Probings and Re-Probings - Essays in Marxian Reawakening
Probings and Re-Probings - Essays in Marxian Reawakening
Probings and Re-Probings - Essays in Marxian Reawakening
Edited by
Sankar Ray
Shaibal Gupta
Preface 5
Note 8
Introduction 9
1. Ancient Indian Dialectics and Marx 31
Shannon Brincat
2. Marx’s Theory of Prehistory: In Memory of György
Márkus. My Great Master Whom I Never Met 51
Julio Boltvinik
3. The Origins of Marxist Oriental Studies in the USSR
and Its Stalinist Distortion 82
Craig Brandist
4. A Short History of Black Marxism in the USA 110
Kipton E. Jensen
5. From Early Marx to Véquaud’s Countercultural
Indophilia: Similar Aesthetics Founded on
Romanticism and Communitarian Utopia 141
Hélène Fleury and Damien Ehrhardt
6. Sartre and Alienation: A Marxian Perspective 163
Kumari Sunitha V.
7. The Untimely Marx: Marx’s Critique of Political
Economy and the Political Dimension of Critical
Economics 189
Riccardo Bellofiore
8. Guevara and Marx: Critical Remake of an Old Film 218
Roberto Massari
4в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
are of the view that the ‘Marxian vision of art differs greatly
from socialist realism and even from the neo- (if not post-)
Marxist philosophy of critical theorists like Adorno and the
Frankfurt School.
Kumari Sunitha V. in her paper, ‘Sartre and Alienation:
A Marxian Perspective’ posits Jean Paul Sartre’s ideation
of alienation in the French philosopher’s basic frame
of existentialism and the latter’s postulates. Sartre
“addresses the fundamental problems of human existence:
death, nothingness, freedom, bad-faith, anxiety, political
commitment, the meaning of existence itself.” He remains an
‘existentialist in his Marxist phase and during his final overtly
anarchist phase’. The paper sequentially summarizes Sartre’s
Being and Nothingness, segregates existence from essence
(despite a gap in his definition of existence), that of freedom
from necessity and separation of subject from object that form
the crux of Nothingness in Existentialist philosophy. ‘Man is
the being through whom nothingness comes to the world’.
For Sartre, the origin of nothingness makes a man a
non-being. Destruction, a form of change in consciousness
is, for Sartre, a purely human act, since for destruction to
exist there must be ‘first a relation of man to being—that is,
a transcendence, and within the limits of this relation, it is
necessary that man apprehends one being as destructible’.
The act of questioning or interrogation is performed by
dissociation of man from the causal series of being or the causal
order of the world. This is affected by nihilating withdrawal,
Sunitha infers. For Sartre, freedom is inseparable from man,
there being no difference between the being of man and his
being free which the author thinks ‘an exaggerated view of
human freedom’. One finds a combinatorial commutation in
the Existentialist guru’s words “there is no determinism; we
are free, we are condemned to be free”.
She interprets the Marxian concept of alienation as
something where “everything seems to happen as if men
experienced their alienation and their reification first in their
own work, where in actuality each one lives first as a child,
,QWURGXFWLRQв19
Introduction
India is the birthplace of dialectical thinking in our world—
or it is the first written record of such a form of philosophical
and critical thinking. My research has been concerned with
tracing how dialectical thinking developed in the Axial Age,
across a range of civilisations. In this paper, I highlight some
of the key aspects of dialectics in Ancient Indian thought—
elements that I believe need to be reclaimed in contemporary
critical theory to revitalise dialectical thinking today. There
are a number of ontological assumptions that inform my
conception of dialectics: (i) that the world, and everything
in it, undergoes constant change (the doctrine of flux); (ii)
that everything in the cosmos is internally related (however
closely or distant that relation may be) (which is the idea of
interconnection or interdependency, otherwise known as the
philosophy of internal relations), and; (iii) that these processes
of the internal relations between all things are the forces for
the change that we observe and experience as humans in
the phenomenal world. Humankind has been fascinated
with this constancy of flux, desiring to better understand
this existential given of our word between interdependency,
internal relations, and change. Yet this has also been equally
concerned with a knowledge interest: to help direct ourselves,
to guide humanity toward a more emancipatory future. And
my firm belief is that the best way to understand our world—
32в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
NOTES
1. The extent to which these civilisation interacted and shared
knowledge-systems is a matter of speculation. Yet given what
we know of trade and travel routes of this period, it is highly
likely there was both cross-pollination of dialectical thought and
also auto-generation of dialectical systems particular to each
locale.
2. Karl Jaspers, The Origin and Goal of History.
3. See F. Engels, “The Dialectic of Nature,” in Karl Marx, Frederick
Engels: Collected Works: Frederick Engels: Vol 25, Intl Publishers,
1987.
4. K. Jaspers, The Origin and Goal of History, 2.
5. See H. Kulke, “The historical background of India’s axial age,”
in The Origins and Diversity of Axial Age Civilisations, (Ed. S.N.
Eisenstadt), NY: SUNY, 1986: Chapter 16.
6. L. Renou (ed.), Hinduism, NY: Washington Square Press, 1963: 7.
7. S.S. Joarder, “Pondering Dialectical Nature in Indian Thoughts,”
3KLORVRSK\DQG3URJUHVV9ROV/,/,,, January-June, July-December,
2012.
8. Note: Krishna embraces dualism when he praises nonviolence
but not its complement, violence. This appears as one of the very
few times duality is retained but it is only retained because both
are characterised by attachment and difference, whereas in the
latter pair only violence is attached and nonviolence unattached.
As explained by Dorter, precisely because Arjuna does not
want to fight, his fighting would not be an act of violence, i.e.
attached. To act from dharma rather than desire exempts the
action from being violent. See K. Dorter, “A Dialectical Reading
of the Bhagavadgita,” Asian Philosophy, 2012, 22(4): 320.
9. R. C. Zaehner, 7KH%KDJDYDGJLWDZLWKD&RPPHQWDU\RQWKH2ULJLQDO
Sources, New York: Oxford University Press, 1973: 200.
10. Dorter, “A Dialectical Reading of the Bhagavadgita,” 308.
11. I thank Jonardon Ganeri for a discussion on this point.
12. All quotes taken from Bimal Krishna Matilal, Logic, language and
Reality, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1985: 1-22.
50в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Julio Boltvinik
1. Overview
Departing from the premise that the best homage to Karl
Marx in his bicentenary is the development of his thought.
This lecture is an attempt to put together two aspects of his
thought, which have remained isolated from each other, and
try to show that together they constitute Marx’s Theory of
Human Prehistory.
The first aspect is Marx’s philosophical anthropology
(MPhA) or ‘ontology of the social being’, as Lukács called
it, present in his 1844 Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts
(EPhM) (but not only there), which has been masterfully
systematised and developed by György Márkus (1934-2016) in
Marxism and Anthropology (M&A) 1971/1978), with a passage
in Grundrisse (pp. 704-06, Penguin Books, 1973) which might
be identified by a central idea it puts forward: that the objective
limit of capitalism (OLC) is reached as science and technology
(S&T) are applied to production.1 Thus, while MPhA explains
the genesis of man, anthropogenesis, or the Beginning of Human
Prehistory, the passage referred from the Grundrisse signals
the End of Human Prehistory according to the meaning given
to prehistory by Marx. Seen together they constitute Marx’s
52в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
s
lue
Va Ethical Progress
Sociality
s
ed
Ne Anthropologic
Progress
Work:
mediated
activity
(tools)
ies
cit
pa
Ca
y Univers
om alisatio
n n
to
au
on m-
ati do Technical
er ee
Lib Fr Self made history Progress
have the specific forms of the tool in their mind. Toth argues
that, nevertheless, to produce them they required a superior
brain capacity to that of present day apes. Leakey describes
the position of other authors which sustain that present-day
apes do have the required manipulative skills, and the spatial
concepts, to manufacture these tools, which Leakey refutes by
noting the failure of the experiments which have tried to teach
them to manufacture them. On the contrary there is consensus
that the Achulean tools, which were first produced 1.4 million
years ago (by Homo erectus) required their producers to have
a mental template of what they wanted to produce, in other
words, that they intentionally imprinted a specific form into
the material. There is also consensus that this task required
advanced cognitive capacities. Leakey points out that the
development of Olduvaian or Achulean tools allowed the
human being to incorporate (through hunting or scavenging)
meat into their diet, widening its survival and reproductive
possibilities. Leakey and Toth date 1.4 million years ago, the
first conclusive evidence of work “in a form which belongs
exclusively to human beings” (Achulean tools) to express it
with Marx’s words. On these bases, I posit four initial stages
in the use and development of tools by the human being (and
its ancestors): eventual use of tools (apes); systematic use of
natural tools (bipedal apes); semi-conscious manufacture of
tools (Homo habilis); and conscious manufacture of tools (Homo
erectus). This is associated with the growth of the human brain
through natural selection. If in a given population (which has
a given distribution of brain sizes) the persons with the largest
brains are more successful in producing tools, their survival
and reproductive probabilities will be larger, which will
produce the growth of the average brain.
Leakey interprets a text by Darwin from the Descent of
Man as positing the simultaneity of three aspects of the human
evolution: the erected posture, the size of the brain and the
making of tools. The quotation by Leakey (2001, op. cit. p. 5)
is as follows:
Marx’s Theory of Prehistoryв69
NOTES
1. Györ gy Márkus, Marxism and Anthropology. The Concept of
the ‘Human Essence’ in the Philosophy of Marx, Van Gorcum
Publishers, Assen, The Netherlands, 1978. There is a second
edition in English with an introduction by Axel Honneth and
Hans Joas: Modem-Verlag, Australia, 1988, which takes the text
of the book from the 1978 edition. Although I mainly worked
with the excellent Spanish translation by Manuel Sacristán,
Marxismo y ‘antropología’, Grijalbo, Barcelona, 1973 and México,
1985, I have based the wording and quotations in this lecture
mainly on the 1978 English edition
2. Unfortunately , the English translation of M&A translates
Bedürfnisse as ZDQWV instead of needs which is the correct
translation and also the usual one. A note from the translators
(including Márkus himself) arguing why they opted for this
translation, turns upside down the usual use of the terms wants
and needs in English and makes many paragraphs of the English
translation unusable. I have followed the Spanish translation in
these (and some other) cases. This big mistake might explain
why M&A is so little known by English-speaking scholars.
3. Here I have adopted the usual (and correct) translation of
Bedürfnisse as needs, and not as ZDQWV as the translators of the
English edition have done.
4. Márkus quotes a difficult to get English edition of the EPhM. In
the Penguin edition (in Karl Marx, Early Writings) this sentence
is on page 327. Márkus has changed the usual (and incorrect)
translation of Gattung to English as species-being, by the more
precise “genus”.
5. Chris Stringer and Peter Andrews, The Complete World of Human
Evolution, Thames and Hudson, London, 2005, 240 pp.
6. Richar d Leakey, The History of Humankind. Unearthing our Family
Tree, Phoenix, London, 2001.
7. The first part of the paragraph is from page 72 of the Penguin
Books edition (2004) and the second part (starting from ‘But the
hands..’) is from page 71, showing that Leakey is not very careful
in handling his sources.
8. “Arqueología cognitiva: atisbos de la mente homínida” (Cognitive
archaeology: signs of the hominid mind), Ludus Vitalis, Vol. X,
No. 18, México, 2002, pp. 89-109; and “Género Homo: ¿modificar
o conservar el ambiente?” (Homo genus: modify or conserve the
environment?), in Jorge Martínez Contreras (editor), Senderos de
80в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
REFERENCES
Darwin, Charles, The Descent of Man, Penguin Classic, 2004.
Ferrreras Arsuaga and Martínez Mendizábal, “El origen de la
mente” (The origin of the mind), Investigación y ciencia, No. 302,
November 2001, Barcelona.
Ford, Martin, The Lights in the Tunnel. Automation, Accelerating
Technology and the Economy of the Future, Acculant Publishing,
San Bernardino, CA, 2009.
Gorz, André, 5HFODLPLQJ :RUN %H\RQG WKH :DJH%DVHG 6RFLHW\, Polity
Press, 1999.
Heller, Agnes, 7RZDUG D 0DU[LVW 7KHRU\ RI 9DOXH (Southern Illinois
University, 1972).
Leakey, Richard, The History of Humankind. Unearthing our Family Tree,
Phoenix, London, 2001.
