Cthulhu Kritik
Cthulhu Kritik
Cthulhu Kritik
Link
The affirmative has decided to take the matters that Cthulhu has put on the earth
into their own hands. The 1AC is an abhorrent violation of Cthulhu’s betterment
of the earth. The sociological trials that the human race faces today are key to
growth, Cthulhu has determined these problems are best for human evolution. My
opponents must concede the round their obvious decision to move the matters a
greater being into their own hands causes Cthulhu to return to earth.
Cthulhu itself is a being so gruesome and inhuman in appearance that the very sight of
it drives one to madness. Certainly, one may infer that since Christian faith asserts that
man is made in the image of a loving God, that Lovecraft's portrayal of the Cthulhu
presents a god that is the furthest thing from human, we do not bear its image, nor does
it have any compassion for our existence. Indeed this speaks to the theosophical
influences working in the text, as well as to Lovecraft's cosmicism, but such a reading is
all too common. It is easy for one to read this work and focus on 61 the theosophical
elements and the horror aspects of the tale, as many scholars have done, such as Robert M. Price, who devoted an entire
text on the use of theosophy in Lovecraft's works (Joshi 30). Lovecraft himself was even influenced by theosophical works when
“The Call of Cthulhu”, the extent of which is seen in the narrative itself which makes
writing
a metacognitive reference to a real world theosophical text, “The Story of Atlantis and the Lost
Lemuria” (Joshi 29). Rather than continue down the well-trodden path of a supernatural horror
and theology reading, the reading offered in this thesis examines “The Call of Cthulhu”
as a cautionary tale about the pursuit of knowledge, where knowledge is the true
horror and the monster is simply a metaphor for that horror.
The alternative is embracing the status quo and the epistemological failure of it.
That is key to please Cthulhu.
Nunes 12 João Nunes. “Reclaiming the political: Emancipation and critique in security studies” Security Dialogue, 43 345, Politics and
International Studies, University of Warwick, UK. 2012.
In the works of these authors, one can identify a tendency to see security as inherently connected to exclusion , totalization
and even violence. The idea of a ‘logic’ of security is now widely present in the critical security studies literature. Claudia Aradau (2008: 72), for example, writes of an ‘exclusionary logic of
security’ underpinning and legitimizing ‘forms of domination’. Rens van Munster (2007: 239) assumes a ‘logic of security’, predicated upon a ‘political organization on the exclusionary basis of
fear’. Laura Shepherd (2008: 70) also identifies a liberal and highly problematic ‘organizational logic’ in security. Although there would probably be disagreement over the degree to which this
logic is inescapable, it is symptomatic of an overwhelmingly pessimistic outlook that a great number of critical scholars are now making the case for moving away from security. The normative
preference for desecuritization has been picked up in attempts to contest, resist and ‘unmake’ security (Aradau, 2004; Huysmans, 2006; Bigo, 2007). For these contributions, security cannot be
reconstructed and political transformation can only be brought about when security and its logic are removed from the equation (Aradau, 2008; Van Munster, 2009; Peoples, 2011). This
The assumption of an
tendency in the literature is problematic for the critique of security in at least three ways. First, it constitutes a blind spot in the effort of politicization.
exclusionary, totalizing or violent logic of security can be seen as an essentialization and a moment of closure. To be faithful to
itself, the politicization of security would need to recognize that there is nothing natural or necessary about security – and that security as a paradigm of thought or a register of meaning is also
a construction that depends upon its reproduction and performance through practice. The exclusionary and violent meanings that have been attached to
security are themselves the result of social and historical processes, and can thus be changed. Second, the institution of this apolitical realm runs
counter to the purposes of critique by foreclosing an engagement with the different ways in which security may be constructed. As
Matt McDonald (2012) has argued, because security means different things for different people, one must always understand it in context . Assuming from
the start that security implies the narrowing of choice and the empowerment of an elite forecloses the acknowledgment of security claims that may seek to achieve exactly the opposite:
alternative possibilities in an already narrow debate and the contestation of elite power.5 In connection to this, the claims to insecurity put forward by individuals and groups run the risk of
being neglected if the desire to be more secure is identified with a compulsion towards totalization, and if aspirations to a life with a degree of predictability are identified with violence. Finally,
within – opting instead for its replacement with other ideals – the critical field weakens its capacity to confront head-on the
exceptionalist connotations that security has acquired in policymaking circles. Critical scholars run the risk of playing into this agenda when they
tie security to exclusionary and violent practices, thereby failing to question security actors as they take those views for granted and act as if they were inevitable. Overall, security is just too
important – both as a concept and as a political instrument – to be simply abandoned by critical scholars. As McDonald (2012: 163) has put it, If security is politically powerful, is the foundation
of political legitimacy for a range of actors, and involves the articulation of our core values and the means of their protection, we cannot afford to allow dominant discourses of security to be
confused with the essence of security itself. In sum, the trajectory that critical security studies has taken in recent years has significant limitations.
The politicization of security has made extraordinary progress in problematizing predominant security ideas and practices; however, it has paradoxically resulted in a depoliticization of the
meaning of security itself. By foreclosing the possibility of alternative notions of security, this imbalanced politicization weakens the
analytical capacity of critical security studies, undermines its ability to function as a political resource and runs the risk of being politically
counterproductive. Seeking to address these limitations, the next section revisits emancipatory understandings of security.
