Philosophy of Biology: Ingo Brigandt

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 33

Draft of a contribution to The Continuum Companion to the Philosophy of Science, edited by

Steven French and Juha Saatsi. Continuum Press, London.

Philosophy of Biology

Ingo Brigandt

Philosophical questions about biology have been addressed by philosophers and scientists for

centuries. Yet as a genuine discipline within philosophy, philosophy of biology started to emerge

in the 1970s (Byron, 2007). One motivation for this was the fact that much of traditional

philosophy of science—growing out of logical positivism—focused on physics as the exemplar

of science. Thereby past philosophy of science simply assumed that accounts of confirmation,

theory structure, laws, and explanation would apply to biology as well, creating biased or

inadequate views about the nature of science. But rather than directly addressing issues in

general philosophy of science in the context of biology, philosophers of biology have for the

most part engaged in questions that originate from within biology, pertaining to concepts from a

specific biological field or to phenomena from a particular biological domain. Some of these

questions have been raised by biologists, resulting in debate and fruitful interaction among

scientists and philosophers. This interdisciplinary practice of contemporary philosophy of

biology is illustrated by the International Society for the History, Philosophy, and the Social

Studies of Biology, and by philosophical journals to which many scientists contribute. Most

questions in philosophy of biology are epistemological questions, e.g., about the character of

particular biological explanations, models, and concepts, and are sometimes combined with

issues about scientific method and practice. Yet these issues also tap into metaphysical

considerations, at least insofar as they hinge on facts about the biological world.

Originally, most discussions in philosophy of biology centred on issues in evolutionary

biology and systematics. For instance, the units of selection debate ponders which kind of entity
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 2

is the fundamental player driving evolutionary change—the individual, the group of individuals,

the gene, or even the species. Arising out of disputes among evolutionary biologists, the

epistemological question is how genuine explanations in terms of natural selection actually work.

The related metaphysical issue is at what level of biological organization evolutionary causation

by selection takes place, and philosophers have offered several clarifications to these biological

questions. Given the many statistical models of evolutionary theory, philosophical interpretations

of the nature and role of probabilistic factors (e.g. genetic drift) are put forward. The

adaptationism debate concerns the circumstances in which phenotypic traits of species are best

explained with exclusive reference to natural selection. In this context, attempts by

sociobiologists and evolutionary psychologists at explaining the evolution of human behavioural

and cognitive traits have been criticized by philosophers as falling short of the standards for

acceptable evolutionary explanations. Philosophical studies of the meaning of ‘biological

function’ discuss what the ascription of functions to biological traits involves (occasionally, but

not always a reference to a trait’s selection history), and whether functional and teleological

explanations are distinct from causal explanations.

In addition to the traditional philosophical questions pertaining to evolution (which are still

live issues), nowadays molecular and experimental biology are of increasing philosophical focus.

This philosophical trend is largely due to the rise of genetics and molecular biology, with such

biological advances prompting the philosophical debate as to whether classical genetics and

possibly other biological disciplines can be reduced to molecular biology. It has also been argued

that the notion of ‘genetic information’ is empirically misguided or of no explanatory relevance

in biology. Apart from the role of genes and non-genetic factors in explanations of the

development of organismal traits, developmental biology has recently become a biological field

subject to philosophical interest, as a link to evolutionary issues has been created by the recent
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 3

emergence of evolutionary developmental biology. With the scientific advance and societal

importance of the life sciences and modern biomedical sciences, contemporary philosophers of

biology also address issues in philosophy of medicine. Whereas views about the biological world

have traditionally been based on higher animals (and plants), very recent scientific findings about

microorganisms (largely driven by their now recognized medical relevance) may soon lead to

challenges for philosophical views of biological individuality, social organization, the notion of

species, and the idea of a universal tree of life.

It is beyond the scope of any single article to provide a review of the major issues and

positions in philosophy of biology (for overviews see Hull, 1974; Sober, 1993; Griffiths and

Sterelny, 1999; Hull and Ruse, 2007). Instead, the aim of this chapter is to lay out what

implications biology has for some issues in general philosophy of science, including natural

kinds, conceptual change, discovery and confirmation, explanation and reduction, and

naturalism. Some of these offer additions and corrections to general metaphysical, semantic and

epistemological views, and illustrate fruitful ways of conducting philosophical investigations that

go beyond the practice of most of general philosophy (as the section on ‘Naturalism’ discusses).

Natural kinds

A few decades ago, the notion of natural kinds gained prominence in philosophy, in particular in

the context of the causal theory of reference (Putnam, 1975) and rigid designation across

possible world (Kripke, 1980). Ever since, it has enjoyed widespread acceptance, particularly in

metaphysics. However, while philosophers not acquainted with the philosophy of biology still

take species and higher taxa (e.g. vertebrates) to be a prime example of natural kinds, in the

1970s the biologist Michael Ghiselin (1974) and the philosopher David Hull (1978) argued that
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 4

species are not natural kinds. Instead, a particular species is an individual, a whole having the

organisms of that species as its parts. This position has been extremely influential among

biologists and philosophers of biology. Recently, following Richard Boyd (1999), some

philosophers have put forward a revised notion of natural kinds that is claimed to apply to

species. As a result, in contemporary philosophy of biology there are diverging views about

which of the various biological things are natural kinds, what notion of ‘natural kind’ is

appropriate for biological kinds, and how biological kinds relate to kinds studied by other

sciences.

Whereas in a nominal kind several objects are grouped together by mere human convention,

the idea of a natural kind is that there are groupings of objects that conform to the objective

structure of the world (Bird and Tobin, 2009). The traditional notion of natural kinds was closely

tied to kinds in physics and chemistry. It assumes that a kind is defined by a property called an

‘essence’, which has two functions. First, the essence determines the metaphysical identity of the

kind. An object belongs to the kind if and only if the object possesses the essence. Second, the

essence causally brings about the various properties characteristic of that kind, grounding the

explanatory importance of natural kinds. For instance, the essence of oxygen is its atomic

structure (including having eight protons and electrons). This atomic structure explains various

physical and chemical properties of oxygen, in particular which compounds it can form and how

it behaves in chemical reactions. Typically, essences have been taken to be intrinsic (internal)

properties, as the example of chemical elements illustrates.

