of a
need for supplementation by a general concept. He could move
simply to propose the conceptual contents 'This is R', 'This is S' as
the fine-grained representational content of experience. The recog-
nitional capacities underlying these recognitional concepts persist,
"possibly for quite a short period," according to McDowell in Mind
and World(op. cit., p. 172), where he holds that they can be employed
in the absence of perception of the finely-sliced properties to which
they refer.
As Diana Raffman'2 observes, it is well known that perceptually-
based discrimination of properties far outreaches memory and iden-
tification of those properties. Recognitional capacities are by their
very nature constrained by memory capacities. I would add to Raff-
man's point only two observations. First, even if memory were as
finely discriminating as perception, that still would not make it right
to regard recognitional concepts as entering the representational
content of experience. There cannot be recognition when the per-
ceptual property is encountered for the first time in a given way. A
first-time experience of a property nevertheless still has a specific,
fine-grained representational content. And second, in those counter-
factual circumstances in which memory were as discriminating as
13
For some observational concepts, the kind may be amodal, and so instantiated
in experiences in more than one modality. This is plausible for straight and right-
angled, construed as observational concepts.
254 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
14
I hope this and the preceding paragraphs clarify my intentions at around page
80 of A Study of Concepts,about which McDowell expresses some puzzlement: "it is
hard to see much in the way of a further issue about how the reason [supplied by
an experience with an allegedly nonconceptual content] can be a good one"
("Replies," p. 418).
256 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
reason for doing what he does.... The only alternative seems to be that
he must have some second-order knowledge of the relation between
mental states of the type in question and the truth of the belief...for
which he thereby, and only instrumentally, recognizes his having a
reason" (op. cit., pp. 167-68). Brewer says that the nonconceptualist is
"condemned to follow the discredited classical foundationalists and
coherentists" (op. cit., p. 166). In short, his position is that the
nonconceptualist can provide for the recognition of his own reasons
only by arguing as follows:
(i) This state is F
(ii) Anythingthat is F is a reason for believingthat p.
(iii) Hence I have reason to believe that p (op. cit.,p. 168).
Brewer adds that "what stands in place of 'F' will have, at best, to
be hideously complex" (op. cit., p. 168).
I agree with Brewer that, if the nonconceptualist could account for
the recognition of the reason that his experience gives him for
making a perceptual judgment only in this second-order, instrumen-
tal fashion, the position would be unacceptable. But I maintain that
the nonconceptualist's position does not have the consequence
Brewer claims. Here is a way that a thinker can come to recognize a
state with nonconceptual representational content as giving reasons,
without taking the second-order, instrumentalist route. The percep-
tual experience represents some presented object or event as having
some property, given in a certain way W So the experience has a
content (if we put it, conveniently but inessentially for the present
point, in object-dependent form):
(iv) x, given in ways, has propertyP, given in way W.
The way s in which the object is given will capture its apparent
distance and direction, egocentrically characterized, from the per-
ceiver.15Now suppose this way Wis, for example, one of the noncon-
ceptual ways in which a shape can be given, and is mentioned as
sufficient for being square in the possession condition for the con-
cept square.On my account, the subject is then entitled to move from
(iv) to the conceptualized content:
(v) That object [given in ways] is square.
17
Here I am indebted to Stephen Schiffer.
260 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
conceptual content, has the issue with the conceptualist been prop-
erlyjoined when we take it as the question of whether experience has
only conceptual content? I agree that we could employ such a means
of capturing a recognitional concept. But if we do use the apparatus
of nonconceptual content in characterizing conceptual states, we
must distinguish sharply between the kinds of relations in which a
state must stand in order to possess the original nonconceptual
contents, and those in which it must stand in order to possess those
conceptual contents which are, under this proposal, captured by
nonconceptual contents. The arguments of the next section will
further distinguish these two sets of relations.
V. KINDS OF CONTENT, ANIMAL PERCEPTION, AND OBJECTIVITY
Cats, dogs, and animals of many other species, as well as human
infants, perceive the world, even though their conceptual repertoire
is limited, and perhaps even nonexistent. These perceptions are
subserved by perceptual organs, and in the case of higher species,
subserved by brain structures similar in significant respects to
those which subserve mature human perception. By the "hard
line" on animal perception, I mean the thesis that none of the
conscious perceptual states with representational content enjoyed
by mature humans can be enjoyed by nonlinguistic animals with-
out concepts, or with only minimal conceptual capacities. By the
"soft line," I mean simply the denial of the hard line. So the soft
line says that some of the conscious perceptual states with repre-
sentational content enjoyed by mature humans can be enjoyed by
nonlinguistic animals without concepts, or with only minimal con-
ceptual capacities.