Márkus György, Marxism and Anthropology. The Concept of the ‘Human
Essence’ in the Philosophy of Marx, Van Gorcum Publishers,
Assen, The Netherlands, 1978. There is a second edition in
English with an introduction by Axel Honneth & Hans Joas:
Modem-Verlag, Australia, 1988, which reproduces the text
of the 1978 edition. [Although I mainly worked with the
excellent Spanish translation by Manuel Sacristán, Marxismo
y ‘antropología’, Grijalbo, Barcelona, 1973 and México, 1985, I
have based the wording and quotations in this lecture mainly
on the 1978 English edition, but I have frequently combined both
translations. In some cases this has been necessary to avoid the
mistakes incurred in the English translation; in other cases the
Spanish translation seemed better].
Marx, Karl, Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts (1844), in Marx,
Karl, Early Writings, Penguin Classics, 1992, pp. 279-400.
—— “Excerpts from James Mill’s Elements of Political Economy” in
Karl Marx, Early Writings Penguin Classics, 1992, pp. 259-278.
—— Prologue to Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, 1859,
referred as Preface to A Critique of Political Economy in David Mc
Lellan, Karl Marx, Selected Writings, Oxford University Press, pp.
424-428.
Marx’s Theory of Prehistoryв81
must not let Foucault get away with confusing them with each
other, nor with letting us forget that history does not get made
without work, intention, resistance, effort, or conflict, and that
none of these things is silently absorbable into micronetworks
of power’ (1983, 245).1
Hegel and India
As postcolonial theory developed, a typical target of attack was
Hegel’s disparaging, and undoubtedly prejudiced, comments
about Indian thought. The idea of a unitary discourse of
‘Orientalism’ is superficially convincing here, but the matter is
not so simple. As Rathore and Mohapatra have shown, some of
Hegel’s most notorious interventions were primarily directed
against his own German contemporaries, the Romantics who
he held over-enthusiastically to have exaggerated the wisdom
found in the Gita (2017, 24). When posturing against his rivals
Hegel ‘rode roughshod over the subtle distinctions which,
during cooler and more contemplative moments, he himself
took great pains to tease out, articulate and explore’ (2017, 80).
Indeed, Hegel regarded Indian thought significant enough
for him constantly to engage with it throughout his career
and to write some 80,000 words on the topic. While redolent
with caricatures characteristic of the age of imperialism,
‘insofar as he touches on central farcical and corrosive tenets
of Brahminism’, Hegel’s critique shares much with ‘a long
history of other pre-eminent Indian critics of the origins,
perpetuation, and persistence of caste in India, from Buddha,
Kabir, Ravidas, Tukaram, Guru Narnak—all either scarcely
known or unknown to Hegel—to his contemporary Jyotirao
Phule, to recent pioneers such as Periyar, Iyothee Thass, and
B.R. Ambedkar’ (2017, 32).
Whatever Hegel’s orientalist failings they pale before
those of Nietzsche and Heidegger, the European philosophers
central for poststructuralist critics of Eurocentrism. Both
were proponents of the ‘Greek romance of philosophy’ that
promoted an image of classical Greece ‘as the pure origin of
modern Europe, writing out of this genealogy the influence
86в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
NOTES
1. For a general discussion of Said’s critical remarks about Foucault
and the difference between Said’s project and that of postcolonial
studies see Brennan (2006, 91-125).
2. In the case of Alaev, one wonders the extent to which this
amounts to a self-criticism of his many ‘Marxist’ works of the
7KH2ULJLQVRI0DU[LVW2ULHQWDO6WXGLHVLQWKH8665в105
REFERENCES
Abdel-Malek, Anouar, 1963. ‘Orientalism in Crisis’, Diogenes, 11:
103–40.
Achcar, Gilbert. 2013. ‘Marx, Engels and Orientalism: On Marx’s Episte
mological Evolution’. In Marx, Orientalism, Cosmopolitanism.
London: Saqi Books, pp. 68–102.
Alaev, L.B., 1963. ‘Izuchenie istorii Indii v SSSR 1917–1934’. Narody
Azii i Afriki, 2: 160–172.
Alaev, L.B., 2018. Problematika istorii Vostoka. Moscow: URSS.
Anderson, Kevin, 2010. Marx at the Margins. On Nationalism, Ethnicity
DQG 1RQ:HVWHUQ 6RFLHWLHV, Chicago and London: Chicago
University Press.
Anon, 1949. ‘Neotlozhnye zadachi sovetskikh istorikov
vostokovedov’, Voprosy istorii 4: 3-8.
Anievas, A. and Nisancioglu, K. 2015. +RZWKH:HVW&DPHWR5XOH7KH
Geopolitical Origins of Capitalism. London: Pluto Press.
Banaji, J. 2010. Theory as History: Essays on Modes of Production and
Exploitation. Leiden: Brill.
Barannikov, Aleksei Petrovich, 1937. ‘Prem Sagar i ego avtor’. In Lallu
Dzhi Lal, Prem Sagar. Translated and Edited by A.P. Barannikov.
Moscow and Leningrad: Akademiia Nauk SSSR. pp. 5–91.
——— 1941. O nekotorykh polozheniiakh v oblasti indologii’.
Sovetskoe vostokovedenie, 11: 169–86.
——— 1948. ‘Tulsi Das i ego Ramaiana’. In Tulsi Das, Ranaiana ili
106в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Press.
Heinrich, Michael, 2015. “Je ne suis pas marxiste”. Neues Deutschland,
January 24, 2015. English translation here: https://libcom.
org/library/%E2%80%9Eje-ne-suis-pas-marxiste%E2%80%9C
(accessed 10 May 2018).
Israel, Jonathan, 2006. Enlightenment Contested: Philosophy, Modernity,
DQGWKH(PDQFLSDWLRQRI0DQ², Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Iuzbashian, K.N. 1986 $NDGHPLN ,RVLI $EJDURYLFK 2UEHOL .
Moscow: Nauka.
Karttunen, Klaus, 2015. ‘The Beginnings of Indology and Modern
Historiography in India’. In Klaus Karttunen (ed.) History of
Indological Studies. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, pp. 53-78.
Kemper, Michael. 2006. Studying Islam in the Soviet Union, Amsterdam:
Vossiuspers Uva.
Kemper, M. 2009. The Soviet Discourse on the Origin and Class
Character of Islam, 1923–1933. Die Welt des Islams 49: 1–48.
Kemper, M. 2010. Red Orientalism: Mikhail Pavlovich and Marxist
Oriental Studies in Early Soviet Russia. Die Welt des Islams 50(3–
4): 435–476
Konrad, Nikolai, 1927. Iaponskaia literatura v obraztsakh i ocherkakh.
Leningrad: IZhVIa.
Konrad, Nikolai, 1935. Vostok: Literatura Kitaia i Iaponii. Moscow:
Academia.
Kosach, Grigorii G. 2001. Krasnyi flag nad Blizhnim Vostokom? Kompartii
(JLSWD3DOHVWLQ\6LULLL/LYDQDYHJRG\. Moscow: RGGU.
Kosach, Grigorii, G. 2009. .RPPXQLVW\%OL]KQHJR9RVWRNDY6665
HJRG\. Moscow: RGGU.
Kosambi 2010 [1912-24]. ‘A Narrative (Nivedan)’. In Dharmanand
Kosambi: The Essential Writings, 53-219. Ranikhet: Permanent
Black.
Kosambi, Dharmanand. 2010 [1935], “Civilization and Non-Violence.”
In Dharmanand Kosambi: The Essential Writings, 327–57. Ranikhet:
Permanent Black
Mani, Braj Ranjan 2015. Debrahmanising History: Dominance and
Resistance in Indian Society. New Delhi: Manohar.
Murugesan, K. and C.S. Subramanyam. 1975. 6LQJDUDYHOX )LUVW
Communist in South India. New Delhi: People’s Publishing House.
Norris, Christopher, 2015. Deconstruction After All: Reflections and
108в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Kipton E. Jensen
“To learn about the present in light of the past also means to learn
about the past in light of the present. The function of history is
to promote a profounder understanding of both past and present
through the interrelation between them” (E.H. Carr, as quoted
in Kosambi, 1962: 62).
Recognition of difference and conflictual social relationships
constitutes the methodological starting point of anti-
oppression theorists. These range from critical race and
postcolonial scholars to traditional and heterodox Marxists
alike (Dhamoon 2010; Rein 2007; Bannerji 1995). Exploitation
is one of the paradigmatic ‘conflictual social relations,’ to be
sure, but so too are alienation and oppression. As Abigail
Bakan puts it: “Alienation and oppression are central to
the reproduction of capitalist exploitation” (2014: 103). The
capitalist system in particular and competitive culture in
general depends upon separation if not conflict between
individuals. The focus of this essay is on freedom qua non-
alienation. It shows how racialised differences in the USA
have been used to suppress freedom.
Nikhil Pal Singh suggests that while there are important
exceptions, “thinkers in the Marxist tradition have largely
failed to give sustained and sympathetic attention to this
issue [viz. the role of racism in the history of capitalism]”
(2017: 79). This frustration with how the American Left has
$6KRUW+LVWRU\RI%ODFN0DU[LVPLQWKH86$в111
1. The black man was stolen from his native land, from his wife
and child, brought to these shores and made a slave. He was
chained and whipped and robbed by his “white superior,” while
the son of his “superior” raped the black child before his eyes. For
centuries he was kept in ignorance and debased and debauched
by the white man’s law. . . The African is here and to stay. How
came he to our shores? Ask your grandfathers, Mr. Anonymous,
and if they will tell the truth you will or should blush for the
crimes (Debs, 1903).
most menial tasks, have the least” (1927: 5). Debs seems to
have intellectually understood the role of racial ideologies in
America and elsewhere in arresting or otherwise retarding
the evolutionary or teleological development towards class
consciousness and revolutionary solidarity. Debs believed
both early and late that it was “only through an organised
struggle in the labour and socialist movement ... that the
Negro would win equality.” This idea still appeals to a wide
array of critical race and class theorists. Perhaps the alleged
“instinctive” dimension of Debs’s Marxism is captured in his
oft cited claim that “while there is a lower class, I am in it, and
while there is a criminal element I am of it, and while there is
a soul in prison, I am not free.” Debs often insisted that “for
myself, I want no advantage over my fellow man, and if he
is weaker than I am, all the more is it my duty to help him.”14
Similar to Debs’s 1918 commemoration lecture ‘Honoring
Marx,’ 100 years ago, I’m keen to focus more on the manner
of man he was than the particular theories he espoused. Debs
conceded that “no pen or tongue could possibly do Marx
justice,” but he came pretty close in his own description of
Marx as a “triumphant awakener of the long-asleep and the
revolutionary leader of the long-enslaved masses” ([1918]
2007: 473; also in Brommel, 1978: 208).15
Debs first read Das Kapital in an Illinois jail, where he
was imprisoned in 1895 for his role in the Pullman Strike.
Instructive parallels can be drawn between Marx and Debs,
to be sure, but it is also true that—as Thoreau put it in
“Walking” (1851)—the Mississippi was “a Rhine stream of
a different kind.” By 1918, Harrison was taking his message
of Black Marxism, as it were, to the South; by 1918, Harrison
had left the Socialist Party, fallen out with Du Bois, and
was in the process of founding the Liberty League, which
provided a platform for Garvey and the UNIA. In the 1920s,
the dominant voice on the left was the CPUSA; at about the
same time, Stalin became more prominent than Marx within
the Party. According to Robinson: “Stalin, himself a member
of a Russian national minority, had been the authority through
124в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
on the side of the class that produces its own product as capital
NOTES
1. Bakan here cites Robin Blackburn (1997, 2011), Angela Davis
(1983), W.E.B. Du Bois (1969), C.L.R. James (1989), August Nimtz
(2003), Walter Rodney (1972), Eric Williams (1944); we might
also add Keenga-Yamahtta Taylor (2016). Bakan also discusses
various anti-racist theorists who acknowledge the importance
of certain elements of Marxism (e.g. Carole Boyce Davies, Ania
Loomba, Charles Mills, Sherene Razack, Nikhil Pal Singh, and
Ella Shohat) as well as those who, like David Roediger, “attempt
to develop analytic tools to bridge the theoretical gap” (2014: 100
ff.)
2. Fitzhugh writes—in Sociology for the South—that “[d]espite the
$6KRUW+LVWRU\RI%ODFN0DU[LVPLQWKH86$в133
See
documents/1864/lincoln-letter.htm
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Alexander, Michelle. 2010. 7KH1HZ-LP&URZ0DVV,QFDUFHUDWLRQLQWKH
Age of Colorblindness. New York: New Press.