But it is easy to see that on this construal species cannot be natural kinds. For species are

able to undergo unlimited evolutionary change. Whatever intrinsic property of an organism one

chooses, be it a particular phenotypic feature or a genetic property, while many organisms

existing at a point in time may share this internal property, future members of this species may
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 5

not. Likewise, applying the traditional view of natural kinds to species does not do justice to

biological variation. While acknowledging differences among species members, the so-called

essentialism still assumes that there is a natural biological state of the species governing all its

members (Sober, 1980). The deviation of individuals from this alleged natural state is seen as

being due to unusual intervening factors (e.g. environmental influences), so that the natural state

(species essence) is seen as real, and any variation is explained away as an accident. The

empirically adequate picture, in contrast, is that variation across individuals is maintained and

created by biological mechanisms and is a feature of major scientific importance.

Arguing that species are not natural kinds, Ghiselin (1974) and Hull (1978) suggested that

every species is an individual. Just like an organism is composed of cells, a species is an

individual made up of organisms. A species does not have members as a set, class or kind does;

instead, a species is a whole that has various organisms as its mereological parts. The motivation

for this position is that an individual is precisely the metaphysical thing that is able to undergo

change. An individual exists in a certain period of time only, being present at specific spatial

locations at any point in time. An individual can substantially change across time; and similarity

among its mereological parts is not required of an individual, in contrast to the view that the

members of natural kinds are identical in many properties. In analogy to this, a species comes

into being at a specific point in time, inhabits concrete locations, undergoes evolutionary

modification, and goes extinct.

The view that species are individuals became the dominant view among philosophers of

biology and in particular biologists (Ereshefsky, 2007). But recently Richard Boyd (1999)

developed a revised notion of natural kinds that is designed to capture kinds as found in biology

and the social sciences; and several philosophers and handful of biologists have picked up on it

(Wilson et al., in press; Rieppel, 2008). On this approach, a natural kind is a so-called
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 6

homeostatic property cluster (HPC). First, the major assumption is that a natural kind is not

defined by a simple property that all kind members share (an essence). Instead, a kind is

characterized by a cluster of many properties that are more or less correlated, where a kind

member need not possess all of these properties, and none of the properties is shared by all kind

members. In fact, exhibiting a certain kind of variation can be characteristic for being a certain

biological kind, and such a correlation and variation structure is in need of explanation (Wilson

et al., in press). The correlation of properties is not accidental, but due to some causal features

(dubbed ‘homeostatic mechanisms’). For this reason, the grouping of the members into a kind

answers to features existing in nature, so it is a natural rather than a nominal kind. The statistical

correlations or causal relations among the properties of the cluster make it possible for the kind

to figure in scientific induction and explanation.

Second, the HPC construal of kinds explicitly maintains that properties of the cluster

characterizing a natural kind need not be intrinsic, but may well be relational properties. For

instance, a higher taxon (e.g. mammals) includes those species that are descended from a

founding species, and having a certain ancestry is an extrinsic property of a species. Several

species can share this relational property of having the same ancestry while differing in various

(intrinsic) properties. Apart from common ancestry, the identity of a species may be defined by

the ability of individuals to interbreed, which is also a relational property (of an individual)

consistent with evolutionary change. As a result, historical entities such as species and higher

taxa can be natural kinds, assuming that the identity of the latter is at least partially characterized

by relational properties (Griffiths, 1999).

These developments in philosophy of biology have several implications for theorizing about

natural kinds in general. First, accounts that species are individuals pointed to serious drawbacks

of traditional, essentialist conceptions of natural kinds, and have offered a whole new way of
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 7

thinking about biological entities. In addition, the HPC construal of kinds developed a revised

and novel notion of natural kinds, motivated by a naturalism according to which philosophical

notions should be tied to scientific practice, in this case kinds as they occur in biology. While the

individuals vs. kinds debate focused on species and higher taxa, the HPC approach has

broadened this scope by considering and attempting to capture many other putative biological

kinds. In fact, Boyd developed the HPC account to likewise include kinds from the social

sciences. Kinds are studied by different scientific disciplines, and there may well be different

types of natural kinds, a diversity to which philosophical theories should be sensitive. It has also

been suggested that some things (e.g. species) can at the same time be an individual and a natural

kind (Dupré, 1999; LaPorte, 2004; Brigandt, 2009), offering new metaphysical possibilities and

pointing to problematic philosophical dichotomies.

Second, the HPC approach has highlighted the relevance of relational properties. Samir

Okasha (2002) acknowledges that relational properties often individuate biological kinds

(individuation being one function of traditional essences), but he claims that relational properties

do not support biological explanations (in contrast to the second function of traditional essences).

However, relational properties are in fact an important ingredient in explanations in biology and

the social sciences (Brigandt, 2009). Equations in ecology and economics explain dynamic

change based on the existence of stable relations among some entities. More generally, while the

causal capacities of biological entities (including molecular entities such as genes) are partially

based on their internal structure, these causal capacities obtain only in certain biological contexts

or given a suitable relation with other biological entities. Many causal capacities being non-

intrinsic properties, biological explanations have to appeal to relational properties as well.

(Biologists arguing against some versions of reductionism have always emphasized the
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 8

explanatory relevance of the structured contexts in which some entities occur [Brigandt and

Love, 2008].)

Finally, while proponents of the view that species are individuals have defended it by

metaphysical arguments (Hull, 1978; Ereshefsky, 2007), the HPC approach highlights

epistemological considerations. For a natural kind is a grouping of objects that—despite the

heterogeneity among the members of a biological kind—underwrites scientific generalization

and explanation (thereby ‘accommodating’ scientific demands, as put by Boyd, 1999). More

generally, any kind of representation scheme used by scientists (be it grouping objects into kinds,

be it considering objects as part of an enduring individual) is used to meet certain epistemic

purposes such as making particular inductive inferences or putting forward certain explanations.

Philosophical accounts of the metaphysical nature of scientific entities have to pay attention to

the epistemological reasons that make scientists refer to these (rather than other) entities and use

them successfully in their theorizing by representing them in a certain way (Brigandt, 2009;

Love, 2009). Different representations and classifications are used in different scientific contexts,

resulting in the philosophically relevant fact that the totality of kind concepts and classification

schemes used by biologists cross-classify nature (Dupré, 1993).

