John Marshall: The Great Originalist
John Marshall: The Great Originalist
John Marshall: The Great Originalist
Christopher Wolfe
McInerny Center for Thomistic Studies
The United States has enjoyed an unusual degree of political continuity in its
fundamental political framework, with a Constitution now over 220 years old. Even over that
long a period of time, there have been relatively few amendments, though it is arguable that there
have been numerous de facto or informal changes in the document as well. But there has been
only one occasion when the nation seemed to be on the verge of self-destruction: the Civil War.
The Civil War was fundamentally a war to decide which reading of the original
Constitution would prevail. The South took a decidedly “small-f federalist” view of the
document, arguing that the North was trying to “consolidate” the nation, curtailing states’ rights,
contrary to the true meaning of the Constitution. The North took a more nationalist – a “large-F
Federalist” view of it – arguing that the South was illegitimately interpreting the Constitution as
One way to pursue this debate is to look at the constitutional jurisprudence of Chief
Justice John Marshall. Was Marshall a consolidator, reading his nationalizing Federalist views
into a federalist document? Or was Marshall a faithful interpreter of the original Constitution
This is far from being a merely arcane historical issue, since the whole question of how –
or even whether – to interpret the original document is still very much with us. When I first
began to study American constitutional law, in the early 1970s, there was little debate among
legal scholars and political scientists about the process of interpreting the U.S. Constitution. It
* The original version of this chapter was presented at a conference on “Marbury v. Madison and
Judicial Review: A Bicentennial Reconsideration,” sponsored by the Institute of United States
Studies in London, May 29-30, 2003.
2
was simply taken as a given that, within very broad limits, judges ought to “do the right thing,”
that is, advance justice, and not worry excessively about the linguistic or interpretive path to
reach that goal. There were certainly some political constraints on judges, and a great deal of
debate about particular constitutional issues, but there was little debate about the process itself.
a leading scholar of judicial politics, at a panel of the American Political Science Association’s
constitutional interpretation, the response I got was something along the lines of: “that’s not an
interesting question.”
That changed, of course. Raoul Berger was the first scholar to challenge the scholarly
1976. In the early 1980s, the Federalist Society was founded as a haven for legal conservatives
in the liberal groves of legal academe. It was difficult for the legal establishment simply to
ignore them, because they had support from a political administration that took their ideas
In its original form, this debate was between “interpretivists” and “non-interpretivists,”
but gradually the terminology shifted to “originalists” and “nonoriginalists.” I think part of the
reason for this was that “non-interpretivists” realized the rhetorical disadvantages of that term, in
a nation where many ordinary citizens still operate under the illusion that judges’ authority to
strike down law is derived from their interpretation of the Constitution. More importantly,
3
“interpretation” that not only were rhetorically more attractive, but also harmonized better with
subjectivist and historicist understandings that were dominant among the legal, as well as other,
intelligentsia.
Originalists – those who view interpretation as a search for the “original intent” of the
law – were somewhat divided on the appropriateness of that denomination. It had the advantage
fixed or stable point of meaning. But it also had the rhetorical disadvantage of being tied to
“old” views – in the case of the Constitution, views two centuries old – that many modern
originalists, moreover, are fundamentally textualists, and they would prefer a standard that is
defined less by time than by a text. That is why scholars like myself find the term “original
intent” less descriptive of our position than, say, the “real meaning” approach to constitutional
interpretation. Unfortunately, “real-meaningism” doesn’t flow off the tongue quite as easily as
“originalism,” and the term would be regarded as tendentious by our opponents (who are, after
all, the large majority in the Land of Legal Scholarship), so it seems unlikely that it will supplant
At any rate, whatever the titles of the opposing sides, the debate continues. For the past
two decades it has been fought out bitterly in the Senate, in the dispute over judicial nominations.
Senate liberals, who generally view judges as “politicians in robes,” not surprisingly want to
know the political views of conservative nominees (though they sometimes refer to them as their
“constitutional views”, as in “will you support Roe v. Wade?”), and they generally suspect
4
(rightly) that Republicans nominees will not be to their liking. Senate conservatives sometimes
make the case that judges should interpret the law (by which they mean sticking to text and
original intent – which often could have the effect of undermining liberal Court precedents)
rather than make law, and that the Senate therefore has no business questioning them about their
political views. At other times, they engage in their own search for unpopular political positions
that flow from legal views held by nominees. There are no reasons to suspect that this impasse
Both sides in this debate, on occasion, invoke the great Chief Justice John Marshall in
support of their cause. The purpose of my paper is to describe where Marshall stands in the
ongoing debate about originalism. The title of this chapter indicates my answer to that question.