Anderson, Kevin. 2010. “Marx at the Margins: On Nationalism,
Ethnicity, and Non-Western Societies,” Global Discourse, 2:2,
174-182.
Aptheker, Herbert, and David Walker. 1965. One Continual Cry: David
:DONHU·V$SSHDOWRWKH&RORUHG&LWL]HQVRIWKH:RUOG,WV
Setting & Its Meaning. Aims Historical Series No. 1. New York:
Published for A.I.M.S. by Humanities Press.
Bakan, Abigail B., and Enakshi Dua, eds. 2014. 7KHRUL]LQJ$QWL5DFLVP
Linkages in Marxism and Critical Race Theories. Toronto: University
of Toronto Press.
Bannerji, Himani. 1995. Thinking Through: Essays on Feminism, Marxism
DQG$QWL5DFLVP. Toronto, Ont.: Women’s Press.
Baum, Bruce. 2006. The Rise and Fall of the Caucasian Race: A Political
History of Racial Identity. New York: NYU Press.
Badiou, Alain. 2013. Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil.
London: Verso.
Blackburn, Robin. 2011. The American Crucible: Slavery, Emancipation
and Human Rights. London: Verso.
Brommel, Bernard J. 1978. Eugene V. Debs: Spokesman for Labor and
$6KRUW+LVWRU\RI%ODFN0DU[LVPLQWKH86$в137
Countercultural Indophilia
Hélène Fleury
Damien Ehrhardt
NOTES
1. Among others: Yves Véquaud, L ’art du Mithila (Paris: Les
Presses de la Connaissance, 1976); Die Kunst von Mithila, trans.
Cornelia Pechota and Hilde Weber (Genève: Weber, 1977); The
Art of Mithila. Ceremonial Paintings from an Ancient Kingdom,
trans. George Robinson (London: Thames and Hudson, 1977);
FURP(DUO\0DU[WR9pTXDXG·V&RXQWHUFXOWXUDO,QGRSKLOLDв155
10. Margaret A. Rose, Marx’s Lost Aesthetic. Karl Marx and the Visual
Arts (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1984), 83.
11. Anil Bhatti, “Some Reflections on Marxism and an Aesthetic of
Resistance. An Essay,” Interpreting the World to Change it. Essays
for Parbhat Patnaik, ed. Chandrasekhar and Jayati Ghosh (New
Delhi: Tulika Books, 2017), 238.
12. Hans P. Thurn, Kritik der marxistischen Kunsttheorie (Stuttgart:
Ferdinand Enke Verlag, 1976), 17. See also the title of the first
part of Biewer, 21: “Eine nicht geschriebene Ästhetik”.
13. Lifshitz, 32-39.
14. “Debatten über Preßfreiheit und Publikation der Landständischen
Verhandlungen,” in Karl Marx, and Friedrich Engels, Werke
(Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1976), 1: 28-77.
15. Hans Heinrich Eggebrecht, Musik im Abendland: Prozesse und
6WDWLRQHQ YRP 0LWWHODOWHU ELV ]XU *HJHQZDUW (München: Piper,
1996), 595.
16. Karl Marx, and Friedrich Engels, Werke (Berlin: Dietz Verlag,
1968), 40: 465-588.
17. Friedrich Engels, and Karl Marx, Die heilige Familie, oder Kritik der
kritischen Kritik: Gegen Bruno Bauer & Consorten (Frankfurt/M.:
Literarische Anstalt [J. Rütten], 1848), 266: “Die kritische Kritik,
welche der ‚romantischen Kunst‘ das ‚Dogma der Einheit‘ zum
Vorwurf macht, setzt, um ein ‚wahrhaft einiges Ganze‘, um eine
‚wirkliche Einheit‘ zu erhalten, an die Stelle des natürlichen
und menschlichen Zusammenhangs zwischen Weltzustand
und Weltbegebenheit, einen phantastischen Zusammenhang,
ein mystisches Subjekt-Objekt, wie Hegel an die Stelle des
wirklichen Zusammenhangs von Mensch und Natur ein
absolutes Subjekt-Objekt, das die ganze Natur und die ganze
Menschheit auf einmal ist, den absoluten Geist setzt”.
18. Louis Althusser, Pour Marx (Paris: Éditions La Découverte,
1965).
19. Karl Marx, and Friedrich Engels, Werke (Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1978),
3: 379: “Bei einer kommunistischen Organisation der Gesellschaft
fällt jedenfalls fort die Subsumtion des Künstlers unter die lokale
und nationale Borniertheit, die rein aus der Teilung der Arbeit
hervorgeht, und die Subsumtion des Individuums unter diese
bestimmte Kunst, so daß es ausschließlich Maler, Bildhauer usw.
ist und schon der Name die Borniertheit seiner geschäftlichen
Entwicklung und seine Abhängigkeit von der Teilung der Arbeit
hinlänglich ausdrückt. In einer kommunistischen Gesellschaft
gibt es keine Maler, sondern höchstens Menschen, die unter
FURP(DUO\0DU[WR9pTXDXG·V&RXQWHUFXOWXUDO,QGRSKLOLDв157
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Althusser, Louis. Pour Marx. Paris: Éditions La Découverte, 1965.
Biewer, Frank. “Karl Marx (1818-1883) und Friedrich Engels (1820
1895).” In Klassiker der Soziologie der Künste: Prominente und
EHGHXWHQGH$QVlW]H, edited by Christian Steuerwald. Wiesbaden:
Springer Fachmedien, 2017, 21-44.
Bourdieu, Pierre. Les Règles de l’art—Genèse et Structure du champ
littéraire. Paris: Éditions du Seuil, 1992.
Butler, Judith. Undoing Gender. New York and London: Routledge,
2004.
Christiansen, Samantha, and Zachary A. Scarlett. The Third World in
WKH*OREDOVNew York and Oxford: Berghahn Books, 2013.
Eagleton, Terry. Marxism and Literary Criticism. London: Methuen &
Co., 1976.
Eggebrecht, Hans Heinrich. Musik im Abendland: Prozesse und Stationen
YRP0LWWHODOWHUELV]XU*HJHQZDUW. München: Piper, 1996.
Fink, Carole, Philip Gassert, and Detlef Junker. 7KH :RUOG
Transformed. Washington: German Historical Institute and
Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Garcia Lorca, Federico. La désillusion du monde: choix de poèmes.
Translated by Yves Véquaud. Paris: la Différence, 1989.
Heinich, Nathalie. Être artiste: les transformations du statut des peintres
et des sculpteurs. Paris: Klincksieck, 1996.
Hugo, Victor. La Légende des siècles: SRqPHVFKRLVLVHWSUpVHQWpVSDU<YHV
Véquaud. Paris: la Différence, 1989.
Leary, Timothy. Turn On, Tune In, Drop Out. Oakland: Ronin Publishing
FURP(DUO\0DU[WR9pTXDXG·V&RXQWHUFXOWXUDO,QGRSKLOLDв161
Inc., 1965.
Lifshitz, Mikhail. The Philosophy of Art of Karl Marx. Translated by
Ralph B. Winn. London: Pluto Press, 1976.
Löwy, Michaël, and Robert Sayre. Révolte et mélancolie: Le romantisme
jFRQWUHFRXUDQWGHODPRGHUQLWp. Paris: Payot, 1992.
Marmulla, Henning. “Rethinking the Writer’s Role: Enzensberger
and Cuba—or a Story of Self-Censorship.” In A Revolution of
3HUFHSWLRQ" &RQVHTXHQFHV DQG (FKRHV RI , edited by Ingrid
Gilcher-Holtey. New York and Oxford: Berghahn, 2014.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. Werke. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1961
[Vol. 13], 1962 [Vol. 23], 1968 [Vol. 40], 1978 [Vol. 3].
McDonough, Tom, Guy Debord and the Situationist International: Texts
and Documents. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press, 2002.
Pagis, Julie. 0DLXQSDYpGDQVOHXUKLVWRLUHeYpQHPHQWVHWVRFLDOLVDWLRQ
politique. Paris: Presses de Sciences Po, 2014.
Roszak, Theodore. The Making of a Counter Culture: Reflections on
WKH7HFKQRFUDWLF6RFLHW\DQGLWV<RXWKIXO2SSRVLWLRQ, Garden City:
Doubleday & Co., 1969.
Rousseleau, Raphaël. “Introduction: les années 60 comme seconde
renaissance orientale?”, international conference &RXQWHU
Culture in Indian Arts: Neo Tantric Painting, Literature, Music &
'DQFHLQWKHVV[Coordinators: Tiziana Leucci and Raphaël
Rousseleau]. Paris, Musée du Quai Branly, May 28, 2015.
Schnapp, Alain, and Pierre Vidal-Naquet. Journal de la Commune
étudiante. Paris: Seuil, 1968.
Thurn, Hans P. Kritik der marxistischen Kunsttheorie. Stuttgart:
Ferdinand Enke Verlag, 1976.
Trebitsch, Michel. “Voyages autour de la Révolution: Les circulations
de la pensée critique de 1956 à 1968.” In /HVDQQpHV/HWHPSV
de la contestation, edited by Geneviève Dreyfus-Armand, Robert
Frank, Marie-Françoise Lévy, and Michelle Zancarini-Fournel,
with the collaboration of Maryvonne Le Puloch. Paris: Editions
Complexe, 2008, 69-89.
Trespeuch-Berthelot, Anna. “L’interface situationniste et ses
paradoxes.” In /HV ´DQQpHV µ FLUFXODWLRQV UpYROXWLRQQDLUHV
edited by Bantigny Ludivine, Boris Gobille, and Eugénia
Palieraki. Rennes: Presses Universitaires de Rennes, 2017, 161
182.
Urban, Hugh. “The Power of the Impure: Transgression, Violence and
Secrecy in Bengali Sakta Tantra and Modern Western Magic”,
Numen No. 50 (2003), 269-308.
Vaneigem, Raoul. 7UDLWpGHVDYRLUYLYUHjO·XVDJHGHVMHXQHVJpQpUDWLRQV.
162в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Filmography
Mithila, codirected and coproduced by Ludovic Segarra,
Georges Luneau, and Yves Véquaud, assistant director: Surya
Dev, 1974. Duration: 53 min 17s. Capital Films, production.
Broadcasting: LS Productions, ORTF. Paris, Bry-sur-Marne:
INA.
6
A Marxian Perspective
Kumari Sunitha V.
present state. But that change can have meaning only before
a witnessing consciousness. Destruction for Sartre is purely a
human act because “in order for destruction to exist there must
be first a relation of man to being—that is, a transcendence,
and within the limits of this relation, it is necessary that man
apprehends one being as destructible”.7 The act of questioning
or interrogation is performed by dissociation of man from the
causal series of being or the causal order of the world.8 This
is affected by ‘nihiliating withdrawal’. In interrogation, we
ask a question and this pre-supposes ignorance. It is a non-
being. The answer to the question may be either affirmative
or negative. If the answer is negative it is clear that we appear
before some non-being. Sartre, thus, comes to the conclusion
that “Man is the being through whom nothingness comes to
the world….”9 Whenever one raises a question, he argues,
one puts oneself at a distance from the object questioned
and from oneself. The answer, even the affirmation which
involves negation, he calls the non-being of limitation. The
‘non-being of knowing,’ the possibility of ‘non-being of being
in the transcendent being’ and ‘the non-being of limitation’–
this triple non-being’10 characterises every question and the
being of the one who questions. His identification of man
with consciousness (immanence) and with ‘nothingness’ as a
reality of this immanence is stated as follows: “Evidently it is
necessary to find the foundation of all negation in a nihiliation
which is exercised in the very heart of immanence; in desolate
immanence, in the pure subjectivity of the instantaneous
cogito we must discover the original act by which man is to
himself his own ‘nothingness’”.11 Thus, man, defined in terms
of nothingness and pure subjectivity, is first detached from
whatever is determinate, objective and real being. And when
the basic determinations of man’s objective social existence are
nihilated, the subject or consciousness also becomes nothing
because Sartre thinks that consciousness is consciousness
of something which it is not, and the “consciousness as it is
shown in the discussion on the “meaning of question, ‘is a
being’, the nature which is to be conscious of the nothingness
of its being”. Or it arises “in the World as a No.”12
166в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Bad-Faith (Self-Alienation)
According to Sartre Nothingness, freedom and anxiety provide
the conditions, which make possible the movement of bad-
faith. To him bad-faith is a form of self-deception (alienation),
which in making use of freedom denies it. In lying, one
hides the truth from others. But in bad-faith, one hides the
truth from oneself. Bad-faith does not come from outside.