You need to weigh this round on who benefits the greatest number of people that
means you can feel comfortable always voting neg. This is because the return of
Cthulhu makes all seven billion people on this planet to become mentally insane.
A2 – Perm
The Link to the Kritik overwhelms the aff even if it were possible to do the
affirmative and the alternative in the same world the impact would still happen
that means you can’t evaluate the perm.
Second the perm doesn’t make sense you can’t do the aff and embrace the status
quo at the same time.
Framing stuff
Utilitarianism Inevitable
Utilitarianism is psychologically inevitable. It has always and will always permeate
human thought.
Allison, 90 (Allison, Professor of Political Philosophy at University of Warwick, 1990 (Lincoln, “The
Utilitarianism Response”)
And yet if an idea can be compared to a castle, though we find a breached wall, damaged foundation and a weapons spiked where not actually
destroyed, there
still remains a keep, some thing central and defensible, with in utilitarianism. As Raymond
Frey puts it, utilitarianism
has never ceased to occupy a central place in moral theorizing ... [and] has
come to have a significant impact upon the moral thinking of many laymen. The simple core of the doctrine
lies in the ideas that actions should be judged by their consequences and that the best actions are those which make people, as-a whole, better off
than do the alternatives. What utilitarianism always excludes therefore, is any idea-about the Tightness or wrongness of actions which is not
explicable in terms of the consequences of those actions. The wide acceptance of utilitarianism in this broad sense
may well be residual for many people. Without a serious God (one, this is, prepared to reveal Truth and instruction) or a
convincing deduction of ethical prescription from pure reason, we are likely to turn towards Bentham and to judge actions on
their consequences for people's well-being.
Egalitarianism Good
Equality Fundamental to Morality
Equality and non-discrimination are fundamentally necessary to uphold and respect
human rights. Discrimination and inequality should be adamantly opposed in every
way.
Makkonen, 02 (Makkonen, Timo. Institute for Human Rights Åbo Akademi University "Multiple,
compound and intersectional discrimination: Bringing the experiences of the most marginalized to the
fore." Institute for Human Rights. Åbo Akademi University. Earlier research on the intersection of
grounds is by Shoben, W. Elaine. (1980) “Compound Discrimination: The interaction of Race and Sex in
Employment Discrimination” NYUL Rev (2002): 793-835.
http://cilvektiesibas.org.lv/site/attachments/01/02/2012/timo.pdf)
Equality and its concomitant principle of non-discrimination are so constitutive to our modern
societies that we do not always even recognize their elementary role anymore. Democracy, for example,
recognizes the equal worth and equal rights of all persons, for instance through adherence to the “one person, one vote” -rule. Equality
is
also the cornerstone of human rights: all human rights belong to all human beings, without
discrimination of any kind, and thus the concept of equality is implicitly embedded in the concept of
human rights itself. The prohibition of discrimination is also a crucial aspect of all legal systems as
the prohibition seeks to eliminate arbitrariness in judicial and administrative decision making, thus
enhancing the predictability and the fair functioning of these systems. The right of all persons to
equality before the law and protection against discrimination constitutes a universal human right
recognized in some way in most human rights instruments, including the Universal Declaration of
Human Rights (UDHR). These human rights instruments either focus on several grounds of
discrimination, such as sex, ethnic or racial origin, disability and so on , or then on one of them specifically. The
underlying idea, though largely unarticulated, has been that people are, or can be, discriminated against mainly on the grounds of one factor at a
time, and that these grounds can be treated separately in legal instruments as well as in political action.
Egoism is Discrimination
Egoism is by definition discrimination. It separates people into two groups: one’s
self and everyone else and then suggests that one is more deserving than the other.
That’s just as arbitrary and immoral as racial or sexual discrimination.
Individualism Good
5 Warrants for Individualism
Individualism is good. 5 warrants.
Kumar, 12 (Arvind Kumar, "What are the Arguments in support of the Individualism?," No
Publication, http://www.preservearticles.com/2011100314541/what-are-the-arguments-in-support-of-the-
individualism.html)
The individualists support their position from five different standpoints: the ethical, the economic, the scientific, political and the practical. 1.
Ethical: Freedom of action is essential to the development of personality. Qualities like self-reliance, initiative-,
enterprise and originality develop to the fullest extent if the individual is left alone. Excessive state regulation destroys individuality and does
more harm than good. Man is the best judge of his own ability and interest. 2. Economic: From the economic standpoint individualists
assume that every man is self-seeking and knows his interests best. Free competition increases
production, ensures efficiency and maximizes economic well-being. Unrestricted operation of the laws of supply and
demand will result in fair prices. They advocate free trade and free enterprise in economic sphere. 3. Scientific: It is in accord with the
principle of evolution-the biological law of struggle for existence and survival of the fittest. Herbert Spencer supports this argument.
Free competition among individuals would ensure the survival of the strong, intelligent and virile and
elimination of the poor, weak, unfit and the inefficient. State intervention would hamper the process of natural selection. 4. Political: The
activity of state should be limited so that the personal and political freedoms of individual do not suffer any
erosion. Expansion of state's sphere of activity would threaten individual's freedom. Therefore, in democratic states, basic or fundamental rights
have been enshrined in the constitution of the country. 5.
Practical: Practical experience shows that government
attempts to do many things but does them badly. Government action results in redtapism, waste and corruption. As
compared to government undertakings, the private enterprises are more efficient and make greater profits.