Marshall is the “great originalist.” Nothing could have been a more appropriate description of
him than the epitaph given him by his close friend and colleague, Justice Joseph Story: Marshall
North or South had the better understanding of the original Constitution. Marshall’s
Alexander Hamilton and the James Madison of the Constitutional Convention of 1787 (in his
“nationalist” stage – quite different, in important respects, from the later Madison).1 Most
1For more on Marshall’s constitutional jurisprudence, see chapters 2-4 and the Afterword of The
Rise of Modern Judicial Review 2d. ed. (Lanham, Md: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994). Note that
I refer here to Hamilton’s constitutional interpretation, not his more nationalist political thought.
I would also argue that Marshall’s jurisprudence reflected the constitutional thought of other
important but less well-known Convention figures, such as Oliver Ellsworth, who ably
represented the central critical mass of the Convention: all of them desirous of a strong national
government that preserved a broad role for the states.
Marshall rightly rejected the constitutional jurisprudence of Thomas Jefferson. Despite
5
importantly, it was rooted in the Constitution itself, properly interpreted according to rules of
In order to discuss the question of whether Marshall was “the great originalist,” I will
begin by describing what I mean by originalism – and even in describing originalism, I will have
to draw on Marshall.
Originalism
The basic principle of originalism (or “real-meaningism”) is that the interpreter seeks to
ascertain and give effect to the will of the law. To achieve this goal, Americans had the benefit
of rules of construction well developed in British law, as represented by Blackstone’s “Rules for
Statutory Construction” in his Commentaries on the Laws of England. Blackstone points out
there that the goal is to ascertain and give effect to the intention of the lawgiver. That intention
was made known “by signs the most natural and probable.” The five basic signs are “the words,
the context, the subject-matter, the effects and consequences, or the spirit and reason of the law.”
The last sign is particularly important, for “the most universal and effectual way of discovering
the true meaning of the law, when the words are dubious, is by considering the reason and spirit
his public prominence, I think that Jefferson’s understanding of the Constitution was an after-the-
fact effort to change or modify or to “save” a constitution about which he had serious
reservations. (I discuss this in my unpublished dissertation “Constitutional Interpretation in the
American Founding” [Boston College, 1978], pp. 90-101.) The only real “Jeffersonians” at the
Convention – the other delegates from New York – left after the defeat of the New Jersey Plan.
I mention views at the Convention, not because the political philosophy of its members is
in any way authoritative, but because it helps us understand how and why they wrote the text of
the Constitution that was approved by the people in the ratifying conventions and that is
authoritative.
6
possible to find meaning in isolated words, but a sophisticated textualism that looks to the words
Marshall, operating within the same common law tradition, describes the the basic
To say that the intention of the instrument must prevail; that this intention must be
collected from its words; that its words are to be understood in that sense in which
they are generally used by those for whom the instrument was intended; that its
provisions are neither to be restricted into insignificance, nor extended to objects
not comprehended in them, nor contemplated by its framers; is to repeat what has
been already said more at large, and is all that can be necessary.2
If the words are clear, they are simply to be obeyed. If, however, due to the imperfection of
human language, the words are not clear, then “it is the well-settled rule that the objects for
which it [a power] was given, especially when those objects are expressed in the instrument
itself, should have great influence in construction.”3 The method of ascertaining the “objects,”
which are especially important to note in cases where the words bear more than one meaning, is
to examine “the subject, the context, and the intention of the person using [the words].”4
Where do these rules come from? As Hamilton suggested in a remark in The Federalist,
the “rules of legal interpretation are rules of common sense, adopted by the courts in the
construction of the laws.”5 They are not the result of some kind of abstruse or hidden technical
analysis, but simply a set of commonsense rules for ascertaining the meaning of a speech or
document, put into a more or less systematic order on the basis of generations of experience
Probably the single most difficult issue in discerning the outlines of originalism – and the
most important source of division among originalists themselves – is the question of the role of
history. That is, originalism tends to break down into two forms, one of which is more textualist,
and the other of which is oriented toward historical sources of original intention. (Raoul Berger
would be an example of the latter, whereas my own work inclines strongly to the former.6) Even
the textualist variant of originalism requires history in certain limited ways. For example, it is
necessary to know the meaning of the words as they were understood by those who wrote the
law. It is also necessary to know the historical circumstances in which a document was written,
in order to understand the “reason and spirit” of the document’s provisions. But the differences
between the two approaches appear in evaluating the appropriateness of the more common form
Marshall’s originalism was, I believe, the textualist variety. This can be seen most clearly
in his discussion of intent in McCulloch v. Md.. In that case Marshall explicitly takes up the