Conceptual change

Recent philosophical accounts of conceptual change have often been developed as a reply to the

incommensurability challenge. Thomas Kuhn (1962) argued that the same term can be used with

radically different (incommensurable) meanings in two paradigms (different theoretical

frameworks), so that effective communication across paradigms and a rational choice of one

such theory over the other is impossible. Paul Feyerabend (1970) claimed that the content of two
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 9

theories containing incommensurable concepts cannot be compared. The standard reply to the

incommensurability challenge has been to focus on the reference of scientific terms (Putnam,

1975; Fine, 1975; Devitt, 1979). For even if a term is used with different meanings in two

theories, the term may nonetheless refer to the same entity across these theories, so that the

theories can potentially make conflicting claims about this common referent and are thus

comparable. The causal theory of reference provided an explanation of how stable reference

despite substantially different theoretical views about the referent is possible (Sankey, 1994).

According to this theory, a term’s reference is not fixed by (potentially false) descriptions of the

referent, but a term is introduced by causal interaction with the referent and refers to that natural

kind thusly picked out (so that the structure of the world plays a part in reference determination).

Some cases from the philosophy of biology offer a broader the perspective for general

discussions of conceptual change. With the advent of evolutionary theory, biological views about

the nature of species clearly changed. However, given that Darwin could communicate his

arguments to his contemporaries, philosophers have questioned whether the pre-evolutionary and

the Darwinian conception of species are incommensurable concepts and whether they are even

different concepts at all (Beatty, 1986). Thus, the question is how these two conceptions of

species are related, whether they are distinct concepts, and in either case how to make room for

some conceptual continuity despite theoretical change. Moreover, nowadays different species

definitions are used by biologists (Mayden, 1997 lists 22 major definitions), and philosophers

typically assume that many of them are indeed distinct concepts. One species concept considers

those organisms that can interbreed with each other to be of the same species. Other species

concepts focus on considerations of common ancestry and phylogenetic lineages, and still other

use ecological criteria to delineate species. Not only do these concepts offer different criteria of

what a species is, but they also lead to different classifications of individuals into species, so that
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 10

these concepts differ in their extensions / reference. Most philosophers and biologists endorse a

pluralism about species concepts, i.e., the idea that there is not one single true species concepts

(yet to be found or agreed upon), but that biology needs a multitude of different species concepts

(Dupré, 1999; Ereshefsky, 1992; Kitcher, 1984b; Wheeler and Meier, 2000). The justification is

that each species concept picks out some causal factors that influence the formation of partially

distinct groups of organisms and that different species concepts are needed for different scientific

purposes or in different biological disciplines. This situation raises several philosophical

questions. How are these different definitions of species related? Arguably the fact that the term

‘species’ is used in many different ways does not lead to substantial problems in communication

among scientists (Kitcher, 1984b), but a philosophical analysis of this issue is needed. Does the

context of use determine which particular species concept is referred to on a certain use of

‘species’ (so that no ambiguity arises), or is there some ambiguity that does not matter much as

some of the species concepts overlap in their intension and extension?

A case that is currently subject to extensive philosophical debate is the gene concept. With

the scientifically important advent of molecular genetics, semantic change resulted, with the

classical gene concept and the molecular gene concept typically being considered different

concepts. A philosophical question is how the molecular concept could rationally grow out of the

classical gene concept (Kitcher, 1982), where it has to be taken into account that the molecular

concept neither replaced nor reduced the classical concept, and both continue to be used in

tandem (Weber, 2005). Moreover, even reference changed in this historical period (Burian et al.,

1996), as among other things both gene concepts individuate genes differently and thus differ in

their extensions. Marcel Weber argues that geneticists have tracked not one but several

(overlapping yet distinct) kinds by the term ‘gene’, and uses the notion of ‘floating reference’ for

the idea that the reference of the gene concept has changed constantly, though in a gradual
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 11

fashion, suggesting that “this floating of the term’s reference seems not to have diminished its

theoretical importance or practical usefulness” (Weber, 2005, p. 224).

In addition to conceptual change in the course of history, nowadays the molecular gene

concept is used in quite different ways by different types of molecular biologists, resulting in the

meaning and reference of the term ‘gene’ sometimes varying from context to context (Beurton et

al., 2000; Brigandt, in press-b; Falk, 1986; Stotz and Griffiths, 2004). This situation is due to

findings in molecular genetics and recently in genomics. A gene is not a continuous stretch of

DNA coding for one product, where all genes have the same structural features (which would

permit a unique definition of what a gene is). Instead, it turned out that many different kinds of

(structurally characterized) DNA segments are involved in the production of RNA and

polypeptides. One genetic segment can code for many products, and several separate genetic

segments may be needed for a single product. In the latter case some biologists consider these

separate DNA segments as different genes and others as one gene physically spread out within

the genome. As a result, philosophers discuss how to study and characterize the current semantic

variation surrounding the molecular gene concept. While Moss (2003) argues that there are two

distinct gene concepts used in molecular biology and Griffiths and Stotz (2007) opt for three

basic gene concepts, Waters (2000) controversially maintains that one shared molecular gene

concept underlies all varying uses. Since apart from ‘gene’ nowadays further terms are used to

refer to DNA elements involved in the coding for gene products (e.g., ‘transcription unit’,

‘exon’), another possible, though very unconventional option is to suggest that in the future the

term ‘gene’ will be or should be replaced by a plurality of other terms (Kitcher, 1992).

These considerations from recent philosophy of biology have implications for general

philosophical theories of conceptual change. Many traditional accounts have focused on

reference to rebut the incommensurability challenge. However, even if a theory of reference


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 12

ensures that a scientific term has the same referent in two theories (so that they can make

conflicting claims), given that the term may be used with a different meaning in each of these

theories the notion of reference alone does not solve Kuhn’s original challenge—how

communication across different approaches and rational theory choice is possible despite

variation in meaning. Several accounts of conceptual change have already acknowledged that the

historical change in the meaning of terms is to be philosophically understood (e.g., Kitcher,

1982; Nersessian, 1984). Cases from biology like the change of the gene concept show that

scientists confidently discard previous definitions they used to put forward, and philosophical

accounts have to explain why it can be rational for scientists to modify a term’s definition. And

even the very reference of a biological term can be subject to change, so that a philosophical

approach that assumes stability of reference cannot account for this aspect of conceptual change.

