Can There Be A Feminist Science Longino
Can There Be A Feminist Science Longino
Can There Be A Feminist Science Longino
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Hypatia
51
52
53
and then apply the results of that examination to the idea of feminist
scientific inquiry.
II
I distinguish two kinds of values relevant to the sciences. Constitutive
values, internal to the sciences, are the source of the rules determining
what constitutes acceptable scientific practice or scientific method. The
personal, social and cultural values, those group or individual
preferences about what ought to be I call contextual values, to indicate
that they belong to the social and cultural context in which science is
done (Longino 1983c). The traditional interpretation of the value-
freedom of modern natural science amounts to a claim that its con-
stitutive and contextual features are clearly distinct from and indepen-
dent of one another, that contextual values play no role in the inner
workings of scientific inquiry, in reasoning and observation. I shall
argue that this construal of the distinction cannot be maintained.
There are several ways to develop such an argument. One scholar
is fond of inviting her audience to visit any science library and peruse
the titles on the shelves. Observe how subservient to social and cultural
interests are the inquiries represented by the book titles alone! Her
listeners would soon abandon their ideas about the value-neutrality o
the sciences, she suggests. This exercise may indeed show the influence
of external, contextual considerations on what research gets done/sup-
ported (i.e., on problem selection). It does not show that such considera-
tions affect reasoning or hypothesis acceptance. The latter would re
quire detailed investigation of particular cases or a general conceptua
argument. The conceptual arguments involve developing some version
of what is known in philosophy of science as the underdetermination
thesis, i.e., the thesis that a theory is always underdetermined by the
evidence adduced in its support, with the consequence that differen
or incompatible theories are supported by or at least compatible with
the same body of evidence. I shall sketch a version of the argument
that appeals to features of scientific inference.
One of the rocks on which the logical positivist program foundered
was the distinction between theoretical and observational language.
Theoretical statements contain, as fundamental descriptive terms, terms
that do not occur in the description of data. Thus, hypotheses in parti-
cle physics contain terms like "electron," "pion," "muon," "electron
spin," etc. The evidence for a hypothesis such as "A pion decays se-
quentially into a muon, then a positron" is obviously not direct obser-
vations of pions, muons and positrons, but consists largely in
photographs taken in large and complex experimental apparati: ac-
celerators, cloud chambers, bubble chambers. The photographs show
54
all sorts of squiggly lines and spirals. Evidence for the hypotheses of
particle physics is presented as statements that describe these
photographs. Eventually, of course, particle physicists point to a spot
on a photograph and say things like "Here a neutrino hits a neutron."
Such an assertion, however, is an interpretive achievement which in-
volves collapsing theoretical and observational moments. A skeptic
would have to be supplied a complicated argument linking the elements
of the photograph to traces left by particles and these to particles
themselves. What counts as theory and what as data in a pragmatic
sense change over time, as some ideas and experimental procedures come
to be securely embedded in a particular framework and others take their
place on the horizons. As the history of physics shows, however, secure
embeddedness is no guarantee against overthrow.
Logical positivists and their successors hoped to model scientific in-
ference formally. Evidence for hypotheses, data, were to be represented
as logical consequences of hypotheses. When we try to map this logical
structure onto the sciences, however, we find that hypotheses are, for
the most part, not just generalizations of data statements. The links
between data and theory, therefore, cannot be adequately represented
as formal or syntactic, but are established by means of assumptions
that make or imply substantive claims about the field over which one
theorizes. Theories are confirmed via the confirmation of their con-
stituent hypotheses, so the confirmation of hypotheses and theories is
relative to the assumptions relied upon in asserting the evidential con-
nection. Conformation of such assumptions, which are often unar-
ticulated, is itself subject to similar relativization. And it is these assump
tions that can be the vehicle for the involvement of considerations
motivated primarily by contextual values (Longino 1979, 1983a).
