How Secular Is European Secularism
How Secular Is European Secularism
European Societies
Publication details, including instructions for authors
and subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/reus20
To cite this article: Rajeev Bhargava (2014) How Secular is European Secularism?,
European Societies, 16:3, 329-336, DOI: 10.1080/14616696.2014.916335
Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the
information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform.
However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no
representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or
suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed
in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the
views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should
not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources
of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions,
claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities
whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection
with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content.
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes.
Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-
licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly
forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://
www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions
Downloaded by [York University Libraries] at 16:50 29 December 2014
European Societies,
2014
Vol. 16, No. 3, 329–336,
http://dx.doi.org/
10.1080/14616696.
2014.916335
330
European secularism BHARGAVA
could intervene in every matter of all religions, to help or hinder them but
no corresponding power was available to any religion including Catholi-
cism. I shall call this model, the idealized French model (Model 1).
While France was developing its own political secularism, another
model was developing in America. Here new residents of this territory had
fled from religious persecution and toleration in Europe, deeply valuing
the religious liberty of individuals to associate and form their own
churches. Over time a consensus grew, enshrined in the first amendment
to the constitution, that the best way to protect the interest and freedom of
one’s own denomination was to keep state power completely away from all
denominations. Thus, church-state separation was installed for the sake of
religious liberty and denominational pluralism. This strict separation was
understood in the USA as mutual exclusion, i.e., the exclusion of the state
from the affairs of the religion and the corresponding exclusion of religion
from the affairs of the state.
So, we have two models of secularism, one that developed in France
and the other in the USA, but neither took shape in the rest of Europe,
where it developed later and took a different form. Here a progressive
secularization of society and the permeation of secular humanism in
European social imaginary led to the weakening over time of confessional
states. Gradually, faiths that were previously tolerated became publicly
visible and civic disabilities of individuals belonging to minority religions
were slowly, in varying phases, removed. Eventually it led, in the latter
half of the nineteenth century and the beginning of the twentieth century,
to the availability first of civil rights and later political rights to all
individuals regardless of their religion. This does not mean that
institutional arrangements pertaining to the dominant religion were
disbanded. Just that as the power of the church declined and religion
became less salient in their lives, people simply stopped bothering about
those arrangements. Consider the mandatory presence of a fixed number
of Anglican bishops in the House of Lords. This form of secularism is
different from France because it allows some support for single religion
331
EUROPEAN SOCIETIES
but not any negative intervention. It is also different from America where
constitutionally speaking the state can neither support nor hinder religion.
By the standards of American and French models of political secularism
which have hitherto shaped our normative conceptions of it, the European
version is fairly moderate. Hence, Tariq Modood’s apt term for them:
moderate secularism (model 3). Formally speaking, the public or official
monopoly of dominant religions remained intact, even as their social
power has considerably declined.
These are not the only models of political secularism; however, other
conceptions have emerged outside the west that have transformed its
meaning. Two of these have developed in the subcontinent and at least one
Downloaded by [York University Libraries] at 16:50 29 December 2014
332
European secularism BHARGAVA
normatively and sometimes merely affirmed. The term used by Gandhi for
this was ‘communal harmony’. Soon after independence, this idea found
political articulation in public discourse as secularism, strictly speaking,
political secularism. The state must show sarvadharma sambhāv (be equally
well disposed to all paths, god, or gods, all religions, even all philosophical
conceptions of the ultimate good). The task of the state as an entity separate
from all religions was to ensure trust between religious communities, to
restore basic confidence if and when it was undermined. This happens under
conditions when there is a threat of interreligious domination and when a
majority religion threatens to marginalize minority religions. So here
secularism is pitted against communalism – a sensibility or ideology where a
Downloaded by [York University Libraries] at 16:50 29 December 2014
community’s identity, its core beliefs, practices and interests and constitu-
tively opposed to the identity and interests of another community.
Secularism came to be used for a certain comportment of the state,
whereby it must distance itself from all religious and philosophical
conceptions in order to perform its primary function, i.e., to promote a
certain quality of sociability, to foster a certain quality of relations among
religious communities, perhaps even interreligious equality under condi-
tions of deep religious diversity (Model 4).
A second conception developed too, even more ambitious, that tried to
combine its major aim of fostering better quality of social relations with an
emancipatory agenda, to not only respect all religions and philosophies but
also to protect individuals from the oppressive features of their own
religions or religious communities – or to put it differently, to confront
and fight both interreligious and intrareligious domination, simulta-
neously. This is the constitutional secularism of India.
Several features of this model are worth mentioning. First, multiple
religions are not optional extras added on as an afterthought but were
present at Indian secularism’s starting point as part of its foundation.
Indian secularism is inextricably tied to deep religious diversity. Second,
this form of secularism has a commitment to multiple values, namely
liberty, equality, and fraternity – not conceived narrowly as pertaining to
individuals but interpreted broadly to cover the relative autonomy of
religious communities and their equality of status in society – as well as
other more basic values such as peace, toleration, and mutual respect
between communities. It has a place not only for the right of individuals to
profess their religious beliefs, but also for the right of religious
communities to establish and maintain educational institutions crucial for
the survival and sustenance of their distinctive religious traditions.
The acceptance of community-specific rights brings me to the third
feature of Indian secularism. Because it was born in a deeply multireligious
society, it is concerned as much with interreligious domination as it is with
intrareligious domination. Whereas the two Western conceptions of
333
EUROPEAN SOCIETIES
334
European secularism BHARGAVA
335
EUROPEAN SOCIETIES
Address for correspondence: Rajeev Bhargava, Centre for the Study of Developing
Societies, 29, Rajpur Road, Delhi 110054, India.
Email: rbhargav4@gmail.com
Downloaded by [York University Libraries] at 16:50 29 December 2014
336