Furthermore, in addition to diachronic change, terms such as ‘species’ and ‘gene’ show that

even at one point in history both the meaning and the reference of a scientific term can vary

across uses. (Other possible such cases are the homology concept [Brigandt, 2003] and the

notion of a stem cell [Shostak, 2006].) Semantic variation raises several questions to be

addressed (Brigandt, in press-b). What are the reasons for variation in a particular term’s usage?

How are different uses of a term related, and what structure does the semantic variation have—

do different biological subdisciplines or approaches each favour a different use, can one and the

same scientists use the term differently in different research contexts? To which extent does

semantic variation hamper communication? While in his early work Kuhn assumed that

differences in meaning are intrinsically problematic, some instances of semantic variation may in

fact be beneficial to scientific practice, e.g., by promoting a division of semantic labour (Wilson,

2006). To the extent that semantic variation is compatible with successful communication, why

is this possible and when and how does semantic variation support scientific practice?
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 13

Discovery and confirmation

Accounts of confirmation in general philosophy of science typically attempt to advance a theory

that is as universal as possible and covers all scientific fields and empirical domains. Assuming

that confirmation in science is inductive, such a logic of induction describes the form of the

confirmation relation between evidence statements and theory, abstracting away from the

particular empirical content involved in a particular instance of confirmation—just like deductive

logic determines whether premisses entail the conclusion in terms of the form but not of the

content of the statements involved. However, recently the philosopher of physics John Norton

(2003) pointed out that the search for formal schemata of inductive inference has proven largely

futile. Reviewing different kinds of inductive schemes and their known flaws (such as inductive

generalization, hypothetico-deductive accounts including error statistics, abduction, and

Bayesianism), he concludes that there is a strong trade off between generality and inductive

strength: schemas of induction that are of universal scope are either unreliable (conclusion is not

supported by premisses in too many instances) or circular (and thus useless for the purposes of

inductive as ampliative inference). His diagnosis is that we have been misled by deductive logic

in thinking that there are universal schemes of inductive inference.

In contrast, Norton proposes what he calls a ‘material theory’ of induction, according to

which induction is grounded not in universal schemas but rather in empirical matters of fact. To

illustrate this with a simple example (of mine), formal accounts of analogical reasoning as a type

of induction construe an inference from an object a having property P to object b having this

property as justified in case objects a and b are similar in that they share properties Q1, Q2, …

Such a formal account has to acknowledge that the inductive inference Pa ├─ Pb is justified only

insofar as the degree of similarity between objects a and b is significant and the properties Qi are
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 14

relevant for the property P to be projected (Salmon, 2002). However, what is relevant or

significant crucially depends on features of the particular case, and thus the plausibility of the

inference is essentially contingent on empirical information (matters of fact), while the

inference’s logical form is actually quite insignificant for its justification. On Norton’s account,

new empirical knowledge generates new inferential power (by providing additional matters of

fact), but not by yielding novel abstract schemes of inference. As matters of fact relevant for an

induction hold only in certain scientific domains, scientific induction is local. Individual

instances of induction may be too domain-specific to be categorized together with other

inductions under a general type of induction.

While Norton’s proposal is motivated by unsuccessful attempts to put forward formal

schemata of induction in general philosophy of science, recent philosophy of biology provides

more direct support for the idea that confirmation in science is not based on universal schemes,

but domain-restricted and contingent upon specific empirical content. For instance, Marcel

Weber (2005, Ch. 4-5) offers a detailed discussion of confirmation in experimental biology. He

scrutinizes the oxidative phosphorylation controversy, a debate in biochemistry that started in

1961 with two rival accounts but could not be settled until 1977. Weber rejects Bayesian

confirmation theory, arguing that in this scientific case it would have made erroneous normative

suggestions about theory acceptance. (On a Bayesian analysis the true biochemical theory should

have been accepted too early—in 1966, at a point where the total evidence did not favour one

hypothesis over the other.) Deborah Mayo’s (1996) error-statistical theory aligns with

experimental biology better than Bayesianism, as her approach does not assume that scientific

inference solely consists of a confirmation relation between theory and evidence and it instead

captures the piecemeal production of evidence and scientists’ attempts to control for error.

However, Weber argues that a statistical notion of error cannot apply to experimental biology, as
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 15

the relevant reference class for an experiment is unclear, so that no error frequencies can be

assigned. Based on the practice of experimental biology, he concludes that epistemic norms used

by biologists are not universal rules (as in Bayesianism and error statistics), but domain-specific,

empirical considerations. In the context of evolutionary biology, Elliott Sober (2008) argues for a

pluralism about scientific inference, where different inference methods are appropriate in

different situations. He emphasizes that scientific inference methods are not a priori and valid for

every case, but presuppose specific empirical assumptions and thus are legitimate only in a

certain range of empirical cases.

A similar picture applies to discovery in biology. Originally, philosophy of science—

growing out of logical positivism—did not view scientific discovery as a philosophical issue at

all. Back then the distinction between the context of discovery and the context of justification

was such construed that while scientists may come up with hypotheses by any possible means

(including non-rational psychological processes), the subsequent justification of a hypothesis

always has to follow standards of rationality. Consequently, only confirmation was viewed as a

subject for philosophy, while the process of discovery may be studied by psychology or

sociology. Due to more recent developments in philosophy of science such as the New

Experimentalism movement (Hacking, 1983) and naturalism, discovery in experimental and

theoretical science is nowadays viewed as a rational process—in the sense that scientists use

reasoning strategies and discovery heuristics that are reliable at yielding plausible hypotheses, or

at least more likely to yield to fruitful hypotheses than other strategies (Nickles, 1980; Wimsatt,

2007). Thus, discovery is in need of philosophical analysis.

However, given the traditional philosophical ideal according to which rationality consists in

formal logic and the use of universal principles, early accounts of discovery in biology have

followed this philosophical model. For instance, Ken Schaffner (1974) initially argued that
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 16

discovery (just like justification) is reasoning using deductive logic, though he himself came to

abandon this idea. In his reanalysis of the biological case addressed by Schaffner (the lac operon

model of gene regulation), Weber (2005, Ch. 3) argues that this instance of discovery involved a

variety of analogical reasoning, in a form that is prohibited in the context of justification.