In fact, a freedom founded on nothing cannot help negating
itself. Sartre describes men in bad-faith to substantiate this
very assumption that a freedom may be and is negated by
itself without any external coercion or manipulation. “But
consciousness affects itself with bad-faith.”21
This state of man’s existence arises on the basis of the unity
of facticity (of limited objective presence) and transcendence.22
Man as a facticity is what he is; he is in itself, just as any other
object. But he is at the same time a transcendence, one who
negates his present condition and transcends it towards what
is not. So transcendence or man’s free being projects itself as
a thing of its own and thus nihiliates freedom. In fact, Sartre
conceives man as a being, which is what it is not and which is
not what it is. To put it concretely, man is a consciousness than
he is a thing and not consciousness and not a thing. Because
consciousness is a perpetual negation, it negates itself to be an
object and negates its objectivity (facticity) to be what is not
(transcendence)23 This dualism of man’s being becomes an
ontological basis for bad-faith (self alienation). Let us analyse
the Sartrean concept of bad-faith with his examples. First of
all, we could take his example of a woman who consents to go
out with an amorous suitor. She must decide but she seeks to
postpone the decision. It is at this time that the bad-faith comes
into play. She leaves her hand in his, but does not notice that
she is doing so. She becomes ‘a thing,’ all intellect divorces her
soul from her body and transforms her body into an object
or thing into the mode of ‘being in itself’. Her hand becomes
a ‘thing’; neither consenting nor resisting, she loses her
subjectivity, her freedom and her responsibility for decision.
She exists in bad-faith.24 From this example, Sartre states that
6DUWUHDQG$OLHQDWLRQ$0DU[LDQ3HUVSHFWLYHв169
their continuous insistence that they are free men; nearly all
of Sartre’s women (Inez and Estelle of No Exit, Electra of the
Flies, Marcelle of The Age of Reason, Lizzie in The Respectful
Prostitute, Jessica of Dirty Hands) are in bad-faith by virtue of
their sexuality.
Let us see how Sartre exemplifies bad-faith with a waiter
in the café, “…his movement is quick and forward, a little too
precise, a little too rapid. He comes toward the patrons with
a step a little too quick. He bends forward a little too eagerly;
his voice, his eyes express an interest a little too solicitous
for the order of the customer. Finally there he returns, trying
to imitate in his walk the inflexible stiffness of some kind of
automaton while carrying his tray with the recklessness of
a tightrope-walker by putting it in a perpetually unstable,
broken equilibrium, which he perpetually re-establishes by a
light movement of the arm and hand. All his behaviour seems
to us a game. He applies himself to chaining his movements
as if they were mechanisms, the one regulating the other;
his gestures and even his voice seem to be mechanisms; he
gives himself the quickness and pitiless rapidity of things.”25
If the waiter adopts such a regulated behaviour pattern, is it
simply a matter of internal negation of consciousness, or are
there external norms of that society, which condition him to
be an automaton? Of course, Sartre does not deny the fact of
social conditioning,26 but even then asserts that the man in
question is playing at being a waiter. As if there is an abstract
image of a waiter posited beyond the being of the waiter in
question and he is simply trying to represent it. He says, “But
if I represent myself as him, I am not he; I am separated from
him as the object from the subject, separated by nothing, but
this nothing separates me from him, I cannot be he I can only
play at being him, that is imagine to myself that I am he….
What I attempt to realise is being-in-itself of the café-waiter,
as if it were not just in my power to confer their values and
their urgency upon my duties and the rights of my position,
as if it were not my free choice to get up at each morning at
five o’ clock or to remain in bed, even though it meant getting
6DUWUHDQG$OLHQDWLRQ$0DU[LDQ3HUVSHFWLYHв171
NOTES
1. Jean Paul Sartre, Being and Nothingness, Trans. Hazel E. Barnes,
(New York, Philosophical Library, 1956), 3.
2. Ibid., 5.
3. Ibid., 3-5.
4. Ibid., 24-25.
5. Ibid., 126.
6. Every page of Sartre's Being and Nothingness analysis is
markedly influenced by the Heideggerian Concept of Being.
Ibid., 34.
7. Ibid., 39.
8. Ibid., 58.
9. Ibid., 59.
10. Ibid., 36.
11. Ibid.,84.
12. Ibid.,86.
6DUWUHDQG$OLHQDWLRQ$0DU[LDQ3HUVSHFWLYHв185
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aaron, R., Sartre’s Marxism, Encounter, Vol. 24, 1964.
6DUWUHDQG$OLHQDWLRQ$0DU[LDQ3HUVSHFWLYHв187
Verso, 1980.’
Avineri, Shlomo, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1968.
Blackham, H.J., Reality, Man and Existence: Essential Works of
Existentialism, New York: Bantam Books, 1965.
Bell, Daniel, The End of Ideology, Gencoe III: Free Press,1960.
Desan Wilfred, The Marxism of Jean Paul Sartre, New York: Doubleday
Co.,1966.
Doland, Palumbo, 7KH &ULVLV RI )DLWK)DWKHU6RQ 5XSWXUHV DQG
$OLHQDWLRQIURP WKH 6HOI 7KHLU ,QWHUFRQQHFWLRQ LQ WKH :RUNV RI
Sartre and Camus, Johns Hopkins University Press,Vol. 44, No.
3 (March, 1982) -12.17, https//www.jstor.org/stable/44376086
Drake, David, Sartre and May 1968: An Intellectual in Crisis, Sartre
Studies International, Vol. 3, No. 1, 1997, 43-65, https//www.jstor.
org/stable/23511087.
Fleming, Michael, Sartre on Violence: Not So Aambivalent?, Sartre
Studies Internatonal, Vol. 17, No. 1, 2011, (20 40), https//www.
jstor.org/stable/23512862.
Habermas, Jurgen, 7KH 1HZ &RQVHUYDWLVP 7KH &XOWXUDO &ULWLFLVP DQG
the Historians Debate, Oxford: Polity Press, 1989.
Hegel, G.W.F. Phenomenology of the Spirit, trans. A.V. Miller, Oxford:
Clarendon Press.1979.
Heidegger, Martin, Being and Time, trans. Macquarrie and Robinson,
Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1962.
Heinemann, F.H., Existentialism and the Modern Predicament, New
York: Harper and Row, 1958.
Hoffman, K., Existential Philosophy: A Study of its Past and Present
Forms, New York: Harvard University, 1949.
Jearas, Norman, Essence and Appearance: Aspects of Fetishism in
Karl Marx’s Capital, 1HZ/HIW5HYLHZ 66, 6983, 1971.
Kirkpatrick, Kate, Sartre: An Augustinian Atheist, Sartre Studies
International, Vol. 21, No. 1, 2015, 1-20. https//www.jstor.org./
stable/24720557.
Marx, Karl, On Religion, Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1976.
Marx, Karl, The German Ideology, Moscow: The Progress Publishers,
1974.
Marx, Karl, The Capital , Vol. 1, New York: International Publishers,
1967.
Marx, Karl, Engels, 1971, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844,
Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1971 (1974).
Sartre, Jean Paul The Transcendence of Ego, trans. F. Williams, New
York: Noonday Press, 1962.
188в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Sartre, Jean Paul, $GLHX[ $ )DUHZHOO WR 6DUWUH E\ 6LPRQH GH %HDXYRLU
trans. Patrick O’Brian, London: Penguin, 1985.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Being and Nothingness, trans. H. Barnes, New York:
Philosophical Library, 1956.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Benny Levy, +RSH1RZ7KH,QWHUYLHZVtrans.
Adrian van den Hoven, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1996.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Existentialism and Humanism, trans. P. Mairet,
London: Methuen, 1948.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Imagination, trans. F. Williams, Ann Arbor, Michigan:
Michigan University Press, 1962a.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Literary and Philosophical Essays, trans. A. Michaelson,
London: Rider, 1962b.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Nausea, trans. B. Alexander, New York: New
Directions, 1949.
Sartre, Jean Paul, No Exit, trans. G, Steward and L. Abel,
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969a.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Sartre: An interview in 1HZ <RUN 5HYLHZ RI %RRNV.
March, 26, Vol. XIV, No. 6, 1970.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Age of Reason and the Reprieve, trans, E. Sutton,
New York: Penguin, 1947.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Dirty Hands, trans, G. Steward and L. Abel,
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969b.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Emotions: Outline of a Theory, trans. B Frechtman,
New York: Philosophical Library, 1948.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Flies, trans. G. Steward and L. Abel.
Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1969c.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Wall, trans. Alexander in Existentialism: From
Dostoevsky to Sartre. New York: W. Kaufmann, 1956.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Itinerary of a Thought. 1HZ/HIW5HYLHZ 1969d, 43-66.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Search for a Method, New York: Random House,
1963a.
Sartre, Jean Paul, The Words: An Autobiography, trans. B Frechtman,
New York: Penguin, 1964.
Sartre, Jean Paul, Sartre on Genet (Question and Method, pp. 31-64)
in R.D. Laing and D. Cooper (eds.) Reason and Violence, London:
Tavistock Publications, 1963b.
Svenaeus, Frederick, The Phenomenology of Falling III: An Explication
Critique, and Improvement of Sartre’s Theory of Embodiment
and Alienation, Human Studies, Vol. 1, 2009, (53-66) https//
www.jstor.org/stable/40270700
Weinstein, Michael A., Deens, Sartre and Humanist Traditions in
Sociology, 357-86, in Mary Warnock (ed.) Sartre, Garden City
New York: Doubleday and Co., 1971.
7
Riccardo Bellofiore
Introduction
My generation—I began my studies of economic theories in
1973, but somehow had been introduced to Marxian theory
already in the late 1960s—has been informed by the great
tradition of Maurice Dobb and Paul M. Sweezy.2 To be sure,
we came of age by committing a sort of patricide towards
these figures. I don’t regret my intellectual path, which is
evident in my teaching. My distance from the view about
Marx regarding to economic theory that was dominant in the
1950s and 60s is significant. However, as time goes by, I feel
that my generation has lost something important: personally,
I have always tried to stress not only the discontinuity, but
also the continuity with Dobb and Sweezy. They were giants,
within the larger conversation of economic theory: like Sraffa,
they were respected and quoted by mainstream academics.
More than that, they were able to understand the different
languages of the contrasting theories, an art that seems to
be lost today. With very few exceptions, the Marxists of my
generation became insulated individuals, if not sects, creating
an idiosyncratic world (many incommensurable worlds,
actually), not knowledgeable of other theories, very often
even unable to communicate among themselves.
190в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
capitals); the second step was the inquiry about the many
capitals (competition among capitals). The second step
should have been dealt with only after he had completed
the first. Marx eventually included competition already in
Volume I, Chapter 12. To understand why, let us ask: what
is “competition” for Marx? Competition has two meanings
in Marx, and these two meanings are not well understood
by interpreters, or are conflated. I think they need to be
distinguished, and this distinction may become in some cases
even an opposition. On the one hand, Marx took the notion
of competition prevalent in Ricardo and in the Classicals: it
refers to the tendency of the rate of profit to be equalised among
the different branches of production, because of the mobility of
capital. A similar though not identical notion of competition
can be found in Walras, and even more in Marshall. This kind
of competition gives rise to the discrepancy between simple or
direct prices (the prices proportional to the labour contained
in commodities) and production prices (the capitalist prices
embodying an equal rate of profit). This competition is
discussed in Volume III. In Volume I, we find another notion of
competition altogether: the competition within industries, or
ZLWKLQEUDQFKHVRISURGXFWLRQ, where many capitals are struggling
in a fight to the death through the introduction of innovations.