5 The Federalist, ed. Wills (New York: Bantam, 1982), No. 83.
6 For more on this issue, through a discussion of H. Jefferson Powell’s well-known article on
“The Original Understanding of Original Intent” (98 Harvard Law Review 885 [1985]) and
Berger’s critique of it, “‘Original Intention’ in Historical Perspective” (54 George Washington
Law Review 296 (1986]) , see my How To Read the Constitution: Originalism, Constitutional
Interpretation, and Judicial Power (Rowman and Littlefield, 1995), chap. 3.
8
question of the “intent” of the necessary and proper clause, and finds it by noting the terms of the
clause at issue (the necessary and proper clause) and its placement in the document, arguing to
what he says “must have been the intention” of those who wrote the Constitution, “as manifested
in the whole clause.”7 Of course, Marshall could not have had recourse to the debates of the
Convention of 1787, since only the Journal was available at the time of McCulloch (1819) and
Madison’s Notes on the Convention were only published after his death, in the mid-1830s. But
the facts that Madison’s Notes were a purely personal project and that they were not published
earlier indicate that legislative debates were not accorded authority at the time.
The central reason for this is that the only absolutely clear basis for the authority of the
Constitution is the popular ratification of the text of the document itself. We cannot know with
the same certainty that anyone’s opinion about the meaning of the document was meant to be
given authority. To rely on extrinsic sources of the meaning of the document as the primary
source would be to undercut the clarity and certainty that are such essential elements of the rule
of law. Moreover, the language of the document will inevitably be our only guide in many cases,
as time passes, since the framers (and ratifiers) would not have thought of an increasing number
early years of American government, and more specifically by John Marshall, is this: an
interpreter is to begin with the words of the document in their ordinary popular usage and
understand them in light of their context. That context includes the words of the provision of
which it is a part, but also extends to the much broader context of the document as a whole,
especially its structure and the subject-matter with which it deals. The intent of provisions is
commonly ascertainable from the terms and the structure of the document, that is, it can be
An important assumption behind these rules is that the document is not a mere grab-bag
of disparate provisions but a coherent whole, with objects or purposes that can be inferred from it
and in light of which it ought to be read. Constitutional interpretation can, indeed, be likened to a
dialectic that moves back and forth between specific words and phrases of the Constitution and
The deeper assumption underlying these early rules of interpretation is a fairly traditional
“realist” epistemology: that the Constitution has a fixed, determinate meaning intelligible to
those who give it a fair reading. Communication through human language is possible, the
founders thought, unlike some modern philosophical schools (e.g., deconstructionism) that stress
the inevitable and radical subjectivity of all language, which stands as a bar to genuine
by interpreters (an individual, group, or the society at large), to a greater or lesser extent, as they
go along. The framers of the Constitution, on the contrary, looked to the Constitution as an
intelligible fixed standard that made possible a republican rule of law, rather than of men.
Having given a basic statement of the originalist approach, I want to follow up with a
series of observations about this approach to interpretation. First, the approach, as employed by
Marshall, was not a “mechanical” process, as later scholars sometimes described it (or at least
10
later forms of it8), nor did its advocates maintain that an answer to every problem could be
deduced from the Constitution (on this, more below). They did think it resulted in a form of
government that is empowered to deal with all those problems. While the Constitution contained
fixed, fundamental principles (substantive and procedural), the founders prudently realized that
there was substantial variability in the specific ways to accomplish those fixed goals, and so they
did not try to hamstring future governments with too-narrow conceptions of either the powers of
government or the limits thereon. Nor was interpretation reduced to merely verbal analysis, as if
it were simply parsing out the words, phrases, sentences, and paragraphs of the document. The
rules of interpretation requiring attention to context, subject matter, and the reason and spirit of
the law guaranteed that statesmanlike interpretation could be done only with a fair measure of
political prudence.9
frequently used dichotomy between “strict” or “narrow construction” and “broad” or ”loose
construction.” At the very least, one should distinguish between a “narrow construction” on one
extreme, a “loose construction” on the other, and a “broad but strict construction” in the middle.
