The Metaphysics Behind Discrimination - Pages
The Metaphysics Behind Discrimination - Pages
I. Habitable Kinds
1
PREFACE
Many years ago, as I was finishing my PhD studies in Bloomington, Indiana, I took a wonderful course on
feminist art. I had already met and was fond of professor Peg Brand, and she was teaching this class with other
two professors: the artist Judy Chicago and the art historian Jean Robertson. The idea was to have an art
historian, a philosopher and an artist collaborate on the class. We also had a couple of top-notch guest lectures:
I was already working on finishing my dissertation so I did not need the credits and therefore sat in the
class. I learned a lot of aesthetics and feminism in that class, both theoretically and from first hand experience. I
saw first hand the difficult tensions between feminists from different generations, and I became good friends
with Judy and Peggy. From Judy, I also learned first hand about the importance of women re-appropriating the
representation of themselves and, specially, of their bodies (one of the main topics of her “Dinner Party”).
However, there were mostly a lot of questions that remained open at the end of the class and that have
been going around in my head ever since (for the last twenty years). In particular, there seems to be a
presupposition among many feminist artists that part of the importance of women re-appropriating their own
artistic representation is that these representation play an important role in shaping our expectations of women,
so that if we had an artistic canon where women are only represented as subject in the works of male artists, we
are in fact letting these men determine what to expect of women and thus define what it is for a woman to be a
real woman. However, I found very little theoretical detail on working out how exactly this works.
Fast forward to the second decade of the new millennium and a lot of the topics in feminism we used to
discuss in the late nineties are starting to become more common in philosophical discussions in Mexico – at
least at my place of work, the Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas at the National University. So in 2015 I
2
started trying to finally put my thoughts into words. Chapter three was written at that time … and shelved. A new
turning point happened in 2017 when I attended Sally Hasslanger’s Gaos Lectures entitled “Structures of
Injustice.” Those lectures helped me finally structure my thoughts and the first two chapters of this book
originally started as notes to Hasslanger’s lectures, which I also discussed briefly with her (that is the main
reason they were written in English, and therefore, why the book ended up written in English as well).
Sometime in 2015, I met with a couple of my colleagues to go to the theatre and we started talking
about this project of mine and I told my friend Moisés Vaca that the plan was to give it a formal treatment. He
strongly advised me against it. He said that it would reduce the text’s potential impact. And it is true, I always tell
my students, in class and talks, that one of the disadvantages of systems of representations that strongly rely on
general semantic conventions – natural and formal languages, and other symbolic systems, etc. – is that they can
hardly be understood but by those who know the relevant conventions. But I also tell them that they also tend to
be very advantageous in terms of precision and expressive power. There are plenty thoughts that we cannot
communicate but with the aid of these sorts of representational systems. Thus even though my approach to
these phenomenons was very formal – I am after all, foremost a logician and an analytic philosopher, even
though one trained in deconstruction and post-structuralism – there are no formulas or any of the typical
In the end, this book is dedicated to those who have had the most patience to teach me about the
importance and commitment to social justice: Estefana Barceló, Cony Aspeitia, Alicia Silva, Nazan Ustundag,
but I am also thankful to the many other people who have taught me so much about these topics: Orfe Castillo,
Peggy Brandt, Karen Hanson, Ángeles Eraña, Judy Chicago, Laura Lecuona, Daisy Løvendahl, Benjamin
Buckley, Bree Morton, and many others whose names I am missing right now.
3
I. HABITABLE KINDS
In early drafts of this book, I used to call the topic of my interest “social categories” because that was the usual moniker in
most of the literature I was used to. However, I have since changed it to “habitable kinds” to signal my interest in talking
of these categories, not only as they are socialized, but mostly as they are inhabited by us. In other words, yes, I am
interested in the categories we use to talk about humans (yet not only humans),1 but mostly in so far they are also used to
talk about ourselves, about who we are, and who we are not, who we want to be and who we do not want to be, etc.
In general, habitable categories are important because they play a central role in at least three important sorts of
human practices which I will call theoretical, normative and subjectivizing practices. Habitable kinds play an important
roles in our theoretical practices because they figure centrally in the many ways we try to describe, explain and predict the
world, specially the human world. Habitable kinds figure prominently in many of our scientific practices, not only in the
human sciences – economics, anthropology, sociology, linguistics, etc. – but also in the medical and biological sciences.
Consequently, it is not surprising that much fundamental work on the ontology and epistemology of this sort of categories
has been done within the field of the philosophy of the human and social sciences. However, not all the theoretical work
habitable kinds do has scientific pretensions. Outside the sciences, we usually appeal to these categories to make sense of
the world. We expect people to behave in certain ways because we identify them as belonging to one kind or another
similarly as we use other categories to generate expectations in other aspects of reality. As Muhammad Ali Khalidi has
correctly stated, our “folk categories do not play [only] an epistemic role, [and thus] we should not expect them to
correspond to natural kinds, and we should not expect the folk to defer to the experts.” (Ali Khalidi 2013, 64)
Besides these theoretical uses, habitable kinds play a central role in all of our normative practices. How we
evaluate someone’s actions is deeply interwoven with what kind of person we think hey are. How we evaluate our own
actions is deeply interwoven with what kind of person we think we are. Inhabiting a kind usually entails duties as well as
1. After all, we also inhabit categories inhabited by non-human animals and it is not rare por some of us to identify with
these categories even more that with exclusively human categories like gender, class, race, etc. A close friend once
reported to me that she identified not as a woman, or Mexican or morena – even though her material circumstances would
have grant her such identities –, but instead identified herself as a micro-organism, a la par with other animals.
4
obligations, and there are duties and obligations that are conditional on our habitant some kinds or others. Minors
commonly have different rights than grown ups, aliens have different duties than citizens, etc. Even the most abstract
theories of obligation recognize this (Demolombe & Louis 2006). And even though most of the literature has focused on
ethical and political normativity, after the foundational of work of Bourdieu (1979), there has been a raising awareness
that habitable categories affect and are affected by our aesthetic judgments (Lamont and Molnár 2002, Bennett et al.
2009). In a now classic 1996 paper, Bethany Bryson has convincingly argued that “individuals use cultural taste to
reinforce symbolic boundaries between themselves and categories of people they dislike.” (Bryson 1996, 885). To put it
bluntly, people like or dislike certain, say, musical styles, not so much because of how those styles sound, but of how they
see themselves in relation to those who stereotypically like or dislike those styles (Weinstein 2000).
Finally, habitable kinds are key to a series of practices through which we develop our own subjectivity.By
inhabiting certain categories and not others, we identify with some people and not with others; we make sense of our own
existence and experience. As Mady G. has noted, “the main purpose of self-identification and classification is to foster
community and counteract feelings of confusion, otherness, and shame.” (G & Zuckerberg 2019) “I never spent anytime
whatsoever contemplating the subject of femaleness – wrote Elizabeth Gilbert in her 2009 autobiographical essay – For
that reason … I never became very familiar with myself” (Gilbert 2010, i) The question of who one is is usually answered
by giving a list of categories one identifies with. Even on he negative side, resisting the pull of certain categories we assert
our own subjectivity. Literary critic Stephanie Burt calls this aspect of subjectivization “the resistance to memoir, to
narrative” – which echoes Paul De Man’s deconstructive resistance to theory –, that is, the resistance “to identifying your
true self with one story” even while referring to such stories in the search for this elusive true self (Burt 2012). The
categories we inhabit also shape our desires, our thoughts and actions. As Burt herself writes, the desire to look pretty has
a different significance when one is a woman that when one is a man, or neither (ibidem).
In sum, habitable kinds live extremely heterogenous lives and a good philosophical account of them should
recognize it. It is tempting to think that one could just divide and conquer between these fields and talk about theoretical,
normative and subjective habitable kinds. However, concepts are not that well-behaved and they cannot be contained
within one single field, and the functions themselves are also deeply interwoven. One might think that the subjectivizing
functions are quite independent from the theoretical ones, for example; however Felwine Sarr (2016) and other have
5
argued that in order to heal the effects of colonization, third world subjects must also develop the sort of intellectual
sovereignty that requires a decolonization of the theoretical scholarship on the categories we inhabit. This means that for
categories to play the role we want in building our subjectivity, we must also change how we theorize about them, thus
bringing together their subjectivizing and theoretical roles. Precisely one of the reasons why it is such a pressing issue to
be clear on the metpahysics of habitable kinds is precisely because they are the vehicles of cross pollinization between
domains. Scientific theories, for example, have the sort of authority that makes them very attractive for ethical and political
normative co-option (López Beltrán 2004). As we will see, different theoretical stances tend to stress different uses and
functions, yet the goal of our exploration has been to develop a metaphysical account of categories of this sort that
It has been argued that a mark of social and structural oppression, marginalisation and injustice is that it targets not only
individuals but groups (or individuals as members of a group). Adopting such a stance, as I will do here, requires clarifying
what is meant when we say that a certain human (or even, perhpas, a non-human animal) group X is marginalised (in a
context C). After all, this later claim is substantially ambiguous. It could be a descriptive claim, meaning that:
A. A (generic) X is at a disadvantage with respect to a (generic) non-X (most commonly a hegemonic group Y) in
a common context C.
For example, to say that women are marginalised in Mexico might mean that women make less money that men, are less
represented in positions of power, receive less education and health services, etc.
B. A (generic) X is at a disadvantage with respect to a (generic) non-X (most commonly a hegemonic group Y) in a
In other words:
2. From now on I am going to obviate saying that these claims must be read as generic and with respect to a hegemonic
group in a common context. Also, in theses B onwards, marginalisation will mean A-marginalisation
6
However, B itself can be read, and has been read in at least two senses:
Weak-B. At least some of the causes of why the Xs are marginalised are that the Xs have certain properties that
Prima facie, A is very good, yet defeasible, evidence of B. It would be quite a coincidence if the Xs were marginalised for
causes that are more or less evenly distributed on the Xs and the Ys. However, some people take B to be a stronger claim:
Strong-B. At least some of the causes of why the Xs are marginalised are actions intended to marginalise the Xs.
Even though A is good evidence of weak-B, most current theories of marginalisation recognize that neither A nor weak-B
Furthermore, between weak-B and strong-B there is another thesis of marginalisation that has been important in
The idea is that passing for a member of a hegemonic group ameniorates some of the marginalisisng effects of belonging
to a marginalised group. For example, gays that pass as heterosexuals are less discriminated that gays that do not. It is not
obvious how to best characterise passing, for it depends on what it means to be an X or a Y. For example, it can mean to
show the appearence of being a Y, or something stronger like perfoming the values of Y. Borrowing an example from
Knobe and Prasada, one can say that Part of why Hillary Clinton has been able to rise as one of the main presidential
candidates has been because she embodies masculine values and traits.
Now, I say that C stands between weak-B and strong-B because strong-B gives us good but defeasible evidence of
C is also important because it is usually linked to a different set of claims regarding the marginalisation of X. So
far, A, B and C are all individualistic accounts of marginalisation. In other words, in them, for Xness to be marginalised is
nothing above the Xs being marginalised. However, for Xness to be marginalised can be conceived in a non-individualistic
way. In other words, so far X-ness has been conceived as a property (or set of properties) that individuals have or have not.
But Xness can also be conceived as something else that emerges from the joint action and customs of the Xs. This
anthropological sense of Xness is most obviously and readily applicable to ethnic groups, where Xness refers not to any
property that the X have but to the links that bind them together as Xs, i.e., their cultural products, customs, etc.
7
For example, in a recent interview American celebrity chef Anthony Bourdain expressed concern that when
people think of haute cousine they do not consider Mexican food, even though there is very good Mexican haute cousine.
Indeeed, in Mexico, and outside Mexico as well, Mexican food is strongly associated with “antojitos”, that is, comfort food
and snacks, and not with haute cousine. Now, since comfort food and snacks are commonly valued less that haute cousine,
this marginalises not (or not only) Mexicans as individuals, but Mexicanity itself.
Thus, we have:
As I mentioned, D-marginalisation is clear in cases of ethnic marginalisation, for example, of Kurds in Turkey, where
there are explicit measures to diminish the use of the Kurdish language and other similar cultural manifestations.
However, as we will see again in the next chapters, it does not apply as easily to other marginalised groups, for example, to
women in modern Western societies because their lives are more tightly interwoven with the lives of non-women – not
just because they live together, but because they commonly build string bonds of caring and other affects with them. To
paraphrase Paloma Hernández, it is more common for a woman to have a non-woman child or life partner that an African-
In the rest of this text, we will talk about social discrimination in a broad enough sense to cover all these forms of
discrimination A, B and C.
If my characterisation of social marginalisation is right, it hinges heavily on human categories. Thus, in order to better
understand and challenge this sources of injustice, it is important to understand the social distinctions and classifications
that underly them. In the words of Katharine Jenkins, “when embarking on ameliorative projects, we should be careful to
reflect on how we are conceptualizing the agents of ameliorative inquiry.” (Jenkins 2016, 406) It is not surprising,
therefore, that much recent work on the philosophy of social injustice has dealt with problems that belong to the
metaphysics of distinctions, in general, and of human distinctions in particular. It must no be surprising either that much
political debate regarding these distinctions comes sharper into focus once we get clear on the metaphysical status of our
8
so-called habitable human categories and related issues. Thus, the goal of these small texts is to draw a few distinctions of
my own on the many debates surrounding the metaphysics of the distinctions behind discrimination hoping that they may
I will divide metaphysical questions regarding discriminatory social categories [from now on, when I talk of
categories I will mean habitable categories of this sort, except when explicitly indicated] in four broad kinds: Aristotelian
Aristotelian questions are questions about the metaphysical basis for these distinctions, i.e., what makes (or would make)
someone belong to a certain human category or another. I call these questions “Aristotelian” because, as
well will see further ahead, they are very closely related to what is currently known as “Aristotelian
metaphysical questions”, i.e., questions about the relations of fundamentality between different kinds of
facts and objects. So, Aristotelian questions regarding social kinds, for example, have to do with questions
like: how do human kinds relate to human action and, in particular, human agency? how strong do they
determine or constraint our actions? how are they determined or constrained by our actions?, etc.
Quinean questions are questions about whether these categories are empty or not. I call them “Quinean” because they
are ultimately about what there is. My friend and colleague Angeles Eraña has suggested that we see the
distinction between Aristotelian and Quinean questions as the metaphysical analogue of the well-known
Structural questions are questions about the structure of the systems of categories the categories belong to.
Meta-metaphysical questions are questions about how to answer questions of the previous two kinds, i.e., what criteria
I will give now a brief summary of some of the key issues in each of these sorts. Hopefully, this will bring new light into the
distinction itself.
9
1. Aristotelian Questions
In broad strokes, we can classify the main positions in the Aristotelian debate in three major camps: common-sense, ethno-
I call the first camp “common sense accounts” because they endorse common sense answers to the Aristotelian
questions (or something as close to them as possible). So, for example, considering that the difference between men and
women is just biological (Institute of Medicine (US) Committee on Understanding the Biology of Sex and Gender
Differences 2001), that poverty just is the scarcity of material resources, that belonging to a given generation is just being
born on certain dates, that being short is just having a below average height, that being Hispanic is just to be an American
with Native Spanish speaking ancestors, that being a Mexican is just to be born in Mexico, that being dirty is just having
bad habits of hygiene, that being ignorant is lacking much important knowledge, etc. are all common sense accounts of the
distinctions underlying different cases of discrimination and oppression. Some social categories, however, lack a
straightforward common sense definition. A common sense account of the category of naco in Mexico, for example, has
Few philosophers endorse common sense accounts nowadays. They are commonly considered naive and
misguided insofar as they fail to address (or, even worse, perpetuate) the oppressive and discriminatory nature of the
distinctions they are supposed to characterise. A purely biological characterisation of gender differences, for example,
might fail to account for the power asymmetries between those that inhabit them. Characterising poverty as scarcity would
suggest that the problem is economical, instead of political – one of resource distribution, instead of one of exclusion and
discrimination, etc. Furthermore, common sense accounts tend to present themselves as ideologically neutral when, in
fact, they heavily reflect the prevailing ideology of those who hold them. In other words, what is common sense or not
depends heavily on the context and, in particular, to who holds power in such a context. Thus, giving ontological weight to
This is an important methodological issue. We philosophers (especially analytic ones) rely quite a lot on folk
intuitions and on what we take to be common-sense. But once we get into a politically charged discussion, we
must recognize that these folk intuitions vary across subcultures. Now what? Well, to settle on mainstream
intuitions and common-sense is to make a political decision to further marginalize what Kristie Dotson called
“diverse practitioners” in the field. (Talia Mae Bettcher 2018)
10
Efforts towards addressing these shortcomings have given rise to more sophisticated theories that stress their
social, historical and ethnic aspects. According to these socio-historico-ethnic accounts what makes someone belong to
a given category are the social and cultural traits and relations she has in common with others like her. Thus, feminists who
consider the sex/gender distinction central to understanding womanhood adopt an ethno-social stance towards gender in
this sense (Lecuona 2018). Similar stances lay behind ontological theses like identifying the Mexican nationality with
certain cultural practices, habits, signifiers, values, etc. shared by many, but not all, and certainly not only the people born
or living in Mexico. Social constructivist theories are another paradigmatic example; for example, considering that what
makes someone short, dirty or ignorant are her failing to meet certain standards of height, hygiene or knowledge that are
not objective (like an average, for example) but depend on many social factors that deeply interweave them with other
social categories, like class, race and gender; thus how clean need a white American woman be in order to be clean is
substantially different from how clean an African American man must be in order to fit the same category. [I will deal with
social-constructivist theories in more details in the next chapter.] Philosophers who think that what makes a person an
African American is a common history or common experiences are also embracing a socio-ethnic stance towards these
categories.
Ethno-Social accounts have been usually criticised for relying on an overtly simplistic view of social causes and
mechanisms. For instance, according to these criticisms, attempts to define what it is for someone to belong to a certain
habitable category, like a nationality or a race, by appealing to a common history fail because they just move the question
one level up. This is so, because they still need to explain what makes certain historical facts part of this common history
and not others. Trying to define the Mexican identity by appealing to a historical process of mestizaje, for example, gives
rise to the problem of trying to define what historical facts, process and effects are part of this so-called mestizaje and
which are not; but this problem is not actually simpler than the original one, and furthermore, it is not clear that we can
solve it without appealing to some prior notion of Mexican identity. Thus, the proposed account fails to historically
ground our national identity. Historical facts are just not sharp enough to serve as the kind of foundations that historicists
Other ethno-social accounts face similar shortcomings: whatever ethno-social mechanisms they appeal to end up
being much messier than expected. As a result, their attempts at providing an ontology well suited for a system of
11
redistributive justice face a series of problems that challenge their political and theoretical soundness (probably the best
known of which is commonly known as the “nonidentity problem”). For example, as aforementioned, many Ethno-Social
accounts aim to make constitutive of a habitable category at least some social injustices the members of such category have
endured in such a way as to make them worthy of the benefits of restorative redistribution of resources. For example, it has
been argued that part of what makes someone Native-American is to be the kind of people who have and still endure the
negative effects of European colonialism in America, and that this is part of what makes some forms of Affirmative action
in their benefit just. However, filling the blanks of exactly how to link Native identity to colonization has proved to be an
elusive matter, precisely because the current life and situations of American natives are so embedded in the overall effects
of colonialism. We want to recognize that practically every aspect of current native American identity has been shaped by
colonialism, and we want to say that the overall effect of colonialism on current native Americans has been harmful, yet we
do not want to reach the seemingly unavoidable conclusions that being a native American or being born one is some kind
Socio-ethnic accounts have also been criticised as being alienating to the subjects that inhabit them because they
place social categories outside the classified subject and thus do not leave enough room for genuine agency (see
Thompson 1968 and Casey 1995 for class, Born & Hesmondhalgh 2000 and Jardina 2019 for ethnicity, Abrams 1995
and the works there discussed for gender, Guerrero MacManus 2018 for human, etc.). As Philippe Bourgeois has written,
“a focus on structures often obscures the fact that humans are active agents of their own history, rather than passive
victims.” (1995, 17) By defining social kinds by the social conditions under which the persons who belong to them live,
including those that oppress them, it makes such oppression constitutive of the kind, and as such, they seem to leave no
room for liberation (without abandoning the category itself) (Mikkola 2016).
This concern has given rise to a new set of theories that have been broadly called “identity accounts”. Identity
accounts can be easily summarized as accounts of the belonging to a habitable category as a kind of constrained act (or
something act-like like a skill or personal project).3 In the words of Appiah (2018), habitable categories are “an activity,
not a thing … not a fate but a project”. Identity accounts incorporate the insights from both socio-ethnic and common-
3. I am skipping over the debate on whether it is the act itself that constitutes our identity or something deeper that
manifests itself in such act, either something that we feel or perceive within oursleves (and thus, something for which we
have privileged firt person access) or the feeling itself. Most theorists and activists see no important distinction here.
12
sense accounts as constraints to the act, but reinstate the agent at the center of her belonging to one category or other.
Thus, they hold categories like womanhood, disability, nationality, foreignness, etc. not so much as things that one is, but
more fundamentally, as things one does. To be a Mexican, for example, is to choose to act in a certain way in given
occasions – like partying the night of September the 15th by listening to ranchero music from mid-20th Century and
eating certain food (like tacos and pozole) and not other (like hamburgers) – constrained by the social and material factors
affecting her in her context – such as those that would make it hard for her to find good tacos in downtown Reykjavik, but
would make it hard to avoid if she lived in downtown Coyoacán neighborhood in Mexico City.
This performative aspect of identity is very well illustrated by a key scene in Xaime Hernández’s Wig Wam Bam
(1994) episode of his long lasting Chicano series of novels. After a couple of hipsters make racist commentaries to her at a
party on the East Coast of the USA, Margarita Luisa Chascarillo complains to her friend and lover Esperanza Leticia
Glass, telling her she is more than happy to leave town, meaning going back to their Chicano neighborhood in southern
California. Esperanza tries to make little of the event and to have Margarite drop the subject stating that “It’s the same shit
all over…” Margarita gets angry at the lack of solidarity from Esperanza, who has Colombian ancestors but, unlike her, can
pass for white and American. “Ok, then don’t go back to California! – she screams at her lover – Shit, just ‘cause you can
turn off your ‘ethnic’ half whenever it’s goddamn convenient!” I was born in Mexico, as were my parent. My skin is brown,
my hair is black and my mother tongue is Spanish. I have lived most of my life in Mexico City and currently live in the
typical Mexican neighborhood of Coyoacán, just a couple of blocks from historical monuments of early Colonial history.
For me, it is very easy and natural to be Mexican, so much that it might seem more appropriate to say that I did not have to
do much to be Mexican and that I was just born this way. That being born in the place where I was born, into the family and
culture I was burn made me Mexican. This is just what the socio-ethnic accounts hold. However, not everyone shares the
same circumstances and the above scene illustrates this very well. For Esperanza, her situation allows for her to become
either white American or Colombian depending on what she does. She has reached a point where she has to act in one way
or another. This decision is materially constrained by her circumstances – her skin color, her ancestry, her relation to
California and to Margarita – but it is still hers to make. Whatever way she acts will have not only an ontological effect, but
also an ethical one. The way Xavier Hernández sets the scene it is clear that the ethical decision is to resist her whiteness
13
and live up to her Colombianess.4 For identity accounts, if we look back at a case like mine, after considering Esperanza’s
choice, we can see that there is also an element of choice and action: that being born in Mexico, being brown, etc. are not
what make me Mexican, but only the material circumstances that constrains my actions, but it is ultimately these actions
that ground my Mexican identity. Considering borderline cases is very helpful in this respect in so far as allows us to
disentangle the action from the circumstances that frame it (Jardina 2019).
Presenting these three broad tendencies this way, of course, abstracts from important differences within each one
of them. My presentation so far is also misleading, insofar as it leaves the impression that the matter has been (or should
have been) settled and that identity theories are just better. Nothing is further from the truth, as accounts of the three sorts
have both advantages and disadvantages over the others. Common sense theories, for example, have the obvious
descriptive advantage of respecting common sense. Furthermore, their being based on common sense does not mean that
they can also be (or become) very sophisticated accounts. An economic account of poverty, for example, can be as naive or
Consequently, they can also argue that criticisms against them are question-begging in so far a they asume, instead of
show, that (at least part of) the social aspects of discrimination lie within the ontological category itself, instead of
belonging to the more complex material and social network it is situated in.
Ethno-Social accounts, in turn, criticise identity theories for being either not a genuine alternative to socio-
ethnic theories or overtly individualistic and drawing the boundaries between categories in the wrong place (where
‘wrong’ here means both ‘inaccurate’ and ‘unjust’) by overestimating the importance of individual action and choice. This
basic criticism branded at identity theories is that the notion of a constrained act of identification at the center of identity
theories is an ill-defined notion, unstable between two equally undesirable positions. On the one hand, if a constrained act
of identification were just the mere act of freely asserting one’s will of belonging to a certain social group, that would
cheapen the social categories to the point of being too arbitrary for being of any use in the fight for social justice. Such an
4. This does not mean that all such choices have always such a clear ethical profile. Consider the case of Nicole Richie, who
was adopted when she was 3. Her African American parents, the successful singer and songwriter Lionel Richie and his
then-wife Brenda Harvey, knew Nicole's biological parents, who were Mexican American. She went to live with and be
cared for by the Richies since early in her childhood and was legally adopted at nine. Growing up in the spotlight, she was
pressured into testifying to her ethnic identity and she could have chosen to identify as Mexican American or African
American without much ethical fault.
14
action would not be a constrained action. On the other hand, if we require the act to be socially recognized within the
group as being the kind of act that constitutes the kind, then what identity theorists mean by a constrained act is nothing
but what socio-ethnic theorists call a social practice. Thus, identity theory would not be an actual alternative to socio-
ethnic theories, and would not have achieved the desired des-exteriorization of our social ontology. Thus, in order for
identity theories to be a genuine alternative there must be some third alternative, but it is not clear that there is really such
a third way, even though identity theorists have certainly made substantial efforts in giving us one.
Furthermore, critics also claim that allowing those who would otherwise be identified as members of privileged
group to identify as members of historically disenfranchised groups gives them unfair access to resources aimed to restore
historical injustices. For example, it has been argued that making it easier for people to ‘self-identify’ within a particular
category or other could well be abused by unscrupulous members of privileged groups who might use these measures to
access resources reserved for members of discriminated groups. (Stock 2018) These critics also argue that the categories
defined by identity theories put together people which, from the perspective both from the common sense and socio-
ethnic perspective are too diverse to serve in efforts to diversify sites of power like governing bodies or boardrooms.
According to these critics, people who identify with categories different from the ones they have been assigned and people
who do not might have such different bodies, social histories, structural power, access to resources, etc. that one could not
properly represent the experiences and concerns of the other. Thus, there is no use in including them in one common
category.
On the other hand, identity theories have also been criticized recently of making it too hard for those who could
and should benefit the most from it of being recognized as inhabiting a given marginalized category. By insisting on an
active engagement with the category, identity theories seem to require from those who are already in a practically
diminished status to make an extra effort to be recognized as such. According to this criticism, by belittling victimhood,
2. Quinean Questions
Related to the Aristotelian debate, but not fully determined by it, the Quinean debate holds mostly between eliminativists
– those who take discriminatory categories to be empty – and well, whatever you want to call non-eliminativists. I have
15
already used the term “common-sense theories” above, but the term would also be adequate for non-eliminativists).
Furthermore, as I will develop in more detail in the third chapter, eliminativists usually (but not necessarily) endorse
common sense accounts, and use them as arguments for their eliminativist arguments. For example, some people have
argued that races are empty because our common sense conceptions of what a race is – i.e., substantial phenotypic
differences between social groups of common ancestors – do not correspond to anything in biological reality. Similarly,
some philosophers have recently argued that since it is constitutive of our common sense understanding of some social
categories that people that belong to them are somehow inferior, and this is patently false, nothing can fit inside them (I
will not mention examples, because these categories are commonly expressed by the use of slurs and other derogatory
terms. This phenomenon will be addressed in further detail in the third and final chapter).
I find it interesting that this relation between eliminativism and common sense happens in other areas of
metaphysics, for example, in the philosophy of mathematics, where nominalists (that is, eliminativists regarding
mathematical entities) adopt a common sense view of the ontological nature of mathematical objects – i.e., that they are
abstract entities – and then use this common sense account as a premise for the conclusion that there are no mathematical
objects.
Even though in the rest of this manuscript I will focus on Quinean and Aristotelian questions, I still want to give
at least a superficial presentation of what other sort of metaphysical questions can we make regarding habitable categories,
3. Structural Questions
Besides the Quinean and Aristelian questions, there are also important questions regarding the structure of these systems
of categories, its dynamics and context of application. In this regards, I identify five major questions:
1. Are categories unified or are they fragmented? For example, is there one, unified thing that it is to be a Mexican or is
2. What categories belong to the same system of classification? For example, is Jewishness a race? Are races and
ethnicities the same sort of categories? How many human genders are there?
16
3. Are the categories within a system mutually exhaustive and/or exclusive? For example, is it possible for someone to
be neither a man nor a woman? Is it possible for someone to be both rich and poor?
4. How do the categories develop over time? For example, how old must a woman be in order to be a spinster? Can one
5. In what socio-historical contexts do these categories apply? For example, are there races outside colonial and post-
colonial societies? Are races in miscegenation regimes (like the United States of America) the same sort of categories
as races in mestizo regimes (like Mexico or England) Are communist societies actually classless?
4. Meta-metaphysical Questions
1. Epistemological and methodological questions about what factors should be taken in consideration when
answering the (Aristotelian, Quinean and Structural) questions above and what weight should be given to them. For
example, what role should the empirical sciences play? and, furthermore, which sciences should be taken in
consideration (natural, human, social)? What credence should be given to autobiographic testimony and narratives
and from whom? Should we only listen to the voices of those who belong to the relevant oppressed groups or is there a
place for the voices of the rest of the community even if they profit from their oppression? Furthermore, should
2. Questions about the goal or goals of answering those questions? For example, how descriptive/prescriptive should
our answers be? Should we adopt a critical stance towards these categories? If we aim at prescription, should our
prescriptions be reformist or revolutionary, modest or radical? (Cappelan 2018) Also, what sort of facts do we want
our metaphysical theses to explain? For example, should our metaphysical theories explain why we have the
theoretical, ethical and political debates that we have or should they aim to solve them? A metaphysical account that
makes, for example, gender (metaphysically) necessarily oppressive begs the Quinean question or effectively answers
it?
17
3. Questions about how general or determinate should the answers be? Are we looking for absolutely general answers
that are context sensitive, or should the answers themselves be valid only in constrained historical circumstances?
How thinly should we slice contexts in order to find adequate answers to these questions? How much vagueness of
inditerminateness should be allowed or expected? If our goal is a metaphysics to drive our political action, how
These questions might seem peculiar to social metaphysics or to the metaphysics of politically relevant (not
necessarily social) kinds; however, this is would only be true under a very broad notion of social metaphysics. In the
philosophy of science, for example, analogous meta-metaphysical questions are also relevant. Many philosophers of
cognitive science, for example, who work on the metaphysics of mind conceive of their work as normative or critical as
they are not trying to understand what are the metaphysics of mental categories but what must be the metaphysics of
mental categories. Once again, this is because – as we will see in the next chapter, many (perhaps most) scientific
categories have social and practical (ethical, political, etc.) consequences. For example, where we draw the line between
say, entities with minds and entities without minds will have great consquences to those very entities.
Keeping metaphysical questions sharply identified also helps in disentangling them from questions of other political and
ethical sorts, like: what role do they play in the emergence of social injustices, oppression and discriminatio? how do we
challenge unjust categories? and how do we build better ones? What do they tell us about the moral responsibility (or lack
thereof) of the members of society in the development and maintenance of their unjust consequences? What do they tell
us about the moral responsibility (or lack thereof) of those who fall under them in their actions as members of those
groups?
18
D. Does it make sense to speak at such an abstract level?
One might be skeptical about the value of talking about habitable categories in such abstract, detached and general terms
as I plan to do here. About seventy years ago, Bernabé Navarro was already skeptical of such an abstract ontological
“I do not see what we aim to achieve with these ontology reflections [combining] in an almost muddled way, on
the one hand, existentialism, historicism, scholasticism, and on the other, Freud, Aristotle, Saint Thomas,
Goethe, Bloch, Toynbee, Octavio Paz, Javier Villaurrutia, etc. and even some folk tales ... “ (Navarro, 1982, 12)5
In a recent online debate, to put another example, Audrey Yap wrote that it was unacceptable for philosophers to address
these issues as if they were an “abstract philosophical puzzle” instead of an issue of vital importance for so many – perhaps
all – people:
“So setting aside the question of terminology, what I do have a serious problem, with, are people who are happy
to speculate about [habitable categories] gender identity… as though it were an abstract philosophical puzzle to
be solved, and not something that is about actual living people. When taking one side of an argument involves the
invalidation of a lot of people’s identity and lived experience I think it’s right that we be extremely hesitant to take
it. That’s not to say it’s entirely off limits to talk about gender identity or to disagree with trans folks or other
philosophers. Not all trans folks or feminist philosophers agree with each other on these issues anyway. But cis
people and trans people have a different stake in the matter…” (Yap 2018)
Unfortunately, I have little to say to convince anyone already skeptical of dealing with social problems as pressing as these
at such a theoretical and abstract level. I just hope that my work shows its own value on its own. As a brown, queer,
Mexican, the topics I deal with on this text have strong existential significance for me and I certainly have a stake on the
matter. As a heterosexual cis-male with a privileged academic position, the topics I deal with on this text have strong
“I’m afraid there’s a tendency among some philosophers to suppose that philosophical investigations into race,
gender, disability, trans issues, and so forth are no different methodologically from investigations into the
5. “…no vislumbro a qué punto preciso se quiere llegar con las reflexiones consideradas como ontológicas – o que traten
de conducir a la ontología – en las cuales se utilizan y manejan, en forma entremezclada y casi confusa, por una parte, el
existencialismo, el historicismo, la escolástica, y por otra, a Freud, Aristóteles, Sto. Tomás, Goethe, Bloch, Toynbee,
Octavio Paz, Javier Villaurrutia, etc. y hasta algunas leyendas populares y folklóricas…” Even though the text was
published in 1982, by the author’s own account, it was written around thirty years earlier.
19
question whether tables really exist. One difference, however, is that while tables aren’t part of the philosophical
conversation, trans people, disabled people, people of color, are part of the conversation.” (Bettcher 2018)
As I have already mentioned, there are still important open debates regarding the proper methodology for social
ontology. However, it is worth noticing that nothing I have said so far entails that a single answer will work for all habitable
categories. In a recent conversation, at the National University’s Diversities Workshop, Siobhan Guerrero presented
many concerns we might have about just transposing metaphysical arguments from one kind of habitable categories to
another. For example, it is relatively clear that material conditions are fundamental for determining who is or is not a
bourgeois or a proletarian, but we should not generalize this to other categories such as gender or race. Material
conditions may also be fundamental, or maybe not, but this is a question that must be resolved on a case-by-case basis. In
the end, Guerrero argues, the metaphysics or race will most likely be substantially different from that of gender. The
historical and political differences between these categories are so radical that any account that might serve to build better
racial relations could reinforce gender injustices if applied to these other categories. This is because the struggle and
oppression experienced by minorities of each type has been substantially different in each case. Even within a single
historical and cultural context, the way in which ethnic minorities are discriminated against and oppressed tends to be
radically different from the way in which gender minorities are discriminated against and oppressed. For example, there
does not seem to have been an analogous to cultural appropriation as a strategy of erasing racial identities in the case of
gender. Consider as an example, the situation of the Kurdish minorities in Turkey, whose cultural manifestations have
been systematically appropriated by Turkish nationalists with the nefarious purpose of erasing their identity as an
autonomous ethnic group. Nothing similar seems to have happened in the case of gender minorities. Although it is true
that the cultural contributions of gender minorities have been disparaged and appropriated, it does not seem appropriate
to characterize this as a case of cultural appropriation (Serano 2016). This is because race tends to be more closely related
to culture than gender – mono-gender cultures are less common than mono-racial ones (Chauncey 1994). Therefore, it
seems that, at least prima facie, the loss of cultural goods is a harder blow against racial minorities than against gender
minorities. This means that, for example, given their very different historical antecedentes, the threat of cultural
appropriation is a more serious threat for the Afro-American or Rom identity than for the identity of women or trans
people. So it seems that the difference in public reactions to cases like Caitlyn Jenner’s and Rachel Dozal’s is justified,
20
although it is true - noted Guerrero - that there is still much to be learned about the different ways people inhabit
categories like gender and race in order to determine how different they actually are.
In an informal discussion, Paloma Hernández pointed out to me that, perhaps, one of the most important
differences between racial (and ethnic) differences in segregated contexts like in the USA or Argentina (and unlike
‘mestizo’ contexts like those of Mexico or the UK) and gender differences is that, while the former tend to be experienced
‘from a distance’ so to speak, the latter are present in many of our most intimate relationships. In other words, the
experience of living intimately with people belonging to other gender categories (either as relatives, couples, colleagues,
neighbors, etc.) is substantially more common than the experience of living intimately with people of other ethnicity, race
or class.
Guerrero is also right in pointing out that a good metaphysical account of race and gender must account for this
type of differences. For example, it must account for why testifying to our own gender plays such a central role in the
construction of our subjectivity, while there does not seem to be anything analogous in the case of race. In her
presentation, Guerrero alluded to the important role that desire plays in gender identity – “the idea – associated with
Jacques Lacan – that your sense of who you are grows from your sense of what you want, what you lack, so that in order to
keep being the person you recognize as yourself, you have yo keep wanting something you cannot have”(Burt 2012; see
also Long Chu 2017) – and how it seems to be absent from most racial identities. Ever since the seminal work of Foucault
on human sexuality, it has been claimed that an important part of belonging to one genre or another is to desire certain
things and not others. There does not seem to be anything analogous in the case of race, although in contexts such as the
United States, miscegenation remains an important issue and, in this sense, desire also plays an important role in the
construction of race in that context. If Guerrero is right, since desire is something that, at least in our popular psychology,
is private, subjective and, above all, something for which we have privileged access, this would explain why gender is also
something for which we have privileged access (but race is not). It would also explain why gender cannot be a political
choice. In the words of Andrea Long Chu (2017), whom I read months after listening to Guerrero,
"... nothing good comes of forcing desire to conform to political principle ... one can not be aroused as an act of
solidarity, in the same way that it can fill envelopes or march on the streets with its fighting sisters. Desire is, by
21
However, I take it that even if it is true that different sorts of categories have different metaphysical profiles, it is precisely
because they show a different behavior when considered under the same criteria. Thus, for example, if it is true that there
is a stronger metaphysical link between gender and self-testimony that between, say, class and self-testimony, this must
manifest itself as differences in the way we shall answer specific general questions about gender and class as habitable
categories. Thus, it is fundamental to know the general issues and challenges that faces any metaphysical account of any
habitable category in order to even try to understand whether different sorts of categories are metaphysically different.
22
Regarding a putative ontological kind X (mathematical objects, artifacts, races, theoretical entities, etc.), it is important to
distinguish between three different metaphysical questions (of what I have called the Aristotelian and Quinean kinds): do
Xs exist and, if so, what do their existence depend on?, why are they X?, and why do we make a difference between Xs and
Not-Xs?
The first question is the Quinean ontological issue identified in the previous chapter of whether certain kind of
objects exists and, if so, whether they are natural, socially constructed, fictitious, etc., the second is the question of what
metaphysically grounds certain truths or facts, and the third is the issue of whether or not our concepts cut reality at its
seams. The questions are different and, for the most part, independent.
Thus, for example, in the philosophy of physics, it is important to distinguish between the questions:
1. Are forces real, i.e., do the entities in the extension of the predicate “(is a) force” exist, and if so, are they part of the
fundamental furniture of the world or does their existence depends on the existence of other objects or facts
regarding, for example, human conventions, the constraints of cognitive architecture, cultural perspective, personal
preferences, etc.?
2. Why are forces forces, i.e., what makes the objects in the extension of the predicate “(is a) force” be forces? Is there a
fact of the matter whether or not something is a force or not, or does it depend on our conventions, cognitive
3. Why do we make a distinction between forces and non-forces? Does the concept “force” cuts reality at its seams or
does it only make sense for our social practices, cognitive architecture, preferences, etc.? Is it a natural kind or is it
Notice that the third question is not why a particular entity x is an X rather than a non-X (that would be the second
question), but the question of why do we make a difference between the Xs and the Ys. Thus, the second question is
23
independent of the first in so far as it applies to all sorts of entities: fundamental, derived, fictitious, socially constructed,
etc. However, it is not completely independent from the second because, even though socially constructed properties
cannot be natural kinds, not all natural properties are natural kinds, and thus it makes sense to make the further question
of why do we mark certain differences and not others. Whether the Xs are natural, fictitious, socially constructed, etc. it is
The third question is a question of joint-carving, because, presumable, if the answer to a question of this third
kind necessarily and substantially appeals to our practices, cognitive architecture, preferences, etc., then the distinction
1. Social Construction
Being a realist (or a fictionalist or a social constructivist, etc.) regarding a type of objects means different things depending
if one is taking a position regarding each of these three questions. Consider the first question: If one is a Quinean, being a
realist regarding the Xs does not mean much else besides believing that the Xs exist, and that must be the end of it; but if
one is an Aristotelean, one may still wonder whether the X are fundamental or not and if they are not (all) fundamental,
what does their existence depend on. If one believes only things with objective existence are real, then one will reject as
real those entities that exist, but whose existence depends on human conventions, the constraints of cognitive
Consider some examples. We usually make a distinction between socially constructed entities like words,
passports, baseball bats and nations on the one hand, and not socially constructed entities like neutrons, lumps of coal,
and clouds on the other, even if we admit that some entities, such as domestic cats and melodies are difficult to classify.
What makes a nation socially constructed is that its existence metaphysically (not just causally) depends on certain human
social actions and/or practices. Clouds, in contrast, are usually considered to exist independently of our social actions and
practices. We have done nothing to make them exist and they could have existed even if society had never developed on
this earth. This is a distinction at the level of question one, since it concerns the existence of entities of a certain sort.
24
Regarding the second question, we usually make a distinction between socially constructed facts like fanny packs
being uncool and Paris being the capital of France, and not socially constructed facts like every planet with an atmosphere
having clouds or Mauna Kea having an altitude of 4,205 meters. Again, we have cases that are difficult to classify like the
seventh note of a musical scale being its leading tone or tomatoes tasting good. In this regards, we say that Paris is the
capital of France is a socially constructed fact because part of why this is actually so is because of our social practices,
institutions and actions. In contrast, the altitude of Mauna Kea is putatively independent of our social constructions, that
is, nothing we have done or could have done could have changed its altitude (without causally affecting its physical reality,
Notice that socially constructed facts could involve both socially constructed entities – that is, entities whose
existence is socially constructed – and not-socially constructed entities; just as socially constructed entities and not
socially constructed entities could both be involved in not socially constructed facts. This is why I have insisted that the
socially constructed nature of entities is independent of the social construction of facts. For example, it is a socially
constructed fact that diamonds are precious stones, even though the existence of diamonds is not socially constructed. On
the other hand, it is not a socially constructed fact that Paris is rainy, even if Paris is a socially constructed entity.
Now, a property is socially-constructed if having it is a socially constructed fact, and not otherwise. Thus, being a
precious stone, or cool, or expensive, etc. are socially constructed properties; being rainy, having certain given mass or
One might argue that since Paris would not exist were it not for our social practices and conventions, it could not be rainy
without them either. Fair enough, so a more precise formulation of what makes a fact socially-constructed is required. To
this end, I propose that a fact is socially constructed if it depends on our social practices and actions for more than just the
Along these lines, one could argue that Mauna Kea having an altitude of 4,205 meters is a socially constructed
fact since there would be no such thing as meters if not because of our current social practices of measurement. However,
25
this would be a mistake that is easily avoided if one is careful to make a difference between predicates (in language) and
properties (in the world), in particular, between how we use a predicate to fix a property and the property thus fixed. A
Suppose there is a young girl standing just to the left of a huge rock, half buried in the ground (the rock, not the
girl). She claims to be able to move the rock from her right to her left side without using any tool or machinery, and willing
to bet half a thousand dollars to prove it. Furthermore, you are allowed to try moving the rock yourself so that you can
verify that it is not a trick rock or something else pretending to be a rock, etc. After trying to move the rock, you confirm
that it is heavy indeed and half buried to the ground. So you agree to the bet. Once the bet is set, she turns around on her
place 180 degrees. “Now – she says – the rock is no longer to my right, it is to my left”. Thus she wins the bet.
The joke is funny, presumably, because of an equivocation in the expressions “to my right” and “to my left” as
uttered by the cunning girl. The rock did not actually move, in so far as it did not change location. Yet, it is true that it was
on the girl’s left side and now it is on her right side. This is because we usually use the expressions “to my right” and “to
my left” to refer to spatial locations using ourselves as point of reference. However, we can also use them to talk about our
spatial relation to such spatial locations and the objects that occupy them. When the girl claimed that she could move the
rock from her left to her right, we assumed her to be using those expressions in the first way: we assumed she was using
herself as a point of reference to fix a couple of spatial locations, not in the second sense. Thus, we believed she was going
to change the location of the rock, not her spatial relation to the rock.
This joke illustrates the importance of making a distinction between the property we talk about and how we fix
such property. When we use “to my left” to talk about the location of an object, we use ourselves as props to fix the spatial
property, but we are not part of the property in the metaphysical sense. Consequently, whether an object has such
property does not depend on us. In contrast when we use “to my left” to talk about our spatial relation to an object, we
Something similar happens when we use expressions like “four days”, “4,205 meters”, etc. We use social
conventions to fix the properties corresponding to these predicates, but the conventions themselves are not part of the
properties expressed. Thus, we can truly say that many years had passed before we developed the convention of measuring
time in years; and that Mars was already million kilometres from the Earth before the development of the metric system.
26
Furthermore, we can also say that Mars would still be that far, even if we had never developed the metric system, for the
Thus, we could talk about using predicates like “millions of light years from the Earth” or “three pounds” to
socially fix properties that are not themselves socially constructed. These properties are not socially constructed because
what makes an object being millions of light years from the Earth or weighting three pounds is not any social convention,
practice or anything similar. None of our social practices put the sun at the distance it is, but our social practices of
measurements allowed us to describe such distance by using the expression “149.600.000 kilometers from earth”.
Finally, Aristotelian questions are improtant because we usually care about whether a kind is socially constructed or not,
meaning, whether it makes a socially constructed distinction or not. As aforementioned, we say that a distinction is
socially constructed if it makes sense only in function of certain human social practices, actions or institutions. For
example, we usually say that electrons are a natural kind because the distinction between what is an electron and what it is
not is there in nature, independently of our social practices, institutions, etc. In contrast, the distinction between the
owner of a property and others is a socially constructed one because its central function is to help us regulate our social
practices. Thus, owning something is a socially constructed kind, not a natural one.
As I had mentioned before, the question of whether a kind is natural, socially constructed, subjective, etc. is not
completely independent from the questions of whether the corresponding property is natural, socially constructed,
subjective, etc. However they are different questions, because even though socially constructed properties cannot be
natural kinds, not all natural properties are natural kinds, i.e., we can make distinctions in nature that nature itself does
not make. Medicine is full of such examples. Whether a condition is endodental or periodontal, for example, does not
depend on our social conventions at all, but on the physiological and physical conditions of our mouth; yet, the distinction
between endodontics and periodontics is socially constructed. Nature makes no such difference, it is our practices of how
we approach conditions of each kind that makes them different to us (here, today).
27
4. An Example in the Philosophy of Disability
In a large body of work, Shelley Tremain has sustained that the concept of impairment is socially constructed and,
presumably, this is what she means: that the distinction between impaired and not impaired bodies is not a distinction that
would make sense except for our social practices, institutions, values, etc. We can express this by saying that whether a
body is impaired or not depends on our social practices, institutions, values, etc. However, doing so would be very
unhelpful and confounding since it would be ambiguous between three substantially different claims of the sort I have
identified in this text: (1) a claim regarding the existence of impaired bodies as entities, (2) a claim about the metaphysical
status of impairment as a property and (3) a claim concerning the status of impairment as a concept. In order to determine
what is the correct reading for this claim, it is helpful to understand why philosophers like Tremain care whether a
concept is socially constructed or not. In this regards, Ron Mallon’s words are very relevant:
Some theorists defend constructionist views because they believe that they more adequately explain the
phenomena than competing views. But many constructionists have more explicitly political or social aims.
For this latter group of theorists, revealing the contingency of a thing on our culture or decisions suggests
that we might alter that thing through future social choices. It also may indicate our responsibility to do so
Thus, I take it that the correct reading is as a claim about why we make a distinction between impaired and not impaired
bodies, instead of a question about facts or entities. In other words, if impairment is socially constructed in this sense, we
could change our social practices and values in such a way that bodies that are currently considered as impaired could no
longer be so. However, this change would be a change similar to the one performed by the cunning girl in our joke above:
the bodies would not change their intrinsic properties, but our relation to them would change. But this would not be a less
important change, on the contrary. Changing our social practices would not (directly) make people who currently cannot
see, see, for example, but it would make their bodies no longer impaired, and this would be a signifiant political
achievement.
This critical stance stands in sharp contrasts with positions like those of Michael Oliver, the so-called British
Model of Disability, and others who make a distinction between disability, which they take to be socially constructed and
28
oppressive, and impairment, which they consider not socially constructed and thus neutral regarding social oppression.
Consider, for example, motor neuron disease, a progressive terminal condition that affects the nerve cells that
control voluntary muscle activity such as walking, breathing and swallowing. Clearly, such a fatal health condition
is a disadvantage in its own right, but it also has an accumulative disadvantage that has negative effects on other
functionings such as on one’s livelihood, relationships, and psychological well-being” (Vehmas and Watson,
2014. My emphasis)
According to Vehmas and Watson, nothing social is involved in making motor neuron disease a physical impairment.
Having such a condition is disadvantage in its own right. I take it that Tremain’s point is that these models of disability
(and impairment) miss the difference between the second and third questions above, i.e., between the socially constructed
nature of properties and facts on the one hand, and kinds and distinctions on the other. In consequence, they try to turn
into different properties – disability and impairment – what are actually two different aspects of one and the same property
– disability. For Tremain, if there were such a thing as impairment, it would also be socially-constructed in the very same
Tremain and, in general, critical theorists of disability insistence on the inseparability of the social dimension of
disability has a political aim: to raise awareness of the way the notion of disability is linked to exclusion. In particular, to
how the way we normally use such a notion serves to justify the exclusion of certain bodies. As I have tied to argue, from
the fact that there is a heterogeneity of bodies and capacities it does not follow that there is a distinction between bodies
with 'normal' capacities and bodies that do not. Of course, any capacity has some value – there is a substantial sense in
which it is better to have the capacity for singing on tune than not having it, for example. The challenge is to try to argue,
… capabilities through which we aspire [and which are such a] part of humanness … that a life without [them]
could not be a good human life. [There is] a threshhold of capability to function … beneath which those
characteristic functions are available in such a reduced way that although we may judge the form of life a human
one, we will not think it a good human life. (Nussbaum 1992, 220-1)
29
This presents a double challenge to those who wish to justify this distinction: on the one hand, they must justify the very
existence of the distinction and, on the other, the need to justify how it is drawn. For Tremain and other critical theorists
and social constructivists it is clear that the function that the distinction has commonly played in our society is primarily
economical and political: the non-disabled is the one who must contribute economically (paradigmatically, by working)
while our minimum obligations usually include only the non-disabled; that is, our obligations of accommodation to bodies
with disabilities are constructed as supererogatory. Thus, when bodies are excluded, the notion of disability serves to
Understanding the social construction of impairment this way has the advantage of not giving “far too much
significance to language and representation” (Tremain 2015, 10). What is socially constructed is not merely the way we
fix the extension of the term “impaired” among bodies, but the way we make distinctions among bodies. And making
distinctions, of course, is not something merely linguistic, but a social practice and, in the case of concepts like
impairment, a social practice with enormous significance on the experiences and identities of real human persons.
“Concepts, classifications, and descriptions are never “merely” words and representations that precede
what they come to represent, but rather are imbricated in (among other things) institutional practices, social
policy, intersubjective relations, and medical instruments in ways that structure, that is, limit, the field of
possible action for humans, including what possible self-perceptions, behavior, and habits are made
Thus, one can be a realist regarding both the impaired bodies as entities and the material facts behind our judgments of
impairment, while also recognising that impairment as a concept, that is, as a way of making a distinction among bodies, is
socially constructed and, therefore, not something given but something we should be responsible of.
In general, I gather that social-constructivism is a safer bet as an answer to the third question than it is as an
answer to the first two. After all, making distinctions is something we do and, as such, it is not surprising that many times
the reason why we make the distinctions we do has a lot to do with our social interactions. This would explain why people
30
can go as far as claiming that everything is socially constructed, without saying something absurd. What they mean is that
the way we parse the world is always dependent on the social context in which such parsing occurs.
31
Warning: the following post mentions racial slurs, and even though I am convinced such mentions are not offensive, they might
nevertheless be triggering to survivors.
Social categories associated to discrimination have recently become a fertile ground for (analytic) linguistic philosophical
reflection because they are strongly associated with the use of human predicates. If social constructionists are right (as
characterised in the previous two chapters), how we use social predicates is part of what the correspondign categories are.
Discrimination is something we do with words (but not only something we do with words).
One of the phenomena that a linguistic theory of slurs must account for is the fact that even though both the
following assertions are offensive unacceptable, they seem prima facie to be unacceptable in different senses:
This difference manifests in the fact that even though some people (who, presumably, hold certain negative
attitudes towards some other people, including Selena Quintanilla but not John Wayne) would find (1)
acceptable, no competent speaker would find (2) acceptable. The deep question, of course, is what does
“unacceptable” means here and what is the difference between these two cases.
Many philosophers have tried to explain this phenomena in terms of truth. So, we have two broad camps
regarding this issue: Elminativist take (1) and (2) to be both false, and try to explain the difference in terms of
32
something extra non-semantic (perhaps pragmatic, perhaps attitudinal) putting the offensive element of slurs
inside their semantic content. I call them “eliminativist” because they think slurs are empty terms; since slurs
encode in their semantic content conditions (including negative stereotypes) that are not satisfied by any object,
they are empty. Social constructivist accounts take (1) to be true and (2) false, so they try to explain slur’s
offensive element in terms of something extra non-semantic (perhaps pragmatic, perhaps attitudinal, cf.
Langton 2012, McGowan 2012, Saul forthcoming, etc.) putting the difference between (1) and (2) inside the
slur’s semantic content. I call these accounts “social constructivists”, because they take slurs to refer to socially
constructed kinds.
The same difference holds for other terms that are not slurs, like “cool”:
But, more interestingly, the same difference (or, at least, a very similar one) seems to hold also for racial terms
The difference manifests in the fact that even though most people would find (5) acceptable, almost no biologist
would find (6) acceptable. The reasons biologist (and some philosophers) reject (6) and (5) is because:
“Although the phenotypic characteristics, the manifest features that have traditionally been used to divide
our species into races, are salient for us, they are superficial, indicating nothing about important differences
in psychological traits or genetic conditions that constitute some racial essence.” (Kitcher 2007)
The argument goes something like this: Since the use of terms like “hispanic-american” “assumes an inner
essence, as in "blood", that was necessary and sufficient for membership of the original races, before any
33
interbreeding” (Papineau 2016), this assumption must be considered part of the conditions defining the
extension of the concept in such a way that if the assumption is false (as it seems to be, from a biological point of
view) then the extension is empty. In other words, it is an analytic truth that for someone to be hispanic-
american, there must be some hispanic-american blood in him or her; since there is no such thing as hispanic-
Once again, many philosophers have tried to explain this phenomena in terms of truth, and so we have
two broad camps regarding this issue: most realist naturalists advocate elminativist accounts of race and
therefore take (5) and (6) to be both false, trying to explain the difference in terms of something extra non-
semantic (perhaps pragmatic, perhaps attitudinal) putting the biological essentialist element of race terms
inside their semantic content (Appiah 1996, Zack 2002). I call them “eliminativist” because they think racial
terms are empty terms; since racial terms encode in their semantic content conditions (including biological
essentialism) that are not satisfied by any object, they are empty. Social constructivist accounts take (5) to be
true and (6) false, so they try to move the essentialist element out of the semantic content (for example, by
taking an externalist stance towards the semantics of racial kinds, like Haslinger 2008), putting the difference
between (5) and (6) inside the racial term’s semantic content (Omi and Winant 1994, Mills 1997, Haslanger
2000).
Notice that the same holds also for the terms “man” and “woman”, as I noticed after reading Nancy
Bauer (2015). Some people think that since the use of these terms presupposes false biologically essentialist
theses, they are empty, while others think that this presupposition is not part of the term’s semantic concept.
A usual analogy is also done with terms like “witch” and thus the debate turns into how better to
describe the situation regarding the witch hunts of the past (and unfortunately also of the present): Witches
were hunt and burnt (Atwood 1980) or women were accused of and tried for witchcraft?
34
A similar point can be made about astrology: is it better to say that none is actually an Aries since part of
what we commonly mean by “an Aries” is not just someone who was born on certain days, but also someone
whose character and-or fate is determined at least in part by his or her being born on those days? Or is it better
to say that some people are Aries, but that the widespread belief that Aries have common personality traits or
fates determine at least in part by their being Aries is superstitious and ultimately false? Does it make a
difference?
In all these cases, there is a rising consensus that the solution must depend on the practical
consequences of adopting one view or another. Is it better to just get rid of these terms and start anew with
better – more just and more accurate – concepts? Or is it better to keep them around but re-appropriate them
A few years ago I spent a month in Istanbul with a sociologist friend of mine who has been actively engaged with
the Kurdish situation in her country and one thing she always tried to make clear to me was of the Turkish efforts to erase
the Kurdish identity. For years, she told me, the Turkish government had been actively engaged in convincing their
citizens that there are no such things as Kurds, i.e., that Kurds are not a different ethnic group from Turks, with a different
culture or history, but a group of Turks that, at most, can be distinguished by their peasant roots and their coming from
certain region in Turkey. I know this to be true not only because of my friend telling me about this, but because of talking
to Turkish people and confirming that this was they way of conceiving of Kurds. The Kurd case, of course, is not
exceptional of ethnic minorities, even if it is an extreme case. One of the mechanisms that marginalize ethnic minorities is
the erasure of their ethnic identity. This is why ethnic minorities strongly reject the conclusion of elliminativist arguments.
In other words, that is why they strongly reject claims that there are no such things as African-Americans or Mexicans,
even if they are supported by reasons and developed in the pursuit of social justice
35
2. How talk of real tacos is like slurring
Current theories of slurs in philosophy of language aim to explain two phenomena: their offensiveness and their
extension, each associated with a contrast among these statements: to explain the slur’s offensiveness is to
explain the difference between (1) and (2), i.e., why (1) is offensive in a way (2) is not; explaining the slur’s
extension is to explain the difference between (1) and (3), i.e., why (1) is acceptable to some users (who,
presumably, hold some negative attitude towards people like Salma Hayek) in a way that (3) is not.
Even the offensiveness problem is certainly important, I will concentrate on the extensional issue
because it is the one that has stronger metaphysical bearings, in particular, with what I have previously called the
Quinean question. In general, we have two broad camps regarding this issue: Eliminativist accounts take (1) and
(3) to be both false, and try to explain the difference in terms of something extra non-semantic (perhaps
pragmatic, perhaps attitudinal) putting the offensive element of slurs inside their semantic content and,
consequently, as constitutive of the referred social kind. I call them “eliminativist” because they think slurs
(and, as previously stated, similar predicates) are empty terms; since slurs encode in their semantic content
conditions (including negative stereotypes) that are not satisfied by any object, they are empty. Social
constructivist accounts take (1) to be true and (3) false, so they try to explain slur’s offensive element in terms of
something extra non-semantic (perhaps pragmatic, perhaps attitudinal, cf. Langton 2012, McGowan 2012,
Saul forthcoming, etc.) putting the difference between (1) and (3) inside the slur’s semantic content. I call these
36
accounts “social constructivists”, because they usually take slurs to refer to socially constructed kinds as
In order to describe the phenomenon that both eliminativist and social-constructivist theories of
extension aim to explain let me introduce the (presumably theoretically neutral) notion of a slur’s “target”.
Someone (or some thing, event or action) is targeted by a slur if applying the slur to that person results in a
Thus expressed, the aim of both eliminativist and social constructivist theories is to explain the relation
between a slur’s target and its extension. Eliminativsts take slurs to have an empty extension (which partially
explain why sentences like (1) are unacceptable in a way that sentences like (2) are not) but not empty targets
(which partially explain why sentences like (3) are unacceptable in a way that sentences like (1) are not). Social
constructivists take a slur’s target and extension to be actually the same (which explains why sentences like (3)
are unacceptable in a way that sentences like (1) are not) while trying to explain the difference between
Social constructivists, thus, are monists regarding slurs’ semantic content, for they find no need to
introduce anything like a slur’s target; the usual notion of extension is enough. Elliminativists, in contrast, are
dualist and as such have the usual disadvantages of dualist theories, i.e., they have to explain why we have two
notions here instead of one, and most pressing, why the introduction of the new notion is not just naming the
One way theories of extension can and have tried to demonstrate the distinction’s explicative power is
by showing its relevance in accounting for other linguistic phenomena (properly different from slurs). This is
what I will attempt to do next: I will try to show a substantial link between the difference between a slur’s target
and its extension and a similar distinction that can be drawn when dealing with what Prasada and Knobe have
37
B. Dual-Concepts
Many predicates, like “chef”, “marriage”, “taco”, etc. accept adjectival modification by being preceded by the
word “good”. Thus, we can talk of “good music”, “good advice”, “good times”, etc. However, few of them accept
modification by both “true” (or “real”) and “good”. Thus, we can talk both of a “good man” and a “real man”,
“good rock” and “true rock”, “good friends” and “real friends”, etc. According to recent work by Joshua Knobe,
Sandeep Prasada and George E. Newman, the reason why we use the “real” modifier in these later cases is because
these predicates corresponds to what they call “dual-concepts”: an abstract and indeterminate notion associated to
a bunch of concrete criteria that we use as defeasible guides into its extension. For example, behind the predicate
“rock music”, there is an abstract notion that involves other abstract notions like rebelliousness, youthfulness, etc.,
and a series of concrete criteria like screaming vocals, electric guitars, driving beats, etc. The abstract notion
defines true rock music; even though we expect rock music to have screaming vocals, electric guitars, driving beats,
etc. and we expect music with screaming vocals, electric guitars, driving beats, etc. to be rock music, it need not be.
There is rock music (both good and true rock music) that has no screaming vocals, electric guitars, driving beats,
etc. and there is music with these concrete features that is not rock music.
Knobe, Prasada and Newman (2013) have hypothesised that concepts of this kind re all (at least partially)
normative. They hold that for something to be rock music, for example, it must embody certain values. To defend
this claim they have shown that (i) people classify some entities as falling under the normal extension of these
concepts without being truly in their extension. For example, people accept that some rock music is not truly rock
“The new song ‘Born to Rebel’ features screaming vocals and electric guitars. However, the song was
actually created by a marketing firm that was putting together an advertisement designed for elderly
people who are interested in imitating youth culture, and serious music fans al- ways say that it has no real
energy or feeling.”
38
Furthermore, they have also shown (ii) people classify some entities not falling under the normal extension of these
concepts as being truly in their extension. For example, people accept that some music one would normally not call
They have also shown that natural concepts do not show this behaviour. Nothing is a lion without being
truly a lion and vice versa. We might say of something that it seems to be a lion without truly being one, but not that
it actually is a lion, but not a true or real one. Similarly, we do not say of something that is not an actual lion that it is
truly a lion. Yet, we do say of people who are not actual men that they are truly men (Leslie forthcoming).
Of course, not all predicates that allow for both modifications fit Knobe et al’s model. We talk both of
“good stories” and “true stories”, but what we mean by “true story” is not a story that satisfies some abstract
criteria we use to define stories, but instead just a story that narrates events that actually happened. In other words,
we would not say of a story that is not a true story because even though there is a sense in which it is clearly a story,
ultimately, if you think about what it really means to be a story, you would have to say that it is not truly a story.
Thus, it is better to narrow the aim of dual character concepts not to concepts corresponding to predicates that
allow for both “true” and “good” modification, but to predicates that allow for “good” and “is truly a”
modification. Thus we exclude cases like “story” because even they there are “true stories”, we do not talk about
However, Knobe et. al. have no explanation for why only concepts that are defined in terms of normative
abstract values show this kind of behaviour. After all, it seems prima facie that any concept that is defined in
abstract and indeterminate terms, yet has determinate concrete objects in their extension could, at least in
principle, show similar behaviour. As I mentioned earlier, if abstract and indeterminate criteria are hard to detect in
determinate concrete objects, it makes sense that our cognitive apparatus use instead determinate and concrete
criteria as defeasible guides into its extension. The defeasible nature of this later criteria makes room for cases
where it would be helpful to talk of the objects that satisfy the abstract and indeterminate criteria of the concept but
not the determinate and concrete ones as truly falling under them. There is no reason why the former criteria need
39
to be normative. Yes, normative criteria tend to be abstract and indeterminate, thus making concepts with a
normative dimension more likely to show this sort of dual behaviour, but this need not be so. The challenge, thus,
would be to find other concepts of an abstract and indeterminate nature. However, Knobe et.al. have not found
them, and thus have concluded that all dual concepts are normative in nature.
For our current purposes the relevant issue surrounding these so-called dual character concepts can be
presented as part of giving a linguistic account of the behaviour of the adverb “real” in expressions like “real
woman”, “real rock and roll” or “real taco”. Sometimes, “real” is used in contrast with fictitious or unreal
entities, so for example, when we say that “Josie and the Pussycats is not a real band, but Elizabeth and the
Catapult is” what we say is true because Josie and the Pussycats is a fictitious band, while Elizabeth and the
Catapult is an actual band of real people based in Brooklyn, New York, USA. Other times, “real” is used in
contrast with apparent as when we say that “increasing oil extraction might seem like a good idea but is not a
real solution to our energy crisis”. However, there are other cases that seem to fit in neither of these categories.
Consider, for example, the sentence “Hard shell tacos are not real tacos.” Hard shell tacos are tacos (i.e., they
do not just seem to be tacos), they are real entities and yet, some people might reject that they are real tacos. It is
for this kind of cases, that some people find a similar distinction like the one between a slur’s target and its
extension. Compare the three sentences above with the following three sentences:
Generaliziang from Prasada and Knobe’s general points, I would say that even though some people (who,
presumably, hold certain negative attitudes towards hard shell tacos and/or a positive one towards tacos) would
find (4) acceptable, no competent speaker would find (6) acceptable. Thus, a good linguistic account of “real”
40
ought to explain two aspects of the adverb “real” as it occurs in cases like (4): its evaluative and extensional
aspects. The evaluative aspect of “real” manifests in the shared intuition that (4) seems to express a negative
attitude towards hard shell tacos absent from (5), which seems more neutral and descriptive. The extensional
aspect manifests in (4) being acceptable to some users (who, presumably, hold certain negative attitudes
towards hard shell tacos and/or a positive one towards tacos) in a way that (6) is not.
Once again, philosophers that have tried to explain this phenomena can be classified in two broad kinds
analogous to the ones we identified in the case of slurs: Elminativist accounts of “real”, take (4) and (5) to be
both true, and try to explain the difference in terms of something extra non-semantic (perhaps pragmatic,
perhaps attitudinal) putting the evaluative element of “real” outside its semantic content. I call them
“eliminativist” because they think the denotation of “real” is the null operator: real tacos are just tacos and tacos
are just real tacos, and thus the extension of “tacos, but not real tacos” is empty. Social constructivist accounts,
take (4) to be true and (6) false, so they incorporate the difference inside the semantic content of “tacos, but not
real tacos”. For them, not all tacos are real tacos. I call these accounts “social constructivists”, because they take
“real” to be a non-trivial operator that maps the properties corresponding to dual character concepts to socially
constructed kinds.
Again, it seems that driving a distinction between a predicate’s target and its extension might help
explain the issue under debate. Terms like “tacos, but not real tacos” have an extension and a target. Just like in
the case if slurs, eliminativist reject the distinction, while social constructivist endorse a dualist theory where
some entities, like hard shell tacos, are in the expressions’ target, but not its extension.
If this account of “real” is right, then eliminativists regarding slurs have a defense against the criticism
that the distinction they introduce between a slur’s target and its extension is ad-hoc and thus has no
Terms like “tacos, but not real tacos” have an extension (which may be empty or might include only
things like tacos de guisado or tacos mineros) and a target (that includes all sort of tacos, including hard shell
41
tacos). Just like in the case if slurs, eliminativist reject the distinction, while social constructivist endorse a
dualist theory where some entities, like hard shell tacos, are in the expressions’ target, but not its extension.
Now, we can make explicit the links between my semantic distinction between target and extension, and thus
the debate on the Quinean ontological question regarding habitable categories. In the previous section, I have
called attention to a straightforward relation between dual-concepts and slurs. If I am right, this means that slurs
express concepts that are structured just like dual concepts – they have a purely descriptive dimension and a
harder normative core, which usually differ extensionally –, except that while the usual examples Knobe et.al.
use for dual-concepts are positive (except, as they rightly mention, “pimp”), slurs are negative. Their external
descriptive dimension corresponds to what I call their target, while their normative core determines its actual
extension. Thus, just as expressions like “real taco”, “true woman”, “false metal”, etc. presuppose the relative
acceptance of certain normative values and stances regarding tacos, women and metal respectively, the use of
slurs also presuppose the acceptance of normative values and stances regarding their targets. So far, the analogy
is total. Thus, it would be correct to say that people who use, for example, the n slur possess a dual concept
whose external descriptive content identifies a group of people whose bodies are marked as targets for the slur,
and a normative core that embodies hateful and negative attitudes towards African Americans.
And just as the distinction at the heart of the notion of dual concepts can shed light on the semantics of
slurs, thus my distinction between a slur’s target and its extension can be useful to shed light on the structure of
dual concepts. Thus, we can speak of an expression like “real tacos” having a target and an extension, where the
target is made up of those objects that satisfy the dual concept’s external descriptive conditions, and the
extension is made up of those objects that embody its core normative values.
42
The paradox of stereotyping and disapproval
I. The paradox
I am interested in the intersection between two common phenomena that contribute to the
marginalisation of whole groups of people (because of their gender, race, class, etc.). Each one of
them by itself contributes to this sort of marginalisation, no doubt, but their interaction generates
new challenges to the understanding of the phenomenon of marginalisation. The first one is
stereotyping and the second one is disapproval. I call “stereotyping” the phenomenon of expecting
people belonging to a certain group to exhibit certain traits and not others, like expecting women to
behave in feminine ways, men to be masculine, native people to be spiritual and in touch with the
earth, good looking people to be dumb and shallow, etc. I call “disapproval” the phenomenon of
approving of or otherwise valuing, without justification, certain human traits while disapproving of
or devaluating others. When we value rationality over intuition or intelligence over strength, we
engage in this sort of devaluation. I will not say much about how each one of them contributes to the
marginalisation of groups of people, for I hope that to be clear enough: they restrict human
autonomy by pressuring us to behave in a certain socially sanctioned way. [More] “or less subtly
hostile, threatening, and punitive norm-enforcement mechanisms [are always] standing at the ready”
to punish those who deviate from social expectations”. (Manne 2019, 47)
The phenomenon that interests me is how their interaction generates a sort of paradox or
double bind, so that marginalised groups cannot win and escape the circle of marginalisation. As
43
Manuel Vargas has argued, “it is not uncommon for subordinated populations to face choices sets
where all the options are stigmatized” (manuscript), however I have found no previous literature
identifying this particular mechanism double binding marginalised groups. The paradox occurs when
the traits expected from a particular human group in a context are also the ones devaluated in that
same context. For example, when we expect Latin people to be passionate, but disapprove of
behaviour ruled by passion instead of reason; or when we expect women to be domestic while
devaluating domesticity, etc. I hope it is fairly straightforward to see how expecting from a group of
people traits that are devaluated contributes to the marginalisation of that group.
constitutive link between expectations and evaluations: expectations generate value and value
generate expectations. If we approve of a certain trait, we will expect people to behave that way and,
vice versa, if we expect people to behave a certain way, we approve and thus value when they actually
behave that way. This is so because we approve of people behaving the way they are expected to
behave and we expect people to behave the way we approve of. This seems to be tautologous.
Now it is easy to see how this generates a paradox where we expect people of certain groups
to behave a certain way (the way that fits the corresponding stereotype) but also to not behave that
way (because we disapprove of it). This means that, if you belong to any one of this groups, you
cannot escape disapproval: if your behaviour fits the stereotype, your behaviour is devaluated by
disapproval because the traits that conform the stereotype are devaluated in your context, but if your
behaviour challenges the stereotype, then it is devaluated precisely for not conforming to social
expectations.
44
This paradox is specially insidious in so far as it also generates a double negative bind within
commonly challenge stereotypes? By celebrating and promoting people who exhibit traits and
behaviours outside their stereotypes, like when we celebrate strong women, successful minorities,
caring men, family oriented gays, etc. In other words, we value in people of marginalised groups
traits that do not fit the stereotypes associated to those groups. However, since these traits that do
not fit the stereotypes are also the ones also traditionally valued, we in fact contribute to the
devaluation of the traits in the stereotype; in other words, we engage and reinforce what I have here
called “disapproval”. By challenging stereotypes, we reinforce the disapproval of the traits and
On the other hand, how do we challenge this disapproval? By celebrating and promoting
people who exhibit traits and behaviours unjustifiably disapproved of by society, like when we
celebrate sexual perversions, street-smarts, sensibility, effusive displays of emotion, etc. However,
when we celebrate this traits in people for whom those traits are part of their corresponding
stereotypes, we are de facto reinforcing those stereotypes. And therein lies the paradox: if we
celebrate people whose behaviour fits the stereotype we reinforce the stereotype and when we
celebrate people whose behaviour does not fit the stereotype, we reinforce the devaluation of the
traits associated with that very people. When we celebrate, for example, feminine traits in women, we
challenge the disapproval of feminine traits, but reinforce the stereotype that women ought to be
feminine; on the other hand, if we celebrate women who are not feminine and thus challenge the
45
stereotype, we reinforce the disapproval of feminine traits. If we celebrate the value that the hard
manual labor performed by immigrants adds to our society, we reinforce the stereotype of immigrant
as hardworking manual labourers; but if we celebrate immigrants who do not engage in hard
working manual labor, we reinforce the devaluation of hard manual labor. Either way, marginalised
In the previous section, I argued that when we expect people of certain groups to behave a certain
way (the way that fits our stereotype of the group they belong to) but also to not behave that way
(because we disapprove of such behaviour), we condemn people from these groups to unavoidable
disapproval: if their behaviour fits the stereotype, their behaviour is devaluated by disapproval
because the traits that conform the stereotype are devaluated, but if their behaviour challenges the
stereotype, then it is also disapproved of precisely for not conforming to social expectations.
One might respond to my diagnosis by arguing one of two things. First, that the paradox
emerges from an equivocation in the term “expectation”. Second, that there is a symmetry at the
heart of the paradox that would allow us to derive the opposite conclusion: that there is a positive
double bind such that whatever people from these marginalised groups do we cannot but get social
approval for our actions. I will address each one of them in turn.
First, one might argue that the kind of expectation at play in stereotypes is very different
from the kind of expectation we talk about when we say that values engender expectations (i.e., that
approving of a certain behaviour P from an agent a implies expecting such agent to behave as to P):
46
the one is descriptive (or predictive, if you will), while the other is prescriptive. And while it is is true
that expectations, in general, have no normative value, recent work by Knobe, Prasada and Newman
(2013) reveals that, when dealing with social concepts, our expectations do have a strong normative
dimension and, as S.J. Leslie has already noticed, this has direct consequences on the
marginalisation of social groups. Thus, what we expect from women, men, etc. is not only descriptive
of our very concept of men, women, etc. but has also a normative dimension about what makes
The second issue is harder to deal with, for it is true that the paradox could be run “in
reverse”: when we expect people of certain groups to behave a certain way (the way that fits the
corresponding stereotype) but also to not behave that way (because we disapprove of it) this could
mean both that if you belong to any one of this groups, you cannot escape disapproval and that if
you belong to any one of this groups, you cannot escape approval: if your behaviour fits the
stereotype, your behaviour is approved precisely for conforming to social expectations, but if your
behaviour challenges the stereotype, then it is approved of because the traits that conform the
stereotype are devaluated in your context. So it should be a win-win situation for members of these
groups. Yet, we know de facto that this is not so, so there must be a flaw in the previous reasoning.
However, even though I have thought deeply about this I cannot find a way out that is not ad-hoc
(for example, byarguing that disapproval tendencies are stronger than approval ones).
47
I hate to hear you talk about all women
A few years ago, Tasmanian artist Sonia Singh started recycling plastic dolls into what she called
“Tree Change Dolls”. In 2015, they became a sensation on news and social media with coverage on
media from different parts of the world. Repurposing and customising fashion dolls has been a very
48
extended practice and common hobby for years. However, Singh’s dolls touched a nerve because of
her choice, both of source material and end result. For her Tree Change Dolls, Singh favours Bratz
dolls, a brand of fashion dolls very popular in the early 2000s, notorious for their heavy made up
faces with big pouty lips and non-conservative outfits.6 She erases her features, draws new faces on
them, with no make up and smaller lips [See figure 1] and dresses them in plain clothes: knit
sweaters and loose pants. According to Singh, she tries to give them a “more down-to-earth, natural
looking style”.7 Most news coverage of the dolls presents them as a welcome reaction to what many
“…Sonia Singh who changes Bratz dolls in a way that they look like more real kids. … She
removes seductive and coquettish make-up on the faces of those dolls and repaints a new
and realistic faces. She also puts on non-sexualized clothes which are sewed or knit by her
mother. As can be seen in the picture below, the after dolls seem much more “natural”,
“innocent”, and non-sexualized, while the before one is hypersexaulised, too fancy and
coquettish.”
However, Didem Şalgam notices that this situation places women in a loose-loose situation. She
continues:
“I understand people’s discomfort with Bratz dolls. Like most fashion-type dolls, Barbie
being the most (in)famous of these, they present beauty ideals that are mostly unattainable:
impossibly large eyes, perfect makeup, thin bodies. … And certainly compulsory femininity
6. Another distinctive features are their big heads, small torsos, extremely long legs and big feet. Sonia
Singh also gives them new, more realistically proportional sized feet.
7. From the Vice Land documentary “Tree Change Dolls”, retrieved on January 1st, 2017 at https://
www.youtube.com/watch?v=lG-7e1vaB18.
8. Didem Şalgam: (2015), “The Roles of Toys in Gender and Sexual Identity Construction in Early
Childhood”, International Play and Toy Congress Proceedings, Publisher: Ataturk University, pp.434-441.
49
can be harmful, particularly (though not only) to gender non-conforming kids. But even
conceding all these points, I am left with a gnawing concern about the ways society at large,
In other words, if we celebrate Bratz dolls, we collaborate with the oppression of women by
strengthening the prevailing stereotype and feminine ideal for women, but if we oppose them, if we
literally erase these feminine features from their faces and bodies – as happens in the Tree Change
Dolls case – we perform also a rejection of actual features of the actual faces and bodies of actual
Feminity thus becomes a double-edged sword in the feminist struggle. On the one hand, as
Whitney Chadwick has insisted, the few artists that have been celebrated within the canon of
Western Art have been those who have embodied masculine ideals of art-making, “categories
defined by traditional notions of male genius” (Chadwick 1996, 10), becoming ‘exceptions’ that
9. This example is specially pressing because it laso deals with intersectionality. As Şalgam herself points
out: “You see, Bratz dolls are stylized as “urban” — that is, in the style of Black and Latina women in
segregated and low-income neighborhoods across the United States. Bratz dolls have four characters, one
of which is white, and all of whom wear the same “trashy” style. And it makes me uncomfortable to see
mainstream feminism praise the removal of characteristically Black and Latinx style markers from these
mostly brown dolls and call them then more beautiful…” In this respect, The Change Dolls are another
example of the “endless pop culture and political debates that are easier to talk about if we remember that
people have multiple, intersecting identities that color their experiences and our reactions to them.” (Jenée
Desmond-Harris, “Washington, you need to understand intersectional feminism: It’s much bigger than
‘check your privilege’.” Voxmedia.com. Jan 21, 2017, retrieved on february 14th, 2017) In particular, it ignores
that some people are both women and urban and American and Latinas, for example, an as such their
relation to Bratz dolls is substantially different from a white Tasmanian woman such as Sonia Singh.
50
reinforce the very hermeneutic practices that exclude women from the art canon. It is also not rare
for artists who celebrate traditionally feminine images and traits (both in nature and culture) in
order to challenge the devaluation of such images and traits to be accused of reinforcing a feminine
stereotype that has been traditionally oppressive to women. On February 2017, for example,
American singer Beyoncé Knowles performed live during an important American awards show,
noticeably pregnant, a medley of recent songs of hers that, in the words of Olivia Blair, “honed in on
the themes of motherhood, family and feminism”,10 while dressed in a golden suit that evoked
It was clear for many interpreters of her performance that hers was a celebration of feminity
with a feminist intension. Nevertheless, her performance was also criticized, from within feminism
10. Olivia Blair: “Grammys 2017: Watch Beyoncé's showstopping performance in full: The night belonged to
one woman”, The Independent, online edition,Tuesday 14 February 2017. Retrieved on Tuesday 14 February
2017 at http://www.independent.co.uk/arts-entertainment/music/grammy-awards-2017-beyonce-lemonade-
video-full-performance-a7577121.html
51
itself, precisely because of her celebration of traditional images of feminity. An anonymous comment
on a social network that circulated widely afterwards serves as a good example of such a reaction. It
claimed that her performance “absolutely erases trans bodies and queer bodies bc she’s limiting
gender definitions to specific performances and she’s narrowing the space by which gender can be
defined.”11
photographs, in collaboration with fashion designer Christy Dawn, and actress Diana García, titled
“femininity”. In an interview with fashion magazine, L’Officiel, she claimed that her aim was to
Once again, criticisms from within feminism itself were fast to surface. Mexican philosopher Ana
Piquer, for example, posted on her facebook page a message expressing her “disgust” at how “softness,
containment, and beauty remain the stereotypical traits for talking about femeninity” and about how
this sort of discourse “reproduce and perpetuate [traditional] gender roles, from within patricarchial
All of these examples are structurally analogous and serve as clear examples of the paradox I
have presented here. In both of them, we see two ways of trying to challenge the way stereotypes
contribute to the marginalisation of a group of people pitted against each other. Those who choose
to celebrate the stereotypical features of the group in question are criticised for strengthening the
stereotype, while those who choose to challenge the stereotype are criticised for their contributing to
the already widespread disapproval of features associated with the group in question. The paradox
lies in that both camps are well intentioned and challenge an actually important factor in the
disenfranchisement of the relevant group, while at the same time the charges brought against their
actions are also both well intentioned and justified. In this case, the group is women and the
12. “…en realidad no somos lo mismo. La feminidad es la energía creativa, la energía de belleza, de contención, de armonía
y de sensualidad.. La feminidad y nuestro mensaje es de armonía suavidad y belleza. Buscamos comunicar la aceptación y
de abrazarnos como mujeres, de resaltar las cualidades de la energía femenina.”
53
stereotype is femininity, but the same pattern repeats itself for other disempowered groups. Writing
“It is understandable, to a certain extent, that gay men would seek to challenge the stereotype
that they are feminine or “sissies” by masculinizing their bodies through diet and exercise. This
challenge, however, ultimately has toxic effects by reinforcing gender norms as opposed to
subverting them…While adhering to masculine norms may temporarily mitigate the effects of
oppression, conformity does little to dismantle the systems which cause it.” (Iovannone 2018)
Eugenio Derbez
In order to illustrate how this paradox is not privative to gender, consider the case of Mexican actor,
writer and producer Eugenio Derbez. After a long successful career as a comedian in Mexico, he
moved to Hollywood at 51 and eventually became successful enough to develop his own
productions. He used his privileged position in Hollywood to try to change how Mexicans are
portrayed in mainstream American cinema. In a 2018 interview, he stated, “Whenever you see a
Latino in Hollywood, he is a drug dealer, a criminal, a gang member or, at best, a gardener. I wanted
to change that image”13. A chance to put such intentions into action came in 2018 when he
developed a re-make of Garry Marshall’s 1987 comedy Overboard. The lighthearted class-war
13. “Siempre que ves un latino en Hollywood es un narcotraficante, un criminal, un pandillero o, en el mejor de los casos,
wealthy boss that he is her working-class husband, after he loses his memory in a boating accident.
For the remake, Derbez thought it would be a good idea to challenge stereotypes by having the
spoiled rich man be a brown Mexican – played by Derbez himself – and for the poor, abused working
class cleaning woman to be white and American – played by Anna Faris. In other interviews, he
stated:
When MGM approached me to talk about the movie, they were thinking of me to play
the carpenter, Kurt Russell’s character. Flipping the roles was the smart thing to do
That change was very good, because we broke stereotypes, since the logical thing
would have been for the Latino to be the carpenter and for the millionaire to be a
are always the poor, the jodidos [those screwed over by poverty], and the idea here was
to present both the universe of someone like [Mexican Billionaire] Carlos Slim and
Derbez’s idea was to challenge the stereotypes non-Mexican Americans have of Mexicans as working
class and instead present “the universe of” rich Mexicans and thus challenge such stereotype.
Unfortunately, there was backlash from people who thought that by placing a rich Mexican as
protagonist, Derbez was ignoring the reality of those Mexicans who suffer the most from
14. “Gringa” is a Mexican slur targeting Americans, very socially accepted in Mexico.
15. “Ese cambio fue muy bueno, porque rompimos con los estereotipos, ya que lo lógico hubiera sido que el latino fuera el
carpintero y la gringa la millonaria… Quisimos mostrar a un tipo distinto de mexicano, porque en Hollywood, siempre
somos los pobres, los jod…, y la idea por aquí es que apareciera tanto el universo de alguien como Carlos Slim como el de
los trabajadores de construcción que son representados por Adrián Uribe, Jesús Ochoa y Omar Chaparro”
55
discrimination in the United States, i.e., immigrant workers. The few that appear in the film, argued
Flores (2018), serve “como mero adorno” [as mere ornament]. In consequence
Eugenio Derbez is not committed to the culture that has inspired him, which
has given him "fame" and which he still exploits. (Flores 2018)16
Once again, we see the same paradox here. Challenging the stereotype of Mexicans as working class
results in the unintended reinforcement of the very class system that oppresses the target of such
stereotypes, i.e., Mexicans in the United States of America. Once again, one faces a loose loose
situation in which both options – to challenge the stereotype or to re-valuate the features included
in the stereotype reinforce the very apparatus of oppression in which heart the stereotype lays.
16. "Eugenio Derbez no está comprometido con la cultura que lo ha inspirado, que lo ha llevado a la "fama" y de la que se
sirve todavía”
56
REFERENCES
Abrams, Kathry (1995) “Sex Wars Redux: Agency and Coercion in Feminist Legal Theory”, Columbia Law Review 95:
304–376.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony (2018) The Lies that Bind: Rethinking Identity: Creed, Country, Color, Class, Culture, Liveright
Publishing.
Báez-Jorge, Félix (2002) “Los indios, los nacos, los otros… (apuntes sobre el prejuicio racial y la discriminación en
México)”, La Palabra y el Hombre 121: 21-40.
Bauer, Nancy (2015) How to Do Things with Pornography, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Baumeister, Roy F. and Mark Muraven (1996) “Identity as adaptation to social, cultural, and historical context” Journal
of Adolescence 19, 405–416
Bennett, Tony; Mike Savage; Elizabeth Silva; Alan Warde; Modesto Gayo-Cal and David Wright (2009) Culture, Class,
Distinction, Routledge.
Bettcher, Talia Mae (2018) “When Tables Speak”: On the Existence of Trans Philosophy, Daily Nous, guest post, posted
on May 30, 2018 at 8:28 am. URL=<http://dailynous.com/2018/05/30/tables-speak-existence-trans-
philosophy-guest-talia-mae-bettcher/> Retrieved on May 30, 2018.
Born, Georgina and David Hesmondhalgh (2000) Introduction to Western Music and Its Others: Difference,
Representation, and Appropriation in Music, University of California Press.
Bourdieu P. (1979) Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgment of Taste. Transl. R Nice, 1984. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Bourgois, Philippe (1995) In search of respect: selling crack in El Barrio, Cambridge University Press.
Bryson, Bethany (1996) “Anything But Heavy Metal": Symbolic Exclusion and Musical Dislikes”, American Sociological
Review Vol. 61, No. 5 (Oct., 1996), pp. 884-899
Burgess, John A. (1998) “Error theories and values”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76:4, 534-552
Bürki, Yvette (2014) “Prácticas discursivas y estereotipos: La figura del naco en la sociedad mexicana actual” in Marco
Kunz, Cristina Mondragón and Dolores Phillips-López (eds.) Nuevas Narrativas Mexicanas II, Linkgua:
399-427.
Burt, Stephanie (2012) “My Life as a Girl”, The Virginia Quarterly Review, 88(4).
Cappelan, Herman (2018) Fixing Language: An Essay on Conceptual Engineering, Oxford University Press.
Casey, C., (1995) Work, Self and Society: After Industrialism, Routledge, London.
Chadwick, Whitney (2006) Women, Art and Society, second edition, revised and expanded, London: Thames and
Hudson.
Chauncey, George (2008) New York: Gender, Urban Culture, and the Making of the Gay Male World, 1890-1940,
Hachette
57
Convery, Alison (2011) Feminist Theory and Discursive Intersections: Activating the Code of ‘Political Correctness’ A
thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy of the University of Newcastle.
Daly, C. & Liggins, D. (2010) “In defence of error theory”, Philosophical Studies 149: 209–230
Delanty, Gerard & Piet Strydom (eds.) (2003) Philosophies of Social Science: The Classic and Contemporary Readings,
Open University
Demolombe R., Louis V. (2006) “Norms, Institutional Power and Roles: Towards a Logical Framework”. In: Esposito F.,
Raś Z.W., Malerba D., Semeraro G. (eds) Foundations of Intelligent Systems. ISMIS 2006. Lecture Notes
in Computer Science, vol 4203. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg
DeVere Brody, Jennifer (1992) Clare Kendry's "True" Colors: Race and Class Conflict in Nella Larsen's Passing,
Callaloo 15 (4): 1053-1065.
Epstein, Brian (2010) “History and the Critique of Social Concepts”, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 40, No. 1, 3-29.
Flores, Luis Enrique (2018) “"Hombre al agua", la amnesia del compromiso social”, Mexico Nueva Era 14-05-2018.
URL=<https://mexiconuevaera.com/espectaculos/cine/2018/05/14/hombre-al-agua-la-amnesia-del-
compromiso-social> Retrieved January 27, 2019
Fusco, Coco (2019) “Sex, Art & Misoginy”, The New York Review of Books, 66 (8):35-37.
G, Made & J. R. Zuckerberg (2019) A Quick & Easy Guide to Queer & Trans Identities, Limerence Press.
Gilbert, Elizabeth (2009) Committed: A Sceptic Makes Peace With Marriage, AC Black.
Guerrero MacManus, Siobhan F. (2018) “Naturalezas, culturas y arquitecturas disciplinarias. La infrapolítica de un
debate (necesariamente) interminable”, Metatheoria 8(2): 77-85.
Hernández, Xaime (1994) Wig Wam Bam, Seattle: Fantagraphics.
Hom, Christopher (2008), “The Semantics of Racial Epithets”, Journal of Philosophy 105 (8):416-440
Institute of Medicine (US) Committee on Understanding the Biology of Sex and Gender Differences (2001) Exploring the
Biological Contributions to Human Health: Does Sex Matter? Wizemann TM, Pardue ML, editors.
Washington DC: National Academies Press.
Jardina, Ashley (2019) White Identity Politics, Cambridge University Press.
Iovannone, Jeffrey J. (2018) “We Need To Talk About Toxic Gay Masculinity”, The Establishment. https://
medium.com/the-establishment/we-need-to-talk-about-toxic-gay-masculinity-70dbcd13e775 Retrieved
on January 10, 2019.
Jenkins, Katherine (2016), “Amelioration and Inclusion: Gender Identity and the Concept of Woman*”, Ethics 126:
394–421
Jeshion, Robin (2013) “Slurs and Stereotypes”, Analytic Philosophy 54 (3):314-329
Judt, Tony with Timothy Snyder (2012) Thinking the Twentieth Century, Penguin.
58
Khalidi, Muhammad Ali (2013) Natural Categories and Human Kinds: Classification in the Natural and Social Sciences,
Cambridge University Press
Knobe J., Prasada S., Newman G.E. (2013) “Dual character concepts and the normative dimension of conceptual
representation”, Cognition. 127(2): 242-57.
Knorr Cetina, Karin (1993) “Strong Constructivism - from a Sociologist's Point of View: A Personal Addendum to
Sismondo's Paper”, Social Studies of Science Vol. 23, No. 3 (Aug., 1993), pp. 555-563
Lamont, Michèle and Virág Molnár (2002) “The Study of Boundaries in the Social Sciences”, Annual Review of
Sociology, Vol. 28, pp. 167-195.
Langton, Rae; Sally Haslanger y Luvell Anderson (2012) “Language and Race”, Routledge Companion to the Philosophy
of Language, eds. Gillian Russell and Delia Graff Fara (Routledge University Press), 753-67
Lecuona, Laura (2018) “El género y su tiro por la culata” Revista de la Universidad de México 840: 53–60.
Lecuona, Laura (2016) Las mujeres son seres humanos, colección Caja Chica, Dirección General de Publicaciones de la
Secretaría de Cultura.
Leslie, Sarah-Jane Leslie (2015), “Hillary Clinton is the Only Man in the Obama Administration”: Dual Character
Concepts, Generics, and Gender”, Analytic Philosophy, Volume 56, Issue 2, Pages 111–141
Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Long Chu, Andrea (2017) “On Liking Women.” n+1 30 (December 2017): 47–62.
López Beltrán, Carlos, Peter Wade, Eduardo Restrepo y Ricardo Ventura Santos (2017) Genómica Mestiza : Raza,
nación y ciencia en Latinoamérica, Fondo de Cultura Económica.
López Beltrán, Carlos (2004) El sesgo hereditario: ámbitos históricos del concepto de herencia biológica, UNAM.
Lycan, William (2015) “Slurs and lexical presumption”, Language Sciences 52. Pp. 3-11.
Manne, Kate (2019) Down Girl: The Logic of Misogyny, New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Mikkola, Mari (2016) The Wrong of Injustice: Dehumanization and Its Role in Feminist Philosophy, Oxford University
Pressmeth
Navarro, Bernabé (1982) “Reflexiones sobre lo mexicano” Theoria 3: 12-13.
Nunberg, Geoff, (2017) “The Social Life of Slurs”, en Daniel Fogal, Daniel Harris, y Matt Moss (eds.) (2017): New
Work on Speech Acts (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press).
Nussbaum, Martha, (1992) Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentialism. Political
Theory, Vol. 20, No. 2 (May, 1992), pp. 202-246
Rudder, Christian (2014) Dataclysm: Who We are (When We Think No One's Looking). Crown Publishing Group, New
York, NY, USA.
Sarr, Felwine (2016) Afrotopia. Philippe Rey.
59
Sennet, Adam & David Copp (2014), "What kind of a mistake is it to use a slur?", Philosophical Studies
Stock, Kathleen, (2018) “Academic philosophy and the UK Gender Recognition Act”, Medium, May 7. https://
medium.com/@kathleenstock/academic-philosophy-and-the-uk-gender-recognition-act-6179b315b9dd
Retrieved on May 7, 2018.
Thompson, E.P., (1966) The Making of the English Working Class, Vintage Books, New York.
Tremain, Shelley L. (2017) Foucault and Feminist Philosophy of Disability, University of Michigan Press.
Vargas, Manuel (manuscript) If Aristotle had Cooked
Vehmas, Simo, and Watson, Nick (2014) “Moral wrongs, disadvantages, and disability: a critique of critical disability
studies”. Disability and Society, 29 (4). pp. 638-650
Vincent, C. and SJ.. Ball (2007) `Making Up' the Middle-Class Child: Families, Activities and Class Dispositions,
Sociology 41(6): 1061-1077
(2006) Childcare, Choice and Class Practices: Middle-Class Parents and their Children. London,
Routledge.
Vincent, C., S.J. Ball and S. Kemp (2004) ‘The Social Geography of Childcare: Making Up a Middle-Class Child’, British
Journal of Sociology of Education 25(2): 229–44.
Weinstein, Deena (2000) Heavy Metal: The Music and its Culture, New York: Da Capo Press.
Yap, Audrey (2018) commentary posted on May 17, 2018 at 4:41 PM on Anne J. Jacobson’s post “TERFs turf” at the
blog Feminist Philosophers, retrieved on May 26, 2018. URL=“https://
feministphilosophers.wordpress.com/2018/05/16/terfs-turf/#comment-163737”
Zack, Naomi (2002) Philosophy of science and race, New York: Routledge.
60