Prices—also the simple or direct prices—are established as
a social or market value as the monetary expression of the (socially
necessary) labour time, which may well be different from the
individual value determined by the individual labour time
contained. Those who introduce a new machine, a new
organisation of labour, etc., lower their individual labour time
EHORZ the socially necessary labour time: as a consequence,
their individual value drops below the social (or market)
value, and they beget an extra surplus value. The same process
can be replicated for the prices of production. Innovators
can wage a ZDU against the other firms producing the same
use value by beginning to decrease the selling price, and
thereby stealing the market from other capitalists. This kind
of competition is a FXWWKURDW competition. It is a competition
7KH8QWLPHO\0DU[в207
Reproduction
In Section 7 Marx is anticipating the heretical monetary
macroeconomics of the twentieth century. I am referring to
Wicksell, Schumpeter, the Keynes of the Treatise on Money,
and later to the French-Italian contemporary circuit theory of
money. The difference between Marx and these authors being
that, as de Brunhoff insisted, Marx was mostly writing within
the tradition of the monetary theory of credit, and these
“heretics” were and are (like me) committed to the alternative
view of the credit theory of money.23
The similarity is that the reasoning about the class
relation and divide is explicitly set within an initial PDFUR
monetary setting. Total capital advances the money wage-bill
as finance for production in order to buy labour power from the
working class.24 In Chapter 23, Marx writes that to have a clear
understanding of what is really going on we have to abandon
the perspective of the single capitalist and the single worker,
and look instead at the capitalist class and the working class.
The capitalist class advances money drafts to workers, order
notes, that are given back by the latter to the former to get
their share of what they have produced. In this transaction, the
so-called money “veil” performs an essential function: capital
includes in its own mechanism workers as its internal other,
and the means of subsistence (as the variable capital buying
labour power) are the means to get living labour power.
In fact, in the Results of the Immediate Process of Production,
Marx even writes that it is not the workers that acquire the
means of subsistence, but that the means of subsistence buy
the workers. Marx has no ambiguity here in clarifying that
what has to be taken as given is the UHDO ZDJH RI WKH ZRUNLQJ
FODVVDVDZKROH³a point which is lost in most of contemporary
Marxist economics: individual workers may have freedom of
choice about their individual basket of consumption goods,
but that is definitely not true for workers as a class; they have
to buy what the capitalist class leave them as available goods.
This is the same conclusion that the monetary heretics reach,
210в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
but also the same conclusion that follows from Keynes’ view
of the investments as the autonomous driving component
in private effective demand; and, even more so, the same
conclusion as Kalecki. It is, without doubt, a PDFURPRQHWDU\
WKHRU\RIWKHFDSLWDOLVWSURGXFWLRQDQGGLVWULEXWLRQRIQHZYDOXHDQG
surplus value.
The Ex Ante Monetary Socialisation of Labour
A quite explicit consequence of Marx’s new viewpoint—a
consequence which, once again, is missed in most readings—
is that the “macro” logic (the logic of the totality)—is not only
different, but unique, prior and opposite to the “micro” logic:
what “appears” from point of view of the “micro” logic, the
logic of “individuals”, what more properly speaking was
a phenomenal manifestation (an Erscheinung) in the earlier
sections, is now revealed as an illusory semblance (a Schein).
We have to look back down the path we have travelled, we
must read Capital I EDFNZDUGV.
Marx began with money and the commodity, then he
moved to capital and how it is produced. The single capitalist
was taken to be an average representative of total capital.
On the labour market, the phenomenal manifestation means
that workers and capitalists are free and equal subjects. This
is not false, at that layer of the inquiry. With reproduction
and now assuming the standpoint of the totality, the inquiry
is transposed into a directly social, macro, monetary, class
perspective. This is a very different outlook than the one
taken by the so-called “macro-monetary approaches” within
Marxism today: their logic is just a logic of aggregation. My
alternative macro foundation leads to opposite conclusions
compared to the micro logic. This is apparent in the fact that
the working class is tied to capital as a whole by a relation of
slavery: the free and equal bargaining of the individual worker
was just a necessary “objective illusion”.
When reading Marx, one must be warned that the meaning
of categories changes along the way in his Darstellung, in
exposition. This does not mean that the previous meaning of
7KH8QWLPHO\0DU[в211
NOTES
REFERENCES
Adorno, T.W. ([1966] 1990), Negative Dialectics, London: Routledge.
Adorno, T.W. ([1968] 2002), Introduction to Sociology, Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Althusser, L., Balibar É., Establet R., Macherey P. and Rancière J.
Boston: Brill.
Backhaus, H.-G. (1997), Dialektik der Wertform. Untersuchungen zur
216в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Roberto Massari
source of Che’s Marxist training, given that she had been his
“teacher”: this was able to happen because she was more
prepared than Ernesto, having a degree in economics, and
above all because she had an anti-orthodox Marxist training
with roots in Apra (therefore more genuinely Latin American)
and not Sovietic (that is, Stalinist and dogmatic).
I have already provided an account of those “Roman”
conversations with Hilda in my book of 1987 Che Guevara.
Pensiero e Politica Dell’utopia [Che Guevara. Pensamiento y
Política de la Utopía], and it is not the case to repeat here. It
may be interesting, however, to mention the titles or names of
the authors that the two read, commented on and discussed
(sometimes even animatedly as Che wrote in a letter to the
family): Tolstoy, Gorky, Dostoevsky, Kropotkin (Memoirs of
a revolutionary), Engels (Antidühring, Origins of the Family,
Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, etc.), Lenin (What is to be
Done?, Imperialism) and of course various works by Marx, in
addition to The Communist Manifesto and Capital. About the
latter, Hilda wrote:
...and Capital by Marx, with which I was more familiar for my
studies of economics (p. 36)].
Wanting to summarise Hilda Gadea’s point of view regarding
that phase of intense theoretical sharing and fresh and
enthusiastic Guevarian adherence to Marxism, I must say that
in the conversations she had with me she placed the emphasis
on two aspects which were then indeed crucial and which
time has instead dispersed among the mists of the theoretical
divergences that are now surpassed and obsolete.
In the first place, Hilda kept alive and transmitted to
Ernesto the conception that the revolution in the backward,
dependent or developing countries cannot rely on the national
bourgeoisie, neither as such—that is collectively in historical
concretions of certain dependent capitalist classes (those which
when I talked to her I referred to as “sub-imperialistic”)—
nor on their allegedly progressive sectors. These sectors
appeared inevitably marked by class interests that ultimately
232в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
would have led them to clash with the processes of real social
emancipation, both in the rural world and with the urban
proletariat. Regarding to Hilda and to the credit of Guevara,
it must be recognised that he never failed in this fundamental
political intuition derived from the best theoretical tradition of
20th century revolutionary Marxism.
Secondly, she tried to win Ernesto over to a radical
critique of Soviet Marxism, both for the responsibilities it
had in the past for the degenerative process of the October
revolution, and for its contemporary policy of convergence
with imperialism in maintenance of the global status quo. It is
true, however, that Hilda harboured illusions about Chinese
communism, and at the time the USSR-China conflict was a
burning topic. We will see that Guevara will not always listen
to her on this double aspect of a single international reality
born in Yalta and will go through oscillations in favour of and
against Soviet Marxism, for and against so-called “Maoism”,
unfortunately losing life before arriving at a superior synthesis
of both these refusals.
But more about that later.
INTERVAL
Scene 5 [Sierra Maestra, 1956-58]
The interval was real: an authentic “epistemological” break it
could be said with Althusserian irony, since between departure
for the Granma expedition and the victorious conclusion of the
Las Villas campaign—which Guevara ended with the battle
of Santa Clara which gave rise to his “legend»—there was
an interruption in philosophical reflection on Marxism texts
and reading itself of the texts. The interruption lasted a little
more than two years, starting with the departure from Tuxpan
(when the only person with a previous military experience
was the Italian Gino Doné [1924-2008] who had taken part
in the Resistance in Veneto), passing through occupation of
the two main military strongholds in Havana—under the
leadership of Che and Camilo Cienfuegos (1932-1959)—and
ending with the establishment of the new regime headed
by Fidel Castro. They were times of guerrilla warfare on the
mountains and attacks in the cities, strikes, agrarian reform,
expropriation and nationalisation, and the creation of a new
state structure. Certainly not times of theoretical reflection, of
study or of exploring the Marxian message.
Guevara’s Episodes of the Cuban Revolutionary War and the
memoires of various fighters give the perception of a profound
disregard for the problems of political theory by the Castro
leadership—in this very differently from what had happened
in the first period of the Russian Revolution—and one gets the
impression that Che was closed in a sort of theoretical self-
isolation. He admitted this himself in writing to the political
figure that I personally consider to have been the most
representative of the Cuban revolution (commander René
Ramos Latour [«Daniel”, 1932-1958]), who died in combat,
but only after having stood up to Che in a controversy that
deserves the greatest attention and instead, out of political
hypocrisy, is almost always ignored or in any case belittled.
On December 14, 1957, Che wrote him a long letter, very
critical of the positions of the llano (the M26-7 in the cities
236в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
where Daniel had been the main leader after the death of
Frank País [1934-1957]), stating:
I am, through my ideological preparation, one of those who believe
that WKHVROXWLRQRIWKHSUREOHPVLQWKHZRUOGLVWREHIRXQGEHKLQGWKH
VRFDOOHG,URQ&XUWDLQ and I consider this movement as one of the
many provoked by the anxiety of the bourgeoisie to free itself
from the economic chains of imperialism.
I have always considered Fidel as an authentic leader of the left
bourgeoisie, even if his personality is characterised by personal
qualities of extraordinary value, which place him far above his
class.
With this spirit I started the struggle: honestly ZLWKRXW
the hope of going beyond liberation of the country, ZLOOLQJWROHDYH
when the conditions of the next struggle turn all the action of
the Movement to the right (towards what you represent” (my
italics)].
It would be too long here to explain the subject of
the polemic that is however of the greatest interest for
understanding the dynamics of the Cuban revolution, and in
any case I have already done so in detail on other occasions.
But at least two aspects must be kept in mind: a) Guevara had
come to consider himself definitively part of the communist
(Soviet) camp and, as a Marxist, he considered himself an
isolated militant within a bourgeois democratic movement
like the M26-7 and, although he was engaged in an armed
struggle, he was willing to trust only up to a certain point
(here Hilda Gadea’s teaching was evident); b) as early as 1957
he believed he could not conclude his revolutionary action
within the Cuban movement and, with authentic prophetic
spirit, announced his intention to leave for “other lands of
the world»—as was to happen less than ten years later—if
his ideological training should become incompatible with the
ongoing revolutionary process. It was unequivocal proof of
the internationalist spirit that animated his recent adherence
to communism, although for the moment it coincided with the
Soviet orientation.
*XHYDUDDQG0DU[в237
for Che not only the scholar who “interprets history and
understands its dynamics”, but also he who “foresees future
events”, who “prophesies” (further on he even speaks of the
“predictions of Marx the scientist”), who is “architect of his
own destiny” and, besides interpreting nature, now has the
tools to “transform it”. Hence the obvious reference to the
need for revolutionary action as a logical consequence of so
much scientific knowledge of nature, history and the world
made possible by Marxism, now considered definetely to be
a science.
This flatly materialistic vision was certainly derived from
very simplistic interpretations of works by Engels ($QWL
Dühring, Dialectics of Nature, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific)
and Lenin (0DWHULDOLVP DQG (PSLULR&ULWLFLVP) which are not
cited here, but which Ernesto had read in Guatemala and
Mexico. The equation of Marxism with the mathematical,
physical or biological sciences—which had been a common
currency for Marxology in the Stalinist period—now opens
into the grossest philosophical evolutionism when Guevara
draws a line of continuity between “Marx, Engels, Lenin,
Stalin and Mao Zedong”, even going so far as to include the
“new Soviet and Chinese rulers” in this pyramid scheme of
presumably Marxist thinking (Escritos y Discursos, p. 204]):
of all these, according to Che, one should have followed “the
body of doctrine” and even “the example” (but on Kruschev
he would change his mind shortly thereafter ...).
It would be ungenerous to continue with other quotations
from this naive listing of the presumed scientific-naturalistic
merits of Marxism—which strangely however is never called
here “dialectical materialism” according to what instead
Stalinist tradition would have prescribed—and if anything
we should take it up with how many (many, too many)
have indicated in this article one of the top peaks reached by
Guevara in his re-elaboration of Marxism. Unfortunately, C.
Wright Mills (1916-1962)—who included this unique Che text
in his famous anthology 7KH0DU[LVWV³is one of these.
242в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
agree with his judgment on Bolivar and with the analysis which,
together with Engels, Marx made of Mexicans, taking for granted
certain theories about race or nationality which are inadmissible
today. But great men, discoverers of luminous truths, survive
in spite of their small errors, which serve to make them more
human: they can make mistakes without this damaging our
clear awareness of the level reached by these giants of thought.
And for this reason we say that the essential truths of Marxism
are an integral part of the cultural and scientific community of
peoples and we accept them with the naturalness that comes
from something that needs no further discussion (pp. 93-4).