Narrow construction would be the tendency to read the words more narrowly than a fair reading
of the text requires. Loose construction would be the tendency to read them too broadly. Broad
but strict construction is the recognition, flowing from a faithful (or “strict”) interpretation of the
text, of the appropriate breadth of government powers and limitations, without permitting them
to be expanded improperly. The simple dichotomy of strict (or narrow) and broad (or loose)
construction is made to the detriment of clarity. It improperly equates strict construction with
narrow construction and broad construction with loose construction. But, as Marshall showed,
strict construction ought not to be narrow, and broad construction ought not to be loose.
"adaptable" in a particular sense. Identifying that sense is crucial, since the most obvious and
one of the most frequent criticisms of maintaining the original meaning of the document is that it
will become outdated and inadequate for new and modern circumstances. In what does the
adaptability of the Constitution lie? Not, it should be said in the first place, in the ability of an
interpreter to read new meaning into the document in order to bring it up to date. Rather, the
adaptability lies in three factors: 1) the broad language used by the framers – it provides for
regulating, not horses and buggies or steamships, but "commerce," and permits Congress to
supply the nation, not with muskets and cannon, but with "armies"; 2) the substantial discretion
left to the ordinary political process for choosing which means are best used according to the
particular circumstances of a given time in order to implement the broad powers of the
Constitution, especially in the necessary and proper clause; and 3) the power of amendment, by
12
which the nation could add new powers to or impose new limits on government, as long as there
This is a point on which there has often been serious misunderstanding of Marshall. For
example, Henry Abraham’s The Judicial Process, at one time a leading textbook in the field,
accordance with what Mr. Justice Holmes later referred to as “the felt necessities
of the time.” After all, had not that same Marshall written, in the great
McCulloch v. Maryland decision, that our laws were made under a Constitution
that was “intended to endure for ages to come and, consequently, to be adapted to
the various crises of human affairs”? Probably no Judge did more to this
“adapting,’ and more incisively, than did Mr Chief Justice Marshall, who often
reminded his countrymen that “we must never forget that it is a constitution we
But this attempt to prove from Marshall’s own words that he was intentionally a legislator
who “adapted” the Constitution fails to make its case. Marshall’s whole discussion of the need
appropriate means to give effect to the powers granted by the Constitution. There is no word in
any of Marshall’s writing or opinions that suggests the duty of judges to adapt the Constitution.11
10 As Martin Diamond pointed out in The Founding of the Democratic Republic (Itasca, Ill.: F.E.
Peacock Publishers, 1981), the amendment process requires, above all, a nationally-distributed
majority.
11 Judicial adaptation came later – for example, in Woodrow Wilson’s Constitutional
Government in the United States (New York: Columbia University Press, 1908).
13
legislation, for an interpreter is not a better interpreter for failing to ask whether he is interpreting
adaptability rather than its being adapted, as the founders (including Marshall) understood it – is
adequate.12 For now, let me simply say that assertions of the “outdated” character of the
Constitution, understood as it was understood by those who wrote and ratified it, are often found
persuasive by those who wrongly accept the dictates of historicism (the necessary
“timeboundedness” of all human thought) and assume the outdatedness rather than proving it.
And, moreover, all too often allegations of outdatedness are more subtly based on altogether
controversial contentions that amount to little more than the personal preferences of some
particular individual or group, that do not have any special authority in a republican government.
“Outdatedness” may not simply be in the eye of the beholder, but it is controversial enough to
Fourth, another danger – possible source of distortion – that many people face when they
evaluate the case for originalism is that they are so impressed by both sides of the argument in
many constitutional controversies that they are tempted to adopt the sophist's position, that there
12 Moreover, even if one concluded that the Constitution is inadequate because it is “outdated,”
there could be an equally long discussion as to which institution of government could make up
for its inadequacy. After all, even if the Constitution does not provide enough power or limits on
power, it is not by any means clear that the judiciary ought to be the branch to "adapt" the
Constitution by adding new powers or imposing new limits. But that is a separate question. For
arguments on the Constitution’s adequacy, see my Judicial Activism, rev. ed. (Rowman and
Littlefield, 1997), especially chapter 1.