The point of this extremely telescoped argument is that one can
give an a priori specification of confirmation that effectively eliminat
the role of value-laden assumptions in legitimate scientific inquir
without eliminating auxiliary hypotheses (assumptions) altogether. This
is not to say that all scientific reasoning involves value-related assump-
tions. Sometimes auxiliary assumptions will be supported by mundan
inductive reasoning. But sometimes they will not be. In any given case,
they may be metaphysical in character; they may be untestable wit
present investigative techniques; they may be rooted in contextual
value-related considerations. If, however, there is no a priori way t
eliminate such assumptions from evidential reasoning generally, and
hence, no way to rule out value-laden assumptions, then there is n
formal basis for arguing that an inference mediated by contextual values
is thereby bad science.
A comparable point is made by some historians investigating the
55
111
56
The argument I've just offered about the idea of a value-free science
is similar in spirit to those earlier arguments. I think it makes it possi-
ble to see these questions from a slightly different angle.
There is a tradition of viewing scientific inquiry as somehow inex-
orable. This involves supposing that the phenomena of the natural world
are fixed in determinate relations with each other, that these relations
can be known and formulated in a consistent and unified way. This
is not the old "unified science" idea of the logical positivists, with its
privileging of physics. In its "unexplicated" or "pre-analytic" state,
it is simply the idea that there is one consistent, integrated or coherent,
true theoretical treatment of all natural phenomena. (The indeterminacy
principle of quantum physics is restricted to our understanding of the
behavior of certain particles which themselves underlie the fixities of
the natural world. Stochastic theories reveal fixities, but fixities among
ensembles rather than fixed relations among individual objects or
events.) The scientific inquirer's job is to discover those fixed relations.
Just as the task of Plato's philosophers was to discover the fixed rela-
tions among forms and the task of Galileo's scientists was to discover
the laws written in the language of the grand book of nature, geometry,
so the scientist's task in this tradition remains the discovery of fixed
relations however conceived. These ideas are part of the realist tradi-
tion in the philosophy of science.
It's no longer possible, in a century that has seen the splintering of
the scientific disciplines, to give such a unified description of the ob-
jects of inquiry. But the belief that the job is to discover fixed relations
of some sort, and that the application of observation, experiment and
reason leads ineluctably to unifiable, if not unified, knowledge of an
independent reality, is still with us. It is evidenced most clearly in two
features of scientific rhetoric: the use of the passive voice as in "it is
concluded that . . ." or "it has been discovered that . . ." and the at-
tribution of agency to the data, as in "the data suggest. .. ." Such
language has been criticized for the abdication of responsibility it in
dicates. Even more, the scientific inquirer, and we with her, becom
passive observers, victims of the truth. The idea of a value-free science
is integral to this view of scientific inquiry. And if we reject that idea
we can also reject our roles as passive onlookers, helpless to affect the
course of knowledge.
Let me develop this point somewhat more concretely and
autobiographically. Biologist Ruth Doell and I have been examining
studies in three areas of research on the influence of sex hormones on
human behavior and cognitive performance: research on the influence
of pre-natal, in utero, exposure to higher or lower than normal levels
of androgens and estrogens on so-called 'gender-role' behavior in
57
58
59
60
61
62
notes
I am grateful to the Wellesley Center for Research on Women for the Mellon Sch
ship during which I worked on the ideas in this essay. I am also grateful to aud
at UC Berkeley, Northeastern University, Brandeis University and Rice University
their comments and to the anonymous reviewers for Hypatia for their suggestion
earlier version appeared as Wellesley Center for Research on Women Working Paper
1. This seems to be suggested in Bleier (1984), Rose (1983) and in Sandra Hardi
(1980) early work.
2. For a striking expression of this point of view see Witelson (1985).
3. Ideological commitments other than feminist ones may lead to the same assu
tions and the variety of feminisms means that feminist commitments can lead to
ferent and incompatible assumptions.
4. Cf. note 1, above.
5. This is not to say that interactionist ideas may not be applied in productive con-
texts, but that, unlike linear causal models, they are several steps away from the manipula-
tion of natural processes immediately suggested by the latter. See Keller (1985), especial-
ly Chapter 10.
references
63
64