The criticisms that Guevara addressed to Marx-Engelsian texts
on Latin America could refer to some entries compiled by
Marx and Engels for the 1HZ$PHULFDQ&\FORSDHGLD (published
in New York in 16 volumes between 1858 and 1863, under the
direction of Charles Anderson Dana [1819-1897], also director
for some twenty years of the 1HZ <RUN 'DLO\ 7ULEXQH), but
above all to a letter from Marx to Engels dated December 2,
1854 (in Complete Works, XXXIX, p. 434).
After having reconstructed the complicated story, in my
comment I openly agreed with the two great friends and
disagreed with Guevara. But I added a much more serious
consideration about the fact that, in the essay dedicated
by Che to analysis of the ideology of the Cuban revolution,
there was no mention of the great libertadores (liberators), no
mention of any Latin American thinker or writer involved
in the anti-Spanish ideological struggle, not even José Martí
(1853-1895) himself. Greek philosophers, physicists and
mathematicians from various eras were mentioned, as well
as a lot of Marx, but no one indigenous to Cuba or Latin
America. A foolishness certainly produced by the anxiety of
the neophyte who wanted to show himself more Marxist than
Marx, flaunting an acquired familiarity with his work, but
that cannot fail to leave one taken aback. More than the vulgar
materialist conception of Marxism exhibited therein, it is the
absence of references to Latin American ideologies or political
conceptions which constitutes the most serious deficiency of
244в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
HERESY STORY
Scene 7 [from Moscow to Havana, 1963-65]
The starting scene for describing this intellectual revival
of Guevara’s Marxism is set in Moscow and he described it
himself in one of the stenographic recordings of the bi-monthly
conversations he held at the Ministry of Industry from 1962
to 1964. Here we are especially interested in some of the
recordings of Che’s last year in Cuba as a minister. They are
informal but precious materials; even more precious because
they have not been re-elaborated or reviewed thus, reflecting
Che’s immediate—and by no means diplomatic—thoughts.
These recordings were published in 1967 (but Guevara had
already been able to see the drafts in 1966) in Vol. VI of the
first extremely limited edition (around two hundred copies) of
his works, edited by Orlando Borrego (El Che en la Revolución
Cubana). In Cuba they were never republished, nor ever
included in collections of his works and therefore for a long
time they could be read above all in editions and translations
made abroad: the first were in French, edited by Michael Löwy
(b. 1938) and published by Maspero (1932-2015), and in Italian
by il Manifesto in 1969 and then in my collection of Scritti Scelti
[Selected Writings] of Che in 1993. Until they were finally
included in the volume of Apuntes, published in Cuba in 2006.
The scene takes place on December 5, 1964 in the Cuban
embassy in Moscow where Che is listened to by some
fifty Soviet students, but also challenged by some of them
regarding his theory of the priority of moral incentives, based
250в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
MARXIST STORY
Scene 8 [Prague, 1966]
At this point we must devote attention to this polemic, trying
first of all to imagine the scene: after the lengthy confinement
in the Cuban ambassador’s house in Dar es Salaam, there
is a drastic change of continent—from Africa to the heart of
old Europe; a large villa on the outskirts of Prague; the semi-
clandestine coexistence (Cuban-Czechoslovak “Operation
Manuel”) with some of the closest companions (“Pombo”
[b. 1940] and “Tuma” [1940-1967]); chess games; study and
writing.
Che remained there from March till July 1966, when he
returned to Cuba to prepare for Bolivia, which in the meantime
was definitively decided as a political goal, having abandoned
during summer the previously chosen objective—namely,
Peru. (All of this has been reconstructed and documented in
detail by Humberto Vázquez Viaña, Una Guerrilla Para el Che).
And there Guevara writes the work that is used to define
“The Prague Notebooks” (but published as Apuntes Críticos
a la Economía Política [Critical Notes on Political Economy],
although Che’s target was really the Manual of Political
Economy of the USSR Academy of Sciences). An enormous
work of recompilation of texts (starting from the biographical
compendium of Marx-Engels mentioned above), with long
256в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
BIBLIOGRAPHY
SYNOPSIS
The old film refers to the many written and spoken platitudes
about Guevara’s relationship with Marx in the years when
there was the attempt to downscale this relationship within
the canons of the orthodoxy of Soviet-inspired Marxism. In
reality, the history of this relationship was very complicated
and subject to continuous and major changes. The essay by
Massari reconstructs these changes in the form of film scenes
in which the reader jumps from one place to another of the
Planet (La Paz, Dar es Salaam, Lima, Rome, Moscow, Havana,
Prague and finally Bolivia) to follow directly the reflection on
Marx by a man of action who was also a scholar with great
reading and writing skills.
From the examination of almost unknown and ignored
documentary material—such as the notes on books to read in
the Bolivian Diary written during the guerrilla war in Bolivia in
1966-67, preceded by the letter to Armando Hart of December
1965—a totally new view of Guevara’s relationship with
Marxism, and with the social sciences in general, is obtained.
Massari describes the early development of Che’s
*XHYDUDDQG0DU[в265
relations between men and women, but at the same time they
stressed the historical evolution of family, that is, the social shell
surrounding and shaping relations between the two sexes.
Moreover, according to a new understanding of equality,
feminists employed Marxist and socialist theory in order to
criticise the concept of formal equality. This liberal equality,
indeed, was a mere equality of opportunity deriving from
individuals’ negative rights. Regarding to feminist issues, it
only implied an equal treatment for all the people regardless
of their sex or gender. Unlike this liberal position, feminists
reframed the concept of equality in order to take one’s sex
into account. The category of “sexual difference” became
central within this framework, and feminists’ efforts reversed
the discriminatory use of sex by employing that category to
develop a broader concept of justice. First feminists harshly
criticised the reasoning of conservative people, who tried to
justify women’s submission to men through an analysis of
biological differences between the two sexes. On the one hand,
conservative people’s discriminatory intent was manifest.
Women were naturally inferior to men, so there was no
possibility for them to compete with their male counterparts.
On the other hand, that intent was hypocritically hidden.
Women were naturally weaker than men. They needed to be
protected and overwatched by men because of their inner
fragility. Therefore—conservative people argued—male
paternalism was not to be understood as male oppression;
on the contrary, such a system of protections and constraints
was established in women’s own interests. It was against this
double conservative perspective that first feminists stressed
formal equality between men and women. They did not
deny the set of biological differences naturally distinguishing
men from women. Still, they denied the relevance of these
differences with regard to any legal and political discourse.
They neutralised conservative people’s strategies by
preventing them from taking sexual differences into account.
Notwithstanding that, the insufficiency of formal equality led
feminists to reframe and improve their concept of equality
+LVWRULFDO3URFHVVDQG*HQGHU(VVHQWLDOLVPIURPD'LDOHFWLFDOв271
was never given once and for all. Against every metaphysical
definition of the “human essence”, Marx employed dialectics
to define a reflection taking account of the role of the historical
development without renouncing to the crucial element of
universality.
Strangely, it seems that Marx was not aware of his gradual
convergence with Hegel’s point of view. The interpretation
of Hegelian thought he inherited from Left Hegelians
conditioned his understanding of Hegel’s philosophy for his
whole life. Notwithstanding widespread misunderstandings,
indeed, Hegel never theorised a totalitarian philosophical
system in which all the particularities ended up being
absorbed by an oppressive universality. From his dialectic
perspective, the philosophical system—representing the
full self-comprehension of an age—was in a condition of
precarious balance. On the contrary, the concluded system
had to be reopened every time because of the historical
movement, and hence the philosophical reflection had to start
conceptualising reality over and over again. Therefore, Hegel
rejected metaphysical and pre-historical (hence, ahistorical)
definition of any essence too. In his 1820 Philosophy of Right,
for example, the universal idea of right was exposed in its
actual development since there was no possibility to separate
the essence of right from its historical evolution:
Die Rechtswissenschaft ist ein Teil der Philosophie. Sie hat
daher die Idee als welche die Vernunft eines Gegenstandes
ist, aus dem Begriffe zu entwickeln, oder, was dasselbe ist, der
eigenen immanenten Entwicklung der Sache selbst zuzusehen.
Als Teil hat sie einen bestimmten Anfangspunkt, welcher das
Resultat und die Wahrheit von dem ist, was vorhergeht, und
was den sogenannten Beweis desselben ausmacht. […] Der
Boden des Rechts ist überhaupt das Geistige, und seine nähere
Stelle und Ausgangspunkt der Wille, welcher frei ist, so daß die
Freiheit seine Substanz und Bestimmung ausmacht, und das
Rechtssystem das Reich der verwirklichten Freiheit, die Welt des
Geistes aus ihm selbst hervorgebracht, als eine zweite Natur, ist.
(Hegel 1911, 18, 27)
+LVWRULFDO3URFHVVDQG*HQGHU(VVHQWLDOLVPIURPD'LDOHFWLFDOв285
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Butler, J. (2002 [1999]). Gender Trouble. Feminism and the Subversion of
Identity, New York: Routledge.
Butler, (2014). “Gender Performance: The TransAdvocate interviews
Judith Butler” in The TransAdvocate, May 1, 2014. Source: http://
transadvocate.com/gender-performance-the-transadvocate
interviews-judith-butler_n_13652.htm
California Federal Savings and Loan Association v. Guerra (1985). 758 F.2d
Dardot, P., Laval, C. (2010). La nouvelle raison du monde. Essai sur la
société néolibérale, Paris : La Découverte.
Derrida, J. (2006 [1993]), Spectres of Marx. The State of the Debt, the
:RUNRI0RXUQLQJDQGWKH1HZ,QWHUQDWLRQDO trans. by P. Kamuf,
London: Routledge.
Fanon, F. (1952). Peau noire, masques blancs, Paris : Éditions du Seuil.
Fanon, F. (2002 [1961]). Les damnés de la terre, Paris : La Découverte.
Fineschi, R. (2001). Introduzione in Marx K., Il capitale. Critica
+LVWRULFDO3URFHVVDQG*HQGHU(VVHQWLDOLVPIURPD'LDOHFWLFDOв289
Social Reproduction
I
While contested opinion(s) on socialist experiences of the
twentieth century is all-pervasive, the academic literature
on this has been relatively thinly spread. The quantum of
views and opinions stand on a knowledge base that is narrow
and the ‘known’ far exceeds the ‘unknown’ in a literature
highly charged by ideological standpoints defined largely
by ‘ways of seeing’. The political economy focus has often
been on questions around the organisation of production
and productive forces—evaluations largely based on a
‘productivist’ paradigm. But, the reorganisation of social
reproduction way beyond the tenets of ZHOIDULVP had been
the greatest promise of revolutionary emancipation from
patriarchy and social oppression—i.e. from the tyranny of
family, private property and the state; and the conscious
political attempt of collectivism rather than individualism
forming the basis of new ‘individualities’ (Tomba 2013).
A radical transition from the capitalist system to socialism
is different from all previous social changes known in history
because it marks the beginning of an entirely different social
organisation—change from a class society to classless society.
This kind of paradigmatic change in human civilisation could
hardly have been peaceful and smooth. Similar episodes of
retrogression had happened when capitalism was replacing
5HYROXWLRQ(PDQFLSDWLRQDQG6RFLDO5HSURGXFWLRQв291
II
Our point of departure is rooted in two inter-connected
Marxist Feminist paradigmatic premises. First, patriarchy is
endogenous to the construct of the macroeconomy. The actual
macroeconomic construct of patriarchy within which the social
hierarchy of paid and unpaid labour operates is very much a
historical process in its social and economic specificity both
in terms of time and space. Thus the ahistorical abstraction
of homoeconomicus based market systems is inadequate in
its explanatory capacity either as point of entry or as a point
of departure in understanding/analysing attempted socialist
transitions.
Second, the transformative aspects of actually existing
296в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
that prevailed in the first few years after the revolution in the
USSR.
Alexandra Kollontai in 1921 outlined the problematic
“in the ‘hypocritical way’ in which ‘sexual problems’ were
relegated to the realm of ‘private matters’ that are not worth
the effort and attention of the collective”. At the same time, she
pointed to the ‘spontaneous wave of new attempts of living
developing from within the social fabric’. Thus Kollontai
captured the contradictions of property relationships, class
contradictions and individualistic morality that was the basis
of alienation even as the new society under the Bolsheviks
was trying to find ways of social organisation to address these
contradictions (Kollontai 2017). Leon Trotsky in 1923 in Pravda
formulated the contradictions emerging within the ‘comunist
family’ due to the larger transformations in the Soviet Union
in the first decade after the revolution. He argued that:
The physical preparations for the conditions of the new life and
the new family, again, cannot fundamentally be separated from
the general work of socialist construction. The workers’ state
must become wealthier in order that it may be possible seriously
to tackle the public education of children and the releasing of
the family from the burden of the kitchen and the laundry.