14
are no right or wrong answers but only more or less plausible (but not compelling) answers. But
the fact that good arguments can be made on both (or several) sides does not prove that there is
no answer. It may mean 1) that the answer can be obtained only with considerable difficulty and
effort, or 2) that the correct answer in some cases is that a given provision can fairly be read in
more than one way. But those are both fair answers.
it is also a theory of judicial review. It says that the basis for judicial review is textual, that is,
the text of the Constitution. That is so because of the nature of judicial power in a republic. In
Hamilton’s classic formulation in The Federalist, the judiciary “may truly be said to have neither
FORCE nor WILL, but merely judgment.” This view was reflected in Chief Justice John
Marshall’s statement that the judicial department “has no will in any case . . . Judicial power is
never exercised for the purpose of giving effect to the will of the judge; always for the purpose of
giving effect to the will of the legislature; or in other words, to the will of the law.”13 To the
extent that this is true – that judges enforce, not their own will, but the will of the people
contained in the law – the power of the judiciary may be said, despite its relatively undemocratic
structural features (appointment rather than election, and effective life tenure except in the rare
“democratic credentials” of judicial review – potentially the most undemocratic of judicial acts,
because it involves unelected and relatively unaccountable judges striking down acts of
democratically elected officials – lie in the Court’s decisions being rooted in the Constitution. To
the extent that such acts are “undemocratic,” it is not because of the nature of judicial power, but
because of the limits that constitutionalism itself sets to democracy: the fact that, as Jefferson
observed (not happily), the dead can rule the living in certain respects.
A very strong form of legislative deference – according to which judges will strike down
laws only in “clear” case – is thus a necessary corollary of the traditional argument regarding the
democratic credentials of judicial review.15 Judicial review does not consist in giving meaning to
ambiguous constitutional provisions – provisions that can fairly be read in different ways. On
what grounds, after all, could judges take one of two fair interpretations of the Constitution and,
choosing one of them, override a similarly fair interpretation adopted by the legislature or
executive? If the phrase is genuinely ambiguous, judges would not be in a position to say that
they are exercising judgment– enforcing the will of the Constitution – rather than their own wills.
of equating “clear” cases with “non-controversial” cases. Judges themselves must decide what is
clear, and the simple existence of some other vaguely “possible” interpretation does not prove
that there is no clear meaning in a given case. The point is merely this: if judges, having
carefully engaged in the appropriate methods of interpretation, arrive at the conclusion that the
Constitution is not clear on a point, then they must defer to the legislature. The significance of
15 I say “a strong form,” to distinguish my contention here from the form of legislative deference
exercised by a modern justice like Felix Frankfurter or advocated by a modern commentator like
Alexander Bickel. These men were highly sensitive to the counter-majoritarian implications of
judicial review, and this led them to be very cautious in employing that power. But it was still a
form of judicial discretion. The form of legislative deference I defend is not discretionary, but
mandatory: where there is no clear incompatibility between the Constitution and a challenged
act, judges have no legitimate grounds for judicial review.
16
this point as a limit on judicial power may seem to be undermined by the fact that it is the judges
themselves who decide what is clear. That is mistaken, though. There is a large number of cases
where no plausible argument can be made that a provision’s meaning is clear. (For example, the
whole category of substantive due process and large swaths of equal protection comfortably fit
within that description.) The recognition of this form of legislative deference would have a
discussion of this point is obscured if one works with a simple dichotomy, assuming either a) that
there is only one possible interpretation of a constitutional provision, or b) that there is a variety
But, in fact, a fuller spectrum of interpretive possibilities exists: a) there is only one
possible interpretation of the provision, b) there is a “fair” interpretation of the provision – that
is, in the final analysis, one clearly correct interpretation – despite other possible and initially
plausible interpretations, c) there is a strong, but not decisive interpretation of the provision (one
that seems best, but about which there is some measure of reasonable doubt), d) there are various
the provision.16
16 For clarity’s sake, I should point out that what I say of interpreting specific “provisions” may
also apply to “structural interpretation” that is fully grounded in a fair reading of the
Constitution, though not embodied in one provision. A good example of this is the principle of
separation of powers.