Another prominent account of discovery in biology was put forward by Lindley Darden (1991)

in the context of Mendelian genetics. Her account is influenced by artificial intelligence

modelling, and she lays out a set of general strategies of discovery. She acknowledges that it is

historically impossible to tell whether these strategies have actually been used, but argues that

they could have been used to arrive at the hypotheses put forward in the history of Mendelian

genetics. However, Weber (2005) rightly objects that this does not settle one important

philosophical issue—whether general and domain-unspecific rules actually are or have been used

by scientists in instances of discovery. Based on his study of experimental biology, Weber is

sceptical about this, and prefers the interpretation that reasoning in discovery involves strategies

that are limited to certain domains and cannot be universal as they are based on specific

empirical considerations.

In sum, many accounts of discovery and confirmation in general philosophy of science have

focussed on formal rules of inference, which by abstracting away from particular empirical

content apply to any scientific field and domain. But “to show that a kind of reasoning can be

rational … is not the same as showing that it employs general rules or procedures” (Weber, 2005,

p. 86). A look at biological practice suggests that scientists’ reasoning in discovery and

confirmation is contingent upon empirical content specific to a particular case and thereby

conforms at best to local and domain-specific principles. This is not to say that a philosophical

study of confirmation or discovery is impossible. While overarching philosophical theories may

be of limited use, more insightful studies reveal the particular scientific principles and
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 17

considerations used in certain cases, highlighting the concrete empirical content (in addition to

formal structure) that justifies the effectiveness and rationality of this kind of reasoning in the

respective empirical domain. This aligns to a large extent with the practice of contemporary

philosophy of biology. Philosophers of biology rarely address ‘confirmation’ and ‘discovery’ in

a direct fashion—at least they often do not phrase their studies in these terms from general

philosophy of science. But their many case studies and discussions pertaining to biological issues

shed light on scientific method and reasoning as used in different parts of biology.

Explanation and reduction

Just like the precise nature of discovery and confirmation in biology can vary with the empirical

domain, biological explanations can take different shapes in different cases and what counts as

an adequate explanation depends on empirical considerations tied to a particular case. Different

accounts of explanation have been put forward in general philosophy of science. The deductive-

nomological model assumes that an explanation is a logical deduction from law statements,

which presupposes that a certain scientific discipline contains laws in the first place (Hempel and

Oppenheim, 1948). Statistical relevance models argue that explanations are not logical

arguments at all (neither deductive nor inductive), and take instead statistical relevance relations

among quantitative variables to be explanatory (Salmon, 1971). Causal-mechanistic models

contend that explanations exhibit causal structures as they occur in physical processes (Salmon,

1984) or biological mechanisms (Machamer et al., 2000). While sometimes these accounts have

been seen as rival approaches, at least from the point of view of many philosophers of biology

there is no need to choose one of them as the correct theory of explanation. For different such

types of explanations occur in different parts of biology, and can even be used in one discipline.
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 18

For instance, explanations in evolutionary biology often combine quantitative models (in line

with deductive-nomological, unification, or possibly statistical relevance accounts) with their

application to concrete populations that exhibit the material features accounting e.g. for fitness

differences (in line with causal-mechanistic models). Furthermore, following the logical

positivist ideal, early accounts attempted to capture what a good explanation is in purely formal

terms, so that for instance the deductive-nomological approach had to offer a syntactic construal

of when a statement is a law of nature (attempts to do so failed). In contrast, what makes a

particular explanation in biology a scientifically acceptable explanation is likely to depend on

empirical considerations that cannot be characterized in a formal-syntactic fashion.

A related philosophical issue is reduction. In the philosophy of mind, accounts of reduction

have centred on ontological issues (emergence, supervenience, how to construe physicalism). In

contrast, while taking some notion of ontological reduction for granted (e.g. that every particular

biological system is constituted by nothing but molecules and their interactions), the

reductionism debate in philosophy of biology has turned on epistemological and methodological

issues. In a nutshell, epistemic reduction is that idea the knowledge about one scientific domain

(typically about higher level processes) can be reduced to another body of scientific knowledge

(typically concerning a lower level). This broad idea can be spelled out in different (stronger and

weaker) ways, so that the reductionism debate concerned not only the question of whether

reduction is possible, but which notion of reduction is the appropriate one for biology—leading

to a diversity of philosophical accounts of reduction.

One basic notion of reduction is theory reduction. Originally developed by Ernest Nagel

(1961) as a general framework for science, it is the idea that one theory (construed as a formal

system) can be logically deduced from a more fundamental theory. Inspired by the rise of

molecular biology, Ken Schaffner (1976) applied it to biology by claiming that the theory of
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 19

classical genetics can deduced from the theory of biochemistry. However, the notion of theory

reduction was immediately criticized (Hull, 1976; Kitcher, 1984a). The proponents of theory

reduction acknowledged that a reduction of classical genetics to molecular biology has not been

achieved yet (and that theory reduction is not an aim of scientists), while arguing that theory

reduction is in principle possible. Yet the critics wondered why such a notion of reduction is

relevant for understanding biological research in practice, including reductionistic methods and

explanations (Wimsatt, 2007). As a result, the notion of theory reduction was largely abandoned

in favour of another class of models, which may be called accounts of explanatory reduction

(Brigandt and Love, 2008). There are different such models, but they differ from the earlier

approach (which assumes that whole theories are reduced) by assuming that generalizations of

varying scope, mechanisms, or even individual facts are the features reductively explained. A

reductive explanation need not be a logical deduction from a theory containing laws; and while it

proceeds by explaining a complex whole in terms of its (lower-level) parts, the explanans need

not exclusively contain terms referring to lower-level entities (in contrast to the logical premisses

in theory reduction consisting of statements of the reducing theory only). Due to these

differences, models of explanatory reduction are much better able to capture the piecemeal

nature of research progress and explanation in molecular biology. Furthermore, an individual

philosopher may be inclined to focus on one notion of reduction and use it as an overarching

model of ‘reduction in biology’. However, when biologists discuss the possibility or

impossibility of reductions they typically mean very specific explanatory or methodological

issues about their particular empirical cases, so that ‘reduction’ as used across different research

contexts may express different scientifically relevant claims.

Many arguments against epistemic reduction fall into one of two categories (Brigandt and

Love, 2008). One type of consideration is that the effects of a biological system, especially of
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 20

lower-level molecular processes, depends on the overall biological context in which it occurs.