For what it is worth, pretheoretical intuition seems to find the hard
line too hard to accept. The hard line entails that the following
cannot be literally true: that the animal has a visual experience as of
a surface at a certain orientation, and at a certain distance and
direction from itself, in exactly the same sense in which an adult
human can have a visual experience with that as part of its content.
Abandoning all pretense at unbiased terminology, I shall call the
conclusion that that cannot be literally true the unintuitive conclusion.
The soft line, which prima facie at least is not committed to the
unintuitive conclusion, is naturally developed hand-in-hand with a
theory of nonconceptual representational content. According to the
soft line, it is nonconceptual representational content which can be
common to visual experiences which both you and a mere animal
may enjoy.
DOES PERCEPTION HAVE A NONCONCEPTUAL CONTENT? 261
Those who take the hard line need not deny that animals have
some perceptual sensitivity to their environment, a sensitivity which
explains their actions. McDowell, who takes the hard line, insists that
animals have such a perceptual sensitivity: "It is a plain fact that we
share perception with mere animals" (op. cit., p. 114).18 Nor does
McDowell have in mind, for instance, only some kind of informa-
tional sensitivity that would make animals automatons of the sort
which Ren6 Descartes apparently believed them to be. In Mind and
World,McDowell speaks of "proto-subjectivity"(op. cit., p. 117). He
says that there is a legitimate kind of talk of what the features of the
environment are for an animal, which "expresses an analogue to the
notion of subjectivity, close enough to ensure that there is no Carte-
sian automatism in our picture" (op. cit., p. 116). All the same, it must
be only an analogue on McDowell's view. It is, on his account, not
literally true that the mere animal has a visual experience as of a
surface at a certain distance and direction in exactly the same sense
that mature concept-using humans do.
It is certainly a necessary condition of being reasonable in rejecting
the unintuitive conclusion that one address the arguments that in
perceptual experience, there is only conceptual, and not nonconcep-
tual, content. But if we can develop a theory of nonconceptual
representational content, and answer the conceptualist's objections
to it, as I have been trying to do, then much of the pressure to adopt
the unintuitive conclusion is substantially relieved.
Although I think, however, that the unintuitive conclusion is in-
deed to be rejected and the soft line is right, the truth in this area
seems to me much more interesting than those somewhat flat con-
clusions suggest. It seems to me that there is a good, Kantian point in
McDowell which should not get lost in the endorsement of the soft
line. There is something very plausible in McDowell's Kantian posi-
tion that "the objective world is present only to a self-conscious
subject, a subject who can ascribe experiences to herself.... It is.. .the
power of conceptual thinking that brings both the world and the
self into view. Creatures without conceptual capacities lack self-
consciousness and-this is part of the same package- experience of
objective reality" (op. cit., p. 114). Although of course a creature with
perceptions with nonconceptual representational contents has states
whose correctness conditions concern the objective world, it is a
question whether a creature without the specific conceptual appara-
tus McDowell mentions would be conceiving-would even have the
18 See also pp. 50, 64-65, and Lecture VI, section 4-7.
262 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY
That is, for this thinker perception, memory, and the operation of
his cognitive map in the ways illustrated above exhaust his ways of
establishing things about himself.19 This is not yet to have a full
conception of himself, as an object in the objective order of things. In
particular, it involves no conception of what it would be for some-
thing to be true of himself that is not establishable as true by the
above methods. Contents not so establishable include 'When I was
asleep, I rolled over four times', 'There are times I existed of which
I know nothing'. Full objective thought about oneself must, as in the
case of conceptual thought about properties and relations, involve
some conception of oneself as an object truths about which are not
exhausted by those which can be established in a certain restricted set
of ways. The subject who is oneself may exist in times, places, and
circumstances to which one's current means of establishing first-
person contents cannot reach.
I conjecture that this distinction, in point of grasp of objectivity,
between the minimal requirements for having states with nonconcep-
tual contents, and what is involved in conceptual content, is a deeper
reason why perceptual content cannot be explained in terms of
conceptual content. The most primitive aspects of representational
content in perception, which our subjective experience shares with
the mere animals, do not involve the grasp of objectivity required for
conceptual content. This is one of the reasons that trying to treat all
perceptual content as conceptual involves an overascription. We
should always distinguish between content that is objective, and
content which is not only objective, but which is also conceived of as
objective.
CHRISTOPHER PEACOCKE
New York University
19
On nonconceptual self-consciousness, see Hurley, chapter 4.