17
(represented by Marshall) held that judicial review was appropriate only in the first two cases,
where there is either a single or a fair interpretation of the Constitution. The requirement of a
“clear” incompatibility between a law and the Constitution typically comes down, under this
or even merely a “strong” one, or b) a “fair” interpretation – the latter justifying judicial review,
but the former not doing so. Making the distinction between a “strong” and a “fair”
interpretation of the Constitution, especially, can be difficult in some cases, and in such cases
there is most likely to be disagreement among those who subscribe to the traditional approach.
(A good example of such a case is Ogden v. Saunders, in which Marshall and his friend and
colleague Bushrod Washington took different sides on the question of prospective bankruptcy
The focus on clarity is important because those who adhere to a traditional or originalist
theory feel the responsibility to say what the law is, not what they want it to be, and they are
aware that giving authority to what is merely one plausible interpretation among a variety of
plausible interpretations of the Constitution seems closer to an assertion of will (as The
Federalist used that term) than judgment. Fidelity to the law is their polestar, and judicial
choices to grant authority to uncertain interpretations of the Constitution does not measure up to
I think it is clear that Marshall’s professed principles were undeniably originalist, and I
will not argue that question here. But there remains the debate about whether his actions
corresponded with his professions. Many scholars argue that, whether intentionally or
unintentionally, Marshall departed from originalist principles in his practice. Now the only way
to resolve this debate is to look at the cases he decided and see whether they correspond with
originalist principles. Of course, one could contend that Marshall was an originalist but that he
sometimes “slipped up,” so a few errors would be compatible with the thesis that he was an
originalist. But, if the slip-ups turn out to be a very substantial portion of his constitutional
jurisprudence, then one would inevitably suspect that the causes were systemic, that they flowed
from his whole approach and were not merely an accidental departure from it.
And, of course, there is another question, too, about Marshall and originalism.
Whichever answer is given to the question of whether Marshall is an originalist, we can still go
on to ask whether it was good or bad that he was or was not an originalist.
good or bad that he was, or was not?”–we come up with four possible positions. First, Marshall
was an originalist, and that is good; second, Marshall was an originalist, and that is unfortunate;
third, Marshall was not an originalist, and that’s too bad; and fourth, Marshall was not an
originalist, and it’s a good thing he wasn’t. As it turns out, we can find representatives for each
of these viewpoints.
“Marshall was an originalist, and that is a good thing” represents the position that I
have taken in The Rise of Modern Judicial Review. While most of the book was intended to
focus on the descriptive account of how judicial review in America was transformed from an
essentially interpretive power into an essentially legislative power, the end of the book does
19
indicate that I think the “traditional” form of judicial review exemplified by Marshall’s approach
was the right one.18 Marshall was, I argue, the greatest representative of that traditional position,
following in the path of Hamilton and Madison (who, generally, despite their differences with
respect to particular constitutional controversies, shared the same general principles), but with
thirty-five years on the bench to become identified, as Story said, as “expounder of the
Constitution.”
“Marshall was an originalist, and that is unfortunate” represents, I think, the view of
Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. We can get a mild sense of this from one of his public
On the occasion of the one hundredth anniversary of the day Marshall assumed the Chief
Justiceship of the United States, Holmes gave a brief speech. Beneath the polite exterior, the
thrust of his remarks is, strikingly, to denigrate Marshall relative to those he would rather
celebrate: “the originators of transforming thought” – among whom Marshall clearly does not
count. Marshall, apparently, did not add much to what had already been done by “Hamilton and
the Constitution” – which testifies to the tie between Marshall and the Constitution, that is, to his
originalism.19
18 It’s not that the conclusion of the book is a surprise. Given that most mainstream scholarship
argues that a traditional or originalist approach to interpretation and judicial review is in
principle impossible, even to make the argument that there ever was a “traditional” era of
American law is to mark oneself as likely an originalist.
19 In John Marshall ed. Mark De Wolfe Howe (University of Chicago Press, 1967), p. 133. Here
are excerpts from the speech:
. . .the beginnings of our national life, whether in battle or in law, lose none of their
greatness by contrast with all the mighty things of later date, beside which, by every law of
number and measure, they ought to seem so small. . . .