Socialisation of family housekeeping and public education of
children are unthinkable without a marked improvement in our
economics as a whole. We need more socialist economic forms.
Only under such conditions can we free the family from the
functions and cares that now oppress and disintegrate it. Washing
must be done by a public laundry, catering by a public restaurant,
sewing by a public workshop. Children must be educated by
good public teachers who have a real vocation for the work.
Then the bond between husband and wife would be freed from
everything external and accidental, and the one would cease to
absorb the life of the other. Genuine equality would at last be
established. The bond will depend on mutual attachment. And
on that account particularly, it will acquire inner stability, not
the same, of course, for everyone, but compulsory for no one.
Thus, the way to the new family is twofold: (a) the raising of
the standard of culture and education of the working class and
5HYROXWLRQ(PDQFLSDWLRQDQG6RFLDO5HSURGXFWLRQв301
REFERENCES
Bannerji, H., S. Mojab and J. Whitehead. 2001 (eds), Of Property
and Propriety: The Role of Gender and Class in Imperialism and
Nationalism, University of Toronto Press.
Bebel, A. 1910. Woman and Socialism https://www.marxists.org/
archive/bebel/1879/woman-socialism/index.htm Last
accessed on March 30, 2019.
Brown, H. 2013. Marx on Gender and the Family, Haymarket.
Croll, E.J. 1981. Women in Rural Production and Reproduction in the
Soviet Union, China, Cuba and Tanzania: Socialist Development
Experiences, Signs 7(1).
Davis, A.Y. 1981. Women, Race and Class, Random House, New York.
Dobb, M. 1969. :HOIDUH(FRQRPLFVDQGWKH(FRQRPLFVRI6RFLDOLVP7RZDUGV
a Commonsense Critique, Cambridge University Press.
Dong, Z. 2014. Mao Zedong and the Independent and Comprehensive
Industrial System and the Modernization of New China, World
5HYLHZRI3ROLWLFDO(FRQRP\5(4).
Dunayevskaya, R. 1944. A New Revision of Marxian Economics, 1944,
$PHULFDQ(FRQRPLF5HYLHZ 34(3).
Engels, F. 1880. Socialism: Utopian and Scientific https://www.
marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1880/soc-utop/index.htm
Last accessed on March 30, 2019.
Gendzier, I.L. 1985. Managing Political Change: Social Scientists and the
Third World, Westview Press 1985.
Goldman, W. 1993. Women, The State and Revolution: Soviet Family
3ROLF\, Cambridge University Press.
Hobsbawm, E. 1998. On History, Abacus 1998: 261.
Kollontai, A. 1909. The Social Basis of the Women’s Question, https://
www.marxists.org/archive/kollonta/1909/social-basis.htm
Last accessed on March 30, 2019.
Kollontai, A. 2017. ‘Sexual Relations and the Class Struggle’, in The
Soviet Women: Selected Essays, LeftWord.
Kollontai, A. 1929. Red Love, Seven Arts Publishing Co., New York.
Kollontai, A. 1929. A Great Love, The Vanguard Press, New York.
Kornai , J. 1979. ‘Resource Constrained versus Demand Constrained
Systems’, Ecoometrica, 47(4), pp. 801-819.
304в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Manufacturing Profits:
$UFKDQD$JJDUZDO
bottles, workers did not get enough time to even drink water.
The intensity of work had risen to such high levels that the
time needed to assemble one car had been contracted to 45
46 seconds which forced the workers to work at brutally high
speeds.
The auto vendor company has seen so much intensification
of work that accidents have become fairly common in this
factory. The workers attribute regular accidents to excessive
workload. The workers complain of being fatigued and
overworked and despite this, the production targets have been
going up continuously. For instance, a terminated worker from
VMC (Vertical Machine Control) said that within a span of 5
years, the production target in a single shift almost doubled
from 60 pieces to 110 pieces. And this was done without
changing the machines physically, simply by increasing the
speed of the machines.
In the garment industry, nearly 20 years ago, there
was a transition from a system of ‘full piece tailor’ wherein
each worker was responsible for making the garment in
its entirety, to ‘chain system’ or the assembly line where
each assembly line has many workers, each responsible for
cutting or stitching a small part of the garment. Supervisors
are deployed to ensure that workers meet rising production
targets. More recently, in order to supervise and increase the
work intensity in the garment industry, devices such as stop
watches and magnetic cards were adopted. According to the
workers, production targets had increased three fold within a
span of 5 years. Production targets have become so punishing
that when one worker collapsed on his seat in a factory of
Orient Craft Limited in 2014, other workers realised this only
after some time had elapsed as they did not have the time
to raise their heads from their sewing machines. The pace of
work is also enhanced by keeping a piece rate worker in the
same assembly line as a time rate worker. This ensures that the
piece rate worker, himself puts pressure on other workers to
work faster.
322в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
HQGV PHHW WKXV LQFUHDVLQJ WKH OHQJWK RI WKH ZRUNLQJ GD\. Even
with overtime, the workers in the garment industry were able
to earn merely Rs. 10,000 per month. The workers also face
arbitrary deduction in wages in many industries. In the units
of garment manufacturers in Gurgaon, a 10-minute delay can
lead to deduction of one hour’s wages.
The wages are much lower than the figure of Rs. 18,000
calculated by India’s 7th Central Pay Commission as a need-
based minimum wage (NBMW) for the ORZHVWranked staff in
government (RUPE 2018).8 In fact, if we look at the garment
sector in particular, even with both husband and wife working,
the family wage turns out to be less than this figure. These
low wages have also been falling in real terms. This can be
exemplified by looking at the basic pay of sampling tailors in
the garment industry. The following chart is based on payslips
of the workers and Labour Bureau Statistics.
The fact that workers are not even paid the value of labour
power is evident from the fact that they need to supplement
their incomes through multiple sources. In the garment sector,
most of the workers are unable to get their families to live
with them. Also a large majority of the workers get rations
from their native villages. These can be regarded as ‘reverse
remittances’ from the agricultural sector. The workers of phone
manufacturer of Greater Noida choose to commute from their
native villages, which may be as far as 80 kilometres, in order
to save on the living costs by renting a place near the factory.
Thus for the worker households, who have migrated from the
villages, rural connections are retained as a ‘second base of
material provision in the city’ (Aspects of Indian Economy, Nos.
71&72). A portion of consumption of the worker household
is met from the agrarian sector, whether it is in the form of
sustenance of a part of the family in the village or procuring
326в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
NOTES
1. A cluster is defined as an area with a radius of 60 kms with more
than 100 units in related and complementary business (UNIDO).
2. The names of most of the companies are being withheld on
purpose. The interviews with the workers have been conducted
by the author along with voluntary groups such as ‘Perspectives’
and ‘People's Union for Democratic Rights’ over a period of
last five years. Some of the case studies have been published as
booklets.
3. The details of the situation in this plant is given in Section II
along with the analysis.
4. Based on Simmering Rage (Aggarwal, A. 2015) and Tailor–Made
0DQXIDFWXULQJ3URILWVв331
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Aggarwal, A. (2015). ‘Piece by Piece’, Himal Sothasian, Labour and its
Discontents, March 2015.
Apex Cluster Development Services Pvt. Ltd. (2015), ‘Final Report
Economic Profile of NCR’, Submitted to National Capital Region
Planning Board.
Bose, A.J.C. and Pratap, S. (2016). ‘Value Chains and Worker Illfare:
Some Comments’, Business Analyst.
Gereffi, G. and Memedovic, O. (2003). ‘The Global Apparel Value
Chain: What Prospects for Upgrading by Developing Countries?’
United Nations Industrial Development Organisation.
Gupta, A. and Choudhury, S. (2016). ‘Global Value Chains: Indian
Automobile Industry’, &&60LGWHUP5HSRUW
Heinrich, M. (2012). An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s
Capital, Monthly Review Press 2012; Indian edition, Aakar
Books, 2013.
Humphrey, J. and Memedovic, O. (2003). ‘The Global Automotive
Industry Value Chain’, UNIDO, Strategic Research and
Economics Branch.
Mezzadri, A. and Srivastava, R. (2015). ‘Labour Regimes in the Indian
Garment Sector: Capital-Labour Relations, Social Reproduction
and Labour Standards in the National Capital Region’, Centre
for Development Policy and Research.
People’s Union for Democratic Rights: Various reports on Maruti
(2001, 2007, 2013 and 2018).
Perspectives, People’s Union for Democratic Rights (May 2015):
‘Tailor-Made Lives’.
332в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Research Unit for Political Economy (2012). ‘Behind the Present Wave
of Unrest in the Auto Sector’, $VSHFWVRI,QGLD·V(FRQRP\1R
http://www.rupe-india.org/52/auto.html#note1.
Research Unit for Political Economy (2018), ‘India’s Working Class
and Its Prospects Part I’, Aspects of India’s Economy, Nos. 71 & 72.
Smith, J. (2015). ‘ Imperialism in the Twenty-First Century’, Monthly
5HYLHZVol. 67, Issue 03 (July-August, 2015).
Sutton, J. ‘The Globalization Process: Auto-Component Supply
Chains in China and India,’ Project Report (London School of
Economics).
12
Giulietto Chiesa
Marx was familiar with the history and culture of India. Who
knows if he read the famous travel book written by Ludovico
de Varthema in the 16th century. But he was, like many other
German students of his time, certainly familiar with Sacred text
like the Upanishads, already quoted by the famous philosopher,
Arthur Schopenhauer, in his 1818 preface to the first edition of
Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung. It was not just India’s history
and culture that he knew of, but also its economic situation.
His studies were focused on the development of the British
imperial system in Europe and Asia.
In an article published in the 1HZ<RUN+HUDOG7ULEXQH (on
June 25, 1853), three years before the beginning of the second
opium war, he describes the country as: “An Italy of Asiatic
dimensions. The same rich variety in the products of the soil,
and the same dismemberment in the political configuration”.
A country “which the British, dissolved into as many
independent and conflicting states as it numbered towns, or
even villages”.
“A world”, he adds, “dominated by the religion of the
lingam and juggernaut; the religion of the monk, and of the
bayadere”.
“The misery inflicted by the British on Hindustan” was for
him very different and intensive, because England had broken
down the entire framework of Indian society.
The British in the East had neglected the public works
provoking “the deterioration of an agriculture which is not
346в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
NOTES
1. And also in Das Kapital he observes that England “sends silver
to India, and buys opium … all of which goes to China to lay
down funds to purchase the silk”.
2. Dona Toor in 1951 (London) collected a selection of Marx’s
articles written in the 1HZ <RUN 'DLO\ 7ULEXQH on the war in a
book entitled 0DU[RQ&KLQD.
14
Against Wisdom
-HDQ-RVHSK%RLOORW
Introduction
Marxism, a criticism of nascent capitalism, has long
established itself as the hegemonic alternative system of
thought in revolutionary movements. It has clearly forced
capitalism to adapt and it has channelled a large number
of national liberation struggles into the world, including
China and Africa, where it has long represented the only real
alternative to the domination of the Western world.
But certain theoretical weaknesses of the Marxist system,
its quick evolution into ideology, even into religion for the
Orthodox Marxist movement, transformed the utopian project
of Marxist communism into a true 20th century dystopia and
marginalised Karl Marx’s thought as rational thought and
political project.
Understanding Marx’s thought trajectory, his theoretical
and practical weaknesses as well as his strengths are far from
being useless scientific work. Time has done its work and the
dispassionate critique of Marxist thought and its utopia can
usefully contribute to increasing the wisdom of the world in
the search for more humane economies, more just societies
and better harmony among humans and with nature.
0DU[RU8WRSLDDQG,GHRORJ\$JDLQVW:LVGRPв353
of political and social events all over the world, Marx himself,
however, testified to a finesse of practical analysis that goes
far beyond the dialectical materialist philosophy of history.
1.2.2. Marx as an economist and political scientist is
better known. In these two economic and political fields,
Marx’s essential ideas can be summarised with five thesis
as suggested by Erik Olin Wright (2010) in his seminal book
Envisioning Real Utopias”.
