Art, Self and Knowledge - Keith Lehrer
Art, Self and Knowledge - Keith Lehrer
Art, Self and Knowledge - Keith Lehrer
1
1
Oxford University Press
Oxford University Press, Inc., publishes works that further
Oxford University’s objective of excellence
in research, scholarship, and education.
Oxford New York
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2
Printed in the United States of America
on acid-free paper
To Adrienne, who ties my art, self, and knowledge together in the loop of her love.
This page intentionally left blank
CON T E N T S
Introduction 3
1. Knowing the Content of Art 9
2. Consciousness, Exemplars, and Art 31
3. Aesthetic Theory, Feminist Art, and Autonomy 47
4. Value, Expression, and Globalization 59
5. Artistic Creation, Freedom, and Self 75
6. Aesthetics, Death, and Beauty 101
7. Aesthetic Experience, Intentionality, and the Form of
Representation 111
8. Theories of Art, and Art as Theory of the World 127
9. Self-Trust, Disagreement, and Reasonable Acceptance 145
10. Social Reason, Aggregation, and Collective Wisdom 159
11. Knowledge, Autonomy, and Art in Loop Theory 173
References 197
Name Index 203
Subject Index 207
This page intentionally left blank
PR EFAC E: W EBSI T E INF OR M AT ION ,
S U M M A RY, A N D ACK NO W L E D G M E N T S
Images referred to in this book in the form of [Web ASK XX] will be found
with supplementary information for the text by linking to website: http://
sites.google.com/site/artselfandknowledge/.
SUMMARY
This began as a book about art and aesthetics as a local area of philosophical
interest. I began, as does the book, with aesthetic experience directed toward
sensory experience and what it is like. The difference between ordinary per-
ception and aesthetic experience has been often noted, but the implications
stand in need of philosophical articulation. Aesthetic attention to sensory
detail not only contrasts with ordinary perceptual experience, it blocks it.
We surpass the more customary representational response. We experience a
form of representational autonomy in how we use the sensory materials to
mark distinctions in conceptual space reconfiguring experience itself. The
sensory experience becomes an exemplar used to mark those distinctions
creating meaning and content, both cognitive and affective. I began with the
idea that this use of the exemplar, exemplarizing, is central to the experience
of art. I concluded that it is central to our conception of our world, including
the world described by science, and ourselves in our world. The under-
standing of aesthetic experience shows us ourselves as autonomous agents
exemplarizing experience to represent our world, ourselves, our world in
ourselves, and ourselves in our world. The exemplars of experience connect
art and science, the internal and the external, the mind and body. They are
Janus faced and show us what the represented object is like at the same time
that they show us how we represent in a way that cannot be fully described.
We exemplarize experience to mentalize body and materialize mentality.
As I created the work, I found myself, an analytic philosopher, appreci-
ating the contributions of such diverse figures as Goodman and Heidegger,
(x) Preface: Website Information, Summary, Acknowledgments
Weitz and Derrida, to mention a pair of odd couples advancing similar views
with a diversity of style. Moreover, under the influence of Peggy Zeglin
Brand, I came to view feminist art as a paradigm of art and what art does and
can do, and I thank her for that influence as well as for the editing work she
did on an earlier version of Chapter 3. Under the influence of Dom Lopes,
Otavio Bueno, and Nola Semczyszyn, I came to appreciate the similarity
between the function of scientific representation and artistic representation
in the construction of theories of our world. My book is intended to crash
the barriers between the discourse of analytic philosophy and continental
philosophy, as well as between science and art, without denying or depreci-
ating the difference. Michelangelo’s Sistine Chapel and Serrano’s Piss Christ,
are both religious art, even if very different. One directs attention to the sep-
arate glory of God and the other to the embodiment of God. To understand
the teaching of Christianity, perhaps you need both.
As I came to the close of the writing of the book, I confronted the issue
of how to connect the reader with images of artworks to which I referred.
My first thought was to reproduce them in the book. I decided instead to
connect the reader with a website containing easy access to the works. I
had two reasons. The first is connected with the theory of the book
concerning the way in which the particular experience of an artwork
functions as an exemplar representation and content thereof in response
to aesthetic attention. The problem with reproductions is that aesthetic
attention to them is different from aesthetic attention to the artwork dis-
cussed and, by the theory I advance, has a different content and meaning
than an exemplar representation of the artwork. For the theory affirms
that the experience of the exemplar is a constituent of the content of the
exemplar representation. So a different exemplar of experience gives you
a different content. So what could I do? I decided that the image of the
artwork on a computer screen takes you closer to the experience of the
original than a printed reproduction no matter how entrenched the use of
such printed images are in art history books. Better than nothing to expe-
rience, perhaps, quicker to access, surely, yet lacking the vivacity of the
original, certainly. I do not claim that the computer images I direct the
reader to on the website I supply are anything close to exact replications
of the original. Some of you will have large brilliant display screens that
captivate and focus your attention. That matters.
SCHOLARLY ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I wish to acknowledge the help that I have received. I wish to thank the Center
for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, Stanford University, for award-
ing me a fellowship to work on this project. I also wish to thank John Hospers
Preface: Website Information, Summary, Acknowledgments ( xi )
ACKNOWLEDGED PERMISSIONS
1. Keith Lehrer, “What Intentionality Is Like,” Acta Analytica 26, 2011, (1)
3–14.
2. Keith Lehrer, “Self-Trust and Social Truth,” in a volume, Self-Evaluation,
Anita Konzelmann, Keith Lehrer, and Bernard Schmid eds., PSSP Series
Springer, 2011, 119–134.
( xii ) Preface: Website Information, Summary, Acknowledgments
T his book concerns the role of art in human experience. The method of
the book is intended to break down walls of philosophical and intellec-
tual oppositions between analytical and continental traditions and between
art and science. Human experience transcends these divisions and unifies
them. Dewey (1934) saw art as making a special contribution to human
experience rather than standing in splendid isolation from it. He is not
alone. Goodman (1968), a leading analytic philosopher, and Heidegger
(1971), a leading existentialist, writing in different ways in opposing tradi-
tions thought that art reveals a special contribution to the world-making
experience of the artist and the receivers of the artwork.
I stand with these philosophers in opposition to many theories of aes-
thetics that search for what separates art from the world outside of art, the-
ories of art as representation, as beauty, as significant form, as expression,
even as deconstruction. I do not deny that art is representational, that it
may contain significant form giving rise to a special emotion, that it may be
expressive of a wide range of human feelings, or that it may deconstruct
previous artworks, removing them from their frames to assemble something
new. My objection is not that art does not do these things. There is some art
that does each of them. But not all art does these things, and not only art
does them. So what is the special contribution that art makes to experience
that contributes to human life? Art uses sensory consciousness as the focus
of attention to create new form and content out of exemplars of experience.
We value art because of the new content it offers to us in our lives. Moreover,
and perhaps most importantly, we are provoked to ask ourselves whether to
transfer the content of the artwork to our world and ourselves beyond the
artwork. When we ask that question, we experience our conceptual
(3)
(4) Art, Self and Knowledge
day. And that is only the beginning of how we can use the color blue. The
exemplar is given. The interpretation is taken from the exemplar as we mark
conceptual space to define content. We confront our autonomy as creators
of form and content as we think about the blue.
Take another example, L’Origine du Monde, a painting by Courbet [Web
ASK 2]. It is a painting of a female sex organ. It confronts us in the Musée
d’Orsay. It says, “Look!” Try not to. You will fail. But what then? Prurient
interest is blocked by the confrontation. It is not a pornographic experi-
ence, however accurate the representation. There is a sensory confronta-
tion and interrogation. What does it mean? That confrontation and
interrogation lead to the experience of it as art. You interpret it. Carolee
Schneemann in her later feminist work, Interior Scroll, shows us how [Web
ASK 3]. We do not fall from heaven, we fall from there. All of us. The origin
of our life, of our world. It must be sacred. We hide from the sacred biology
of our origin. “Not from there please.” “Yes, from there.” The sensory expe-
rience marks the content of the origin of us all. That is art. So, what does
art do? It chats with us on the edge of experience (Hein, 1993). The chap-
ters on art and feminism: “Aesthetic Theory, Feminist Art, and Autonomy”
(Chapter 3); art and death: “Aesthetics, Death, and Beauty” (Chapter 6);
and art and globalization: “Value, Expression, and Globalization” (Chapter
4) show us how to use art to extend the reach of sense into the making of a
world.
We loop back onto our experience to construct a story of ourselves in
our world and note the connection with freedom as Fischer’s (2009) work
tells us. Chapter 5, “Artistic Creation, Freedom, and Self,” is an attempt to
explain how our conception of ourselves arises from the exemplarization of
experience. As the representation of the self loops back onto itself exem-
plarizing the experience of a life, the self becomes unified in the story of a
life. The ownership of the components of the self is explained by a choice,
an ownership choice that expresses the freedom of the self to choose what
experiences to exemplarize into the story of itself by itself.
Art reaches into philosophy to show us something about what our world
is like beyond what can be said. In Chapter 7, “Aesthetic Experience,
Intentionality, and the Form of Representation,” which focuses on inten-
tionality, we turn to art to show us what intentionality and representation
are like as we exemplarize experience. When we use the sensory exemplar
as the term of representation, we take it as an exhibit of what the repre-
sented objects are like. We know what the exemplar itself is like from the
exemplarization of it, but we may take it, at the same time, as an exhibit of
how we represent what those objects are like. The exemplar, when we focus
our attention upon it in aesthetic experience is Janus-faced, showing us in
one direction, what is represented, and, in the other, showing us how we
INTRODUCTION (7)
(9)
( 10 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
I now want to explain how we can know what the content of the work of
art is like. My explanation is that the experience of the work of art results in
representation that uses the experience of the work of art as an exemplar to
stand for a class of experiences of which it is a member. The process is
something that might be called exemplar representation. It differs from other
forms of representation, verbal representation, for example, because the
exemplar, rather than a word, is the term or vehicle of representation. The
exemplar is used to represent a class of objects that is distinguished from
others. It stands for the objects it represents as a predicate. However, unlike
a predicate, it is, at the same time, one of the objects represented, and
functions to exhibit or show us what the represented objects are like. I call
the process of exemplar representation, using an exemplar to represent a
class of objects, exemplarization (Lehrer, 1997). Exemplarization yields a
representation of content in terms of an experienced particular that stands
for other particulars. Exemplarization involves the generalization of a
particular.
The notion of exemplarization stems most directly from the empiricist
tradition most closely related to Hume (1739) and Reid (1785). However,
it has a connection with Plato, who thought of the forms as something like
an exemplar, a standard of the objects that exemplify it. The exemplar rep-
resenting itself and other things that are like it goes back to Plato as
Brickhouse and Smith (1983) note. However, the exemplar on the theory
I am proposing is not some separate eternal and immutable form. It is the
experience itself used as an exemplar or standard to stand for experiences.
This use dispenses with the metaphysics of separation, though the relation
between exemplar and what it stands for is suggested by the relation bet-
ween the form and what it stands for. The exemplar is an individual experi-
ence used as a standard, however, and not a universal separate from
experience.
The special form of representation that yields knowledge of what the work
of art is like, exemplarization, explains the somewhat puzzling features of
representation of a work of art. Description of the content of a work in lan-
guage, though providing useful information for many purposes, seems to
leave out something essential to what a work of art is like. This leads philos-
ophers to say that the content of a work of art, even a representational
painting, is ultimately ineffable. There is a point to speaking about the inef-
fability of the content of a work of art—of a painting, for example—but it
leads to a paradox when one adds that the ineffable content can be known
K N O W I N G T H E C O N T E N T OF A R T ( 11 )
to an observer and appreciated many times over as being the same content.
How can the content be known and recognized repeatedly and be
ineffable?
A related issue concerns the particularity of the content. There are many
paintings of Venus, and someone may observe that the Titian painting of
Venus [Web ASK 4] is a member of the class of Venus paintings. But to
know what the Titian painting is like, it is not sufficient for the purpose of
aesthetic appreciation to know that it is a Venus painting. One must know
what the particular content of the painting is like to appreciate it aestheti-
cally or even to know fully what it is like. It is what this painting is like in the
full particularity of the experience of it that is required for aesthetic appre-
ciation. This appreciation rests on a special particularized knowledge of
what this Venus painting is like. Moreover, the particularity of the content
is not captured by distinguishing between digital and analogue representa-
tions as Goodman (1968) proposed. Digital and analogue representation,
however detailed they may be, still fail to explain the particularity of the
content of the work of art. The distinction between digital and analogue
representation can mark the distinction between a representation of a
species and that of an infima species, but an infima species, even if it has only
one member, is still different from the one member. The member is a
particular, and the species is general no matter how determinate it might be.
If the content is particular, then knowledge of what the content is like must
also be knowledge of the particular in that content. Knowledge of the
particular content is based on representation that gives the particular a role
in the representation. This observation, however natural and plausible, also
leads to a paradox or, at least, a puzzle. For the content of the painting is
something that can be repeatedly experienced. The repetition involves dif-
ferent particular experiences, however similar the experiences might be to
one another. The common content of the different particular experiences
seems to require both that the representation of the content, as well as the
content represented, be both particular and general at the same time. But
how can the representation and the content itself be both particular and
general? How can our knowledge of the content be both knowledge of what
something is like as a particular and, at the same, knowledge of something
common to a class of particulars?
Another problem concerns art and representation. Suppose the content
of a work is similar to the content of the perception of identifiable objects.
It might enable one to recognize some perceived object from the content of
the painting, as Lopes (1996) suggests. As a result, we might hope to char-
acterize or explain the character of the content in terms of its relationship to
the perceived object. However, the content of a painting may be expres-
sionistic and not enable one to identify any perceived object. Or the artist
( 12 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
the void, or of color in the void, or of emotion and feeling in color. We seek
meaning in experience, including the experience of art, and, seeking
meaning, we find it by creating it. A painting created by an artist seeking to
present the possibility of art without content will probably fail to present a
work without content to most observers. The observer searching to find the
content of the work may, if they find nothing, conceive the content of work
paradoxically to be a work about lacking content. What it represents to
them is a work without content, and, paradoxically, it will be about content-
lessness. Contentlessness becomes content. The reason is that we create
content by marking a distinction, as Spencer-Brown (1969) suggested, and
which we shall study later. You mark a distinction between the painting, the
one without content, and other paintings, those of a person, for example.
What is contained in the marked space of experience, the contentlessness,
is the content. There is a content of contentlessness marked in experience.
The content of contentlessness can be exhilarating in the expression of free-
dom or saddening for the nullification of the figurative.
The foregoing remarks might suggest that the enhancement of the con-
ception of content by means of exemplarization is a simple addition of
one kind of content to another. That may be wrong. The enhancement
that results from exemplarization is an alteration that may change the
functional aspects of the conception of content in more complicated ways
than the simple addition of a means of identifying the painting. One may
realize when one observes the painting that one has changed one’s con-
ception of the House of Seven Gables in negative as well as positive ways.
The positive aspect is that the subject has a new way of identifying partic-
ulars, particular experiences of the painting and the house, and so gains
knowledge of how to identify them. But that is not all there is to the
matter. The exemplarization of the particular experience does enable us
to identify further experiences of the painting and the house, but it does
this by converting the exemplarized particular into a sign that both repre-
sents particular experiences and exhibits what they are like. Thus, the
enhanced conception requires an accommodation of one sign, a word, to
another sign, a sensory experience, and the accommodation may involve
more complicated changes in the content or meaning of the word or
descriptive expression.
Consider the person viewing the painting of the House of Seven Gables
after reading about the house, first in Hawthorne, and then in a book about
historical buildings. One might have a definite conception of the house and
what it looks like as a result of imagining a house that fulfills the descrip-
tion. The imagined house based solely on descriptive discourse may have a
functional role in the conception of the house. Now suppose the person
views the painting and exemplarizes the sensory experience to obtain a
sensory conception of the content of it. The sensory conception—that is,
the exemplarized conception—may give the person a conception of the
House of Seven Gables that conflicts with the descriptive content and,
especially, with how the person imagined the house from the description.
Moreover, the person may now choose to alter the functional role of
the descriptive conception enhanced by imagination to accommodate the
sensory conception as a replacement for how the person imagined the
house based on the description. Or, on the contrary, the person may refuse
to alter the antecedent conception of the House of Seven Gables to accom-
modate the sensory content of the painting. Notice, moreover, that the
same problem would arise with a photograph of the house. The person may
be more inclined to accommodate the sensory experience resulting from
exemplarizing a photograph, but, since photographs of the house at differ-
ent times and under different conditions may vary greatly, the same issue
arises, namely, of what role to give to the sensory concept, if any, in the
amendment of the descriptive conception. Indeed, the same problem arises
( 20 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
from actually seeing the house itself as it now appears and exemplarizing
that sensory experience.
The point can be formulated in a way suggested by the excellent account
that Lopes (1996) gives us of the way in which representation is related to
the ability to recognize the external object represented. A change in con-
ception that incorporates the exemplarized experience as a dominant com-
ponent for identifying or recognizing the object represented in the painting
may require rejection of preconceptions of what the sensory experience of
the painting would be like. So the sensory conception resulting from exem-
plarization might require a negative amendment of the antecedent concep-
tion to accommodate the functional role of the sensory experience. In
earlier work, Lehrer and Lehrer (1995) proposed a theory of word meaning
that took the various factors influencing the meaning of words to be vectors
that are mathematically aggregated to obtain meaning. A similar notion of
content as the aggregation of innate, personal, and social influences will
explain the process of generalization and accommodation in the use of
exemplarization.
Notice that the problem becomes more interesting when the question
arises of how one might modify one’s conception of the actual House of
Seven Gables in Salem—for it still exists—as a result of observing a painting
of the House of Seven Gables—mine in Tucson, for example. For a person
might change his or her conception of the House of Seven Gables as a result
of seeing the painting in Tucson. Moreover, the person might, as a result of
accommodating his or her conception to the exemplarized sensory experi-
ence of the painting, perceive the actual house in a different way by focusing
attention on some features and ignoring others in the invariably selective
process of perception. Thus, the painting might alter perceptual knowledge
of the real house, by focusing more attention on the tree standing next to it,
for example. So, knowledge of what the content of the painting is like result-
ing from exemplarization of sensory experience may influence perceptual
knowledge of what the actual house in Salem is like when one sees it. In this
way, therefore, the content of the painting and what it is like may determine
the content of the conception of the house and what it is like. The world of
art and the world of perception may combine to provide a conception of a
new world.
It is useful to compare this notion of our knowledge of what things are like
by exemplarization to what has been said by others about art. Isenberg
(1949), in his justly famous article on critical communication, suggests the
K N O W I N G T H E C O N T E N T OF A R T ( 21 )
The foregoing remarks raise questions about the nature of the content of
the painting. It is important to distinguish the content of the painting from
a model, whether a person or a work of art, for the painting. Should we say,
with Goodman (1968), that the content of the painting may be character-
ized in a way that avoids talk about a nonexistent intentional object,
Olympia, by saying that all that is meant by saying that the painting is a
painting of Olympia is that it is an Olympia-painting? I have already noted
that this characterization fails to capture the phenomenology of seeing
Olympia in the painting. It also fails to accommodate the fact that the nov-
elty of the painting that yields a new conception of Olympia would at the
same time alter our conception of Olympia-paintings. Goodman could, of
course, admit that much, but his account of exemplification would fail to
explain how the novelty is introduced into our conception of Olympia and
of Olympia-paintings. For if the experience of the painting is exemplified
in Goodman’s sense, then it refers to the predicate, “Olympia-painting,”
which, as that is entrenched in our usage, might fail to denote the present
unconventional representation. When, on the contrary, we recognize that
the experience is exemplarized, introducing a novel conception using the
exemplar as a representational sign that applies to a class of experiences
picked out and exhibited by the exemplar, the novelty of the sensory con-
ception is part and parcel of the exemplarized experience of the content of
the painting. Incorporation of the novel exemplar in exemplarization
yields a novel conception of Olympia as well as a novel conception of an
Olympia-painting.
At this point in the discussion, the question naturally arises about the
ontological status of Olympia. Olympia is an intentional object that, in fact,
does not exist. I assume with Reid (1785) and those who followed, most
notably Brentano (1874), that it is a noncontroversial feature of conception
that one can conceive of things that do not exist. The conception of the
content of the painting exists, of course, as a mental state of the observer,
even though the intentional object of the content does not exist. Of course,
the sensory experience, which is exemplarized to yield the exemplarized
content, is something that also exists. Exemplarization involves generaliza-
tion from the exemplar to other individuals and is, as we have noted, a con-
ception that is both particular, in that the particular has a functional role,
and general, in that the functional role involves generalization from the
particular. This account is close to that of both Reid (1785) and Hume
(1739), particularly when the latter gives an account of how an impression
may stand for other impressions and thus become general. Contrary to
( 26 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
With this brief excursion into metaphysics, let us return to the theory of
exemplar representation, exemplarization, and consider the implications
of it for accounting for our knowledge of abstract art as well as other art
forms. Moreover, let us consider how the content of that knowledge
might be extended to explain the emotional content of works of art.
Finally, let us consider how the knowledge of what a visual work of art is
like is related to discursive knowledge concerning the work of art. The
exemplarization of the sensory experience involves generalization from
the exemplar to other individuals, as we have noted. The generalization
will be influenced by innate dispositions, social conventions and cognitive
( 28 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
exemplarize in a way that confirms what he or she says. If they fill in the
meaning of his or her discourse by exemplarizing in a way that confirms
his or her claims, that will confirm his or her trustworthiness for them
and sustain his or her claim to expertise. The test of discursive knowledge
is, therefore, contained in what the painting is like for the observer
obtained from the exemplarization of sensory experience.
ﱞ
CHAPTER 2
( 31 )
( 32 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
when we focus our attention on the qualities of the artwork, we are con-
scious, or can be conscious, of what is contained in the painting. This way
of directing attention is not automatic, though, if Reid (1785) is right, the
child begins with this kind of consciousness. We adults, no longer chil-
dren, have learned a set of practical representational responses which sup-
plement, according Fodor (1983), the innate representation responses of
an input system. The idea is that we respond to sensory stimulation, not by
representing sensory consciousness, but by bypassing such representation
for a more practical mode of representation of the external world. It is
notable that Bergson (1912) insisted on this much earlier, and, in a way,
deplored the practical representational response as leading us to ignore
the immediate deliverances of consciousness. He deplored this ignorance
as ignorance of what reality is like, that is, the immediate reality of
consciousness.
There is a metaphysical dispute here that rests on a dispute about what con-
sciousness reveals to us about the nature of reality. Some think it reveals to
us the immediacy of consciousness, the given presented to consciousness,
while others think we begin with the representation of the external world.