If I were to think of John Marshall simply by number and measure in the abstract, I might
hesitate in my superlatives, just as I should hesitate over the battle of Brandywine if I thought of
20
The more frank assessment appears in Holmes’s private correspondence with Harold
Laski. In their exchange on Marshall, what is as interesting as Holmes’s critical attitude toward
Marshall is his condescension. For him it is was not a case of two intelligent men coming to
reasonable, though different, conclusions. It was a case of Marshall being “outdated,” thinking
in the terms of an earlier and inferior era that had not yet reached the truths embodied in
the judgements of Marshall you give a useful sense of a complex world into
which with great effort a few signposts may be driven while Marshall always
seems to suggest what the world is a damned simple place and he especially
knows all about it. Somewhere lingering in me is a suspicion ( dare I utter it) that
it apart from its place in the line of historic cause. But such thinking is empty in the same
proportion that it is abstract. It is most idle to take a man apart from the circumstances which, in
fact, were his.
I do not mean, of course, that personal estimates are useless or teach us nothing. No
doubt to-day there will be heard from able and competent persons such estimates of Marshall. . .
My own impressions are only those that I have gathered in the common course of legal education
and practice. In them I am conscious, perhaps, of some little revolt from our purely local or
national estimates, and of a wish to see things and people judged by more cosmopolitan
standards . . .
The Federalist, when I read it many years ago, seemed to me a truly original and
wonderful production for the time. I do not trust even that judgment unrevised when I remember
that the Federalist and its authors struck a distinguished English friends of mine as finite; and I
should feel a greater doubt whether, after Hamilton and the Constitution itself, Marshall’s work
proved more than a strong intellect, a good style, personal ascendancy in his court, courage,
justice and the convictions of his party. My keenest interest is excited, not by what are called
great questions and great cases, but by little decisions which the common run of selectors would
pass by because they did not deal with the Constitution or a telephone company, yet which have
in them the germ of some wider theory, and therefore of some profound interstitial change in the
very tissue of the law. The men whom I should be tempted to commemorate would be the
originators of transforming thought . . .
Marshall is rather an overrated person and that he would have been much happier 21
with sturdy Philistines like Field and Brewer and Peckham than with civilized
I only think you should not make it a trait of Marshall especially – it was the mark
of the time, a god-fearing, simple time that knew nothing of your stinking twisters
but had plain views of life. Story and Kent seem to me similar in that was – and I
They were an innocent lot and didn’t need caviare for luncheon.21
Marshall’s world was too simple and innocent for Holmes – just not very sophisticated. A more
comprehensive view of Holmes’s writing suggests to me that what he had in mind was that
Marshall was naive enough to belief in fixed and permanent “truths,” whereas a later age had
come to recognize that – as Holmes wrote on another occasion – every writing is out-dated in 25,
or 50, years.22 This dovetails nicely with the view that Marshall was not an “originator of
transforming thought” but simply someone who re-stated the “old truths” of the Constitution he
was interpreting.
For Holmes, originalism was a mistake, because it was both impossible and undesirable
to interpret the Constitution in light of what the founders thought and said many years ago. Law,
like life, is subject to the flux of evolution, and must be kept up-to-date by “interpreters.”23
20 Mark De Wolfe Howe, ed. The Holmes-Laski Letters (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1953), p. 1007.
21 Ibid, p. 1015.
22 “One of my favorite paradoxes is that everything is dead in twenty-five (or fifty) years. The
author no longer says to you what he meant to say. If he is original, his new truths have been
developed and become familiar in improved form – his errors exploded.” Letter to Benjamin
Cardozo, in Mr. Justice Holmes, ed. Felix Frankfurter, pp. 17-18.
23 For a more general discussion of Holmes on these points, see The Rise of Modern Judicial
22
“Marshall was not an originalist, and that is a good thing” is the view represented by
Benjamin Cardozo in some remarks on Marshall in his classic The Nature of the Judicial
Process. Commenting on Marshall’s dictum that “[j]udicial power is never exercised for the
purpose of giving effect...to the will of the judge; always for the purpose of giving effect... to the
[i]t has a lofty sound, it is well and finely said; but it can never be more than
partly true. Marshall’s own career is a conspicuous illustration of the fact that the
ideal is beyond the reach of human faculties to attain. He gave to the constitution
of the United States the impress of his own mind; and the form of our
constitutional law is what it is, because he moulded it while it was still plastic and
Even the form of Cardozo’s statement, however, indicates that “objectivity” was not in fact
Cardozo’s “ideal.” The whole tenor of his remarks on Marshall’s “failure” is written in the
language of admiration (“the fire of his own intense convictions”) rather than of criticism. More
important, Cardozo subtly indicates that this “moulding” is inevitable because the Constitution is
“still plastic and malleable.” Marshall is not an originalist, then, however he may have thought
of himself, because one cannot be faithful to a document that is “plastic and malleable”, that is,
What is interesting is that this view of Marshall, which dismisses his own statements as
words “well and finely said” but not to be taken seriously, was a widespread view among, not
Review, chap. 10, especially the discussion of Holmes’s opinion in Missouri v. Holland.