One molecular kind can correspond to many higher levels kinds, if this molecular kind is part of

different overall systems. As a result, reductions must usually be able take the context of and

relations among molecular entities and processes into account. The second argument proceeds

from the fact that many molecular kinds correspond to one higher level kinds, due to the fact that

a higher level biological structure or process can be instantiated by different kinds of molecular

processes (in line with multiple realization arguments known from the philosophy of mind). As a

result, explanations in terms of such higher level kinds can have a higher generality

(encompassing several different lower level accounts) or point to causally more robust features

(picking out entities that are stable across time while their underlying molecular constitution

changes). These arguments are effective against accounts of theory reduction, and possibly also

against some models of explanatory reduction. In addition to developing alternative notions of

reduction, the rejection of theory reduction led many philosophers of biology to endorse

pluralism, i.e., the idea that biology needs a diversity of methods, models, and modes of

theoretical reasoning (Mitchell, 2003). Sometimes this was phrased in a bold anti-reductionist

stance as an argument for the disunity of biology (Dupré, 1993; Rosenberg, 1994).

Theory reduction as a model assuming the reduction of various biological fields to one

theory does not do justice to the diversity of different biological approaches. At the same time,

the mere endorsement of pluralism or a disunity of science fails to study the intellectual relations

that exist across disciplines. For this reason, arguably the most promising philosophical

approaches in the last few decades concern the coordination and integration of different

concepts, models, and explanations. For instance, Lindley Darden and Nancy Maull (1977)

developed a model (of ‘non-reductive unification’, as they put it) that argues that integration

proceeds by two fields coming to be linked by so-called interfield theories. For example, the
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 21

chromosome theory of inheritance is an interfield theory that in the early 20th century came to

connect Mendelian genetics (the study of phenotypic inheritance across generations) and

cytology (the study of the material contents of cells). This was a non-reductive integration

because neither did genetics reduce cytology, nor did cytology reduce genetics. In contrast to the

possibility of unification in virtue of several theories reducing to a new, more fundamental

theory, an interfield theory connects theories without reducing them.

Philosophical studies on integration in biology have often been conducted in the context of

molecular, cellular, and experimental biology, with related attention to disciplinary change and

institutional factors (Bechtel, 1986). Accounts of biological mechanisms in these biological

domains have shown that mechanistic explanations often appeal to entities on several levels of

biological organization at the same time (Craver, 2005; Darden, 2005). In a similar vein, the

units of selection debate in evolutionary biology led to some agreement that units of selection

can be found on different levels, so that there is no single level that would a priori be the most

fundamental one in evolutionary explanations, but in each case it is an empirical question at

which level(s) selection takes place (Brandon, 1988). Studies of the emerging integration of

evolutionary biology and developmental biology suggest the epistemological importance of

problems addressed by biologists (Love, 2008). A complex scientific problem such as the

explanation of the evolutionary origin of novel structures necessitates the integration of different

ideas and approaches. Apart from motivating integration, a problem also structures integration by

determining which disciplines, methods, concepts, and models are to be integrated. Integration

(or unification) is not a regulative ideal or aim in itself for biologists, but may be needed to solve

a particular biological problem (Brigandt, in press-a).


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 22

Naturalism

Naturalism is a characteristic feature of contemporary philosophy of science, and even major

strands of philosophy in general. Yet ‘naturalism’ as used by different philosophers can denote

different ideas (Papineau, 2009). It can express certain metaphysical tenets, such as the

commitment to a purely physicalist ontology or the idea that humans (including their intellectual

and moral capacities) are a part of nature as well. A methodological variety of naturalism is

particularly germane to the practice of philosophy of biology (Wimsatt, 2007). Here the idea is

first that given philosophy of science’s task to understand science and its success, philosophical

accounts have to do justice to and reflect actual science. Second, the practice of philosophy of

science is continuous with scientific practice, and empirical methods of science can be useful

tools for philosophers in their attempts to form philosophical notions. This was illustrated by

several themes from this chapter’s earlier sections. Given the plurality of kinds of explanation

used in biology and the fact that ‘reduction’ as used by biologists expresses different specific

commitments in different contexts, naturalistic philosophy has to capture this diversity. If

biologists’ reasoning involved in discovery and confirmation is dependent on empirical

considerations and the particular shape of discovery and confirmation (and what makes it

justified) can vary across biological domains, philosophical accounts of discovery and

confirmation must accommodate this. In the case of conceptual change, sometimes the notion of

reference and the existence of stable reference across theoretical change were considered a

satisfactory reply to the incommensurability challenge. While some discussions in general

philosophy of science have taken place under these assumptions and within these limits, we saw

that the notion of reference alone does not explain how rational theory choice is possible in the

face of meaning differences, and that the reference of biological terms can be far from stable,

prompting the need to philosophically address this.


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 23

In philosophy as a whole, concepts are often put forward and debated by the use of

intuitions. Various possible scenarios are considered and it is determined whether the concept

applies to a scenario (according to one’s intuitions). However, the practice of philosophers of

biology suggests that a more fruitful approach is to view philosophical concepts as technical

terms that—just like scientific terms—are introduced for certain theoretical tasks. Any

philosophical account is to be defended in terms of its fruitfulness and adequacy of performing

this task (an a posteriori question), rather than conforming to a priori intuitions. For instance,

according to widespread intuitions, the identity of a natural kind is determined by an internal

essence. Yet an actual justification for the traditional notion of a natural kind is that it captures

features of physical and chemical kinds and how they figure in scientific explanation (which can

in principle be empirically contested). A novel notion of natural kinds such as the notion of

homeostatic property clusters is needed to the extent that it is necessary to deal with biological

kinds. Above I indicated that different notions and models of epistemic reduction have been put

forward. It is not sufficient to simply motivate one definition of ‘reduction’ and then argue that

classical genetics can be (or cannot be) reduced to molecular biology on this definition, but the

philosophical relevance of this notion of reduction has to be defended, which also involves

reference to scientific practice. Indeed, the notion of theory reduction (defended by the mere in

principle possibility of theory reduction) was challenged for failing to shed light on

reductionistic research in practice.

To give another example, metaphysicians have attempted to analyze the concept of

causation. Any such definition of ‘cause’ is subject to counterexamples (i.e., a scenario that

intuitively is an instance of x causing y but not according to the definition, or vice versa). This

has led to philosophical debates, where the method of conceptual analysis by intuitions does not

even suggest how such a controversy can be settled. On a naturalistic approach, in contrast, a
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 24

look at physics shows that the term ‘cause’ is not used there at all, suggesting that different terms

altogether may be more suitable to philosophically understand the properties of physical systems

and how they make explanations possible. The notion of causation is used in biology (and the

social sciences), but causal talk there can be diverse, so that a philosophical account of causation

and causal explanation in biology has to capture this and cannot assume that a simple definition

of ‘cause’ in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions will be adequate to understand

explanatory practice.