However, even the most radical of those who defend the view that the rep-
resentations of experience are in the first instance representations of the
external world, must acknowledge two aspects of the role of conscious
experience. The first is sensation. We experience sensations, and our
attention is called to them, especially pain, because noticing pains is useful,
indeed, essential, for adaptation to the world. The second consideration,
which Fodor (1983) himself acknowledges, though he suggests it is a
sophisticated rather than original response, is that we attend to what con-
sciousness of artwork is like. That kind of response, that attention to what
the conscious experience of the artwork is like, might naturally be called
aesthetic attention. I do not intend my use of aesthetic attention to be a the-
ory-laden conception. I take it that sometimes, and especially when appre-
ciating art, we focus our attention on what the artwork is like in itself, which
is what I mean by aesthetic attention. In the previous chapter, I proposed
that the cognitive or conceptual response involved in attending to what
conscious experience is like is exemplar representation.
Why insist on the role of the conscious exemplar in an account of
aesthetic attention and the direction of attention to the conscious state?
The answer, given in the preceding chapter, is that such direction of attention
gives us knowledge of what the object of consciousness is like. To have such
CONSCIOUSNESS, EXEMPL ARS, AND ART ( 33 )
those that most attract our attention, that are immediately known to us.
Some affirm that we are directly acquainted with them, which may be true,
but it does not explain how the experience of conscious states gives us
knowledge of them. I do not think that all conscious states are immediately
known. On the contrary, some conscious states, sensations of touch most
notably, provide us with information about the external world, information
about the hardness of an object, for example, without calling attention to
themselves and what they are like in themselves. Some conscious states
pass through the mind without our having any representation of them
because they serve only to represent external things.
Other sensations, pains, for example, attract attention to themselves
and are immediately known. I am inclined to think that all conscious
states can be immediately known when attention is directed to them. It is
a purpose of aesthetic experience to direct attention to the sensory
character of experience, to what the artwork is like. I do not think that it
is a defining characteristic of a conscious state of a person that the person
immediately knows of the existence of the state, however. Some have
argued that the phenomenal character of a conscious state necessitates or
entails that a person has a representation of the conscious state. This claim
is either trivially true by definition, given the use of the expression “phe-
nomenal,” or false. For a person may remain conscious even though the
capacity to represent things is temporarily blocked or permanently lost.
Some seek such unrepresented conscious states in meditation, and I see
no reason to deny that they may succeed in achieving a state in which they
experience intensely rewarding conscious states without having any rep-
resentation of those states. To take a more familiar example, suppose you
are awaking from sleep and experience in your initially confused waking
state a sensation without yet knowing what kind of state it is. You are con-
scious but not yet at a level that carries representation essential to
knowledge along with it. Representation is not necessitated by
consciousness.
Yet we have immediate knowledge of many of our conscious states, espe-
cially in our aesthetic appreciation of sensory experience, consciousness of
a color or a shape. Indeed, once we direct our attention to a conscious state,
we immediately know what it is like. Consider an intense pain that we
cannot help but notice. We immediately know what the pain is like upon
our experience of it. The knowledge of the conscious state is somehow
intrinsic to it. Such knowledge is unlike descriptive knowledge, where we
might search for the right representation of a known state or object.
Representation of the conscious state somehow contains the conscious
state itself yielding immediate knowledge of the state. How do we have this
immediate knowledge of our conscious states?
CONSCIOUSNESS, EXEMPL ARS, AND ART ( 35 )
Conscious states are represented in a special, direct way. They also might be
represented indirectly in other ways, in a linguistic representation, for
example. So an account of immediate representation that contains the con-
scious state is needed. Such an account must explain how the representa-
tion of the conscious state can be immediate, how the state can be intrinsic
to the representation, and how the representation can contain the state
itself. If, however, the conscious state becomes, as I have argued, the repre-
sentation of a conscious state, which is not entailed by the mere existence of
the conscious state, a question remains. How can the representation be
direct or immediate, intrinsic to the state and contain it, when it is possible
for the state to exist without such representation?
A satisfactory answer to this question must give an account of represen-
tational lucidity, as I have called it, and will rest on the notion of exemplar
representation, exemplarization. My reason for describing the exemplar
( 36 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
It is now time to turn to the explanation of how conscious states that do not
logically necessitate or entail any representation of themselves are, never-
theless, components of an intrinsic, direct, lucid exemplar representation of
themselves as the lucid content of the representation. I have been arguing
(Lehrer, 1996, 1997) that there is a loop in representation of conscious
states. Reid (1785) argued that conscious states are both signs of external
objects and, at the same time, signs of themselves. Brentano (1874)—as
my colleague Marek (forthcoming) in Graz and Kriegel (2002, 2006) in
Arizona have reminded me—also held the view that conscious states repre-
sent themselves at the same time as they represent other things. The idea
is an old one and goes back further than the modern period to Carneades,
as represented by Chisholm (1996), who held that such states are self-
presenting. So the idea is old, but the old idea is also an old enigma. How
can a conscious state be at the same time a representation and the content
of the representation? How can the state be both a sign and, at the same
time, the thing signified?
My answer is that the conscious state is in some way self-representa-
tional. The representation must be a loop as Reid, Brentano, Carneades,
and now Kriegel all aver. The loop is effective, as Rosenthal (2000) con-
cedes, at avoiding a regress of representation at higher orders. But how does
the conscious state represent itself? How are we to understand how that
conscious state can be used to represent itself? I suggested in the preceding
chapter that the conscious state can function as an exemplar of a kind of
conscious state incorporated into the exemplar representation, exemplar-
ization, of the state. It is used to represent itself as an exhibit of a state of that
kind. I am conscious of a pain, for example, and the particular pain is used
as an exemplar that represents pains as an exhibit of what they are like. Of
course, the pain used to represent pains, to exhibit what they are like, is
itself a pain. So, when exemplarization works in a paradigmatically simple
fashion, the exemplar is an instance of the kind of state the exemplarized
state is used to represent.
This might suggest that exemplarization produces infallible representa-
tion. How, the infalliblist might ask, can the exemplarized state fail to be an
( 38 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
With these ideas before us, let us turn to the relationship between the exem-
plarization of conscious states and our knowledge of them. When exem-
plarization yields only ostensive representation, self-representation of the
exemplar as one of the states represented by the exemplar, it falls short of
knowledge. The representation of the state by itself in the ostensive repre-
sentation may result in the exemplar being an instance of the states repre-
sented by itself. The representation of the exemplar by itself in this way will
be a correct, or, if one prefers, a veridical representation when the exemplar
CONSCIOUSNESS, EXEMPL ARS, AND ART ( 41 )
Perhaps the most salient argument for the conclusion that there is some
fact about conscious experience that goes beyond scientific understanding
is founded on the premise that there could be creatures who were our
biological duplicates but who were unconscious. That argument, the zombie
argument of Chalmers (1996), leads to the conclusion that conscious states
are not token-token identical with physical states and, indeed, to the
stronger conclusion that conscious states do not supervene on physical
states. Identity and supervenience require a kind of necessity in relation-
ships that is precluded by the possibility argued for by an appeal to the pos-
sibility of the zombie. There is no doubt that we can imagine the zombie,
but the controversial question is whether the imagined zombie is possible.
Reid (1785) long ago noted that we can imagine and conceive of things
that are impossible—indeed, the ability to conceive of and understand
impossible hypotheses is what enables us to reduce them to absurdity. If we
did not understand them, we could not show that they were absurd. So, the
question is simply whether the conceived zombie is possible.
It must be granted that conscious states do not seem to have physical
properties as the conscious subject experiences those states, nor, for that
matter, do physical states when externally observed seem to have subjective
qualitative features experienced by the subject of the conscious state. These
facts of our experience, whether as the subject of the conscious states or as
the external observer of physical states, explain why the zombie should be
conceivable. But does this entail the logical possibility of the zombie and
( 44 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
is optimal for viewing art, when there is attention to what the sensory
experience of the artwork is like, the conscious experience becomes the
exemplar of representation and the basis of knowledge. We know in terms
of the exemplar representation what the experience is like. We need to
know what the sensory surface of the artwork is like—a painting for exam-
ple—in order to appreciate the art. An experience of an artwork that falls
short of conveying knowledge of what an experience of the artwork is like
is not an aesthetic experience of the artwork. Such focus of attention is not
all that there is to appreciating the artwork. Some appreciation requires
knowledge of the world of art and of the world that encompasses art. What
is important about the immediacy, about the focus on conscious experi-
ence of what the artwork is like, is that it opens the mind to reconfigure
experience by taking exemplar representation beyond ostensive represen-
tation of other conscious states. The mind is provoked to reconstruct the
content of the world of art and the world beyond art in a way that keeps it
tied in a referential loop to the exemplarized experience. We shall argue
below that just as the conscious state can, when attention is focused upon
it, become an exemplar representation of other conscious states showing
us what they are like, so the same exemplar of consciousness can be used
to show us what things are like that lie beyond present conscious experi-
ence, and perhaps beyond all experience. If Malevich is right, the sensory
exemplar of the Black Square [Web ASK 12] can show us what something
beyond ordinary experience, the supreme, is like. Rothko paintings can
show us what experience is like when emptied of the perceptual objects of
quotidian experience.
The point of this chapter is a bit paradoxical. It is by focusing attention
on the conscious experience of art, the exemplar representing what the
conscious experience is like, that art can take us, in an exercise of our
autonomy, to new conceptions, to the construction of new content beyond
conscious experiences. That it does so is familiar to any art lover. The con-
sciousness of what art is like takes us to a new consciousness of what we
and the world are like. That is why we love it so. A metaphor, suggested by
Ismael (2007), is a person looking at a map in a mall that says, “You are
here.” You say, fixing your attention on that spot, “Yes, I am here.” Now you
are free to move where you will find your own construction of space as you
move. As I look at a painting, I involve myself totally in the conscious expe-
riences, representing that exemplar of consciousness. I say to myself, “I am
here in this conscious awareness of immediacy, in this bit and parcel of
consciousness.” Fully in the exemplar of consciousness, I find a freedom to
take that consciousness into some new content, some new configuration,
some new conception, of color, “I did not know that black could be like
that,” or “I am lost in the black of nothingness and the totality of being,”
( 46 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
with the conscious experience to show me what the color or the nothing-
ness and the totality of being feels like.
Conscious experience, though it leads us into the conception of our
world and our selves in our world, and, perhaps, in our world in ourselves,
remains as a vivid reminder, as an exhibit, of what the content of our con-
ception is like. So the paradox is that, to choose a term from Peggy Brand
(1998) is that we must, in the aesthetic experience, toggle back and forth
between what the sensory experience, the immediate content of conscious-
ness is like, and what it shows us about what everything else is like. The
point of art, and it is a point well appreciated in the use of scientific repre-
sentation as well, is that you must, in a moment of intentional world forget-
fulness, absorb your attention in the immediacy of consciousness to obtain
the insight and autonomy to remake your world and yourself. This requires
explanation and illustration, which is the purpose of the rest of this book.
ﱞ
CHAPTER 3
( 47 )
( 48 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
studio, that I recorded as a collage painting [Web ASK 14]. Reid (1785)
claimed that we have an original understanding of the meaning of gestures
of the body. That suggests that experiences of gestures of the body, carrying
content, could be used to exemplarize the content of art objects. The inter-
pretation of the visual art by the philosophy students was remarkable and
showed that you do not need words or discursive thought to represent the
content of a work of art. The experience of the artwork can be exemplarized
with gestures of the body, with movement, that reconfigure the content of
the artworks in another artistic action. The improvisation led to further
construction of artworks—collages—responding to the experience of the
dance. Creating an artwork, like creating a world, is the creation of form
and content out of experience with thought and movement.
Having mentioned performance, I shall use feminist performance art to
illustrate the way in which exemplar representation leads to the reconfigu-
ration of the content of experience. It is essential to consider some exam-
ples of art and what the experience of the art is like to understand the way
in which new content arises from exemplar representation. Exemplar repre-
sentation replaces the more ordinary forms of representation. Of course,
there are ordinary and even encapsulated representational responses. These
play an important role in the appreciation of art. The painting The Gay Moon
by Jack Yeats [Web ASK 15], for example, may strike one initially as
abstract, devoid of the figures and shapes of ordinary life. But then, sud-
denly, one sees human subjects and other ordinary objects: trees, animals,
and so forth. The shift, something like a gestalt shift, results from the tech-
nique of not delineating objects, and, in that way, is an exaggeration of
impressionist technique. It is amazing how it works. In this case, attending
to the sensory exemplar leads to exemplar representation of objects without
the viewer exercising any freedom of interpretation.
One sees—a face, the side view of head, a large moon, and some land-
scape—as a result of simply attending to the sensory exemplar. A person
who took a quick look and did not focus attention on the painting might
not linger long enough to see the figures. Once you do see them, it is your
conscious experience, the sensory exemplar that exhibits or shows you
what the men, moon, and landscape are like in the painting as the exemplar
represents them. This level of exemplarization, though it involves the free-
dom of attention, does not reach the level of exemplar representation of
autonomously choosing the exemplar to exhibit further content of what the
work is like. Some would interpret it as the sadness of one of the figures, one
of the men, over the loss of the other. Here there is freedom of interpreta-
tion and the construction of content. Should I construe the painting of hav-
ing the content of loss, perhaps the loss of a brother? It is my choice to let
the sensory exemplar carry that message. The painting confronts you with
( 50 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
Feminist art and feminist aesthetics illustrate the role of freedom in exem-
plarization of consciousness. I turn to feminist art as an illustration of
what art does, not just feminist art. In fact, as indicated previously, I am
very suspicious of the utility of dividing art into schools and types. I see
this as a pedantic task, interesting socially and historically, but distorting
aesthetic appreciation and construction of new content for art, and, by
free transfer from art to the world, to the story of our life. There is pedantic
value in dividing things into classes, into finding the right ism for the
classification of the individual. But it is not the ism that makes the art-
work, rather it is the artwork that makes the ism, by eliciting the conscious
experience of the work, yes, the individual and unique sensory exemplar,
that evokes exemplar representation, exemplarization, to show us what
cannot be said. What the form and content of representation are like
results from exemplarization. I choose feminist art because of the vivid
way in which it confronts us and challenges us to exemplarize the novel
content of the work. All art does this, but feminist artists, seeking to pro-
voke and challenge ordinary consciousness, conceptions, and conven-
tions, break down quotidian responses to things, including art, to reach
beyond the ordinary to the extraordinary experience of the creation of
content out of experience.
Art reconfigures experience; feminist art reconfigures the stereotyped
consciousness of women. All art uses a physical object to confront con-
sciousness, endowing the physical object with features of mentality, with
intentionality and immediacy of conscious experience. Art, especially fem-
inist art, is a mentalized physical object. Since feminist art is often
performance art, the human body used in it obviously has a mental life.
Danto (1994) remarks that art is embodied meaning. Hein (1993) says
that feminist art chats on the edge of experience. Our mental life is filled
with meaning, but art opens the question of the meaning of experience.
There is the felt quality of it, which, when it becomes the focus of our
attention, allows us the autonomy of reconfiguring how we respond to our
sensory encounters with the world. A salient aspect of the art experience,
the way in which our attention is directed to the immediate, to the sensory
exemplar, in an aesthetic stance, frees us to rethink and re-feel as an act of
self-trust. Brand (1998) has noted how we toggle back and forth between
the immediate experience and how we think and feel about our world and
A E S T H E T I C T H E OR Y, F E M I N I S T A R T, A N D AU T O N O M Y ( 51 )
our place in that world. Art, chatting on the edge of experience, invites us to
choose our stance in that world.
I suggest that is the beauty, or, at least the value, of art. The art experience
presents us with a sensory exemplar that can convey and exhibit content.
The exhibited content of the mode of presentation of the exemplar suggests
a reconfiguration of the content of experience outside of art as well as
within. Art, then, is that part of experience that changes us by changing the
content of our experience. My claim here is that feminist art provides us
with a paradigm of what art does and that is why I admire it.
Let me begin with my personal experience. My first encounter with fem-
inist art was Judy Chicago’s The Dinner Party [Web ASK 16] in San
Francisco. I had no idea what to expect. The lines were long, the wait was
excessive, but the experience was exhilarating. The first view was the dinner
table. I live in a house in Tucson that Margaret Sanger had built for herself
and thus sought her place setting [Web ASK 17]. Like most of the pieces,
the relationship to the female sex organ was unmistakable. It was blood red,
and, yes, I remembered. Margaret Sanger had been radicalized by witness-
ing the butchering of women resulting from illegal abortions. But blood is
the material of life and that was more fundamental. My thoughts, raised by
the encounter, evoked conceptualization of the experience of The Dinner
Party. Beyond the particular place setting there was the grandeur of the tri-
angle, the strength of the triangle, and, the feminine biology of the triangle.
The power of the feminine confronted me. And thought raced on. The fem-
ininity was on every plate. Georgia O’Keeffe may have denied the often
noted similarity of her flowers to the vaginal opening, claiming it was only
an interest in scale that led to the flower paintings, but Chicago in her place
setting [Web ASK 18] left no ambiguity. It was a new view of the female sex
organ as a source of creativity and power. My thought was, “Of course, even
Courbet portrayed it as the origin of it all.” I made ceramics at the time I saw
The Dinner Party, and found it hard to take my eyes from those amazing
pieces: subtle, brilliant variations in the grounding of us all, of woman and
earth.
The movement to the walls and rooms documenting the role, the contri-
butions and the experience of women was equally amazing. It was not so
much the detail as the overall impact of the feminine in life. I was left
thinking at the time of the paradoxical character that is the art character of
the experience. It was a revelation of the concealed, a revelation of what we
knew and did not know about the known and unknown world of woman.
I walked and gawked with my eyes hanging out. After a disappearance from
public viewing, The Dinner Party is back on exhibition in Brooklyn. That
venue seems correct to me. Brooklyn is somehow the earthy place, not as
pretentious as Manhattan. It is the alternative place. Jackie Robinson was
( 52 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
with the Brooklyn Dodgers and Judy Chicago is with The Dinner Party in
Brooklyn.
The long disappearance of The Dinner Party after its remarkable initial
success is an indication of the artworld’s discrimination against female art-
ists and feminist artists. The Guerrilla Girl movement was a critique of the
art establishment and remains so. My sympathies are with them. I read
Pierre Bourdieu (1993) and was impressed by the sociological acuteness of
his work explaining the cultural value of art in terms of the exercise of the
power and institutions of the commercial artworld establishment. But,
I objected, that is not what the value of art is about! It was rather brilliant of
Wartenberg (2007), in his text, to place the reading from Bourdieu bet-
ween pieces on feminist art and African art that connect the value of art
with the role it plays in our life. As an artist, I am revolted by the soundness
of Bourdieu’s analysis. His account and the critique of the Guerrilla Girls
tell the same story of the museum object being socially constructed by the
power of the wealthy and privileged. People sometimes ask why I do not
charge more for my art. Art is about what the art object does, how it changes
and reconfigures experience for the viewer, not about commercial value
and the artworld status of the work. The Guerrilla Girl movement, however
central the feminist motivation, is a protest against the power of the art-
world establishment. The central role of art is not the creation of cultural
capital for the sophisticated few. It is the transformation of the life of us all.
I love to show my work and watch the response of others. Vik Muniz
[Web ASK 19] remarked that he does not make art for himself, he makes it
to watch how others respond. Much feminist art is a protest against
established commercial art traditions. However, feminist art objects that
become mainstream retain their feminist power to change consciousness.
There is a deeper point about feminist art, and I think it is widely recog-
nized among artists even when it goes unexpressed. Feminist artists remind
us what art is about. Their point is to change experience, to reconfigure with
conscious experience how we think and feel about ourselves, our world,
and our relation to each other. There is an external world that is not of our
making, and there is our internal world of how we think and feel. The
content of that internal world is constructed out of exemplars of conscious
experience.
Feminist art raises consciousness about feminist issues because it con-
fronts us with a question. What do you think and feel about this? How does
this relate to what you and your world are like? Feminist art confronts you
in the way in which art can and should. It says something, often very explicit,
but asks you something at the same time. What are you going to think, feel,
and do about this? It raises the personal question. What does this experi-
ence mean to you? In bringing that question to consciousness, feminist art
A E S T H E T I C T H E OR Y, F E M I N I S T A R T, A N D AU T O N O M Y ( 53 )
Renaissance paintings of martyrs until Orlan. The martyrs had the courage
to confront material harm for their cause of spirituality as Orlan confronts
material harm for her feminist art. Of course, that is obvious. The paintings
are about the ecstatic in suffering. One student, a male artist, responded to
Orlan’s art, “She has balls to do that for her art. I admire her.” He was an
artist, a film artist. His choice of words was deliberate. It was a capsule of
performance art.
So what about the wonderful color and form in those martyr paintings?
They are exemplars of color and form that are not just about color and form.
They are about suffering, cruelty, and spiritual transcendence of the body.
You do not have to believe in God to understand. You only need to open
yourself to the experience. Let me return to The Dinner Party to close the
loop and tie in the immediacy of experience of color and form and the value
of it. Wollheim (1987) called our attention to a kind of double vision in our
perception of art. Peg Brand reminded us of it. Let us use her metaphor of a
toggle switch. We toggle back and forth between an immediate awareness
of color and form and an awareness of meaning we find in the color and
form. Every artist is struck by a special kind of sensory immediacy that
becomes the focus of aesthetic attention in aesthetic awareness. Dickie
(1994, 1997) denied the importance of aesthetic distance, but there is a
special way of attending to art that is aesthetic and distanced from meaning.
Brand suggests we toggle from this immediacy into the complexity of the
meaning, and the notion of a toggle suggests we can return to immediacy.
I like the metaphor, but I am not sure the psychology is quite right. Once
a certain meaning, a gestalt, for example, is part of our perception, it may
not be possible to toggle back to the immediacy. One of the most striking
painters to exploit the two stage character of perception is Jack Yeats men-
tioned above. Looking at The Gay Moon, at first you will not see the faces,
and then you do. Once you see the faces, you may not be able to toggle back
to original immediate awareness of color and shape. The point I want to
make is that there is an initial perception which may be quite formal and
not figurative. Once the initial take is surpassed, however, you will find it
difficult to return. One way to do so may be to turn the painting upside
down. However, that may, as in a painting I supply, rapidly produce a new
figurative take, a different one, when inverted. I do not want to urge the
importance of a fixed, as opposed to a more flexible, response.
My point is that you become aware in such processes of your configura-
tion of the experience. In the gestalt response, you might experience the
perception as compelled and one from which you cannot get released.
Other ways of configuring an experience—for example, my configuring of
Interior Scroll as being about birth and the mystery of being—is one that
allows the viewer greater autonomy in the configuration of meaning. It is
( 56 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
T his chapter deals with some apparently unrelated issues about art that
are, I shall argue, tied together by exemplar representation. The topics
include value in art, expression of emotion in art, and the impact of art on
globalization.
VALUE IN ART
The first issue—value—was discussed at the end of the previous chapter. People
find a special value in art. I have been inclined to think that a special kind of
value may be a defining requirement. There are many questions that press in
upon a person when she asks whether something is art, questions about art his-
tory, questions about pleasure, but I think a value judgment is implicit in the
affirmation that something is art. An artwork may be disturbing in a way that
blocks pleasure, such as some of Goya prints and paintings [Web ASK 22]
about war, and other works that disturb us, but we value the representation of
war, we value representation of war in that way. Our experience of what war is
like in that work, the conscious experience of war it presents to us, has value.
At the end of the previous chapter, I claimed I experienced the value of
an artwork because of the way in which the conscious experience of it
evoked a reconfiguration of my world and myself in terms of the sensory
experience, the exemplar, which became the vehicle of novel conception.
So what kind of value is the value of the artwork, the value of the experience
it provides? Some will rush in with the answer, wanting to dissect value into
species, that it is aesthetic value. But that is not a felicitous way to answer
the question even if it has a point. The point it has, the correct point, is that
( 59 )
( 60 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
the value arises from the special focus on what the work is like, this focus
may be rightly called aesthetic. If, however, the attitude that we take toward
the object, the attention to what it is like, may properly be called an aesthetic
attitude, it does not follow from this that the value of what it is like is
aesthetic value. My claim is that there is a kind of value, a generic kind of
value, that attaches to our experience of what a thing is like that is
characteristic of our experience of artworks.
Where does the value reside? I want to suggest that the value of the artwork
arises from a relation between the person and the artwork. The value arises, as
my examples of Goya and Schneemann [Web ASK 3] exhibit, from the way in
which we use the sensory materials, the way in which we exemplarize them to
represent the content of the artwork. I cannot appreciate the value of the art-
work without experiencing what the artwork is like. Moreover, the special kind
of value I am proposing that artworks have is both intrinsic to the experience
of what they are like, intrinsic to the relation of experience, and generic. Here I
must rush to draw distinctions. Artworks have value of many kinds, moral,
political, and hedonistic. They are useful for many ends. But when the object is
a work of art for the viewer, he or she has an experience that has a value intrinsic
to it. To say that the value is intrinsic is not to say that it is inexplicable. There is
nothing inexplicable about a kind of value that arises out of the reconfiguration
of experience evoked by the artwork changing the content of experience as an
expression of our autonomy. The value is the value of an experience of our
autonomy in the making of the content of our world and ourselves.
I shall argue below that the kind of value in question is like the value of
the experience of a life. A life need not be attractive aesthetically or morally
to have value. The relation of value in the arts is one that is less perplexing
than one might expect, not because of widespread agreement about value,
but because divergence of interpretation of what artworks are like is both
acknowledged and accepted as appropriate. We do not expect everyone to
agree on the value or merit of an artwork because we expect disagreement
in interpretation and the construction of the content of the work. If differ-
ent people exemplarize artworks in different ways, they will disagree about
the content of the artwork. Moreover, and this is my theme, the value of the
work of art is part of the content and, therefore, is something that you expe-
rience in your relation to the artwork. The beauty, perfection, elegance, and,
in general, the value of the artwork is to be experienced in your relation to
the work of art. Put the matter the other way around, if the value cannot be
experienced in the painting, then it is not there. The value and values of the
painting are in the experience of the painting. We may speak of the value of
paintings no one ever sees, but that, I suggest, is paraphrastic for claiming
that, though unexperienced, the value of the painting, like the color of the
painting, would be evoked by the experience of the painting.
VA L U E , E X P R E S S I O N , A N D G L O B A L I Z AT I O N ( 61 )
child understands on some superficial level, but it does not evoke anger in
the child. It evokes fear. Moreover, the person whose face expressed the
anger felt no anger and, therefore, was not communicating the anger he
felt.
This leaves us with the question of how feelings or emotions or intu-
itions—lyrical ones involving images animated by the feelings, as Croce
says—can be in some material medium that is not conscious, like a painting
or the sounds of a symphony. There are two tempting lines of reply to the
question. The first is that the commonsense attribution of expressed feeling
to the material medium is just an error. Of course, the semblance of the sad-
ness or gaiety of the music or the painting still requires explanation on the
error theory. Moreover, the explanation must be consistent with the
example of the expression of anger by the actor who neither feels anger nor
evokes it in his audience. The most natural error theory is one that says that
the medium communicates a thought of the feeling expressed rather than
the feeling itself. You can have a thought of anger or sadness without feeling
it. Indeed, some results concerning simulation suggest that the thoughts
may be similar to the ones you would have if you perceived someone expe-
riencing the emotion or, in the case of the actor, acting as though he was
experiencing the emotion.
The problem with the error theory is that thoughts or feelings caused by
an object may result when the object does not express the feeling. I may see
some work of art, a smiling painting of The Countess von Schönfeld and Her
Daughter [Web ASK 24] painted by Vigée-Lebrun for Marie Antoinette
and have thoughts of the sadness of peasants who suffered while she smiled.
But the painting does not express sadness. The response might be wide-
spread, after the French Revolution in France, for example, but the painting
still does not express sadness. That is not in the painting. In short, the error
theory, attempting to explicate expressed feelings in art in terms of thought
about those feelings, disconnects the expression of the specific feeling from
what is in the medium, by allowing for association to replace expression.
We must distinguish between reflections caused by a work of art from what
is expressed in the work.
This reflection on the error theory leads us to the idea that the expressed
feeling, the lyrical intuition, is symbolically connected to the feeling
expressed. The idea is that the expressed feeling is somehow symbolized in
the medium. That is the view advanced by Langer (1957). Langer is partic-
ularly important for advocating that the feeling expressed is symbolically
VA L U E , E X P R E S S I O N , A N D G L O B A L I Z AT I O N ( 65 )
it is like. There is more universality of response to art than that. Sinh shows
us what it is like In Every Hamlet. The artist, or the philosopher become
artist, has the capacity to reconfigure experience by the presenting us with
exemplars of experience that challenge us to create new content. The
aesthetic attention to the sensory exemplar, to what it is like, blocks the
standard or conventional representation of the world. When the work is
successful, when it has the value we discussed above, it provokes marking
distinctions in new ways, creating content in new ways, changing the
content of our world. The test of the reconfigured experience rests with
those who receive the artworks. There is no guarantee this will work mira-
cles or work at all. The universality of a philosophy is embodied in the art-
work that realizes the exemplarization of new content to reconfigure our
world.
There is a role for reason and objective analysis in confronting the prob-
lems of globalization in our representation of our world. At the end of the
road of reason, the choice to aggregate or isolate may remain. The problem
is to find a way to change, for we inevitably will, so that our identity is not
co-opted by the aggregation of the identity of the other with our own. So
how do we change without a loss of identity? Is there any way of incorpo-
rating identity? The question, once posed, suggests an answer. The answer
is art. It is the art object that allows us to mentalize an externality. The men-
talized physical surface of the artwork in exemplar representation articu-
lates what we are, our thoughts, our feelings, our culture. It exhibits what
the content of culture is like for us. It is the work of an individual incorpo-
rating the significant other in his or her externalized identity in the artwork.
It shows us that the egocentric predicament, or the sociocentric predica-
ment, is an egotistic socioistic fiction. In the work of art, we are always in a
process of change. We reconfigure. We transform. The original starting
point of representation of our world is reconfigured, for the change in rep-
resentation autonomously exhibits to us what we are like as we change what
we are like.
So far, I have placed emphasis on the creator who reconfigures experi-
ence by showing us what content is like in the work of art. However, what
something is like depends on the receiver, on what it is like for the receiver,
who becomes, therefore, an essential force in what the artwork is like. The
content of the artwork is at the same time, synchronic, diachronic, and
socially activated. I am leaning toward a postmodern conception of art in
what I am about to say: the artwork, experienced as art, not propaganda,
must empower the viewer. This goes beyond respect. The content of the
artwork is a consequence of the autonomy of the receiver as well as the
artist. It is not simply that the meaning or content of the work of art changes
over time, that is also true of the meaning or content of words, it is that the
( 72 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
content or meaning of the work of art must await the response of the
receiver, observer, or spectator. For part of what the artwork is like is what
it is like for the receiver.
I do not deny that there is a chance of co-optation of culture in works
of art. The risk of co-optation, of being taken over by the other, is always
there. But the artwork confronts the viewer with the challenge of creation,
which is the same challenge that confronts the artist. It is the challenge to
reconfigure experience in creation of new content out of a sensory expe-
rience, an exemplar, in the representational process of exemplarization.
The exemplar exhibits what the content of the artwork is like. This is cru-
cial to the issue of co-optation and identity. The receiver must experience
what the content is like in the same way that she experiences his or her
own consciousness, including the consciousness of culture. Experience
of what the content of the work is like takes one into subjectivity, whether
individual or social, as the content is experienced and exhibited in the
experience of the receiver.
Art takes us into an experience of what the content of religion,
politics, and commerce are like in our experience of the artwork. When
we experience what the sensory exemplars of the artwork are like, it is
we, in collaboration with the artist, who decide what the content of the
artwork is like. The artist may intend that we be inspired to find some
meaning, some hurrah for what he or she advocates. Yet our experience
of what the content is like may lead us to represent the content of expe-
rience in another opposed way. Indeed, we may experience the intended
meaning as absurd. We have the capacity to be autonomous receivers of
the artwork. The success of the artwork is not measured by some
abstract message but by the empowerment of the viewer who experi-
ences what the message is like, what the content is like, in a moment of
creative reaction. The receiver preserves identity because the experi-
ence of what the content of the artwork is like is an expression of that
identity, indeed, of what the viewer is like in that protean, heraclitean
dynamic of experience. Change expresses identity rather than
diminishing it. And what if you do not like what the content of the work
of art is like? That is part of what you are like in the experience of the
artwork. Your dislike, the offense you find in the content of the artwork,
enhances your identity.
You can see the loop of content, identity, and expression. You refer back
to yourself in the experience of content, in seeing what it is like. It may
change you, of course, but it is you changing you in the experience of what
the work is like. That loop of the individual and social self ties the content
of what the artwork is like to personal and cultural identity and the recon-
figuration of it. Art changes us by changing how we autonomously think
VA L U E , E X P R E S S I O N , A N D G L O B A L I Z AT I O N ( 73 )
about our world and our place in it. I seek to explain how art can enhance
our autonomy, whether individual or communal, as we reconfigure experi-
ence in art. Can art become the vehicle and exhibition of how we may
reconfigure our world, our place, and ourselves in our globalized world? It
is we who decide as we autonomously create and receive the exhibited
content of our reconfigured world and ourselves within it. That is the value
of art. The value of art is inseparable from the autonomy it gives us in how
we represent our world and ourselves in terms of our experience.
This page intentionally left blank
ﱞ
CHAPTER 5
( 75 )
( 76 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
ARTISTIC CREATION
can misunderstand his creation as well. The reason is that the artist, how-
ever clear his initial intentions in the creation of the work, recedes out of
view, out of his view, in the creative process. At a certain point, all that exists
of the artist is the creative moment. Guston, quoted by Dennett (2001),
replied, when asked what it is like to create art: “When I first come into the
studio to work, there is this noisy crowd which follows me there; it includes
all of the important painters in history, all of my contemporaries, all the art
critics, etc. As I become involved in the work, one by one, they all leave. If
I’m lucky, every one of them will disappear. If I’m really lucky, I will too.”
The act of creation is something new, something beyond the plans or the
intentions of the artist, as that act becomes a new moment in the story of the
artist. We, the viewers and, he, the artist, stand before the artwork, though
not at the same time, left to construct the content of the work out of our
experience of it. The connection between the artist and the viewers is not a
simple act of communication of thought or feeling, contrary to the theory of
Tolstoy (1995). We do feel a connection with the artist, something com-
munal arises, but that is because we both stand before the work, together
transcending time and place, involved in making content, meaning, worlds,
and ourselves out of what the artist has created. It is because he or she pro-
vides the occasion for our common and uncommon creative construction of
form and content out of the experience provided by his creative act that the
bond arises. We may conjecture that he feels and thinks what we feel and
think confronting his work, and experience some identification with him or
her. But, in truth, we are ignorant of why he did what he did, and, in that, we
may share the deepest empathy and identity with the artist. For, in that
creative moment, as Guston indicates, control and intention dissolve into
spontaneity and immediacy. We are left with the conscious experience of
what has emerged and the construction of meaning out of sense and feeling,
out of our consciousness. We stand together looking for the meaning. Our
experience shows us the meaning of content and feeling. Is it the same? Is
the experience of one person ever the same as another? We are deep in meta-
physics that may not matter to either of us. We may love talking to the artist
about her response to her work, for, of course, she made it. But she may love
talking to us about our response, because, though we did not make the
object, instead we created the content of it. What matters is not who made
the object, but what we make of it, what our experience of what it is like
shows us about the work, the world, and ourselves.
Goldsworthy was clearly fascinated with arches, which he made of stones
and ice. The arch is a good example of an art object and a good metaphor for
the social construction of meaning. So far I have laid emphasis on the con-
scious experience in the mind of an individual. But how an individual con-
structs meaning in the activity of exemplarization, in the activity of marking
( 78 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
to the artist and to us, though not in the same way to us as to the artist, what
the process was like that created it. Her conscious experience of the final
product shows her what an episode of creation was like. It is not a record of
the moments of the episode, but it may, nonetheless, remind her of those
moments, showing her what they were like as far as the hand of present
experience reaches into the dark well of memory. The exemplar representa-
tion of the conscious experience of the creative process’s end result shows
the artist what an episode in the story of her life was like. She returns to her
work to experience the story of herself.
To give an account of how the artistic creations of the artist become part
of the story of the artist, we need an account of how free action and self-
expression become the story of the life of the self. Both Velleman (2003)
and Fischer (2009) have offered an account of the story of the self. Velleman
and Fischer think of the self in terms of narrative. Self-expression is a step
into the narrative of life. Fischer argues that the construction of the narra-
tive of the story of life is artistic expression. Freedom is self-expression tak-
ing agency into narrative. My free actions, according to Fischer, are the
sentences in the story of my life. Velleman sees the tying together of a life as
giving meaning to the events and actions of life. Meaning, in this sense, is
content. My free action creates the meaning of the story of my life.
I shall focus on the account of Fischer. In his brilliant and original book,
Fischer (2009) offers us a theory connecting acting freely, self-expression,
and the story of the life of a person. Fischer writes, “When I act freely, I
write a sentence in the story of my life . . .” and continues, “As I said above,
our lives are stories . . .” (Fischer, 2009, 167–168). Then he concludes,
“I have argued that there is a sense in which our lives can be understood as
stories” (Fischer, 2009, 173). Fischer tends to equate the story of our lives
with our lives. He has excellent reflections to offer on free action as self-
expression. However, there is a problem. Simply put, it is that the story of
my life is one thing, and my life is another. My life may consist of my actions.
There may be a meaningful narrative constructed out of descriptions
and interpretations of those actions by myself or another. On the other
hand, those actions may be full of sound and fury signifying nothing as
Shakespeare wrote. Whether there is a narrative constructed or not from
the actions, there is the life of the person composed of those actions, mean-
ingful or not. That life, consisting of those actions, is distinct from any
description, any narrative string of sentences. The life might be lived without
a narrative being constructed, and a narrative might be constructed that
( 80 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
does not describe an actual life. Fischer is left with a chasm between the
story of a life and the life the story is about. He switches in his discourse
between the story the life is about and the life the story is about. How can
the story be the life? My solution to this problem is that the actions may be
treated like samples or exemplars used to represent themselves. This account
is offered as a constructive addition that Fischer could consistently accept
as a solution to the problem. I shall then make some further proposals for
development of the view, inspired by Fischer, that are less clearly consistent
with his theory.
Fischer (2009) qualifies his view of our free actions as sentences in the
story of our lives. He says our behaviors are:
“vehicles” for storytelling or the determination of narrative content. Our lives, then,
considered as sequences of behaviors or even bodily movements, could be thought of as
a way of telling a story—a certain sort of vehicle of narrative content. . . . Strictly speaking
then, our lives are not stories but ways of telling stories, or, perhaps more carefully, ways
of constraining admissible narrative content. They are—as with poems or plays or
novels—the vehicles of content rather than the content itself. The point is similar to the
notion that a sentence (or perhaps a sentence in a context) is the vehicle for content (say,
a proposition that is expressed by the sentence in the context). It is illuminating to dis-
tinguish the properties of the vehicles of expression from those of content itself; for in-
stance, some philosophers hold that the vehicles of content are structured linguistically,
whereas the proposition expressed—that content itself—is not structured at all or at
least not linguistically structured. Of course this particular claim is contentious; for our
purposes it is enough simply to mark the distinction between the properties of vehicles
of content and the properties of content (Fischer, 2009, 173).
EXPERIENCING MY ACTIONS
I am fascinated by the idea that the story of the life of a person, especially an
artist, could result from or consist of the free actions of self-expression. I am
attracted by the idea that acting freely could be construed as a form of
self-expression in the construction of the story. I resonate to much of what
is said, but I have my difficulties with Fischer’s telling of the story of our
telling the story of our lives. My remarks are intended to offer a modifica-
tion of Fischer’s account of meaning, stories of the self and the value thereof.
I believe that an account of the self lies coiled like a worm at the center of an
account of self-expression, free action, and the story of the life of the self.
The story of my life, told by myself or another, is a story of me. The meaning
of my life, and, of me, starts with my experience of my life, even if it does not
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 81 )
end there. Others take over the story, but it is a different kind of story when
it is a story told by me about me. I experience what I am like, what my
actions are like for me, and, therefore, what the content of my story is for
me. Others do not experience my experiences.
Let me focus on the role of experience in my story of myself, my life.
I move my body and by so doing engage in actions, including free actions of
self-expression. However, there are multiple descriptions of actions as
Anscombe (1957) and Davidson (2001) have taught us. There are, in short,
many different ways of representing an action. To say, as Fischer does, that
the movements of my body are the vehicles for representing the content
requires an explanation of my way of representing my actions. There is a way
open to me, namely, in terms of the way in which I experience those move-
ments as my action. Many people may experience the same movements I
make but represent them in different ways as actions. I have a way of repre-
senting my actions, constructing the story of myself and my life, that is
unique to me. Simply formulated, I can represent my action in terms of the
way I experience the action. My experience of the action can be my vehicle
of representation of the action, and, avoiding regress, can be the vehicle of
representing itself. I can tell the story of my life, in terms of my experiences
of my actions.
When Fischer speaks of my bodily movements as the vehicles of content
for the story of my life, he is taking a third-person perspective on the story
of my life. Other people, he suggests, may tell the story of my life differently,
but my bodily movements and my free actions of self-expression constrain
how the story can be told. Those actions, he says, constrain the stories that
can be told. It is clear, given the multiple descriptions of one action,
that what action I have performed is open to multiple representations.
That is, perhaps, why Fischer switches between bodily movements and
actions as the constraints on representations of the story of my life. Those
movements admit of diverse interpretations, different representations of
what action is performed, but the movements of the body seem to provide
a constraint on interpretations and representation. However, my story of
my life, what my life is like for me, depends on how I represent my actions.
My proposal is that I represent my actions in terms of my experience of
them. This brings us back to the account of exemplar representation. It is
the conscious experience of my actions, the focusing of aesthetic attention
on the exemplar of experience, that converts the exemplar into representa-
tion, showing us what the action is like and, in part, what the life containing
the action is like.
An illustration, suggested by his account of story telling as artistic
activity, is when I paint on canvas, as I often do, engaged in artistic activity.
What I paint may constrain interpretation however diverse those interpre-
( 82 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
tations may be. In my painting of Blue [Web ASK 26], whether you inter-
pret it as a painting of sky, gaiety of a clear sky, painting of water, ominous as
the sea, the painting of blue is the vehicle of representation. There are fea-
tures of painting and features of movement that provide constraints on the
story they are used to tell. My interpretation of those movements, my con-
strual of them as some definite action, is grounded, not just in the intersub-
jective account of movements, but in my experience of them. It is my
experience of what I do that leads me to represent it the way I do in terms of
my experience.
How do I represent my actions or movements in terms of my experience
of those movements to tell the story of my life? The role of conscious
experience in representation used as an exemplar answers the question.
Once the exemplar role of conscious experience is included in the story, it
becomes odd to include only actions realized in bodily movements as parts
of the story of my life. Are my thoughts and feelings not part of the story of
my life? Fischer is interested in the role of action as self-expression to con-
nect the story of our lives with freedom and responsibility of action. But the
thoughts and feelings on which our actions are strung, like clothes on a line,
are central ingredients in the story of our lives and the meaning of them.
Let me comment first on the question of value discussed previously, for the
meaningfulness of life depends on the value of the story artistically created.
Fischer concentrates a good deal of energy on the question of what kind of
value the activity of constructing the story has and what kind of value the
product, the story told, has. A robust literature has developed on the rela-
tionship between aesthetic value and moral value. Fischer notes correctly
that telling the story of our life selects something from among the totality.
Storytelling involves choice. As we choose what to include in the story, we
ask what experiences and activities are an expression of self. The choice is
artistic, governed, Fischer suggests, by aesthetic concerns and aesthetic
value. The product of this choice has another kind of value: moral value.
To be candid, I do not buy this way of dividing value up into the activity
and product of our constructing the story of life. The activity may be mor-
ally corrupt. Those concocting the stories may serve their vanity, their lust
for fame, and other worldly concerns. And the product may be one of
beauty, a beautiful mind. I think that the bifurcation in value, as noted pre-
viously, is a deep philosophical error stemming from eighteenth-century
theories of beauty, though not only that. It is a theory of beauty detached
from the concerns of life. Our early ancestors had aesthetic concerns as they
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 83 )
painted walls, themselves, and the utensils of life but would not have under-
stood the isolationist theory of beauty. Whether something was beautiful
was, and is, a matter of how it is connected with life outside of art.
So is the value that endows our stories, either the process of construction
or the product thereof, aesthetic or moral? I think there is mischief in the
question. The construction of the story and the story itself have a kind of
value that is, as I have suggested in previous chapters, generic. The telling of
the story and the story told may be the story of a life that has value. We may
ask whether the life is morally good or aesthetically good. It may be both.
More deeply, it may be neither. It may be a life of value even if it is neither
morally praiseworthy nor beautiful. The film, A Beautiful Mind, about math-
ematician John Nash, is misnamed. It is not beautiful as the subject lives in
schizophrenic delusion interacting with phantoms of the malady. Is it a mor-
ally good life? That seems doubtful. Yet the life has value, a kind of value
more fundamental than our concerns with the pleasures of beauty or the
morals of praise or blame. This is only a proposal arising from my phenom-
enal experience of value. I experience the value of something, a life or an
action or a work. I may be bewildered by the question of what kind of value
it has. One of the most famous paintings of the last century is the Black
Square by Malevich [Web Ask 12]. It blocks the figurative take and leads to
an experience Malevich connected with the supreme. There is merit in it. Is
the merit moral merit arising from leading us beyond the Veil of Maya? One
might say so, but that does not capture the merit of the activity or the prod-
uct. Is it aesthetic? The Black Square is not beautiful. The value of the
painting, like the value of the lives of viewers it seeks to enrich, is generic.
This fundamental form of value is important in our lives. The dissection of
it into species may distract us from the wonder and immediacy of the expe-
rience of value or merit. The appeal to linguistic intuitions about the terms
“moral” and “aesthetic” to describe the experience of this kind can obscure
the experience of value. This is not an objection to Fischer. It is a suggestion
that there is more to the value of a life than is captured by aesthetics and
morals.
VEHICLES OF CONTENT
EXEMPLARS
I have offered (Lehrer, 1997, 2001, 2006) an answer elsewhere that I believe
compliments the account Fischer offers. This idea, developed earlier in this
book, is that my experiences can become samples or exemplars that become
representational, that become vehicles of content, at the same time that
they are part of the content represented. Using what is represented as
the vehicle of representation closes the gap between vehicle and content.
Consider a person who experiences a flash of color that they have never
seen, a flash of red, and knows what it is like from the experience. The
person knows immediately what the experience of color is like from the
way it is experienced. Attention is drawn to it, let us imagine, unlike many
experiences that pass through the mind unnoticed. One knows what the
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 85 )
noticed ones are like, and what they are like is both presented to the mind
and becomes the content of the experience at the same time that experi-
ence represents the content.
Lopes (1996) in his important work on art has proposed that an artwork
represents an object if and only if it enables the viewer to recognize the
object. He takes this as a mark of figurative form or content. I propose that
when an exemplar is used to mark a distinction, content is created, whether
figurative or not. The activity of marking a distinction in terms of an exem-
plar is exemplarization that enables one to recognize objects that constitute
the class of objects that constitute the content. So exemplarization, whether
of something figurative or not, is partially captured by the Lopes notion of
representation. My claim is that the exemplar exhibits the content and is, at
the same time, a part of the content. A distinction is marked by an exemplar
that is part and parcel of the content it represents. Exemplarization uses the
exemplar as a vehicle of representation taking it as an exhibit of a kind or
form of content represented.
Marking a distinction, creating content, is an activity of self-expression.
This leads us back to the story Fischer constructed of the story of a life.
Note the connection between what I am arguing and Fischer’s fascinating
idea of the activity, artistic activity, of constructing a story of a life as an
account of the life of the self. We do not attend to all of our experiences in a
way that marks a distinction. We do not exemplarize everything. A special
focus and attention is required. This is because of the role of experience in
exemplarized content. By contrast, words represents things without being
exemplarized, without being used to show us what a word is like, at least
most words most of the time. The word “word” may sometimes be an
exception, though the word “word” is not a good sample of a word to exhibit
what words are like. The exemplarized experience, of an action—painting,
for example—exhibits what the represented objects are like. Exemplarizing
the experience of action marks the space dividing it into what is and what is
not contained in the marked space.
Sometimes we exemplarize without any reflection. The activity requires
attention, but attention may result from sensory intensity and be driven in
a way that is not of our choosing. Miserable sensations are of this kind.
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 87 )
Now the proposals of Fischer suggest that the story of our life is a story that
would involve further selection. Not everything that catches our attention
with enough intensity to become exemplarized has the salience or impor-
tance for us to think of it as part of the story of our life. When we move to
description, to linguistic representation, that further selection occurs that
makes up the story of our life and carries the meaning of our life, the content
of the self. Philosophers are engaged in the life of discourse, of description,
and they, like narrative artists, are wont to attach special importance to what
they do well. Philosophers talk the story.
Others may be less verbal, especially visual artists. There is a story of
their life, but the story is contained in the selected episodes, especially those
of artistic creation which, being exemplarized, are both part of the content
of the life and vehicles of the content. Verbal description may contribute to
( 88 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
the story of a life. But the story a person has of his or her life may be full of
representation that is not verbal. The visual artist may examine her art, and,
intently conscious of what it is like and what it means about creating it,
think, “That is the most important chapter of my life.” Content is exhibited
and represented by the exemplarization of experience that captures our
attention and interest.
To make the account cogent and to effectively close the gap between the
vehicle and the content of story, it is essential to notice that there are layers
of meaning or content of experience. Return to Monochrome Blue. As I
attend to the sensory experience of the painting, I may first generalize to a
class of experiences and, at the same time, mark the distinction between the
members of that class and other sensory experiences, other colors. As an
artist, I may think of the experience as exhibiting ultramarine blue, aesthet-
ically perfected. I may use the same exemplar to stand for other things, the
paint on the canvas, the paint in tube, the painting Monochrome Blue, and
more romantically, the potential beauty of a blue mood. An exemplar of
experience can represent many things exhibiting what they are like. Some
of those activities of interpretation are not at all automatic. I must decide
what to make of some experiences, what content they represent. This is
something taken—not just given—and created—not just presented. The
way we use the exemplars of experience to make content, to make our
world, is a paradigm of self-expression.
I see something missing from the Fischer story of our story. It is the way in
which we make our world out of our experiences. Goodman (1978) has
insisted on this, so has Heidegger (1971), though he uses other words, of
course. This leads back to Fischer in a loop. For as we focus on our experi-
ences and activities and exemplarize them to yield the content of our world,
we notice, with minimal reflection, that it is we who are making this world.
I compose my world out of salient experiences. This shows me what I am
like. I make my world and notice in that self-expression, that freedom, what
I am like. My story is not just the telling of a story. It is a multimedia creation
out of my experiences, creating content, creating meaning, which may
occur prior to linguistic articulation.
Consider the possibility of undescribed stories of meaningful lives
embedded in the experiences of them. That possibility is realized in the
artistic corpus of great artists—Monet, Van Gogh, Pollock, Vik Muniz—
whose art provides a conscious experience of what their lives are like, as far
as they are revealed in their art to our consciousness for exemplar represen-
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 89 )
tation of what the creative actions of those lives are like. The work of an
artist offers us an aesthetic opportunity for the exemplar representation of
his life as he offers it to himself. Representation of conscious exemplars will
differ, of course, because the conscious experiences of the same object will
differ as will the background information of the interpreter. Moreover,
when an artist, myself, for example, picks up the brush and creates a
painting, there may be the kind of immediacy in the action, the kind of self-
lessness in the immediacy of the creative act, placing some red impulsively
at a spot in the painting. We often act with immediacy in art without
reflecting on how our action fits into the artwork, much less on the story
of our life. That unreflective immediacy is like the unreflective immediacy
of aesthetic experience. The creative act, the act that changes the content of
self and experience, is often unreflective. Tying the act into the meaning of
a life is another creative act. The artist focusing attention on the experience
of what he has done or is doing marks a distinction in terms of the experi-
ence, creating the form and content of the creative action. It is the exem-
plarization of the experience of my behavior that makes it my action, part of
the story of my life, represented by me. I am conscious of creating artistic
content by my activity as I exemplarize the experience of it. The experience
of the action, like the experience of a color sensation, opens the possibility
of the creative self-expression of exemplarizing the action into my life.
I note here the relationship, which again Fischer considers important,
between the creation of the story and aesthetic activity. Aesthetic activity,
artistic activity, whether of an artist of trade or an artist of life consists in a
special reaction, a special focusing of attention on sensory materials that
opens us up to the activity of making content and meaning out of our expe-
riences. However, questions remain. One is the question of how the content
created becomes the content of the story of a life. This need not be automatic.
I may take an action of mine toward a student as benevolent, as an exhibit
of my goodness in the world. A bit of further reflection may reveal another
side. As the student departs from my views, it may become apparent to me
that it was vanity and not benevolence that motivated my education of him.
The initial created content does not fit the world and should not be pro-
jected onto the world. The arts in the usual sense give a clearer example.
I might exercise my freedom to interpret a work of art, to make the content
out of my experience of it. Then I confront my freedom at another step as
I choose whether or not to view the content of artwork as an accurate rep-
resentation of the world outside of the artwork. Whether it is the Black
Square of Malevich blocking representation to lead me beyond the appear-
ance to supreme reality, or Goya blocking the heroism of warriors to show
us the extremities of cruelty of war, I have a decision of whether to choose
to project this content, this conception, as the content of world outside of
( 90 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
the artwork. The choice of projection is an activity of the self and is an act
of self-expression.
The artist in constructing a work of art, in his creative activities, is
revealing to himself and to others what the story of his life is like, the artistic
part of the story at least. The artist might not have produced the work that
awakens our aesthetic awareness of what it is like. We take the experience of
creating representation out of our experiences of what the artwork is like as
revealing something about the intersection between our story and the story
of the life of the artist. We may misunderstand the intentions that initially
drove the making of the piece, of course. There remains something invisible
about the mind of another no matter how intent the other may be on
revealing her thought and feeling to us. However, as we experience the work
aesthetically, as we exemplarize our experience of the work to show us what
the form and content of it are like, part of the story of life of the artist gets
included in the content of the exemplar representation of what the work is
like. For our experience exhibits to us how we conceive of the creative
action of the other, her creation of the artwork. That exemplar representa-
tion of the artwork from our conscious experience becomes part of our
story of the story of the life of the artist. We may be wrong in what we think.
We may wrong in what we think about O’Keefe as we exemplarize our con-
scious experience of her painting of Ice Cave, for example. But it is part of
our representation, our exemplarization, existing before the fall of words
breaks the silence of our response, that painting the work is part of the life
of the artist. We may be unsure of what is communicated, but the incorpo-
ration of action of the artist in our representation of what our conscious
experience is like makes the experience communal.
Is there anything special about art in this form of representation? As I am
conscious of any action of another, I may represent the action of the other
in my representation of what the action is like. There is something special if
not unique about the art experience. It is the communal aspect of focusing
aesthetic attention on the experience of the artwork to form an exemplar
representation of what the work is like in terms of the exemplar to reveal
form and content. That is what the artist does no matter how much is acci-
dental and the result of unconscious influences. The artist has chosen, as a
free and autonomous agent, to confront you with a task she must undertake
as an artist. She chooses to confront you with an object that evokes con-
sciousness and challenges you to construct form and content in the exem-
plarization of the consciousness of it.
The revelation that takes us back to the story with which we began is
simple and transparent. How I choose to construct meaning out of my
experience shows me what I am like. I am doing this. Others may intervene
and cajole me, but I stand as the point of choice of projection. I am that
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 91 )
point of the story I create and the projection of the content onto the world.
My experience of the deeds and episodes of my life are the exemplars that
carry the meaning I give them, however biased or even self-serving my
exemplarization of them might be. I confess I somewhat mistrust the verbal
articulation of the story. There is a story of my life carried by the experi-
ences of my life as vehicles of representation. That level of representation,
however mixed it becomes with verbal representation, is, though fallible in
construction, still grounded in the experiences of my life. I exemplarize
them as the vehicles of content. Art confronts us with the challenge of
exemplarizing the experience of the artwork, and the challenge is extended
from art to life as we form exemplar representation of the experiences of
our life. Art challenges us to exemplarize our experience of art, and extends
the challenge to life. Our representations may not be accurate representa-
tions of the complexities of life, but they are at least grounded in themselves
as they refer to themselves as well as all the rest. They have the security of
self-representation, the exemplar is a member of the class it represents,
however great the adventure of extrapolation beyond the exemplar may be.
Art teaches us to take exemplarization from art to life.
There is another question, raised by Hume (1739). What ties the com-
ponents of the story together into a unified whole? Notice first, as others
have, both Velleman (2003) and Fischer (2009), that interpretation and
projection allows for re-interpretation and re-projection by the same
individual. Simply put, as long as I live, the story might change, including
the story about my past. Another can tell the final story of my life, once I am
dead. And then, of course, it is the story of me told by another and not by
me. And there will be multiple stories, multiple interpretations, even if I
were, per impossible, able to record every moment of my life. It looks, then,
as though the story of the self is equivocal, whether told by the person or
another, whether received by the person or another.
OWNERSHIP CHOICE
To follow Fischer (1994, 2009) further into his story, let me suggest calling
the states that hold the story of the life together ownership states. This may
seem to depart from the idea of Fischer that the ownership of activities is
captured by the view that such activities are ones the agent would think,
“This is up to me.” I suggest that the ownership states are keystone states.
Nevertheless, as I choose activities as being my activities, free acts of self-
expression, that choice is itself a free act of self-expression. As my act of
choice selects my acts of self-expression and is, at the same time, one of
those acts, it chooses itself as a vehicle in the story of my life. That choice is
a vehicle of content, but it is also part of the content of the story. It refers to
my other actions of self-expression and to itself.
Why, in addition to the actions of self-expression, is the ownership
choice necessary? There are two reasons. First, as I have noted, there
may be nothing in the character of the actions to tie them together in a
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 93 )
experimental. The remark of an artist indicates that the work, that is chosen
to be what it is by the artist, is not chosen without any residual conflict bet-
ween preferences, including preferences at different levels of preference. I
can prefer to have the preference structure I have leading to the preference
of my self-portrait, MetaMe, in the collection of Prof. Engel in Geneva,
reproduced on the cover about my work by Olsson (2003), without
resolving aesthetic preferences. It could be more realistic. It could be more
abstract. I could look more confident. I could look wilder. The complexity
and conflict among my preferences is a conflict I prefer. It enriches my art
and keeps it from being predictable. I chose the painting as finished auton-
omously, though not, in Frankfurt’s sense, wholeheartedly, for I preferred
the preference structure leading to that choice even though it was not free
of conflict.
Fischer proposes ownership as a condition of the kind of freedom
required for moral responsibility. The account of ownership choice pro-
posed here in terms of power preference expands into an account of a free
action resulting from a power preference. An ultrapreference for being
guided by a system of reasons is a power preference that makes the reasons
my reasons for action. This goes beyond what Fischer proposes. Guidance
by reasons and being open to such guidance must be something I prefer.
The account is compatiblist, not semi, but full. Fischer has declared himself
agnostic on the issue of the compatibility of freedom and determinism. My
proposal is that freedom of action is the result of my action being up to me,
as Fischer suggests, and guided by reasons as I prefer. My free action is one
I perform because of my power preference for the action to be guided by
my reasons.
Fischer and Ravizza (1998) have insisted on the importance of being
open to the guidance of reasons. They should recognize that whether
something is a reason that will guide my actions—that is, a reason for
me—depends on my preference for being guided by such reasons. As an
artist, to be autonomous and creative, I have to choose what consider-
ations, what critiques, for example, will guide my work, and, more impor-
tantly, by implication which ones will not. An artist may have his reasons
for what he does, though at times he will eschew guidance for spontaneity,
but he must, if he is autonomous, choose what will guide his work. Being
guided by reasons in a way that renders me free and not manipulated by a
line of reasoning requires that I choose, or prefer to choose, to be guided in
my choices and actions by such reasons. It must be up to me, not only that
I do what I do, but that I am guided by the reasons I am. Manipulation by
reasons will not make me free. Suppose I am an artist whose work is manip-
ulated by the reasoning of a successful gallery owner imposing his com-
mercially viable aesthetic using financial pressure. My work is not free
( 96 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
CONCLUSION
Fischer argued that the free actions, the actions of self-expression, play a special
role in the story of the person in that they are the vehicles of content for the
construction of that story. I have argued that those actions are both representa-
tions in the story of life, vehicles of content, and, at the same time, part of content
represented. In this they are like a sample of the life of the person. A sample
plays the special role of being an exemplar functioning as a vehicle of content
and part of the content. The exemplar represents content as part of the story.
It loops back onto itself to become part of what the exemplarized story is about.
Exemplarized actions loop back on to themselves, referring to them-
selves, as they exhibit a part of the story they represent. Finally, I have sug-
gested that there is choice, though not always a reflective choice, of what
actions become parts of the story of the life of the person. Put in the first
person, I appropriate those actions as part of me in contrast to actions from
which I am alienated, an unintended offense to another, for example.
The choice involves a judgment of value, and, I propose, that is a kind of
generic value that a life and the story of the life possess.
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 97 )
So the question arises with respect to every creation: what is it like? That
necessitates the exemplarization of the experience of it. As he chooses, pre-
ferring to choose because he prefers to choose in that way, from those pref-
erences and reasons for preference, his choice is an ownership choice. He is
choosing to make his creation of that piece part of the story of his artistic
life. The distinction between art and life vanishes as he chooses his art, con-
structing form and content in the exemplarization of the form and content
of it. He may not be able to tell us what the form and content of his works is
like. There is a reason. It is that the conscious experience he creates with his
work is part of content, part of what it is like, and is inseparable from the
content. He knows what his work is like, even when he cannot say what it is
like. When he does say what it is like, he will want to show you the work, so
that your conscious experience will fill in that part of the meaning or content
that he cannot verbally express. The content is there, in experience, not
here, in discourse.
What about the ownership choice of the artist? It is special in the way it
is connected with his art. What he keeps tells the story of his life just because
it is a salient action in his life. But what he keeps, the artwork, evokes an
experience that exhibits the content of the work. So, the choice of his works,
of what will be his work and what will not be his work, is a choice of story
within a story. The life is a story, but the content of the works is the content
of a world that he chooses as he chooses the works. Of course, his choice of
the story within the story, the content within the works that he chooses, is
a choice of what he his like. Anyone who acts, on the Fischer account, when
the action is free action of self-expression, exhibits to you in your experi-
ence of his actions, what his story is like. But the artist transcends the first
level of representation in the exemplarization of the experience of his
actions. He creates works that give us another level of representation in the
exemplarization of the experience of his art. We see a story within his story.
This is no regress. His story loops back onto itself as he chooses the first
level of representation incorporating another level in his story which ties
the content of his stories together in his ownership choice. The artist auton-
omous chooses the world and self of his art. The ownership choice loops
back unto itself, tying the created world of the art and artist up, down, and
together.
What about the stories others tell? Is the story told by a person consist-
ing of his free actions of self-expression a constraint on the stories others
can tell of the life of the person? It is more than that. It is the life of a person
chosen by the person as an action of self-expression. Others can comment
on the life of a person, retelling the story in their own way. Only the person
himself or herself can use his or her choices and actions as samples, exem-
plars, keystones of free self-expression of himself or herself. I note in closing
A R T I S T I C C R E AT I O N , F R E E D O M , A N D S E L F ( 99 )
that the contrast between the individual and social conception of a person
are themselves tied together. The story the person tells, the individual story,
is aggregated from the stories others tell about the actions of the person.
The story others tell, the social story, is an aggregation of the stories others
tell about those actions. The model of aggregation I proposed with Wagner
(Lehrer and Wagner, 1981, Lehrer, 1997) is a model of vectors of influence
articulated as the weights we give to the stories people tell. The story of
aggregation with the mathematical modeling of it is a story I and Wagner
have told and is part of my story, a part you may not know, like many of the
most important parts of the stories of the life of a person. There is a social
aggregation that represents a consensual story of a self. The individual may
choose to accept or reject the consensual aggregation of the story. That
choice is a special part of the story of self-expression, the freedom of self,
and, the self itself. The choice of an artist to remain outside the consensual
aggregation is the choice of the artist to remain outside the constraints of
social convention. It is that choice that makes art that part of experience
that changes the content of experience through the autonomy of artistic
choice.
This page intentionally left blank
ﱞ
CHAPTER 6
I have been discussing the role of the artist as he creates an object that pro-
vokes a conscious experience that we respond to aesthetically by
converting it into an exemplar representation. The exemplarization of expe-
rience of creative actions plays a special role in the story of the life of the
artist. As he takes ownership of his creative actions in an ownership choice,
the representation of his actions, his creative actions most especially, become
the story of his life. The exemplarization of the experience of the choice
loops back onto itself to complete the story for the moment. The idea of the
completion of the story of the life of an artist, of the complete representation
of a life, raises the question about the relationship of death to the completion
of the story. As we think about the story of the life of the artist, and in this we
share a common bond and fate of choosing our story until death, the impli-
cations of death for the story of life, for that grand aesthetic act of the exem-
plarization of the experiences of life that completes the life, it is essential to
address the position of death in art, beauty, and the story of life. Death com-
pletes the story of a life. But the experienced moments of life precede death,
if not the process of dying. So, to put the matter in the first person, where I
shall put it for this chapter and hold it there, it seems that my death is not
part of the story of my life for me, not an experience of mine to be exemplar-
ized. Yet, I shall suggest, death adds value and sometimes beauty to a life. If I
am right in this, then the discussion of death will reveal something
fundamental to our understanding of aesthetics. It will reveal that as we
( 101 )
( 102 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
I came into existence did not seem to matter, and, by parity of reason, the
absence of me and my world after my death should matter no more. This is
the symmetry thesis. Yet, empirically, emotionally, death does matter. So
why? There are two answers. One is biological. One is existential. Biology
first. The utility of a biological drive to continue to exist for an individual
and species seems obvious. So perhaps existential anxiety is simply the
reflection of a powerful drive to continue to exist combined with the recog-
nition that it will at some point fail to be realized. There are two useful com-
ponents, a drive to continue to exist and an intellectual grasp of truth. Both
are useful, but when they combine there is the stress resulting from the rec-
ognition of the truth that the drive will be thwarted. One support for this
theory is that reflection on the symmetry thesis does, from my experience,
reduce the anxiety connected with death. Another is that many experience
the disappearance of the anxiety as age reduces the drive to exist. Perhaps
this captures the wit of Zarathustra, who, when asked what he advised about
death replied only, “Die at the right time” (Nietzsche, 1967, 69). By the
right time, he meant, I believe, when the body is biologically ready for
death.
Whatever the truth of the biological thesis, there does seem to be
something more problematic and paradoxical about death. It is probably
related to the insight of Augustine (1950) and Descartes (1986) about the
cogito and, more simply, a kind of necessity in the statement or thought, “I
exist.” But I think that there is more to the death paradox than that. For
someone might reply that, of course, if you think or say you exist, then, nec-
essarily, you do, which means, the thought or statement “I do not exist” is
necessarily false, taken literally, at any rate, but there is no paradox in that.
The paradox is better captured by the philosophy of Sartre (1943), to which
de Beauvoir (1966, 1984) seems committed as well, concerning the self,
consciousness, freedom, and the past.
Suppose I ask what I am, and answer in terms of the story of my life to
date. Is that what I am? In a way, but as Sartre notes, I am my past in the
mode of not being it. The reason is that I am conscious of my projection
into the future and the freedom of choice about it I confront. So part of
what I am is my future choices. However, they do not yet exist. Of course,
my past no longer exists either, except in my present consciousness of it. My
future choices do not yet exist apart from my present consciousness of
them. My consciousness of memories of my past actions and my conscious
anticipations of my future are exemplars I can exemplarize, convert to rep-
resentations, to tell the story of my life. But my present consciousness is
what I am for me now. Looked at this way, the self, the I, is not the past,
which no longer exists, nor the future, which does not yet exist, but present
consciousness, which is its past and its future in the mode of not being
( 104 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
Is there more to be said about death than that it is intelligible and may be
captured in a final thought? There is a loop of exemplarization that ties a life
together. But that leaves open the question of how to think about the life
tied together in a loop. I propose the right way to think about life and, there-
fore, death, is as Fischer (2009) has suggested, aesthetically. A life and the
closure of it with death is a story and an artwork. Heidegger (1949) writes
of Dasein as being unto death. It is clear that for Heidegger, the angst
connected with seeing your being as being unto death was a form of authen-
ticity. But why authenticity? Why lead an authentic life rather than an amus-
ing one, if authenticity does not amuse you? I believe the answer, of which
Heidegger may have approved, is that the experience of beauty, and, espe-
cially, the beauty of a life requires that life be tied together in a way that
requires the recognition of death.
“Death,” Stevens (1990) wrote, “is the mother of all beauty.” He has fas-
cinated and puzzled people with that remark. It is not so puzzling. I recently
attended a ceremony, a large and wonderful outdoor ceremony, to celebrate
the death of my friend Glorya Mueller. She died well, sipping some wine
with family the night before her death. I thought about the life of Glorya as
I had offered to speak. Suddenly, as I focused attention on my experience of
her life, a remarkable exemplar representation of it moved me in special
way. The life of Glorya was a thing of beauty. My appreciation of the beauty
of that life depended, in part, on the exemplar representation of the com-
pletion of it, on the wholeness of it, on its being what it was. I could not
appreciate the beauty of that life, though I admired the way Glorya lived,
until her death. Death gave birth to the beauty of that life. The loop of
beauty spread like rings in a pond when a stone is cast. I thought of her
appreciation of flowers, her wonderful creation of an environment of her
unique hacienda. This seemed to me to be connected with her own sense of
death at the end of life, her acceptance of it, her tying it into the loop of her
life. Other people had pretty flowers. Hers, especially in her presence, were
beautiful. That the life ends, that the world we represent out of the con-
scious experiences of our life will end, gives us a meaning that creates the
experience of beauty. It is not an accident that a sunset, the end of days and
a symbol of endings, is a natural source of beauty.
What is the explanation for this connection between beauty and death?
It is more complicated than one would think. It is connected with the satis-
faction of the senses. We say of wine and women as well as sunsets and
songs that they are beautiful. But to find beauty we must be moved. We are
moved by intensity and the evanescence of experience. Thought loops back
onto endings for completeness. Experience is in the present. Is there just
evanescence? Is the point that it will vanish in a moment? There is something
else. There is eternity in the moment, in the exemplar representation of
( 108 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
passion, not science, that motivates belief in a life after death. We have an
infinite passion for our own eternal beatitude, he says, that enables us to
believe with certainty in the promise of it. So is it unscientific and irrational
to believe in a life after death? I find that answer too quick and dogmatic.
C. D. Broad (1958) and C. J. Ducasse (1951), among others, were empiri-
cists who interested themselves with the issue applying the canons of sci-
ence and reason to the question. I do not think either of them was governed
by superstition. As they examined the evidence, especially Ducasse, they
found most of it was misleading and/or fraudulent. But some evidence was
not so readily shown to be so. A student asked Ducasse what conclusion he
had reached about life after death. “Do people survive bodily death?” he
asked. Ducasse is said to have replied with the question, “Do you want a
scientific answer?” Having received an affirmative reply from the student,
Ducasse answered, “Yes, sometimes, for a little while.” Having met him
when I was a student, I think the reply is one he might well have given. It is
far from the eternal beatitude Kierkegaard passionately desired.
So what about Kierkegaard? It is a subjective matter, as he would have
insisted. I love life but I do not have an infinite passion for eternal beatitude.
Not as far as I can tell. This is not the place to enter into the rationality of
believing in the existence of something for which you have an infinite pas-
sion. A person with such a passion might succeed and put aside rationality
for the sake of faith. But what do I think? I follow the path of reason as far as
it leads me, and at the end of the path, I attempt to reside there. Where
reason dictates neither belief nor disbelief, I am content with uncertainty.
I have had spiritual experiences, however. I trembled, to my surprise,
when I confronted the Wailing Wall and was drawn irresistibly to touch it.
Upon touching it, I experienced a powerful emotion of presence. Such
experiences are rare and mysterious. What is the explanation? What do
they prove? I prefer to enjoy the memory of those experiences and let them
become exemplar representations of something sacred. I do not use them
as a premise of proof. I do not use the experiences as data to be explained.
They become instead exemplar representations of the sacredness of being
like a work of art. Is it life or art? It is art and life exemplarized together in a
loop.
Does this influence, then, my views on death? It leads me toward Spinoza
(2000). I feel myself to be a small modification of being looping back onto
itself of something greater, of the modification of infinite attributes of being,
of nature, perhaps of God identified with Nature. But are the attributes
really infinite? They loop back onto themselves. There is infinity in a closed
loop. This is not knowledge or necessity, however, but an exemplarized
feeling or sentiment. The loop of the self onto itself in the completion of
itself gives rise to the experience of beauty. It becomes a metaphor for a
( 110 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
greater loop of being onto itself of which we are a modification. Life, death,
and beauty are tied up, down, and together in a metaphorical loop of being
back onto itself. The meaning of life is a metaphor—a loop from the exem-
plarized experience of a finite moment to infinite eternity back to itself
(Lehrer, 1997). Enjoy the figure.
“Man be my metaphor.”
– Dylan Thomas
ﱞ
CHAPTER 7
like. It may suffice to say that there is some underlying state that is exem-
plarized in cognitive processing of consciousness. If the existence of the
underlying state is acknowledged, the question of whether to call that state
conscious prior to the cognitive processing may become verbal.
The question then arises as to what happens when a conscious state is
exemplarized. There are two operations that are essential. The first, men-
tioned by Hume (1739), is generalization. There is generalization that may
be in part automatic but may also have a contextual or autonomous aspect.
The experience of a pain and other sensations that attract attention imme-
diately leads to a generalization that is spontaneous and probably automatic.
Generalizing reveals itself behaviorally in subsequent identification and re-
identification. There is, however, another component to exemplarizing that
is often implicitly included in the notion of generalizing, but it is useful to
emphasize this component because of the special importance of it in con-
ceptualization. It is the component of forming a distinction between the
experience and what it is not. Spencer-Brown (1969) argues that conceptu-
alization begins with marking a distinction between something and what it
is not. It is natural to suppose that in generalizing, one distinguishes the
objects in the plurality of the generalization from what is not in the plu-
rality. But the conception of something not being in the plurality adds to
the inferential role of the concept. It is one thing to respond to a group of
objects, and it is a further conceptual step to distinguish that group of things
from what they are not using the exemplar to mark the distinction. Marking
the distinction with the exemplar in that way is essential to the inferential
and, hence, fully conceptual role of the exemplar as a term in thought.
Once the distinction is marked by the exemplar, we have marked what is
contained in the marked plurality from what is not so marked. So marking
a distinction in terms of the exemplar that stands for the plurality in the
marked space is an activity of using the exemplar to mark a distinction bet-
ween those things that have the form of the exemplar and those that do not.
The form of the exemplarized experience consists of the operation of exem-
plarization. The form of the distinction is the operation of exemplarizing
the exemplar to mark a distinction. Spencer-Brown (1969) argued, we
noted, that the laws of form based on marking a distinction, whether by
exemplarization or in some other way, connect with principles of logic that
generate the power of mathematics without paradox. Exemplarizing, I pro-
pose, is generalizing plus marking a distinction.
I should make it clear that the account that I am offering here does not
depend on the account of laws of form proposed by Spencer-Brown. Some
other formal and logical structure might be combined with exemplariza-
tion to obtain the same result. However, it is important to notice that exem-
plarization has the power of conceptualization, of distinguishing the content
A E S T H E T I C E X P E R I E N C E , I N T E N T I O N A L I T Y, F OR M OF R E P R E S E N TAT I O N ( 117 )
reference of the exemplar back onto itself is at the same time a truth loop.
That may explain how we know what the experience is like when we experi-
ence what it is like. We know what it is like by exemplarizing it. We use it to
refer to a plurality of particulars as an exhibit of what they are like in distinc-
tion from others. As a referring exemplar, it has instances as a predicate
does, and instantiates itself. Exemplarization yields conception and
knowledge of what the exemplar is like in a loop of truth.
Some, Papineau (2002, 2007), and my earlier self (Lehrer, 1996) as well,
following the lead of Sellars (1963), have proposed that the analogy of
exemplarization to disquotation, which we noted in Chapter 2, explains the
self-reference. I now think, following Ismael (2007) and Fürst (2010), that
is an inadequate though suggestive explanation. The exemplar is used, not
mentioned, to show us what it is like. A being incapable of understanding
quotation, let alone disquotation, could know what the experience is like.
The referential loop of the exemplar may suggest the analogy of disquota-
tion, but that is not the only way in which something can exhibit what
something is like. Consider a model of self-reference suggested by Reid
(1785) to account for the evidence of a first principle. He remarked that
light, as it reveals illuminated objects, reveals itself at the same time. It is a
more naturalistic model and does not require the semantics of disquota-
tion. The exemplar reveals what a plurality of experiences is like and, being
at the same time one of those experiences, reveals itself.
and at the same time how we conceive of the paint in terms of how it
appears.
We are not constrained to using the exemplar to represent sensory expe-
riences of paint. Our aesthetic response to the work of art may take us to a
more personal and even metaphysical level of interpretation. We may think
of the sensory experience as exhibiting how pretty blue can be. The blue is
very pretty. We may go beyond that and think of the exemplar as showing us
a special feeling, a feeling of how blue can be wonderful. Or further, we
might find that it shows us how agreeable it can be to enter into a void, even
a blue void, that takes us beyond the world of objects and cognition to a
more peaceful and spiritual emptiness. The sensory exemplar can exem-
plarize cool emptiness. But those words do not show us what cool empti-
ness is like. The sensory exemplar can, in a moment of autonomous
exemplarization, refer to that state as it shows us what it is like. That level of
representation is autonomous choice. The choice exhibits the form of rep-
resentation and shows us what autonomously chosen intentionality is like.
It was a mistake of phenomenalists to think that sensory experiences
could only be used to refer to other sensory experiences. It would be the
same mistake some philosophers make when they assume that words or
text can only be used to refer to words or text. Reference is ontologically
promiscuous, and sensory experiences, in this domain as in others, exploit
that promiscuity for their own purposes. One of those purposes is to exem-
plarize the sensory experience to exhibit what the object we conceive is
like, what the paint is like or what cool emptiness is like, in one direction,
and to exhibit how we conceive of that, in the other. Exhibiting both what
is conceived and how we conceive of it, the exemplar provides a Janus-faced
view of what intentionality and the form of representation are like.
It will be noted that there is more to our conception of paint than the
appearance of color shows us, and there is more to paint than the appear-
ance of it. The claim that the exemplarized sample shows us what our con-
ception of the object is like and at the same time shows what the object is
like requires qualification. Ostensive exemplarization of an exemplar of
experience to stand for other experiences that are like it may show us in
some special cases all we know about what the exemplar is like. It may show
us all we know about how we conceive of what it stands for, namely, experi-
ences like it. But when the exemplar is exemplarized to show us what a
material object is like, there is more to what we know about what it is like
than the exemplar exhibits. For example, if the experience is exemplarized
as the appearance of International Klein Blue paint, we know more about
the paint than how it appears. We may know, for example, that it is solid
pigment suspended in a solution and not dissolved. We may also know
more about how we conceive of the paint than the exemplar shows us about
( 122 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
There are automatic levels of response, to be sure, but beyond those there
are exemplar representations we choose. We choose the mode of represen-
tation and the content of it. The content autonomously chosen becomes
part of the content of our world.
We may seek the world of art thinking that however we interpret the art-
works, whatever content arises from the way we use the exemplar to mark a
distinction in exemplar representation, we do so in the world of fiction, as
Walton (1990) insists, using the artworks as props of make-believe. So we
can enjoy the license of make-believe. We can identify with the exemplar-
ized content of good or evil, of heroes or villains, of admirable or nasty, with
a comfort. It is only make-believe. Some have argued, Devereaux (2004)
most notably, that the need to identify with an evil character, a pedophile,
for example, undermines the value, the value of the artwork as art. There is
something very controversial in this claim. The controversy arises from the
simple fact that intentionality, the thought of an object, lacks the magic to
make it exist. It is not part of the world but merely a part of make-believe.
On the other hand, at least in my own case, I find there is something uncom-
fortable about the identification with Humbert lusting after Lolita in
Nabokov’s novel Lolita (1955) no matter how greatly I admire the prose,
the convincing portrayal of the character and the insight into personality it
offers. The point is that you are involved in the world of make-believe you
construct out of the images of the work. How you exemplarize Lot and His
Daughters, by Joachim Antonisz Wtewael [Web ASK 28], in the great
painting of them at the Los Angeles County Museum of Art, is, past the
initial take, up to you. How you exemplarize the sensory material is up to
you after the initial experience of the painting.
My point here is that a bit of reflection shows you that you are using the
sensory materials to represent the make-believe world in the way you
choose. That shows you, with just another step of reflection, something
about what you are like and, perhaps, what you are not like as well. However,
many of us think of the world of make-believe as a domain protected from
the story of what we are and what we are like. We enter the world of make-be-
lieve to go on vacation from both the story of reality and the story of our-
selves. We noted in Chapter 5 that we choose what activities in our life to
own, to exemplarize and make part of our lives, and what activities to drop
in the box of trivial disregards. That activity of choosing is itself your activity
and subject to the ownership choice of what you are like.
Moreover, as we exemplarize sensory experience to form the content of
exemplar representation of the world of make-believe, we confront the
further issue of how much of that exemplar representation to transfer, to
drag from the fictional screen of make-believe unto the outside world of
reality. As we confront that issue and resolve it, we note the most
A E S T H E T I C E X P E R I E N C E , I N T E N T I O N A L I T Y, F OR M OF R E P R E S E N TAT I O N ( 125 )
( 127 )
( 128 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
DEFINING ART
So, do not expect a definition of art based on what we now call art. If I gave
one, the artist in me would set out to create something as art that did not fit
the definition. Art is dynamic, or it fails to do what art does. Might we define
art in terms of what art does? Beardsley took a step in that direction, sug-
gesting a definition of art in terms of the capacity for aesthetic response as
follows:
DB: An artwork is something produced with the intention of giving it the capacity to
satisfy the aesthetic interest (in Wartenberg, 2007, 232).
Moreover, he says things about aesthetic experience that have some accord
with what the ideas I have advanced. He says of the aesthetic experience, “It
takes on a sense of freedom from concern about matters outside the thing
received, an intense affect that is nevertheless detached from practical ends,
the exhilarating sense of exercising powers of discovery, integration of the
self and its experiences,” (Beardsley, in Wartenberg, 2007, 232).
The account of exemplar representation, exemplarization, construct-
ing new form and content, including the content of feeling and emotion,
transferred to reconfigure ourselves and our world offered above has
something in common with Beardsley’s account of the aesthetic character
of experience. Differences could be articulated, but that would involve an
excursion into the interpretation of Beardsley that I shall not undertake
here. I mention Beardsley because of his attempt to define art in terms of
the intention of the artist to produce something with the capacity to sat-
isfy aesthetic interest.
Suppose, following Beardsley, and incorporating the notion of eliciting
exemplar representation that has intrinsic value, I were to attempt to define
art in terms of what I have said it does. What might I say? I might try the
following:
DL: Something is an artwork just in case it is created or chosen with the intention to
elicit exemplar representation of the receiver with new form and content reconfiguring
experience in a way that has intrinsic value.
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 129 )
DL*: Something is an artwork just in case it is created or chosen with the result that it
elicits exemplar representation from aesthetic attention of the receiver with new form
and content that reconfigures experience in a way that has intrinsic value.
This definition gets the intention of the artist out of the definition, which
is desirable, but seems to leave us with the receiver’s exemplarization as
the source of the form, content, and value of the artwork. On this
account, what the artist provokes in the receiver, and, of course, the artist
is one of the receivers, is the central ingredient in the definition. Some
can be expected to demure. They will wish to claim that there is something
intrinsic to the artwork that embodies the form and content of the
work.
I note, however, that the definition does not deny that it is the character
of the artwork that leads to the exemplarization. We could add that and
obtain the definition of art incorporating it below:
Whatever the remaining defects of the definition, which I hope merit explo-
ration and even refutation, it captures the central ideas I have been
advancing. It leaves out the richness of elaboration, which might convey the
value of the theory better than a definition, but I offer it as a word bite for
the pleasure of mastication.
Notice, however, that the definition retains, however concealed, the
circle of reference as exemplarization of art experience creates new form
and content of art. It is a trajectory of the theory of exemplarization rather
than a summary definition of art attempting to tie together the history and
theory of art and aesthetics with a ribbon of finality. Even if I do define art
in a tentative way, confronting both Weitz (1956) and Derrida (1987) who
both deny art is definable, perhaps joining analytic and continental philos-
ophy in disapproval, I do want to say something about traditional aesthetics.
I wish to show where I approve of what has been said, and why, and to show
where I do not approve, applying the work that I have laid out before us.
TRADITIONAL AESTHETICS
receiver. They are part of the content because they are in the sensory expe-
rience that is preserved in the exemplar exemplarized to yield the content
of the work of art.
Does this just push back the question of how feelings and emotions can
be the content of the artwork to the question of how they can be in sensory
materials? We dealt with this question in the earlier chapters, but it is worth
an additional reformulation. Sensory materials, the appearances of faces
and bodies, for example, are, as Reid (1785) noted in the eighteenth century,
signs of the mental life of the other, dissolving the problem of our knowledge
of other minds. How do they become signs? Our original faculties, our
innate principles of response, provide part of the answer. Anyone who has
grimaced at a young baby and watched the automatic crying response of the
baby with unkind amusement, knows that the sensory experience of the
baby contained a message of anger in the face of the adult. I grimace at my
classes to show them that the meaning of the sensory experience is not fully
extinguished. They do not like the expression, even if they laugh. Of course,
nature gets connected with custom, innateness with association, and the
connection between sensory experiences of the face and body and emo-
tions signified becomes more elaborate. Simply put, sensory experience
carries content. Some of it is innate, some of it is the result of custom, and
some of it is our autonomous creation. The point I am making, and it is a
consequence of the theory of exemplarization of conscious experiences, is
that artworks can and do express feelings and emotions that are, in some
cases, not experienced by either the artist, even an artist intending to express
them, nor by the receiver, even one sensitive to expressions of feelings and
emotions. The feelings and emotions are signified in the exemplars that we
use to represent the content of the artwork and are, thereby, part of the
content carried by the exemplar.
I now want to say something about the intentions of the artist and role of
thereof. As Beardsley (2007) noted, one may deny that the intentions of
the artist are the last court of appeal on the interpretation of the artwork,
and, at the same time, bring in the intentions of the artist to define what
makes something a work of art. Let me separate the two issues. It is a maxim
of postmodernism, or, at least a theme, as Barthes (1977) taught us, that the
cost of empowering the viewer as an interpreter of the work, and, therefore,
as receiver of the content of the work, is to disregard the intentions of the
artist. The life of the receiver is at the cost of the death of the artist.
Some artists are very good at committing suicide as interpreters of their
work. Matisse once remarked of his patroness Sarah Stein, “She knows
more about my art than I do” (Collection, 1970). Of course, an artist can
tell you things that may interest you, and fairly so, about what she did, even,
though memory is disputable in such matters. She may tell you what she
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 133 )
thought and felt when she created, or what she thinks and feels now that she
views it. But you must return to the artwork, to your experience of the art-
work, to decide for yourself the relevance or irrelevance of the discourse to
how you interpret the work, which means, how you exemplarize your con-
scious awareness into form and content.
There is, of course, a problem once you have listened to the artist. It may
influence your conscious experience. As you look at a painting, for example,
you cannot see it all at once. You are, in fact, active in your viewing of the
painting, for that is essential to constructing content out of experience.
When you are active, you choose and select where and how you direct your
attention. In fact, the remarks of the artist may dominate your representa-
tion of the artwork, your exemplarization of the form and content of it, by
leading you to ignore parts of the painting, even sections of the painting,
that you should notice. I was once displeased by a painting I did of a nude
model, a young woman presenting herself as strongly sexual, because the
painting of the head was odd and did not fit with the body. A friend, Candace
Smith, who is my counterpart to Sarah Stein, explained my painting to me,
as her finger traced from the head to the crotch of the model and said, “I do
not want to go there.” I realized that the conflict between head and body in
the painting captured my doubt about the sexual expression of the model.
My initial remarks about the painting would have been misleading and
might have led a viewer to regard the painting of the head as just some kind
of failure. As I viewed the painting after the Candace commentary, the
content of the painting, my exemplar representation of the content, was
different. Moreover, I decided that it was one of my most successful paint-
ings. The viewer, in this case Candace, viewing the painting without my
reflections, understood it better than I did, conveying her sensitive exem-
plar representation of content.
My art historian friends must forgive me for the next offhand remarks.
When I go to art museums and listen to some quite knowledgeable curator
pouring out the history of the artwork, I think, “Oh please let them just
look at the painting.” They need to decide first what content their conscious
experience reveals to them in aesthetic attention. They need to see what
content they can find in the painting to add to the content of the painting
and to their lives. That is what matters, and, yes, that is what art is about that
matters to me. Take a favorite artwork of mine, Bed, by Rauschenberg [Web
ASK 29]. It is a bed, with paint applied in a way that is not very elegant,
dripping and messy. Now some art historian might remark on the relation-
ship of the object to abstract expressionism, to drippy Pollock and others
who let paint drip as well. I do not dispute the historical accuracy of such
interpretations. But all that information, however historically interesting,
may lead you to miss a way of exemplarizing your conscious experience aes-
( 134 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
thetically that, I contend, makes Bed an artwork that does something spe-
cial. It provokes the representation of content from the exemplar, taking
you beyond art-talk, beyond the isolation of the artwork in a museum, and
even the artworld in total, to the world outside of art. The messiness of Bed
takes me to an exemplarization of the object as representing that beds are
the messy places of life. Sex, fears, and dreams occur there. Looking at the
object changes the content of the artwork and the content of beds. It took
me beyond that to the further reflection that we find beds safe places. Maybe
the safe places are messy. Maybe that is something we all feel.
I know the art historians are laughing. Now the rest of you go see Bed. A
salient test of the interpretation of art is not the history of the artist, not art
history, but what you find as you direct your aesthetic attention toward the
object. It depends how you take sensory experience, on how you use the
sensory exemplar to construct form and content. And ultimately, it depends
on whether the value of the content constructed carries over into your
experience outside of art. Direct your attention to the immediacy of your
experience. Unblock quotidian representation. Allow yourself the
autonomy to construct content by exemplar representation of your experi-
ence and reconfigure the experience of your life. Then you know what art
can do.
One other traditional theory is formalism. I have mentioned the theory
of significant form of Bell (1910) and Fry (1920) previously. They claim
that the content of the artwork is irrelevant to art, and only the form, the
configuration of color and lines, matters to what makes an object art.
Moreover, the form is significant, they aver, only if it elicits a special emo-
tion, the aesthetic emotion. There is a virtue and a fault in the theory. The
virtue is the emphasis on the immediate sensory qualities. The fault lies in
claiming that all there is to art is a special emotion that it elicits. Why, hav-
ing directed our attention to the form of an art object, which is an impor-
tant first step, should we not find any content in the aesthetic awareness of
the experience of form in art?
It has often been objected that the theory of significant form is arbitrary
in rejecting all figurative and narrative content as relevant to the character
of an object as art. I have another objection. When we attend to our con-
scious awareness of the exemplar, we create both form and content. How
are we to attend to color without noticing what it is like? When we notice
what the color and line is like in the exemplar of experience, we distinguish
it from other experiences or colors and lines. As we mark the distinction in
our exemplar representation, we become aware of form and content. In
marking the distinction, we distinguish the colors and lines, letting them
represent others, and dividing the space into those colors and lines that are
like what we experience from those that are not. In short, awareness of
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 135 )
history and theory of art. He has a remarkable ability to bring not only art
history and art theory but also philosophy, and not just philosophy of art,
into his interpretations of artworks. He says he philosophizes art. He
describes the artwork, as I mentioned above, as embodied meaning. There
is a great deal I appreciate in this account. I would put his last point differ-
ently by saying the artwork is a mentalized physical object because it uses
present experiences for exemplarization and the construction of form and
content by marking distinctions in conceptual space.
There is a point, however, of disagreement. I have argued that exemplar-
ized content is more personal, at least at the first step, less dependent on
sophistication. Danto, as I read him, neglects the first step of responding in
a personal way with aesthetic attention to the artwork with the personal
exemplar representation of your conscious experience. The first step of
exemplarization of your experience to your aesthetic attention may be
innocent of art history and art theory, and what Danto calls the artworld,
that surrounds the work with a social art content and aura. That first
personal step, I propose, may be the most important. There is a richness to
artworks, and the richness is a richness of meaning or content. Meaning is
something we supply, however, and it will depend on who we are and what
we are like.
I do not deny, and I will argue later, that the individual mind is also a
social mind, that the personal and interpersonal aspects of mentality join.
My caveat is that you do not have to be an art sophisticate, or even art-
culture informed, to engage in aesthetic attention to art to obtain a repre-
sentation of the form and content of art and transfer that content to your
life in a way that will change and enrich it. There is a great deal that art can
and does do to reveal the content of art to you that does not depend on art
history, art theory, or the artworld. You have to look, think, and feel, but
you do not have to look, think, and feel about art the way the artworld
does. Moreover, though I understand Danto’s love of the artworld, you do
not even have to have absorbed the lessons of the artworld to pick up the
content the most sophisticated critics and curators discover.
Two examples—very personal, forgive me—illustrate. I took two little
girls, one five and one seven, my granddaughters, Clara and Elsa, to MOMA
in San Francisco to see a light show. Being there, I decided I would take
them to the permanent collection of modern art. I was rather amazed at
how amused and attentive they were. It later occurred to me that they, unlike
adults influenced by the artworld, did not have any expectations of what
they would experience and were quite merry running around looking at all
these surprising things. The seven–year-old, Clara, paused for a long time in
front of a very large abstract, purple, black, and white oil by Clyfford Still
[Web ASK 30]. I got curious and asked her what she thought about the
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 137 )
painting. She replied, “It feels like the sea on rainy day.” I looked at the
painting, and thought, “That is the way it feels,” thinking my agreement
might be based as much on the pleasure of her response as perception. Last
year I went to Paris and visited a Monet show, which was enhanced by the
curator placing some pieces he thought were influenced by paintings of
Monet. Next to the water lilies was—guess what?—a Clyfford Still oil
painting. It was not the one from MOMA, but it was a very similar smaller
version, perhaps a study for the larger piece.
The seven-year-old girl did not need to know art history and art theory
or be a member of the artworld to understand the content of the Still
painting from her conscious experience of it. An artworld curator, in a
moment of personal insight, apparently discovered the same content that
the girl did without the artworld. I admire the innocence of his exemplar-
ization. The first step into art experience may be the most important, and it
just may be the most insightful.
I will mention the second episode with the girls because it involves a
painting I have mentioned before, Monochrome Blue. The two girls were fas-
cinated by this blue rectangle. When I asked them what they thought, Elsa
replied, “The blue is so pretty.” I noted in some remarks of Klein, that, when
asked why he painted it, he said he liked the blue, which was actually an
invention of his, one he patented, International Klein Blue. You do not need
to know the artworld to exemplarize your experience to reveal the content
of a painting as the feeling of rainy day or the prettiness of a color. Such rev-
elation may be the source of the value of the work, for all who appreciate it;
little girls and influential curators appreciating the content and value of the
artwork.
I must, of course, concede, that background knowledge influences how
we represent our experience, including the exemplar representation of it.
That means, I concede to Danto (1994), that how you exemplarize art may
be influenced by art history and art theory in a way that adds value. There
are layers of meaning, layers of content, to be taken from the ambiguous
exemplars of conscious experience. But it is important, as Reid (1785) pro-
posed, to consider theories of the meaning of artworks based on the original
untutored signification of experience. Reid argued that there were certain
signs that we understand by our nature without conventions, agreements,
and the artifices of tutelage. He says of these signs, which he calls natural
signs of our natural language: “The elements of this natural language of
mankind, or the signs that are naturally expressive of our thoughts may, I
think, be reduced to these three kinds: modulations of the voice, gestures
and features” (Reid, 1785, 118). He means the gestures of the body and the
features of the face. This natural language is replaced, “rooted out,” Reid
says, by the learning of artificial and conventional language, which, with all
( 138 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
its advantages for the improvements of knowledge, results in a loss. For the
natural language is the more expressive one, the one with more force and
energy.
Artificial signs signify, but they do not express; they speak to the understanding, . . . but
the passions, the affections, and the will, hear them not: these continue dormant and
inactive, till we speak to them in language of nature, at which they are all attention and
obedience.
It were easy to show, that the fine arts of the musician, the painter, the actor, and the
orator, so far as they are expressive—although the knowledge of them requires in us a
delicate taste, a nice judgment, and much study and practice—yet they are nothing else
but the language of nature, which we have brought into the world with us, have unlearned
by disuse, and so find the greatest difficulty in recovering it.
Abolish the use of articulate sounds and writing among mankind for a century,
and every man would be a painter, an actor, and an orator . . . . he that understands
perfectly the use of natural signs, must be the best judge in all the expressive arts
(Reid, 1785, 118).
This is not the place to enter into an account of Reid’s aesthetics, though his
view have received attention, most recently by Pouivet (2005), who
expounds brilliantly Reid’s views on the role of natural signs in the arts.
What Reid says is consistent with subsequent knowledge, and explains the
importance of the first step into art and the content of art. It reaches deeper
into our nature and our affective life. It allows that the untutored respond to
experience of art and exemplarize the form and content of it without sophis-
tication, and surely, without the history and theory of the artworld. This
connects with the first step into aesthetic attention in which, as far as pos-
sible, the conventions of discourse, including the conventions of respond-
ing to art, are laid aside. What is left to guide our use of the exemplars of
consciousness? Perhaps, as Reid suggests, the language of nature, that
expressive form of representation, we have by our nature. The presence of
such representations in us, however overlaid with the conventions of
artificial language and other conventions of representation, enables us, in
the moment of immediate focus of aesthetic attention, to exemplarize our
conscious experience, using it as the vehicle of the content it carries, retain-
ing the expressive force, energy, and meaning of it.
So far, I have only discussed the first step, the step into art and the
content thereof that results from attention to what the experience is like in
itself. The experience used as a representation carrying content allows us
to accommodate the positive side of Danto (1994) in his interpretation of
the content of the artwork. For we can, starting with ostensive exemplar-
ization directed toward immediate conscious experience, toggle over as
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 139 )
ART PHILOSOPHIZING
The first step of aesthetic attention, the attention to what the conscious
experience is like, converts the experience into an exemplar of what a kind
of consciousness is like. There is a distinction marked in conceptual space,
and what is contained in the space is the initial or ostensive content of the
work. At this point, the response may return to the primitive and original
level of representation or signification Reid (1785) insisted arises from
original powers, capacities of our nature that unfold and reveal themselves
as we mature. I do not claim, though Reid did, that these are our initial
responses in life, nor do I deny it, for the response to immediacy may be a
sophisticated toggle in our later take on the artwork. The use of these
powers in the immediacy of aesthetic attention may require, as Reid also
suggests, an artistic direction of attention to what experience can represent
at an expressive and original level.
The effect of this immediacy and the exemplar representation of it in
some original way blocks, as does the Black Square, the usual representation
of objects. From that immediacy and initial blocking of quotidian represen-
tation, we find ourselves confronted with autonomy of interpretation. We
seek to interpret the experience, to mark a distinction with it, creating form
and content out of immediacy. We often notice, then, some uncertainty
giving expression to our autonomy of interpretation. Reflecting on what
the exemplar shows us, we note that it shows us what is represented, the
content that the exemplar exhibits. It also shows us how we represent the
content, in terms of the exemplar. The exemplar exhibits the connection
between form and content, between representation and what is repre-
sented, as we know what the exemplar is like in exemplarization that exhibits
both the term of representation, the exemplar itself, and what that term
refers to, again, the exemplar itself. Aesthetic attention and the response
based upon it show us how the form of representation, our marking a dis-
tinction, connects the representation with the content it represents in
ostensive exemplarization of experience onto experience.
So the experience of art engages us philosophically. It does more. It
shows us the answer to philosophical inquiry into what the form of repre-
sentation and intentionality are like. Danto (1994) set out to philosophize
art. The reason he succeeds is that art philosophizes. Art is embodied expe-
rience of philosophy. Art engages in artosophy, art philosophizing. How it
does this is readily experienced. Art shows us what things are like in a way
T H E OR I E S OF A R T, A N D A R T A S T H E OR Y OF T H E W OR L D ( 141 )
that goes beyond what can be described. Artosophy shows us how thought
is connected to experience, how to obtain content from experience, some
truth about experience, and, finally, how to use experience in exemplar
representation to show us we can represent and refer to the world beyond
our immediate experience. It shows us how experience can refer to the
world of things and theory by exhibiting to us what they are like in terms of
our experience. We ask in philosophy how experience, thought, and feeling
can represent our world and ourselves. Philosophy leaves out what it is like
to use experience as representation in this way. Artosophy shows us what
philosophy cannot, namely, what it is like to use experience as an exemplar
vehicle of representation.
We have the examples of feminist art before us showing us how to chat
on the edge of experience in art about the role and nature of woman. We
have the Black Square taking us into metaphysics about feeling and objec-
tivity. There are other examples. Starting with a Rothko painting [Web
ASK 7], you may enter into the layers of color and feeling in color leading
you away from the world of ordinary objects into a meditative experience of
reality. Or consider Magritte [Web ASK 31] exploring philosophy in his
very realistic painting of a pipe, with the line on the painting, “ceci n’est pas
une pipe” (this is not a pipe), telling us that the representational exemplar
we experience is not a pipe. The sensory exemplar, like the surface of the
painting of which the exemplar is the phenomenology, though representing
a pipe, is not a pipe. The experience of the painting reveals to us that, though
the appearance represents a pipe as we exemplarize it, the representation is
not what it represents. Exemplar representation can break out of the self-ref-
erential loop of ostensive exemplarization to reach beyond experience.
Magritte exhibits the lesson of Brentano that the exemplar representation
of an object is the representation of an intentional object, the object in the
painting, which need not exist for it to be the content of the painting. The
representation may have been based on a pipe used as a model, something
that does exist, but the exemplar representation, which also exists, is not the
model. The model may be part of the cause of how the representation comes
into existence, but the content of the painting is not the model on which it
was based. The model was small, the representation is large. The model and
the content do not have the same properties and cannot be identical.
Now we reach a basic issue about the content of representation, an issue
about whether the content of representation is derived from the external
objects represented or from the internal way in which we represent them.
Content, as I am using the term, is what is contained in the space marked to
separate what is contained, the content, from what is unmarked and not so
contained. But that does not answer the question of the etiology yet. Is it
the external object that leads us to mark the distinction we do, filling the
( 142 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
signed by the artist. If art can represent life, then life can represent art, and
the two, art and philosophy, are tied together in a loop of reference. I tried
this connection with Karen Ivy dancing to a lecture with the content of this
chapter [Web ASK 33] in front of an image of sculpture. More deeply, Socle
du Monde (Base of the World) [Web ASK 34], an inverted base or pedestal
resting upside down, as the letters of the title on the sculpture show, exhibits
the world as art. It shows you your world as art as you choose the world
beneath the inverted base as the artwork. Your world becomes art and art
your world as you exemplarize your experience of the world of art and the
world beyond art on a common base. You may not be convinced that we
choose the story of ourselves and our world. Your response to the Socle du
Monde shows you choosing your world, and, of course, yourself standing
there in your exemplar representation of your experience of what is beneath
the base. You are amused to find the story of your life in the exemplarization
of art.
This page intentionally left blank
ﱞ
CHAPTER 9
I ended the previous chapter insisting on the role of art in the creation of
new content out of exemplar representation. Then, in a moment of what
might have seemed extravagant for a long-sitting epistemologist, I proposed
that the creation of content to interpret art is something that we may auton-
omously transfer to the world outside of art. I add two caveats on content.
The first is that not all content of exemplar representation, even ostensive
exemplarization of experience back onto experience, is chosen. Some is an
automatic or conventional response. Moreover, among what is chosen, not
all is autonomously chosen. When we focus attention on what our experi-
ence is like, especially in aesthetic attention directed to the immediacy of
experience, we exemplarize experience into representation in terms of the
experience itself, obtaining form and content. As I have insisted repeatedly,
exemplar representation offers us the security of an experiential basis of our
conception since the experiential exemplar that is the vehicle of content
loops back onto itself referentially even as it extends beyond itself to other
experiences, other things, and other worlds.
However, the exemplar representation of form and content confronts us
and reaches beyond the world of art, presenting itself for transfer to the
external world and to the story of ourselves in that world. Again a caveat on
content is needed. Sometimes we transfer content thoughtlessly, and the
transfer passes through the mind and body of the subject to the world and
itself as unnoticed as the sleight of hand of the magician. Art and the content
thereof then change the content of our experience without our bidding and
become part of the fixation of belief. In the purest case, some unreflective
( 145 )
( 146 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
The exemplar representation of the artwork raises the issue of the truth of
the representation and the justification of accepting the representation as
we direct aesthetic attention to the artwork. The exemplar representation
taken as a representation of the form and content of the artwork already
raises these issues when we pass from our personal interpretation to the
question of the correctness of it as an interpretation. Is the figure on the
left of the Yeats painting, The Gay Moon [Web ASK 15], expressing sad-
ness? Is the figure a man? Is he grieving? Is the man on the right of the
painting seen from the back looking at the figure on the left? The questions
multiply. The answers arise from the exemplarization of the phenome-
nology of the surface of the painting. Does the Serrano photograph Piss
Christ [Web ASK 37] express contempt for the crucifix it portrays sub-
merged in a container of the artist’s urine as the medium? Does it instead
use piss religiously to remind us of the incarnation of the divine? Is the piss
a metaphor for anger, our anger at the act, or for something else? Questions
( 148 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
of the evidence. A person may believe that Piss Christ [Web ASK 37], the
photograph by Serrano, mentioned earlier, of a container with a crucifix
submerged in urine to portray Christ on the cross is sacrilegious. After
hearing a Kierkegaardian (1941) interpretation, that the genuine Christian
must accept the incarnation of the godhead, which means Christ was made
of blood and piss as well as skin and bone, she might come to accept the
evidence that the photograph is religious in the way suggested. But still,
thinking of the crucifix submerged, she continues to believe it is sacrile-
gious to present the crucifix in piss. She is offended.
The offended person may consider her own belief in the sacrilege unrea-
sonable as she accepts the denial of it based on reasons offered to her, for
example, the reference to the existential fundamentalism of Kierkegaard
(1941). We may think of belief as a state that arises without our bidding
and that may remain against our will. By contrast, allowing some linguistic
innovation in the use of the word, we may describe acceptance as an atti-
tude of positive evaluation based on the evidence and reasons. So the first
distinction is between belief, which may not be responsive to ratiocination
or evaluation, on the one side, and acceptance, which is the positive atti-
tude resulting from rational evaluation, on the other. The evaluation of
acceptance may involve conscious reflection and ratiocination, or it may
result from a principle of evaluation serving the ends of reflection and rati-
ocination, acting as a rule of thumb or an evaluation surrogate of the latter.
Some perceptual beliefs and memory beliefs have the evidence of sense
and memory to warrant the acceptance of them without reflection. Other
beliefs are accompanied by evidence for them, many memory beliefs, for
example, in terms of the feelings of clarity and certainty.
SR. It is reasonable for S to accept that p only if the evidence S possesses more strongly
supports p than the denial of p.
WR. It is reasonable for S to accept that p only if it is not the case that the evidence S
possesses more strongly supports the denial of p than p.
UR. It is not unreasonable for S to accept that p only if it is not the case that the evidence
S possesses more strongly supports the denial of p than p.
SR and UR allow for the possibility that there may be things that it is not
reasonable to accept but also not unreasonable to accept. Let us take SR and
UR together as R. It is clear that R is relevant to the parity issue concerning
acceptance and the interpretation of art. In the case of parity, it might not
be reasonable for a person S to accept that p in the parity condition by R,
but neither would it be unreasonable for the person S to accept p in the
parity situation by R.
We might say the same thing about a weak notion of being justified in
accepting that p meaning something like that S has some justification for
accepting that p and of being unjustified in accepting that p meaning that S
has some justification for rejecting that p. Consider the following two
conditions:
J. S is justified in accepting that p only if the evidence S possesses more strongly supports
p than the denial of p.
U. S is not unjustified in accepting that p only if it is not the case that the evidence S pos-
sesses more strongly supports the denial of p than p.
This pair of definitions allows that a person might not be justified in accepting
that p on the evidence she possesses but, at the same time, not be unjustified
in accepting that p on the evidence she possesses. Indeed, in the parity
condition, this would be so. It must be acknowledged that this account of jus-
tification does not have as much plausibility as the account of reasonableness
and unreasonableness offered in R. For it is natural to so use the notion of jus-
tification so that one is unjustified in accepting something that is not posi-
tively supported by the evidence. That is, it is natural to say that if a person is
not justified in accepting something, then he or she is unjustified in accepting
it, while it is not equally obligatory to say that if a person is not reasonable in
accepting something, then he or she is unreasonable to accept it.
The explanation for R is that there is a theory of reasonableness that
allows that it is not unreasonable to accept something that the evidence
permits you to accept even though it does not mandate this. For a discussion
of such a theory see Lehrer, Roelofs, and Swain (1967). Reason may permit
the acceptance of something it does not require. We shall continue discuss-
ing reasonableness but the remarks apply to the weak notion of justification
articulated above. A stronger notion of justification is required for the
conversion of justified acceptance of a truth to knowledge, one that requires
evidence to meet objections to what is accepted without resting on error. I
have articulated such a theory in detail earlier (Lehrer, 2000), but here I am
( 152 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
I do not claim that each of these steps follows deductively from the pre-
ceding, though some do. The argument from 1 to 2 seems deductive based
on the verbal reformulation. The argument from 2 to 3 seems to be cogent,
but it is an instance of defeasible reasoning rather than deductive. Step 2
describes a general capacity to be trustworthy, and step 3 describes a gen-
eral application of the capacity in order to be reasonable. The argument
from 3 to 4 is again defeasible because the inference from the capacity to be
trustworthy in order to be reasonable to the capacity to be reasonable is
defeasible. It is, nevertheless, cogent because being trustworthy in order to
be reasonable in what one accepts generally results in being reasonable in
what one accepts. The argument from 4 to 5 is defeasible because it is con-
sistent, though incoherent, to deny that the transfer of exemplarized content
to the world is reasonable. The argument is defeasible for the simple reason
that 4 describes a general capacity of being reasonable while 5 describes a
more specific application of the capacity to the transfer of content under
the condition of parity. Parity will not always arise in the transfer of exem-
plarized content, of course. The argument is important for the reasonable-
ness of the transfer of content under reasonable disagreement. The
S E L F - T R U S T, DI S A G R E E M E N T, A N D R E A S O N A B L E A C C E P TA N C E ( 155 )
tion tips the scale of evidence. I at first accept parity; I then accept that p in
pursuit of the goals of evidence, nevertheless. The balance is tilted and
parity is lost. I accept that p.
I am, by the argument above, reasonable in what I accept, so I am rea-
sonable to accept that p. By the condition R, if it is reasonable to accept
that p, then the evidence supports p more strongly than the denial of p.
How did that come about if I initially accepted the parity condition? My
acceptance of p, my evaluation of the exemplar representation, is part of
the evidence. Parity is undone by acceptance. I cannot consistently main-
tain parity when I accept that p. Parity itself becomes a kind of illusion. In
a moment of epistemic absentmindedness, I forget to notice that my judg-
ment of my representation of my world is itself a source of evidence about
that world. I look at the situation as though my judgment did not weigh
anything on the scale of evidence. But it must. One may be inclined to
think of evidence as being something independent of judgment and repre-
sentation. That is to forget the role of judgment and representation in the
creation of evidence. I receive information and engage in ratiocination
from and about something. Then, however, I confront the decision of what
I am to make of all of it, of my exemplar representation of the world and of
the arguments of others about such representation. I cannot escape the
decision and the responsibility of deciding where my representation and
ratiocination lead me.
The relevance of this reflection to the use of art in world making is
obvious. In the interpretation of art in terms of the content of the exemplars
of aesthetic attention as well as the transfer of the content to the world
outside of art, one confronts disagreement. Imagine a courtier, Sir Positive,
studying a Boucher painting of Madame de Pompadour [Web ASK 5] and
remarking to another, Sir Negative, that the content of the painting cap-
tures what Pompadour is like. A dispute might occur. Sir Negative might
remark that even Pompadour did not think Boucher had captured her like-
ness, and Positive might acknowledge that she noted that but add that the
posture, the attitude, the books, scrolls, and globe show us what she is like.
Negative might reply that the face is everything in capturing what a person
is like, especially the eyes, and the eyes of the woman in the painting are
those of a pleasure-giving mistress indifferent to the objects of state in the
painting. Both might consider the arguments of the other, and, after careful
viewing and conversation, they might disagree about the content of the
painting, about what the experience of the painting shows us about the
content of what Pompadour is like in the painting.
Imagine they agree that they have said all there is to say to each other
about the matter of the painting. Moreover, imagine that each of them sees
and thinks of Pompadour in terms of his own exemplar representation of
S E L F - T R U S T, DI S A G R E E M E N T, A N D R E A S O N A B L E A C C E P TA N C E ( 157 )
reaching the goals of truth and value. One convinced of the merits of the
argument as providing a reasonable or trustworthy probability assignment
needs some further argument for the conclusion that such assignments
are successful in reaching external goals. An analogous problem arises
concerning assignments of consensual assignments of preference for values.
The problem remains to provide some argument that aggregation of the
efforts of individuals to reach truth or value is effective. Initially, the problem
seemed to me to lack a solution. I remained satisfied with noting that the
fixed-point vector aggregated the total information that members of the
group had about other members of the group and, therefore, constituted a
rational summary of such information. Applying the fixed-point vector to
find consensual probabilities of truth or utilities of value was justified by the
principle of rationality that one should use total information to determine
what to accept as true or prefer as value.
The justification above may argue for the adequacy of using weighted
averaging because it is formally equivalent to Bayesian methodology of
using priors to average in a way that sustains coherence (Lehrer, 1983).
However, the desire remains to offer some argument that goes beyond nor-
mative constraints of coherence and rationality to assigning probabilities
that are successful estimates of actual frequencies. There is a liberal tradi-
tion that defends self-trust and individualism in the quest for truth stem-
ming from Mill (1869) as we noted. But one is left with the desire to find
some argument other than political liberalism for thinking that individuals
following the path of self-trust in what they accept will lead to social success
in attaining truth, in short, that social consensus will probably trump indi-
vidual error whatever the vicissitudes of the path.
bear on the problem from Page and his collaborators (Hong and Lamberson,
in manuscript). First of all, there is the result that consensual weights are
better than simple averaging if and only if the weights reflect the accuracy
rates of individuals and those rates differ among individuals. Secondly, the
consensual weights must reflect the accuracy rates of individuals as opposed
to their charisma. Thirdly, and most importantly, the accuracy of collective
wisdom is determined by individual trustworthiness combined with diver-
sity. Individual trustworthiness is a function of the method of repre-
sentation and the models of prediction, that is, the cognitive models of
individuals.
The details of this work are worth the reflection of philosophers, but the
results are what concern us here in considering the role of consensual
weights in collective wisdom. Collective wisdom outperforms individual
expertise on the average. What about diverse weights used for averaging?
We can say this much. Combining individual self-trust and social diversity
in cognitive methods, collective wisdom resulting from averaging with
diverse weights that represent diverse success rates among individuals will
outperform simple averaging.
The question that faces us now, given some encouraging results, is whether
the consensual weights may be used as a measure of diverse accuracy. We
move toward a positive answer by restricting the initial assignment of
weights by individuals to those assignments that are based on the normal-
ization of meta-frequencies, mi(T/S), being the estimated frequency of
the attribute of truth T in the first-level estimates of subject S by individual
i. These m estimates, like the original f estimates, may often not be the
result of statistical sampling. The projection of estimates should, after all,
embrace information about the accuracy of a subject and the cognitive
models used by the subject. It is tempting to require that a subject use the
same cognitive model to estimate the m function as to estimate the f
function for the sake of uniformity. But such a requirement appears unre-
alistic. One might use different models to make predictions about the suc-
cess of physicists than one would use to predict the correctness of physical
hypotheses. Nevertheless, averaging by using weights that estimate the
accuracy of subjects yields the same results in the aggregate as using
weights to estimate first-level frequencies. So, the results concerning the
collective wisdom outperforming individual estimates should transfer to
the metalevel. Reichenbach (1949) proved a long time ago that higher
order aggregation could, under specified conditions, reduce to first-level
( 166 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
Individuals differ in how they use words. We may suppose that there is a
correct way to use words and that the reference of the words of the lan-
guage is determined by that correct use, and with that the truth condi-
tions, no matter what anyone thinks. Putnam (1973) took us in that
direction, and others, having found the path, ran down it to the coal pit of
skepticism for a person concerning what his words mean. We must
acknowledge diversity in how people apply words and the verbal connec-
tions between them. What we have noted above, however, is that cognitive
diversity, that includes diverse ways of representing the world, is an
advantage, not a disadvantage in avoiding error.
What are we to say, however, about the character of the communal lan-
guage, the communal system of conception, if all that exists is the idiolects
and the idiosyncrasies of exemplars in the individuals? The answer is clear
enough (Lehrer, 1984; Lehrer and Lehrer, 1995). The communal language
is like the average person, in this case, a weighted average of consensus we
have characterized above. It is a mathematical fiction, but it is factually
grounded in idiolects and weights that individuals assign to each other,
directly or indirectly, to find the fixed point of aggregation. Moreover, as
individuals interact, as they modify usage in terms of the weights they give
to each other, the communal consensus of sign and concept is approached
by the individuals who converge toward it as they aggregate with others.
What we have learned from Page (2007) and his colleagues is that the diver-
sity resulting from self-trust is an advantage rather than a disadvantage
in obtaining truth and avoiding error. Part of the reason is that self-trust
contains a truth loop of exemplarization and the application thereof. That
security of truth does not take us far into the external world of the interpre-
tation of science and art, but, starting from an internal truth loop and
self-trust in what we accept as we represent things in the external world, we
may expect our cognitive differences to be an asset in avoiding error. The
truth loop of self-trust expands beyond the egocentric to the cognitive
diversity of enlightened inquiry as it loops back onto and into itself.
An overly simplified formulation of the diversity result is this: enlight-
ened inquiry requires diversity of representation to reduce risk of error.
Descriptive language, though it allows for the innovation of metaphor,
achieves the purpose it serves by shared convention. It provides a shared and
common system of representation. What takes us beyond the homogeneity
of linguistic modes of representation is experience and the exemplarization
of diversity. Exemplarization is the mother of diversity in the aesthetic
S O C I A L R E A S O N , AG G R E G AT I O N , A N D C OL L E C T I V E W I S D O M ( 171 )
( 173 )
( 174 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
an explanatory truth loop. Why? We must explain why the theory itself is
true, or it leaves something unexplained. If we leave something unexplained,
we have not maximized explanation. It is not enough that the theory explain
the truth of everything else, even if we were successful enough to obtain
such a general explanation. We must explain the truth of our explanation.
To that end, we need a subtheory, a part of the comprehensive theory that
explains our success in accepting an explanatory theory that is true on our
evidence. I will call this subtheory the truth theory. The explanatory theory
must loop back onto itself and explain why it is true on our evidence in
order to maximize explanation. Loop theory maximizes explanation. An
explanation maximizing theory must explain the truth of itself on our
evidence.
Preceding claims about representation and especially exemplar represen-
tation of art call for the presentation of a loop theory containing a truth
theory that applies to the system of representation itself. When we exem-
plarize our experience of the art object, creating, thereby, form and content
out of the exemplar of experience, the question of the truth of the exemplar
representation of the content of the artwork confronts us. The exemplar of
experience that becomes the exemplar representation may be generalized to
other experiences ensuring that, since the exemplar is one of things repre-
sented, the representation is true of itself. But as the exemplar reaches further
representationally, the simple truth loop of the exemplar back onto itself in
ostensive generalization is lost, and with it the truth security of the represen-
tation. This loss of security occurs at the level of the interpretation of the
artwork, at the level of applying the extended exemplar representation into
the content of the work. We may confront perplexity, and, as a result, our
freedom and autonomy as we exemplarize content while reflecting upon the
work of art. Even here, however, passing beyond the truth loop of ostensive
exemplarization to interpret the work from the exemplar, the need for a truth
theory is apparent. How are we to decide on the basis of our evidence
whether our exemplarized extended interpretation is correct? We may feel
the need of a theory of the truth of interpretation simply to understand what
it means to say that one interpretation is correct and another is not. So, even
before we consider the transfer of exemplar representation to the interpreta-
tion of the world outside of art, we confront the need of a theory of evidence
to tell us what is true on the basis of that evidence.
However, a special importance of art takes exemplar content beyond the
work. Exemplar representation of novel form and content in aesthetic
appreciation and attention offers us a new conception of our world and our-
selves. Should we transfer the content of exemplar representation to the
world outside the artwork? Is such transfer reasonable? Is the world outside
of art enough like the world inside the artwork to justify transfer? The
K N O W L E D G E , AU T O N O M Y, A N D A R T I N L O OP T H E OR Y ( 175 )
However, such scruples have little point once we have stopped dreaming of deducing
science from observation. If we are out to understand the link between observation and
science, we are well advised to use any available information, included that provided by
the very science whose link with observation we are seeking to understand.
( 176 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
The result is that the attainment of truth is explained and not a matter of
luck. It is not luck from the internal perspective because it is explained by
the theory internally accepted. It is not luck from the external perspective
because it is explained by the truth of the theory externally considered.
There is an important conclusion to be drawn from these reflections that
might have pleased Hegel, though we disagree with his identification of
theory and truth. The conclusion is that the loop itself is the explanation.
You might think it is just the theory that is explanatory. But the truth of
theory is required or you have explained nothing. On the other hand, it is
not just truth apart from our conception of it that explains either. You have
explained nothing without a conception of it. The explanation is in the loop,
and it is the loop that is explanatory.
Quine, following Neurath (1931), noted in his early work that one must
rebuild the ship of science, the ship of theory, in the sea of inquiry without
being anchored by truth conditions of observation sentences. He seems to
me to have become more apprehensive about the free-floating character of
theory construction and jumped overboard to find a secure tie to experi-
ence. More literally, he sought to exit from the explanatory loop to secure
truth conditions from experience. This was unnecessary. Experience can be
tied into the explanatory loop in a way that yields the security of a truth
connection within the explanatory loop. The tie is the process I have called
exemplarization, which has been the focal point of the response to con-
sciousness and aesthetic awareness. Exemplarization is an explanatory truth
loop that ties together experience and representation.
Here are the advantages of embracing loop theory. The internal and the
external is explained by a looping theory that we have about the relationship
between the internal and the external, as well as between the subjective and
the objective, the mental and the physical. The advantage of the explanatory
loop is not that it guarantees truth. It is something else. The explanation is
the loop. The advantage of the loop is that when a theory is true, the theory
explains why it is true because it contains a truth theory concerning itself.
The truth of the theory is explained, and correctly so, by its own truth theory.
That is the power of the loop.
If any man should demand a proof of this, it is impossible to satisfy him. For suppose it
should be mathematically demonstrated, this would signify nothing in this case: because,
to judge of a demonstration, a man must trust his faculties, and take for granted the very
thing in question (Reid, 1785, 447).
When he considers the evidence we have for the principle, we arrive at the
fundamental loop of evidence and truth.
“How then come we to be assured of this fundamental truth on which all others rest?
Perhaps evidence, as in many other respects it resembles light, so in this also—that, as
light, which is the discoverer of all visible objects, discovers itself at the same time, so
evidence, which is the voucher for all truth, vouches for itself at the same time.” He adds,
“No man ever thinks of this principle, unless when he considers the grounds of skepti-
cism; yet it invariably governs his opinions” (Reid, 1785, 448).
These lines in Reid are profound. I develop them in my own way and
have applied them in the previous chapter. The First First Principle is a prin-
ciple of evidence, a principle of trustworthiness, and a principle of truth.
K N O W L E D G E , AU T O N O M Y, A N D A R T I N L O OP T H E OR Y ( 179 )
AUTONOMY
Now I want to pass beyond this, I am afraid to a too oft-told tale, to explain
what makes us worthy of our trust. That will take us to autonomy and rep-
resentation, so often mentioned in this book. Autonomy in conception and
reasoning is what leads us to the worthiness of self-trust. Recent research
has convinced us that our more automatic and, perhaps, innate strategies of
belief often lead us into error. However, what is remarkable is that these
authors, and we with them, are able to note the errors of our natural ways
somewhat in the same way that we note the illusions of sense. To note them
is, of course, not to ensure that we shall never again be misled. Nature is
constant and reason is intermittent. But it is clear that, though we may err,
we are not without remedy. For if we reason badly in ways that experiments
reveal, we can discern those errors, and amelioration of what we trust is
within reach. We have metamental ascent and the loop of trustworthiness
to the exemplar representation of experience to lead us into a more success-
ful truth connection.
Moreover, I want to insist on a special point, namely, the role of evidence
in the causal order. Evidence forces our assent. Reason not only responds to
evidence but also produces it as the proof of a theorem makes it evident to
us. We do not need to reduce evidence to something natural to ensure the
role of it in the causal order. We produce evidence, and evidence produces
assent. To think of the evidence as not being part of the natural order is not
only erroneous, it is contrary to the evidence. The same is true of value,
which I have discussed. We experience value, whether it is value of rea-
soning, the value of aesthetics, or the value of evidence. It is tempting to
argue that the value of evidence supervenes on something else, on some
other features of experience. Whether this is right depends on the theory of
supervenience to which one subscribes. But if metaphysical necessity of
dependence is brought in as an explanation, that is a mistake. We experi-
ence evidence and value, no doubt, but experience and how we experience
what we do is part of the contingent causal nexus of the world. It is not
impossible that the causal order should have been different in a way that
would have changed our experience of evidence and value.
Now let us turn to a theory of rational autonomy (Lehrer, 2003). The
problem of rational autonomy is to explain how autonomous preference,
choice, and action can result from reasons we have. For, if we are autono-
mous, then our preference, choice, or action must be in our control, in our
power, up to us. But if preference, choice, and action result from our rea-
sons, how can our preference, choice, or action be in our power and up to
us? What reasons we have, our desires or beliefs, for example, are often not
in our control, not in our power, not up to us. So, if the preferences, choices,
K N O W L E D G E , AU T O N O M Y, A N D A R T I N L O OP T H E OR Y ( 183 )
and actions are caused by our having the reasons we have, then how can
they be in our control or up to us? They are in the power of the reasons and
up to the reasons. I can feel this in a special way in the creation and recep-
tion of art. If I am overwhelmed by reasons to make art in a certain way, or
overwhelmed by reasons to respond to art in a certain way, my sense of my
autonomy of creative choice in creation of an artwork, or response to one,
is lost in the life of reason.
If I am autonomous in what I choose, in choosing the creation or inter-
pretation of artistic content, for example, then I must be the cause of the
choice. The choice must be mine. But how can I be the cause of the choice,
how can the choice be mine, if the reasons cause it? If, on the other hand,
reasons are not causally effective, then it appears that the idea that I act
rationally in response to reasons, is just rationalization. They do not cause
the choice. So the problem is that if my preferences, choices, and actions are
not caused by reasons, then they do not appear to be rational; if they are,
then I do not appear to be autonomous.
The solution is metamental ascent and an explanatory loop. Let me focus
on preference conceived as something that will convert to choice and action
in the right circumstances. Frankfurt (1971) had an important insight that
freedom was explained by higher order preferences. However, preferences
among preferences appear subject to similar problems. If they are caused by
reasons I have for them, then I appear controlled at higher levels by those
reasons. Suppose my reasons consist of beliefs and desires I have. Having
preferences for the satisfaction of my desires in line with my beliefs is com-
patible with the processes being manipulated psychologically or neurolog-
ically by another. Moreover, moving from one level of preference to the
next does not seem sufficient to solve the problem, contrary to what I once
claimed, because the whole sequence of levels of preferences, even if in
accord with each other, leaves open the problem that the whole sequence
might be caused by reasons in a way that is not up to me. The sequence may
even be manipulated by another unknown to me.
Here is why we need the loop. I have proposed earlier (Lehrer, 2004)
that there must be a power preference concerning a choice to do A. The
power preference is a preference for having just the preferences in the struc-
ture of preferences pertaining to the choice to do A that I do have. That
preference will loop back onto itself, because it is a preference in the struc-
ture pertaining to the choice to do A. Looping back onto itself prevents
regression. It remains possible that this power preference is itself manipu-
lated, perhaps by someone who had neurological control of my brain and,
directly or indirectly, of my preferences, and, therefore, choices and actions.
So we must add the further condition that I have the power preference
because I prefer to have it. That is the feeling I suggest of artistic creation.
( 184 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
preference that empowers my activity and makes me the agent of it. Creative
choice without any reason for choosing the way one does may not be as
common as it feels, but it occurs in my experience, sometimes spontane-
ously, sometimes contrived to allow responses to unknown parts and states
of the self. It becomes my choice as it occurs because of my power preference
for the choice, the preference to prefer what the choice expresses just
because I prefer to have that preference. That empowers me and makes the
creative act, choice, and preference mine in the power preference for it.
So power preferences loop back onto themselves as preferences for
themselves, including preferences for being influenced by reasons, or not,
at the same time that they are preferences for other preferences. The power
preferences are like the principle of trustworthiness. In both cases, explana-
tion involves a principle applying to itself as it applies to other things.
Moreover, the loop is explanatory in the case of autonomy as well. It explains
the difference between causes that leave me in bondage and causes that
make me free. I may prefer to respond automatically in constructing an art-
work, exploring the fruits of automaticity in art, but I prefer to let myself
respond in that way, and the structure of the preference for itself is what
enables autonomy and automaticity to combine in artistic creation and
reception.
However impassioned the preferences and choices involved with art,
I am free when the causes of my creation are effective because I prefer them
to be effective. I am in bondage, by contrast, when the causes of my choice
are effective regardless of my preferences. Moreover, the primacy of the
power preference explains how I can be the cause of my preferences and
choices. I am the cause of them, not in some mysterious way, but because of
a power preference. I have those preferences because I prefer to have them.
That is why I am the cause of them, why they are in my power, why they are
up to me, and, artistically viewed, why they are my creation. More needs to
be said in subjunctive conditionals to complete the account, but the power
preference and the primacy of it is what maximizes explanation in a loop.
I note here a connection between trustworthiness and autonomy. It
seems that part of what makes me worthy of my trust in what I accept, or
for that matter, in what I prefer, is that I am autonomous in what I accept
and prefer. Notice that I am not autonomous in what I desire and believe.
Autonomy enters at a higher level. I prefer to satisfy a desire because I have
that preference. There is a power preference for having the preferences that
I do in the matter. Similarly, I have a preference for accepting something
that I believe because there is a power preference for having that preference.
Again, just as I may prefer what I do for the reasons that I do because of an
ultrapreference and a power preference for it, so I may accept what I do for
the reasons I do because of a preference for accepting what I do in that way
( 186 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
and a power preference for it. We are autonomous in the way we rebuild the
ship at sea, including the rebuilding of the truth loop. We often gain that
autonomy by special attention to a work of art that confronts and perplexes
us as we direct our attention to the exemplars of experience we convert into
the terms of exemplar representation of content. The perplexity opens an
aesthetic question about the interpretation of the artwork in terms of the
experience of it. We are empowered to answer the question by an exercise
of self-trust and autonomy. As we move to the next step, to the transfer of
our autonomous exemplarization of the content of the painting to the
content of the world beyond art, we are enmeshed in the loop of self-trust,
justification, and autonomy in the quest for truth.
There is no reason to fear getting lost in the explanatory loop. The loop
ties things together in self-trust. The point about self-trust is that it yields
reasons for what we prefer and accept within the loop. Sartre noted that,
though we are free to choose, we are not free not to choose. He thought, as
a result, that ultimately choice was without justification and without excuse.
But that is not a consequence consistently drawn. On the contrary, choice
brings with it a nexus of reasons, as Sartre (1956) noted. And choice is
inevitable as he also averred. Those reasons will contain justification for
what we have chosen, for the choice in the existential question. Within the
loop of choice, reasons arise for what we accept and prefer.
It might appear now that the loop is only a loop of consciousness, or, at
least of a loop of mentality that fails to connect the internal and external and
leaves us looping within, lacking an external connection. That is, of course,
the mistake of idealism. We discussed it in Chapter 7, but it is worth recon-
sidering here. The explanatory loop connects the internal and the external
at the level of extended exemplar representation. The exemplar of internal
experience exhibits what the external objects it represents are like at the
same time that it exhibits how we represent them. It shows us the form of
representation within the loop. The loop exhibits the truth connection
within the loop. Consider the principle of trustworthiness to the effect that
I am worthy of my trust and my trustworthiness is successfully truth
connected, principle T. It is a principle of internal trustworthiness and
external truth. The truth of the principle loops back onto acceptance of
itself to explain why I am worthy of my trust in accepting it and why it is
successfully truth connected. More simply, principle T says of the acceptance
of itself that it is successfully truth connected, and the truth connectedness
of it is part of what explains why that is true.
Moreover, my general trustworthiness in acceptance and the truth con-
nectedness of it explains why I am worthy of my trust and successfully truth
connected in the particular case. It is important to note that the explanation is
not deductive. I am, fallible though trustworthy. My trustworthiness is only
K N O W L E D G E , AU T O N O M Y, A N D A R T I N L O OP T H E OR Y ( 187 )
fallibly truth connected. In one of my first articles, written with John Canfield
(Canfield and Lehrer, 1961), we argued for the fallibility of explanation, and
that has remained. However, explanation, though fallible, can be cogent and
correct. You do not have to be infallible to be trustworthy and correct any
more than you have to be perfect to be successfully truth connected. It is
important to appreciate the powers and virtues we have, fallible and imperfect
as they may be.
Acceptance and preference, like belief and desire, may concern external
objects. If what we accept is true and what we prefer obtains, there is therein
a connection between the internal and the external. Forgive me for insisting
on something so obvious. I once remarked, in defense of the coherence
theory, that there is no exit from the circle of beliefs in personal justifica-
tion. Philosophers took me to be implying that justification was entirely an
internal matter. But beliefs may be about external things, most of them are,
and the truth of them is, therefore, an external matter. It is systematic truth
that protects justification from defeat and converts the acceptance of truth
into knowledge.
or MetaMe [Web ASK 40] painted by me. The content of the painting may
become the content of the person. Once an artwork acquires meaning or
content through exemplarization, the sensuous or exemplarized content
may be extended beyond the art object to other objects. Here then is a loop
of content from art to the world outside of art and back. I paint me, creating
an artistic content of me. You experience that content and it becomes part
of the content of me for you. Art is that part of the world that changes the
content of the world. It shows us our plasticity as content is created and
changed in an exemplarized loop of content.
Moreover, the exemplarized loop of content plays as an essential role in
the content of science as well as art. Let us consider an example from sci-
ence to illustrate the use of exemplarization in the content of scientific con-
ceptions of the world. There was a great deal known about cells before
anyone knew what the surface of a cell was like. Indeed, most of knowledge,
what was accepted about the cell, though influenced by observation through
light microscopes, was about internal character of the cytoplasm or the
nucleus. Then a scientist, Palade (1955), used the electron microscope to
show us what the surface was like. Consider a photo of the surface of a cell
[Web ASK 41]. The photo is a configuration of digital data and as such is a
creative configuration, broadly considered, then, a work of art. You will see
ribs consisting of dots as you view the photo, the scientific artwork con-
structed from the data of electron microscopy. The question is how to
exemplarize the image, the sensory exemplar, to use it as an exhibit of
scientific form and content. The dots you see were interpreted by Palade as
granules and have come to be called ribosomes. Palade thought the gran-
ules were RNA packets. That is how he interpreted the image, the sensory
phenomenology of the photo, after microscopic investigation led to the
artwork of the photo. If you want to know what the surface of the cell is like,
the sensory experience, the exemplar exhibiting the phenomenology of
the photo shows you. All this is striking enough scientifically, but the
philosophical task is to explain it.
Here is my take, influenced by Otávio Bueno (2004, 2010). There is an
initial stage of observation in which the image produced by the artwork of
the photo is seen by Palade. He looks again and sees it again. Looking again,
the image is re-identified and distinguished from others. He uses the image
to mark a distinction. Even if Palade were to remain agnostic about what he
is seeing, he nevertheless forms, as you do, a rudimentary conception of
the image adequate for re-identification and distinction from other images.
The original image plays a role in re-identification and distinction. The con-
ception remains ostensive exemplarization at this stage.
I know that some of you will doubt that there is such a stage. I do not
claim temporal priority for this stage. Nor do I claim that it is a natural or
K N O W L E D G E , AU T O N O M Y, A N D A R T I N L O OP T H E OR Y ( 191 )
I have said the dissolution of the mind-body problem results from exemplar-
ized content of the work of art. An explanation of how exemplar representa-
tion leads to the conception of the artwork as having intentionality and
phenomenology dissolves the mind-body problem. The features of mentality
are the features of an external material body, the artwork. Exemplarization of
the experience of our conscious states explains our knowledge of what they
are like and what they are about. Similarly, exemplarization of the experience
of works of art explains our knowledge of what they are like and what they are
about. Exemplarization depends on the activity of the brain for the exemplar-
ization of both consciousness and art. The conclusion, however, is that our
knowledge of the features of consciousness and our knowledge of the features
of works of art reveal the same features by the same kind of processes.
Consequently, those features and our knowledge of them show that such
knowledge and such features—intentionality and phenomenology are exam-
ples—cannot be the basis of a mind-body problem. In short, for all our
knowledge of conscious states tells us about these features, they may be states
of the brain exemplarized by the activity of the brain. The same is true of the
artwork. So the idea that physical objects cannot be like anything in the way
that conscious states are what they are like or be about anything in the way
that mental states are about what they are like is refuted by the artwork. The
artwork is a mentalized physical object, and a conscious state is a materialized
mental object. The loop tying the mental and the physical together is a form
of representation. Exemplarization is the form. Wittgenstein (1922) remarked
that the form of representation can be shown but not said. The exemplar
shows what cannot be said as it exhibits the form of representation.
There is a connection of exemplarization with trustworthiness and the
truth connection. We form content incorporating the exemplar. The exem-
plar becomes a sign, symbol, or representation, but it signifies, symbolizes,
or represents itself as well as other experiences. As I trust myself in the pro-
cess of autonomous exemplarization, accepting the content because of a
preference and power preference for doing so, I realize that I must rely on
self-trust. I place my trust in how I understand the object. However, the
reward for self-trust is that my exemplarization yields knowledge of what
the exemplar is like in terms of the exemplarized content. The exemplar,
when the process succeeds, signifies itself as it does other things. The
exemplar is part of content in a way that yields truth. The exemplar is true
( 194 ) Art, Self and Knowledge
components that are basic. It is the loop that maximizes explanation. You
need a system to raise explanation to philosophy, and you need a loop to
complete explanation. You need art to show you how the loop ties the
subjective and the objective, the internal and external, the mind and body
together in experience and to show you what the connection between them
is like. It can only be shown. Art shows us what cannot be said.
This page intentionally left blank
R EF E R E N C E S
( 197 )
( 198 ) References
Cohen, Stewart and Keith Lehrer (1983) “Justification, Truth and Coherence.” Synthese
55:191–208.
Collection (1970) Four Americans in Paris: The Collection of Gertrude Stein and Her Family, exh.
cat., New York: The Museum of Modern Art: 35. (No author cited.)
Collingwood, Robin George (1938) Principles of Art. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Croce, Benedetto (1922) Aesthetic as Science of Expression and General Linguistic, trans.
D. Ainslie. New York: Noonday Press.
Danto, Arthur (1964) “The Art World.” Journal of Philosophy 61:571–584.
——— (1994) Embodied Meanings: Critical Essays and Aesthetic Meditations. New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux.
Davidson, Donald (2001) Essays on Actions and Events, 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Davies, Stephen (1983) “Is Music a Language of the Emotions?” British Journal of Aesthetics
23:222–233.
Dennett, Daniel C. (2001) “In Darwin’s Wake, Where Am I?” Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Association. Delaware: American Philosophical Association.
Derrida, Jacques (1987) Truth in Painting. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Descartes, Rene (1986) Meditations on First Philosophy, trans. Ronald Rubin. Claremont,
C.A.: Arête Press.
Devereaux, Mary (2004) “Moral Judgments and Works of Art: The Case of Narrative Literature.”
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62:3–11.
Dewey, John (1934) Art as Experience. New York: Capricorn Books.
Dickie, George (1974) Art and the Aesthetic: An Institutional Analysis. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press.
——— (1997) An Introduction to Aesthetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dretske, Fred (1981) Knowledge and the Flow of Information. Oxford: Blackwell.
——— (1995) Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, M.A.: MIT Press.
Ducasse, C. J. (1951) Nature, Mind and Death. LaSalle, I.L.: Open Court Publishing Company.
Feldman, Fred (1992) Confrontations with the Reaper: A Philosophical Study of Nature and Value
of Death. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ferrier, James Frederick (1866) “Introduction to the Philosophy of Consciousness, Parts I to VII.”
Lectures on Greek Philosophy and Other Philosophical Remains, Vol. II, eds. Sir Alexander
Grant, Bart and E. L Lushington. London: William Blackwood and Sons, 1–257.
Firth, Roderick (1949) “Sense-Data and the Percept Theory.” Mind 58:434–465.
Fischer, John Martin (1994) The Metaphysics of Free Will: An Essay on Control. Oxford: Blackwell
Publishers.
Fischer, John Martin and Mark Ravizza (1998) Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral
Responsibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
——— (2009) Our Stories: Essays on Life, Death, and Free Will. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fodor, Jerry (1983) The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, M.A.: MIT Press.
Frankfurt, Harry G. (1969) “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.” Journal of
Philosophy 66:828–839.
——— (1971) “Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Journal of Philosophy
68:5–20.
Fry, Roger (1920) Vision and Design. London: Chatto and Windus.
Fürst, Martina (2010) “A Dualist Version of Phenomenal Concepts.” In draft.
Gombrich, E. H. (1972) Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation,
2nd edition. Princeton: published for Bollingen Foundation by Princeton University
Press.
Goodman, Nelson (1968) Languages of Art: An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill.
——— (1978) Ways of Worldmaking. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
References ( 199 )
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich (1977) Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Heidegger, Martin (1962) Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson.
New York: Harper.
——— (1971) “The Origin of the Work of Art.” In Poetry, Language, Thought. New York:
Harper-Collins.
Hein, Hilde and Carolyn Korsmeyer (1993) Aesthetics in Feminist Perspective. Bloomington:
Indiana University Press.
Hong, Lu and Scott Page (2001) “Problem Solving by Heterogeneous Agents.” Journal of
Economic Theory 97:123–163.
——— (2004) “Groups of Diverse Problem Solvers Can Outperform Groups of High-Ability
Problem Solvers.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences November 16 101 (46):
16385–16389.
Housman, A. E. (1936) “Easter Hymns, VVVI” in More Poems. New York: A. A. Knopf.
Hume, David (1739) A Treatise of Human Nature. London: John Noon.
Isenberg, Arnold (1949) “Critical Communication.” Philosophical Review 58:330–344.
Ismael, Jenann (2007) The Situated Self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, Frank (1982) “Epiphenomenal Qualities.” Philosophical Quarterly 32:127–136.
James, William (1981) Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. Indianapolis:
Hackett Publishing.
Kant, Immanuel (1914) Kant’s Critique of Judgment, trans. J. H. Bernard. London: Macmillan.
Kierkegaard, Soren (1941) Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. David Swenson. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Kriegel, Uriah (2002) “Phenomenal Content.” Erkenntnis 57:175–198.
——— (2004) “Moore’s Paradox and the Structure of Conscious Belief.” Erkenntnis
61:99–121.
——— (2006) “The Same-Order Monitoring Theory of Consciousness.” In Consciousness and
Self-Reference, eds. Uriah Kriegel and Kenneth Williford. Cambridge, M.A.: MIT Press.
Langer, Susanne (1957) Philosophy in a New Key. Cambridge, M.A.: Harvard University Press.
Lehrer, Adrienne and Keith Lehrer (1995) “Fields, Networks and Vectors.” In Grammar and
Meaning: Essays in Honor of Sir John Lyons, ed. F. R. Palmer. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lehrer, Keith, R. Roelofs, and Marshall Swain (1967) “Reason and Evidence: An Unsolved
Problem.” Ratio 9:1 38–48.
Lehrer, Keith and Carl Wagner (1981) Rational Consensus in Science and Society: A Philosophical
and Mathematical Study. Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Co.
——— (1989) Thomas Reid. London: Routledge.
——— (1996) “Consciousness.” In Philosophie in Österreich, ed. A. Schramm. Vienna: Hölder-
Pichler-Tempsky.
——— (1996) “Skepticism, Lucid Content, and the Metamental Loop.” In Philosophy and
Cognitive Science, eds. A. Clark, J. Ezquerro, and J. M. Larrazabal. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
——— (1997) Self-Trust: A Study of Reason, Knowledge and Autonomy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
——— (1998) “Reid, Hume and Common Sense.” Reid Studies 2:15–26.
——— (2000) “Discursive Knowledge.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research
60:637–653.
——— (2000) “Meaning, Exemplarization and Metarepresentation.” In Metarepresentation, ed.
Dan Sperber. New York: Oxford University Press.
——— (2000) Theory of Knowledge, Second Edition. Boulder: Westview Press.
——— (2001) “Individualism, Communitarianism and Consensus.” The Journal of Ethics
5:105–120.
( 200 ) References
——— (2002) “Self-Presentation, Representation and the Self.” Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 64:412–430.
——— (2003) “Reason and Autonomy.” Social Philosophy and Policy 20:177–198.
——— (2004) “Freedom and the Power of Preference.” In Freedom and Determinism, eds.
Joseph Keim Campbell, Michael O’Rourke, and David Shier. Cambridge, M.A.: MIT
Press.
——— (2004) “Representation in Painting and Consciousness.” Philosophical Studies
117:1–14.
——— (2006) “Consciousness, Representation and Knowledge.” In Self-Representational
Approaches to Consciousness, eds. Uriah Kriegel and Kenneth Williford. Cambridge,
M.A.: MIT.
——— (2006) “Knowing Content in the Visual Arts.” In Knowing Art, eds. Dominic Lopes and
Matthew Kieran. Dordrecht: Springer.
——— (2007) “Loop Theory: Knowledge, Art and Autonomy.” John Dewey Lecture,
Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 81:121–136.
——— (2010) “Preview of Looking Up/Looking Down.” Arizona Daily Star (Tucson, October 8,
2010).
Lewis, C. I. (1946) An Analysis of Knowledge and Evaluation. La Salle, I.L: Open Court
Publishing Company.
Lewis, David (1988) “What Experience Teaches.” Proceedings of the Russellian Society
13:29–57.
Lopes, Dominic McIver (1996) Understanding Pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lucretius, Titus Carus (1851) On the Nature of Things, trans. John Selby Watson. London:
Henry G. Bohn.
Mill, John Stuart (1859) On Liberty.
Nabokov, Vladimir (1955) Lolita. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons.
Nagel, Thomas (1974) “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” Philosophical Review 83:1–22.
Neurath, Otto (1931) “Soziologie im Physikalismus.” Erkenntnis 3:393–431.
Nietzsche, Fredrich (1967) Thus Spake Zarathustra, trans. Thomas Common. New York:
Heritage.
Olsson, Erik J. (2003) The Epistemology of Keith Lehrer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Page, Scott E. (2007) The Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Palade, George E. et al (1955) “A Small Particulate Component of the Cytoplasm.” J. Biophys.
Biochem. Cytol. 1:59–68.
Papineau, David (2002) Thinking About Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
——— (2007) “Phenomenal and Perceptual Concepts.” In Phenomenal Concepts and Phenomenal
Knowledge, eds. Alter and Sven Walter. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Plantinga, Alvin (1993) Warrant and Proper Function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pouivet, Roger (2005) “Thomas Reid’s Aesthetic Realism.” Journal of Scottish Philosophy
3:35–45.
Quine, W. V. O. (1969) “Epistemology Naturalized.” In Ontology, Relativity and Other Essays.
New York, Columbia University Press.
Reichenbach, Hans (1949) The Theory of Probability. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Reid, Thomas (1785) Essays on the Intellectual Powers of Man. In The Philosophical Works of
Thomas Reid, D. D., 8th edition (1895), ed. Sir William Hamilton. Edinburgh: James Thin.
——— (1983) Thomas Reid’s Inquiry and Essays, eds. Ronald Beanblossom and Keith Lehrer.
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.
Rosenthal, David M. (2000) “Consciousness and Metacognition.” In Metarepresentation, ed.
Dan Sperber. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1956) Being and Nothingness, trans. Hazel Barnes. New York: Vintage Books.
References ( 201 )
Sasse, Julie (2005) Bailey Doogan: Selected Works 1971–2005. Tucson, Arizona: Etherton
Gallery.
Schlick, Mortiz (1959) “The Foundation of Knowledge.” In Logical Positivism, ed. A. J. Ayer.
Glencoe, I.L.: The Free Press.
Sellars, Wilfrid (1963) Science, Perception and Reality. New York: Humanities Press.
Simmons, Ruth J. (2010) Brown Alumni Magazine. September/October 19.
Spencer-Brown, G. (1969) Laws of Form. London: Allen and Unwin.
Spinoza, Benedictus (2000) Ethics, trans. George Henry Radcliffe Parkinson. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Stevens, W. (1990) The Collected Poems of Wallace Stevens. New York: Vintage Books.
Tolstoy, Leo (1995) What Is Art? trans. Richard Pevear and Larissa Volokhonsk. London:
Penguin Classics.
Tye, Michael (2005) “On the Nonconceptual Content of Experience.” in Experience and
Analysis, eds. Maria E. Reicher and Johann Marek. Wien: Öbv & Hpt.
Van Inwagen, Peter (1996) “It Is Wrong, Everywhere, Always, and for Anyone, to Believe
Anything upon Insufficient Evidence.” In Faith, Freedom, and Rationality, eds. Jeff Jordan
and Daniel Howard-Snyder. Lanham, M.A.: Rowman and Littlefield.
Velleman, J. David (2003) “Narrative Explanation.” Philosophical Review 112:1–26.
Walton, Kendall L. (1990) Mimesis as Make-Believe: On the Foundations of the Representational
Arts. Cambridge, M.A.: Harvard University Press.
Wartenberg, Thomas E. (2007) The Nature of Art: An Anthology, 2nd edition. Belmont, C.A.:
Thomas Wadsworth.
Weitz, Morris (1956) “The Role of Theory in Aesthetics.” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
15:27–35.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1922) Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. C. K. Ogden. London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Wollheim, Richard (1980) Art and Its Objects: With Six Supplementary Essays, 2nd edition.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
——— (1987) The Art of Painting. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
This page intentionally left blank
N A M E I N DEX
( 203 )
( 204 ) Name Index
Hein, Hilde, 6, 50, 56, 199 Neurath, Otto, 177, 192, 200r
Hong, Lu, 164–165, 199r Nielsen, Doug, 48
Hospers, John, x Nietzsche, Fredrich, 103, 108, 146, 200r
Hume, David, 10, 21, 25–27, 39, 61, 91,
104–106, 112, 115–117, 123, 149, O'Keefe, Georgia, 51, 78, 90
189, 199r Olsson, Erik J., 95, 200r
Orlan, 53, 55–56, 175
Isenberg, Arnold, 20, 29, 199r
Ismael, Jenann, 45, 119, 199r Page, Scott E., 163–165, 168, 200r
Ivey, Paul, xi Palade, George E., 190–192, 200r
Ivy, Karen, 48, 143 Papineau, David, 44, 119, 200r
Picasso, Pablo, 76
Jackson, Frank, 13, 42, 117, 199r Plantinga, Alvin, 200r
Plato, 10, 76, 127, 197r
Kant, Immanuel, 56, 61, 199f Pollock, Jackson, 88, 133
Kierkegaard, Soren, 108–109, 150, Pompadour, Madame de, 12, 148,
188, 199r 156–157, 189
Klein, Ives, 5, 33, 85, 97, 114, Pouivet, Roger, 138, 200r
120–121, 137
Kriegel, Uriah, xii, 37, 115, 199r Quine, W.V.O., 175–177, 200r
Spencer-Brown, G., xi, 4, 13, 40, 48, 85–86, Van Gogh, Vincent, 88, 108, 148
116, 201r Van Inwagen, Peter, 148, 201r
Spinoza, Benedictus, 109, 201r Velleman, J. David, 79, 91, 201r
Stein, Sarah, 132–133 Vigée-Lebruin, 64
Stevens, W., 101, 107, 201r
Still, Clyfford, 136–137
Wagner, Carl., 70, 99, 160, 199r
Swain, Marshall, 151, 199r
Walton, Kendall L., 24, 124, 201
Swatez, Gerald, xi
Wartenberg, Thomas E., 52, 128,
Thomas, Dylan, 94, 110 197r, 201r
Tierney, Hannah, x1 Weitz, Morris, x , 130, 201r
Titian, 11, 78 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 112, 193, 201r
Tolliver, Joseph, xi Wollheim, Richard, 24, 55, 201
Tolstoy, Leo, 54, 76–77, 130–131, 201r Wteweal, Joachim, 124
Tudor, Anthony, 75
Tye, Michael, 85, 201r Yeats, Jack, 49, 55, 147–148
This page intentionally left blank
S U B J E C T I N DE X
( 207 )
( 208 ) Subject Index
collective wisdom, 7 D
about truth, 164ff dance, 48–49
better than simple averaging, 166 deceived
communal language, a fiction, 170–171 by brain manipulator, 179
completeness, and death, 107 by demon, 179
and theory, 178 death of the artist, 76
conception, 4–5, 7 death, 101ff
of art, 33 and beauty, 107–108
and conceptual space, 4, 187 completeness, 107
of consciousness, 33ff existential, 103
of content and exemplarization, intelligible or not, 102
14ff and loop of exemplarization, 106
of emotion, 65–67 and materialism, 102–103
and intentionality, 112ff and meaning, 108ff
and negation, 105–106 as part of ones life story, 101ff
scientific, 190–192 Dinner Party, 51ff, 55–56, 78
consciousness, 3ff disagreement, 7, 145ff
of art, 32 of interpretation, 60
changing, 53, 129 disquotation, 119
immediacy of, 35, 47 diversity, 159ff
ineffable, 114 and averaging, 163–164
metaphysics of, 32ff and truth, 163ff
raising, 52
convergence, of averaging, 161 E
to consensual probability, 161 emotional
consensus, 7, 159ff content, 27ff
incorporates self-trust, 161 expression 59
versus self-trust, 160 emotions
and truth, 163ff expression of, 59
and value, 163 in the medium, 62
consensual weights, 162 encapsulation, 28
content, 4 epistemology naturalized, 175
of art 9ff error theory, 64
external versus internal accounts evidence, 149ff
of, 168–171 and parity, 149ff
ineffable, 10 part of the causal order, 182
transfer of art, to world, 91, 125, 111ff, theory of, 175
145–146, 174–175 exemplar representation, 10ff, 101,
universal, 70 111ff, 174
vehicles of, 83ff and the external world, 168
contentlessness, 13 and verbal representation, 169
of science, 190–192 exemplarization
sensuous, 189 compared to exemplification 21ff
unrepresented, 34 of consciousness, 33
co-optation, 71–72 defined, 4, 10ff
Countess von Schönfeld and Her ostensive and truth, 29, 33ff, 118–119,
Daughter, 64 189, 191
critical communication, 20ff of physical states, 44, 11ff
cultural in science and art, 167–169
barriers, 68 standard, defined, 38
identity, 72 of the world, 123
Subject Index ( 209 )
discursive 27 movement
and loop, 181 and gesture, 75–76
primitive and discursive, 15ff, 36 and meaning, 75–76
L N
life after death, 108–109 nominalism, 21, 23, 27
Lolita, 124
Looking Up/Looking Down, 48 O
loop objectivity, and subjectivity,
connecting truth and collective wisdom, 166 188, 194
of exemplarization and death, 106, Olympia, 24ff, 78
118–119 ostensive
keystone, 7, 92, 158 exemplarization, 113, 118, 121,
and knowledge, 181 138–139, 191
of representation, 37 generalization, 112
theory 158, 173ff representation, 15ff, 40ff, 174
of token onto itself, 39, 96 ownership choice, 92ff
of truth, 120
L'Origine du Monde, 6 P
Lot and His Daughters, 124 paradigm shifts, 161
luck, and knowledge, 176, 181 paradox
of aesthetic experience, 45–46
M of feminist art, 53
make-believe, 124 and toggling, 46
mapping, one-to-one, 167–168 parity condition, 149ff
marking a distinction, 13, 48, 76, 85–86, undone by acceptance, 156
112, 116, 134–135, 141–142, 190 particulars, 12ff
martyrs, renaissance paintings of, 55 performance art, 48ff
Mary and color experience, 13, 24, 42, 117 phenomenology, 9, 24ff, 66, 113, 191
meaning phenominalist
of art experience, 47 mistake of, 121
and death, 108ff physical objects, 123, 193
embodied, 50, 56, 136, 189 Piss Christ, x, 147, 150
guaranteeing truth, 191–192 postmodernism, 62, 71
of words, 20 empowers the viewer, 71, 132, 192
mentalized physical object, 8, 50, 69, 112, power preference, 94, 184–186, 193
136. 189–190, 193 predicates, 21ff
MetaMe, 95 entrenched, 23
metamental ascent metaphorical, 23, 118
an explanatory loop, 183 presentational symbol, 64–65
leads to truth connection, 182 priming, 122
undoes the errors of nature, 181 principle
metaphysics first, 178
of consciousness 32ff, 77 first first, 178
and necessity, 182 of maximizing explanation, 173,
of properties, 26–27 178–179, 181
mind-body problem, 188ff meta, 178
dissolved, 189, 193 T, of trustworthiness truth
minimal art, 12, 47, 139 connected, 180–181, 186
Monochrome Blue, 5, 33, 85, 88, 114, of trustworthiness, 178
119–121, 137 of truth, 178
Subject Index ( 211 )
U of a life, 82ff
ultrapreference, 94–96 part of the causal order, 182
and reasons, 96, 184 Venus
unconscious, 146–147 painting of, 11, 78
V
W
vagina, 51, 54
world making, 88, 157–158, 171
value
aesthetic and moral, 82
of art, 59ff Z
and consensus, 163ff Zarathustra, 103, 200r
generic, 60, 62, 83, 96, 167 zombies, 43–44
intrinsic, 56, 60, 128–129 agnosticism about possibility of, 43