24 Osborn v Bank of U.S. 9 Wheaton 738 (1824), at 866.
25 Benjamin Cardozo, The Nature of the Judicial Process (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1921), p. 169.
23
only Marshall’s detractors, but also his admirers. Late-nineteenth century admirers of Marshall,
such as Alfred J. Beveridge and Henry Cabot Lodge, tended to play up Marshall’s greatness and
his statesmanship precisely by portraying him as a judge who molded an ambiguous Constitution
in ways they approved of (i.e., by standing on the ramparts of the Constitution against the rabid
Finally, “Marshall is not an originalist, and that is unfortunate” was the view of two
very different sorts of critics, and in very different ways. The original exponent of this position
was Thomas Jefferson, who believed that Marshall was desecrating the Constitution, rather than
being faithful to it. Jefferson, like all the founders, believed that the job of the judge was to “say
what the law is,” rather than to shape it creatively. But his view of what the Constitution said
was quite different from Marshall’s. While it would take some discussion to justify the
following assertion, I would summarize Jefferson’s position this way: after an initial critical
evaluation of the Constitution (in letters to Madison), Jefferson gradually accommodated himself
to the reality of the new Constitution and then came to embrace it, largely by reading into it his
own political views, which were clearly not the views dominant in the Federal Convention of
1787. From his perspective, Marshall followed in the path of Hamilton, by trying to transform
what was really a federalist government (a somewhat modified Articles of Confederation) into a
Another, later version of this fourth view appears in the work of progressivist scholars
like Charles Grove Haines, a legal historian of the New Deal era, who saw in Marshall the
26 See especially Alfred J. Beveridge’s monumental four-volume biography, The Life of John
Marshall (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1916), and also Henry Cabot Lodge, Daniel Webster (New
York: Houghton Mifflin, 1883), chap. 3.
24
establishing judicial review and putting it in the service of property rights, Marshall did
incalculable harm to the nation. He was therefore not an originalist (Jefferson had original intent
Of course, there can be some overlap among these four positions, with some views
combining points from more than one of them. For example, it is not unusual to find critics of
originalism basing their attacks partly on the idea that originalism is impossible, because legal
texts are simply too indeterminate. But how is this proved ? Well, by showing that
interpretations of noted originalists are not, in fact, defensible on originalist grounds. That is,
these critics “put on the hat” of an originalist, for the sake of argument, and using originalist or
textualist principles, they claim to prove that decisions by originalists just don’t stand up to
analysis. Of course, in so doing – if they are correct – they show that originalism is possible.
(Nor is this observation undermined if they rest their critiques, not on supposed clear meanings
of the text, but rather on the argument that these texts are indeterminate. They can only show
that the text is “indeterminate” by employing originalist or textualist grounds of analysis that
show the indeterminacy of the text, that is, that the “correct” interpretation of the text is that it is
Moreover, the second position (that Marshall was an originalist, and that was bad) often
overlaps to some extent with the third or fourth positions (Marshall was not an originalist),
because the idea that “originalism is bad” overlaps with the idea that “originalism is impossible,”
27 Charles Grove Haines, The American Doctrine of Judicial Supremacy (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1932) and The Role of the Supreme Court in American Government and
Politics (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1944) – both of them monumental tomes
attacking Marshall and all his evil works.
25
Conclusion
John Marshall’s jurisprudence was the greatest historical expression of the traditional
approach to constitutional interpretation and judicial review, which today goes by the name of
originalism, usually by taking the broad interpretation of McCulloch v. Md. and transforming it
by an infusion of some notion of judicial power to “adapt the Constitution” to the times. Such a
notion of judicial power is entirely foreign to Marshall’s own thought and practice, because it is
incompatible with the political philosophy of the founding and of the American Constitution. We
should honor his memory on the 200th anniversary of Marbury v. Madison by recognizing his
attachment to those republican principles, and by joining in Justice Joseph Story’s accolade to