In philosophy of mind and several other fields, providing a naturalistic account is often

understood as giving a reductive definition of a philosophical concept in terms of an alleged

‘scientific’ vocabulary. For instance, the aim is to offer a naturalistic reduction of semantic and

intentional notions (e.g., ‘reference’, ‘meaning’, ‘mental representation’), in particular to reduce

the normativity associated with correct vs. incorrect representation. (Some such attempts are

causal theories of reference, teleosemantic accounts of representation, or Fodor’s asymmetric

dependency account of representation.) However, such a naturalistic vocabulary is somewhat of

a philosopher’s fiction. For as we saw in the section on ‘Explanation and reduction’, scientists

use concepts referring to entities on many levels of organization and do not attempt to

reductively define their concepts in terms of the vocabulary of a particular field such as

molecular biology. Biologists provide reductive explanations only when it is empirically

beneficial to do so. As a result, a methodologically naturalistic approach in philosophy of

science—attempting to do philosophy in analogy to scientific practice—is not committed to

settle a priori on a specific vocabulary and attempt to reduce philosophical concepts to it. (To

mention another way of using biological practice as a guideline for philosophical method, Burian

et al. [1996] argue that there is probably no unique philosophical account of meaning and

reference. Just like biological concepts are often used in varying ways—with there being several
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 25

gene concepts—philosophical concepts require local analyses and are best employed in different

versions for different purposes.)

When philosophers talk about ‘explanation’ (e.g. ‘explaining reference’), they often mean a

definition of a philosophical term by means of necessary and sufficient conditions. Explanation

in biology (e.g. ‘explaining life’) involves something different. Biologists do not aim at giving a

definition of life. Instead, the aim is to gain partial but ever increasing insights into the causal

workings of various life processes. Likewise, naturalistic philosophy of science is not so much

concerned with defining ‘knows that p’ in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions, but to

understand the various aspects of knowledge production. This includes empirical issues such as

the cognitive factors involved in belief formation. Various social aspects of the organization of

scientific research are a major reason for the success of modern science, so that many

philosophers of biology pay attention to the sociology of science and history of science (Hull,

1988; Downes, 1993). This use of social and other empirical factors is not inconsistent with

philosophy of science dealing with normative concerns such as the rationality of discovery and

the justified endorsement of theories, as certain social factors can be precisely those that underlie

the rational and effective generation of knowledge (Longino, 2002). Ron Giere (1988) assumes

that naturalistic philosophy of science consists in an empirical-descriptive approach, but cannot

be concerned with normative considerations. However, biologists freely use normative notions,

for instance when talking about proper method, adequate representations, justified hypotheses,

relevant problems, and the proper intellectual aims of their discipline. In a similar vein,

naturalistic philosophers may arguably engage in normative considerations in their subject

matter, the study of science (Laudan, 1990). Just like biologists fruitfully study the causal

interactions of entities on several levels of organization, the aim for philosophers of science

should be to shed light on the relations among phenomena referred to by philosophical (including
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 26

normative) concepts and the phenomena studied by the cognitive, natural and social sciences.

Rather than being reduced or eliminated, normativity is thereby one out of many factors. Due to

its methodological construal of naturalism and its interaction with biologists, historians, and

sociologists, philosophy of biology has become an interdisciplinary approach.

Acknowledgements

I am indebted to Marc Ereshefsky, Alan Love, and Steven French for comments on a draft of this

essay. I thank Steven French and Juha Saatsi for the invitation to contribute to this volume. The

work on this essay was funded with Standard Research Grant 410-2008-0400 by the Social

Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

References

Beatty, J. (1986), 'Speaking of Species: Darwin's Strategy', in D. Kohn (ed), Darwin's Heritage:

A Centennial Retrospect. Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 265-83.

Bechtel, W. (1986), 'Integrating sciences by creating new disciplines: the case of cell biology'.

Biology and Philosophy, 8, 277-99.

Beurton, P. J., Falk, R. and Rheinberger, H.-J. (eds) (2000), The Concept of the Gene in

Development and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 27

Bird, A. and Tobin, E. (2009), 'Natural Kinds', in E. N. Zalta (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of

Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/natural-

kinds

Boyd, R. (1999), 'Homeostasis, Species, and Higher Taxa', in R. A. Wilson (ed), Species: New

Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 141-85.

Brandon, R. N. (1988), 'The levels of selection: a hierarchy of interactors', in H. Plotkin (ed), The

Role of Behavior in Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 51-71.

Brigandt, I. (2003), 'Homology in comparative, molecular, and evolutionary developmental

biology: the radiation of a concept'. Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular and

Developmental Evolution), 299B, 9-17.

Brigandt, I. (2009), 'Natural kinds in evolution and systematics: metaphysical and

epistemological considerations'. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 77-97.

Brigandt, I. (in press-a), 'Beyond reduction and pluralism: toward an epistemology of

explanatory integration in biology'. Erkenntnis.

Brigandt, I. (in press-b), 'The epistemic goal of a concept: accounting for the rationality of

semantic change and variation'. Synthese.

Brigandt, I. and Love, A. C. (2008), 'Reductionism in Biology', in E. N. Zalta (ed), The Stanford

Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition).

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/reduction-biology

Burian, R. M., Richardson, R. C. and van der Steen, W. J. (1996), 'Against generality: meaning

in genetics and philosophy'. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 27, 1-29.
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 28

Byron, J. M. (2007), 'Whence philosophy of biology?'. British Journal for the Philosophy of

Science, 58, 409-22.

Craver, C. F. (2005), 'Beyond reduction: mechanisms, multifield integration and the unity of

neuroscience'. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences,

36, 373-95.

Darden, L. (1991), Theory Change in Science: Strategies from Mendelian Genetics. New York:

Oxford University Press.

Darden, L. (2005), 'Relations among fields: Mendelian, cytological and molecular mechanisms'.

Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 349-71.

Darden, L. and Maull, N. (1977), 'Interfield theories'. Philosophy of Science, 44, 43-64.

Devitt, M. (1979), 'Against incommensurability'. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 57, 29-50.