Thesis 1: The long-term unsustainability of capitalism
under the effect of its own internal contradictions and in
particular the law of falling rate of profit. Yet the obsession
with his “labour theory of value”, actually originating from
the English Classical School theorists such as Adam Smith or
David Ricardo, has led economic Marxism into a deadlock: not
seeing capitalist competition as the very spur of innovation,
of permanent revolution in production methods as well as in
modes of consumption and commercial exchange, including
in the financial sphere, to the point that profit rates have
never been as high as they are today, for example. Moreover,
Karl Marx himself demonstrates in certain texts that with
machinism and technology, the creation of wealth depends
less on work than on the mechanical power associated with
the general scientific and technological level, what is called
the “general intellect” hypothesis which would invalidate
the whole theory of labour value at the heart of Marxism for
decades and thus the theory of exploitation which is associated
with the historical role of the proletariat.
That crises, then, are intimately linked to capitalism
is not false in itself, but all forms of production have also
experienced economic crises, including in Antiquity. And the
French Marxist School of Regulation has shown precisely how
capitalism has learned to regulate itself and to adapt to the
specific conditions of each country more or less willingly or
forcefully. The paradox of Marxism is that it may have allowed
capitalism, under the pressure of its critics, to constantly
adapt, whether defensively or offensively.
Thesis 2: Intensification of the anti-capitalist class struggle
0DU[RU8WRSLDDQG,GHRORJ\$JDLQVW:LVGRPв355
often used to describe in detail the ideal city of More and most
social reformers. In fact, it would have been to his advantage
to focus and analyse in detail the political, social and economic
organisation proposed since they actually almost always bore
totalitarian visions in terms of freedom, were frugal to the
extreme and without proper History. He would have seen then
that they were not only unrealistic but leading to “dystopia”,
i.e. the transformation of an ideal into a dark world, even a
human nightmare.
On the contrary, Marx’s critic of utopias focused on the
socialist visions of Saint-Simon, Fourier, Lasalle, Owen, and
others, including his own son-in-law Joseph Proudhon, all of
whom were treated rather harshly, notably in a famous book
signed by Engels, as “utopian socialists” as opposed to the
“scientific socialism” attributed to Marx. These great social
reformers of the 19th century were accused by Marx and Engels
of proposing “immature theoretical forms compared to the
degree of development of the proletariat and the productive
forces”. They were also accused of pursuing “chimeras” such
as the projects of “Phalansteres” or worker cooperatives, while
“scientific socialism” was predicting the collapse of capitalism
and therefore the priority to organise the proletariat with a
view to its overthrow by revolution. For the rest, in fact, Marx
was content with a vague goal that was communism without
property, without class and without state.
In doing so, Marx fell into the same traps as idealistic
utopia with its two principles: “Want is power”, implying,
everything is possible; and “Necessity is the mother of
invention”, implying, solutions will always be found.
2.3. From Utopia to Dystopia
The paradox of economists is that we owe the description of
the mechanisms of this dystopic metamorphosis to two great
writers: George Orwell and Aldous Huxley.
2.3.1 The “Animal Farm” Model
On the revolutionary rupture envisaged by Marx, George
362в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
dramatically.
Less commented upon, the case of India is also instructive.
The Indian experience is a kind of attempt by Jawaharlal Nehru
of a synthesis inspired by English reformist fabianism between
a democratic political system avoiding totalitarian drift and
a Marxist-style economic model, notably on the pattern of
planification and socialist accumulation. The development
strategy set out in the early 1950s by the Planning Commission
led by the USSR inspired Marxist economist, P.C. Mahalabonis,
turns out in reality to be a significant failure since the growth
rate would not exceed 4 per cent during the First Plan of 1951
1956 and hardly more than 4 per cent during the Second Plan
between 1956 and 1961. After the 1962 war against China,
India entered an infernal spiral of agricultural and balance of
payment crises so that its average post-independence growth
rate—nicknamed the ‘Hindu rate of growth’—was barely
higher than population growth till the early 1980s. India owes
its democratic political model to the exiting impasses of the
Marxist economic model without too many difficulties, even
if the transition lasted almost twenty years, which include the
meanderings of Indira Gandhi during her State of Emergency
from 1975 to 1977, recalling the prognostics of George Orwell
on the totalitarian drifts in this kind of situation where the
ideal deviates too much from the realities and the intensive
use of scapegoats to explain the failure of its own policy.
2.3.2 China and the “Brave New World”
One could say however: what about Post-Mao China? His
resounding success since the pragmatic turn of 1978 could
well constitute a tangible proof of the relevance of Marx’s
theories concerning the Revolution and the transition phase
from socialism to communism, this time well conducted after
several unfortunate but ultimately acceptable experiments
under any experience curve.
(a) On the one hand, the Chinese revolution was a success
in the sense of the overthrow of the ancient feudal-capitalist
order by a communist party inspired by Marx’s thought. But
364в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ
Under Bourgeoisdom
C. Saratchand
1. Introduction
Traditional statements of historical materialism such as (Lange,
1963) are couched in terms of Marxist concepts of productive
forces, production relations, mode of production, exploitation
(private appropriation of surplus labour), etc. However it has
long been recognised that historical materialism has to deal
with phenomena such as gender, race, caste, communalism,
etc., in other words with social oppression (Callinicos, 2002).
The relation between exploitation and oppression is the
subject of this paper.
It is proposed that social oppression is associated
with heterogeneity within social classes1 besides struggle
between classes. Marxist writing often recognised the
heterogeneity amongst the bourgeoisie. For instance (Patnaik,
Chandrasekhar, and Sen, 1996; Patnaik, Chandrasekhar, and
Ghosh, 2004), argued that there were two processes at play here
namely, monopolisation and proliferation of the bourgeoisie.
Monopolisation involves centralisation and concentration of
capital. Proliferation involves the process through which new
entrants make it into the ranks of the bourgeoisie.2 The role of
caste, gender, race, communalism, etc. in these processes has
been significant since they were associated, for instance, with
contradictions between different sections of the bourgeoisie.
([SORLWDWLRQDQG2SSUHVVLRQ8QGHU%RXUJHRLVGRPв373
the proletariat and have brought with them into the working
class their customs, their habits, their waverings and their
vacillations. This stratum constitutes the most favourable
soil for all sorts of anarchist, semi-anarchist and ‘ultra-Left’
groups...The third stratum, lastly, consists of the labour
aristocracy, the upper stratum of the working class, the most
well-to-do portion of the proletariat, with its propensity for
compromise with the bourgeoisie, its predominant inclination
to adapt itself to the powers that be, and its anxiety to “get on
in life.” This stratum constitutes the most favourable soil for
outright reformists and opportunists.”
Postponing commentary about the first and third stratum
(as well as on this formulation as such) to the later sections
of this paper, it may be pointed out that the existence of the
second stratum of the proletariat presupposes the existence
of other modes of production. But it cannot be ruled out that
the persistence of other modes of production is only a matter
of time if the capitalist mode of production has a tendency
to eliminate other modes of production. But (Patnaik, 2009)
points out that the historical experience has demonstrated
that: “While retaining the concept of the mode of production,
however, we must recognise that the capitalist mode of
production is always located within a cluster, surrounded
by pre-capitalist modes of production that are hegemonised
but are nonetheless very clearly extant and by no means
obliterated.” The implications of this argument are examined
later but it is proposed that social oppression is also associated
with the existence of different modes of production.
The rest of this paper is organised as follows: Section 2
examines the implications of unequal rates of exploitation
for historical materialism, Section 3 examines the relations
between the mode of production and the social formation with
special reference to the phenomenon of social oppression.
Section 4 seeks to tie together the arguments of Sections 2 and
3 while Section 5 concludes the paper.
([SORLWDWLRQDQG2SSUHVVLRQ8QGHU%RXUJHRLVGRPв375
its own grave-diggers. Its fall and the victory of the proletariat
are equally inevitable.”
However the revolutionary combination due to association
of the proletariat, i.e. the formation of the revolutionary
proletariat is not spontaneously accomplished by
bourgeoisdom.
When (Stalin, 1953 [1926]) discussed the three strata
amongst the working class, the first he said “is the main mass
of the proletariat, its core, its permanent part, the mass of ‘pure
blooded’ proletarians, who have long broken off connection
with the capitalist class. This stratum of the proletariat is
the most reliable bulwark of Marxism.” This section of the
proletariat, i.e. the revolutionary proletariat, as mentioned
before, is not produced by bourgeoisdom. The revolutionary
proletariat constitutes itself through an authentic democratic
social process of struggle that can combat exploitation and
oppression under bourgeoisdom.
Without combating oppression and exploitation in its
struggles the revolutionary proletariat cannot come into
existence. Since exploitation and oppression are linked
under bourgeoisdom it is not possible to combat one while
disregarding the other.27 Likewise an inability to sustain the
combined struggle against oppression and exploitation will
result in an unravelling of the revolutionary proletariat.
A successful transcending of bourgeoisdom may be more
complex than previously conceived (due to factors such as
those discussed in this paper), but the struggle for it remains
historically relevant and significant.
5. Conclusion
This paper has been concerned with setting out in outline a
framework to examine the relation between oppression and
exploitation under bourgeoisdom. Two factors have been
identified in this regard, namely unequal rates of exploitation
of different types of workers and the coexistence of different
modes of production with one dominant mode of production
([SORLWDWLRQDQG2SSUHVVLRQ8QGHU%RXUJHRLVGRPв389
NOTES
1. (Lenin, 1974 [1919]) had asserted that: “Classes are large groups
of people differing from each other by the place they occupy
in a historically determined system of social production, by
their relation (in most cases fixed and formulated in law) to
the means of production, by their role in the social organisation
of labour, and, consequently, by the dimensions of the share of
social wealth of which they dispose and the mode of acquiring
it. Classes are groups of people one of which can appropriate
the labour of another owing to the different places they occupy
in a definite system of social economy.”
2. (Damodaran, 2008) examines this process in the Indian context.
(Patnaik, Chandrasekhar, and Ghosh, 2004) seeks to explain
the role of the Indian bourgeoisie in the transition from a
dirigiste regime to a neoliberal set up wherein changes in the
monopolisation and proliferation of the bourgeoisie play a key
role.
3. An equal rate of exploitation of all workers is one aspect of a
homogeneous proletariat.
4. Further it may be noted that Marx has discussed the case of
unequal rates of surplus value in one of his manuscripts which
is contained in (Marx, 2012 [1863-68]).
5. A mathematical statement of the implications of unequal rates
of exploitation will be examined in subsequent work.
6. However (Wolpe, 1986) goes on to add that “...it also does not
follow that because race, under certain conditions, may be
interiorised in the class struggle, all conflicts which centre on
race are, therefore, to be conceived of as class struggles. On the
contrary, it will be argued that struggles focusing on race may
take on a form in which class is not interiorised within them.”
Thus the interaction between exploitation and oppression in
each case must be concretely examined.
7. (Kotz, 1994) advances a mathematical model of the relation
between wage labour and family labour.
8. Excessive price volatility may hamper the ability of the state to
sustain a system of commodity money.
9. There remains one other related issue that needs to be addressed.
It has been argued that values (or value magnitudes) are
irrelevant to the process of determination of the general rate of
profit and prices of production (Steedman, 1977). However if
there exists at least one section of workers whose real wage can
([SORLWDWLRQDQG2SSUHVVLRQ8QGHU%RXUJHRLVGRPв391
REFERENCES
Althusser, Louis (2014 [1969]). On the Reproduction of Capitalism:
Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses. Originally written in
1969 and revised thereafter. First published in 1995 in French.
Verso Books.
Banaji, Jairus (2012). “Mode of Production”. In: The Elgar Companion
to Marxist Economics. Ed. by Ben Fine, Alfredo Saad-Filho, and
Marco Boffo. Edward Elgar Publishing, pp. 227–232.
Banerjee, Diptendra, ed. (1985). Marxian Theory and the Third World.
Sage Publications Pvt. Ltd.
Bannerji, Himani (2005). “Building from Marx: Reflections on Class
and Race”. In: Social Justice 32.4, 102, pp. 144–160.
Bhattacharya, Tithi, ed. (2017). Social Reproduction Theory: Remapping
Class, Recentering Oppression. Pluto Press.
396в3URELQJVDQG5H3URELQJV(VVD\VLQ0DU[LDQ5HDZDNHQLQJ