Downes, S. M. (1993), 'Socializing naturalized philosophy of science'. Philosophy of Science,

60, 452-68.

Dupré, J. (1993), The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Dupré, J. (1999), 'On the Impossibility of a Monistic Account of Species', in R. A. Wilson (ed),

Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 3-22.

Ereshefsky, M. (1992), 'Eliminative pluralism'. Philosophy of Science, 59, 671-90.

Ereshefsky, M. (2007), 'Foundational issues concerning taxa and taxon names'. Systematic

Biology, 56, 295-301.

Falk, R. (1986), 'What is a gene?'. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 17, 133-73.
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 29

Feyerabend, P. (1970), 'Against Method', in M. Radner and S. Winokur (eds), Analyses of

Theories and Methods of Physics and Psychology (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of

Science, vol. 4). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 17-130.

Fine, A. (1975), 'How to compare theories: reference and change'. Noûs, 9, 17-32.

Ghiselin, M. T. (1974), 'A radical solution to the species problem'. Systematic Zoology, 23, 536-

44.

Giere, R. N. (1988), Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago

Press.

Griffiths, P. E. (1999), 'Squaring the Circle: Natural Kinds with Historical Essences', in R. A.

Wilson (ed), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 208-

28.

Griffiths, P. E. and Sterelny, K. (1999), Sex and Death: An Introduction to Philosophy of

Biology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Griffiths, P. E. and Stotz, K. (2007), 'Gene', in D. L. Hull and M. Ruse (eds), The Cambridge

Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85-

102.

Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of

Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1948), 'Studies in the logic of explanation'. Philosophy of

Science, 15, 135-75.

Hull, D. L. (1974), Philosophy of Biological Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 30

Hull, D. L. (1976), 'Informal Aspects of Theory Reduction', in R. S. Cohen and A. Michalos

(eds), Proceedings of the 1974 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association.

Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 653-70.

Hull, D. L. (1978), 'A matter of individuality'. Philosophy of Science, 45, 335-60.

Hull, D. L. (1988), Science as as Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and

Conceptual Development of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Hull, D. L. and Ruse, M. (eds) (2007), The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Kitcher, P. (1982), 'Genes'. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 33, 337-59.

Kitcher, P. (1984a), '1953 and All That: A Tale of Two Sciences'. The Philosophical Review, 93,

335-73.

Kitcher, P. (1984b), 'Species'. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308-33.

Kitcher, P. (1992), 'Gene: Current Usages', in E. F. Keller and E. A. Lloyd (eds), Keywords in

Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 128-31.

Kripke, S. (1980), Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Kuhn, T. S. (1962), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago

Press.

LaPorte, J. (2004), Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Laudan, L. (1990), 'Normative naturalism'. Philosophy of Science, 57, 44-59.

Longino, H. E. (2002), The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.


PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 31

Love, A. C. (2008), 'Explaining evolutionary innovation and novelty: criteria of adequacy and

multidisciplinary prerequisites'. Philosophy of Science, 75, 874-86.

Love, A. C. (2009), 'Typology reconfigured: from the metaphysics of essentialism to the

epistemology of representation'. Acta Biotheoretica, 57, 51-75.

Machamer, P., Darden, L. and Craver, C. (2000), 'Thinking about mechanisms'. Philosophy of

Science, 67, 1-25.

Mayden, R. L. (1997), 'A Hierarchy of Species Concepts: The Denoument in the Saga of the

Species Problem', in M. F. Claridge, H. A. Dawah and M. R. Wilson (eds), Species: The

Units of Biodiversity. London: Chapman and Hall, pp. 381-424.

Mayo, D. G. (1996), Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge. Chicago: University of

Chicago Press.

Mitchell, S. D. (2003), Biological Complexity and Integrative Pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Moss, L. (2003), What Genes Can't Do. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World.

Nersessian, N. J. (1984), Faraday to Einstein: Constructing Meaning in Scientific Theories.

Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Nickles, T. (ed) (1980), Scientific Discovery: Case Studies. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

Norton, J. D. (2003), 'A material theory of induction'. Philosophy of Science, 70, 647-70.

Okasha, S. (2002), 'Darwinian metaphysics: species and the question of essentialism'. Synthese,

131, 191-213.
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 32

Papineau, D. (2009), 'Naturalism', in E. N. Zalta (ed), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

(Spring 2009 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/naturalism/

Putnam, H. (1975), 'The Meaning of ‘Meaning’', in H. Putnam (ed), Mind, Language and

Reality: Philosophical Papers, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215-71.

Rieppel, O. (2008), 'Origins, taxa, names and meanings'. Cladistics, 24, 598-610.

Rosenberg, A. (1994), Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science. University of Chicago

Press: Chicago.

Salmon, M. H. (2002), Introduction to Logic and Critical Thinking. Belmont: Wadsworth

Thomson Learning.

Salmon, W. C. (1971), Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh

University Press.

Salmon, W. C. (1984), Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton:

Princeton University Press.

Sankey, H. (1994), The Incommensurability Thesis. Brookfield: Avebury.

Schaffner, K. F. (1974), 'Logic of discovery and justification in regulatory genetics'. Studies in

History and Philosophy of Science, 4, 349-85.

Schaffner, K. F. (1976), 'Reductionism in Biology: Prospects and Problems', in R. S. Cohen and

A. Michalos (eds), Proceedings of the 1974 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science

Association. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 613-32.

Shostak, S. (2006), '(Re)defining stem cells'. BioEssays, 28, 301-08.

Sober, E. (1980), 'Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism'. Philosophy of Science, 47,

350-83.
PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY 33

Sober, E. (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder: Westview Press.

Sober, E. (2008), Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Stotz, K. and Griffiths, P. E. (2004), 'Genes: philosophical analyses put to the test'. History and

Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 26, 5-28.

Waters, C. K. (2000), 'Molecules made biological'. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 4, 539-

64.

Weber, M. (2005), Philosophy of Experimental Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Wheeler, Q. D. and Meier, R. (eds) (2000), Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: A

Debate. New York: Columbia University Press.

Wilson, M. (2006), Wandering Significance : An Essay on Conceptual Behavior. Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J. and Brigandt, I. (in press), 'When traditional essentialism fails:

biological natural kinds'. Philosophical Topics, 35(1&2).

Wimsatt, W. C. (2007), Re-Engineering Philosophy for Limited Beings : Piecewise

Approximations to Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy