Nontraditional Arguments For Theism: Chad A. Mcintosh
Nontraditional Arguments For Theism: Chad A. Mcintosh
Nontraditional Arguments For Theism: Chad A. Mcintosh
DOI: 10.1111/phc3.12590
ARTICLE
Chad A. McIntosh
I N T R O D U CT I O N
Arguments for theism have played a central role in the drama of philosophy. It wasn't until the 20th century that they
were demoted from center stage to the peripheral role they now have. Their descent into philosophical ignobility has
been made complete by contemporary introductory texts and courses that present them in caricatured form as
dismissible curiosities, Aquinas by Russell, Anselm by Guanilo, Leibniz by Hume, Paley by Darwin, and so on. The fact
is, however, arguments for theism have proven tremendously durable. Further, they seem to have a fractal‐like prop-
erty of generating indefinitely many iterations, making talk of “the” cosmological argument, for instance, almost
meaningless.
There has also been growing interest in theistic arguments that, worse than being caricatured, are often ignored
or altogether unknown, as indicated by the recent publication of the conference proceedings on Alvin Plantinga's
infamous lecture “Two Dozen (or so) Theistic Arguments” (Walls & Dougherty, 2018). In this article, I provide an over-
view of theistic arguments1 that cannot neatly be considered variants of traditional arguments, which I group into
seven categories:
I. Cosmological
II. Ontological
III. Design
IV. Moral
V. Miracles
VI. Pragmatic
VII. Experiential
-------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
© 2019 The Author(s) Philosophy Compass © 2019 John Wiley & Sons Ltd
The arguments included in the first three categories should be familiar enough. I include in category (IV) argu-
ments from objective moral facts, obligations, and duties; human dignity and worth; altruism; and arguments from evil
and the nature of justice. Included in (V) are arguments from testimony to the miraculous, historical, and contempo-
rary. Category (VI) includes wager‐style arguments and (VII) arguments from religious experience and personal trans-
formation. I group nontraditional theistic arguments into seven additional categories:
I. Metaphysical
II. Nomological
III. Axiological
IV. Noological
V. Linguistic
VI. Anthropological
VII. Meta‐argument
Each category is based on thematic commonality or family resemblance rather than strict criteria, so some arbi-
trariness and overlap are inevitable. Nevertheless, I think the proposed taxonomy imposes a sufficiently accurate
and meaningful order on the vast literature of theistic arguments. “Nontraditional,” furthermore, should not be taken
to imply “novel.” Some arguments are novel, to be sure, but others have quite the historical pedigree. That said, this
review is limited to the analytic tradition with a contemporary emphasis.2 As a final preliminary note, not included are
arguments against naturalism tout court. Tacking on the proviso “given that theism and naturalism are the only live
options …” would expand the terrain beyond what can be traversed here.3
1 | METAPHYSICAL ARGUMENTS
The widest ranging category of nontraditional arguments take their cue from certain metaphysical entities and facts.
I'll mention seven.
Abstracta generally. Properties, propositions, numbers, sets, logical laws, etc., generally referred to as abstract
objects, have long been appealed to in arguments for theism, from Augustine to Leibniz (on the latter, see Adams,
1983, 1994). In what he calls “the Augustinian proof,” Feser (2017) deduces theism by eliminating the only other real-
ist accounts of abstracta, Platonism, and scholastic realism. Among other problems, Platonism renders abstracta den-
izens of some epistemically inaccessible realm distinct from the mental and physical, and Scholastic realism cannot
account for their necessity or infinitude. Theism avoids precisely these difficulties by locating them in the infinite
intellect of a necessary being. A bit more modestly, E.J. Lowe (2013) argues that God is the best explanation of their
existence. Because “objects of reason,” as Lowe calls them, are nonphysical, infinite in number, and exist necessarily,
they cannot be explained by anything finite, physical, or contingent. Whatever the naturalist's putative explanation of
them (if one is ventured at all), it will not be as good as the theist's, who has in God a nonphysical, necessary being of
infinite rational intellect.
Sets. Menzel (2018) argues that the existence and nature of sets is confirmatory evidence for the existence of an
infinite intellect. A realist about sets cannot explain why, given sets' collective iterative structure (i.e., that larger sets
are formed from smaller ones, which eventually bottom out in urelements), the set‐theoretic hierarchy is only as “high”
as it is. Why can't we continue to construct more out of sets already there? In response, some philosophers suggest
that the structure of the set‐theoretic hierarchy reflects only what sets could exist were their members to exist, and
so, necessarily, sets are contingent. But if what sets there are is just a contingent fact, then realism can't explain why
there are exactly those sets in the hierarchy when there could have been others, or none at all. This is explained, how-
ever, if sets are what an intellect freely chooses to collect. But there are just too many sets with too many members
for them to be the mental collections of anything but an infinite intellect.4
MCINTOSH 3 of 14
Propositions. In addition to being necessary and infinite in number, propositions seem to actually be distinctively
mental in character, making it especially easy to liken them to divine thoughts. Something of a modern classic here
is Quentin Smith (1994), where Smith argues that conceptualism about propositions—the view that propositions
are effects of mental causes (propositional attitudes)—entails the existence of an omniscient mind. Unfortunately,
Smith says little on behalf of conceptualism other than that it is rationally acceptable.5 Others, such as Davis
(2008, 2011) and Anderson and Welty (2011) have gone further, arguing for theism from conceptualism about prop-
ositions, laws of logic, and possible worlds. Consider the truth‐bearing nature of propositions. For the proposition
“Quine is wise” to be true, it must be an intentional object of or about its constituents, intentionality being a hallmark
of mentality. Further, Davis contends, the constituents of propositions are best construed as ideas (e.g., the idea of
Quine and the idea of wisdom), and as such need a mind not just to host them but to properly arrange them so as
to accurately represent reality, i.e., being true. Even the most prominent naturalistic accounts of propositions are con-
ceptualist in spirit, but fall prey to what Keller (2017, 2018) calls “the scarcity objection”: there are more propositions
than any theory committed only to finite minds can account for. The intentional nature of propositions therefore
requires an infinite mind.
Unities. God, it is argued, is necessary to explain certain unities, such as facts, composite objects, and the cosmos.
Respectively, Vallicella (2000) argues that the best candidate for truthmakers are facts. For example, the truthmaker
of “a is F” is a's being F. So, facts exist. But what unites a fact's constituents—a and F‐ness—into one entity? Theories
that do not appeal to an external unifier—whether some further constituent, or just the fact itself—are incoherent. So,
facts exist and depend on an external unifier. Now, if facts exist, they possibly exist, and whatever is possible is
actualizable. The possibility that some fact or other exists is actualizable in every possible world. But if some fact
or other is possibly actualizable in every possible world, there must exist an external unifier in every possible world.
Since such a unifier cannot be an abstract or material object, the only remaining possibility is that it is a mind—et hoc
omnes intelligunt Deum (cf. Kronen & Menssen, 2013). Braine (1988) argues that the all contingent beings are tempo-
ral and composite. But there is nothing intrinsic to their being that explains how they persist through time: Nothing in
the past or future can hold them together, so to speak. Their persistence therefore requires a noncontingent (neces-
sary, atemporal, and incomposite) sustaining cause. Finally and most briefly, Juarez (2017) argues that only God can
be the ultimate explanation of what unifies the many things in the cosmos into the orderly, systemic whole that it is.
The unity cannot be explained by its parts, individually or collectively. Nor can it be attributed to natural laws. Under-
stood descriptively, laws are not causally efficacious. Understood prescriptively, laws themselves require explanation
and so cannot be the ultimate explanation of the unity of the cosmos. Only a transcendent cause would seem to be a
sufficient explanation.
Limits. Rasmussen (2019) has recently advanced an argument for theism based on the nature of limits: Whatever
is limited has an explanation. For example, the size of the Earth is limited, and is explained by, among other things, its
mass. If whatever is limited has an explanation, then, possibly, something is unlimited. This is because the explanation
of limited things cannot itself be a limited thing, lest the explanation be circular and therefore not explanatory at all.
So, possibly, something is unlimited. Now, to be unlimited is to be perfect. But a perfect being, the terminus for expla-
nations, would be necessarily existent. Per S5, if something is possibly necessary it is necessary. Therefore, there is a
perfect being. (Note: This modal inference, valid in system S5, appears in a number of arguments to be discussed, so it
might help to spell it out a bit more here.6 Something is possible if it obtains [exists in, is true in] in some possible
world. Something is necessary if it obtains in all possible worlds. So, if something is possibly necessary, something
is necessary in some possible world. But, by the definition of necessity, if something necessary obtains in any world,
it obtains in all worlds, including the actual world. So whatever is possibly necessary is actual. Since if God exists, he
exists of necessity, if he possibly exists, he actually exists.)
The Applicability of Mathematics. Nobel Prize‐winning physicist Eugene Wigner (1960) famously drew attention to
how mathematical concepts permit uncannily accurate models of natural phenomena. He likened the situation to a
man being given a ring of keys successfully opening a series of doors on the first or second try each time. Similarly,
the use of mathematical concepts to unlock the mysteries of nature seems suspiciously convenient. It at least defies a
4 of 14 MCINTOSH
naturalistic explanation, argues Steiner (1998), proposing instead that the user friendliness of mathematics suggests
they're tailor‐made for us, ready to be exploited for exploration and discovery of the natural world. Craig (2016) pro-
poses that the happy coincidence is best explained by God modeling the world in accordance with either the math-
ematical structures “out there” or those he had in mind.
An interesting and novel twist to arguments in this category is Leftow (2010, 2018), who argues not from realism
about abstracta, but from anti‐realism: By showing how all abstracta—possible worlds, essences, propositions,
hacceities, properties, sets, numbers, relations, etc.—can be reduced to God and His activities, Leftow thinks theism
outstrips all rival theories of abstracta in theoretical virtues: It is more parsimonious in kind and number, has greater
explanatory scope, and has more homely and work‐efficient primitives, all without sacrificing what is so attractive
about realism (namely, objectivity). Insofar as you are attracted to desert landscapes but cannot forsake the objective
waters of realism, theism is the best option.
2 | N O M O LO G I C A L A R G U M E N T S
Nomological arguments for theism are based on the ontological status, structure, and character of the laws of
nature.7
There is a long history of thought on the relationship between God and laws (see brief discussion and references
in Koperski, 2017), but F. R. Tennant (1924) was one of the first to highlight their potential as evidence for theism.
The first to develop an analytically rigorous theistic argument from laws, however, is Ratzsch (1987), who argues that
problems which otherwise beset widely‐held accounts of laws as universally quantified subjunctives can be avoided
by thinking of them as counterfactuals of freedom. But obviously, this would require a free agent with the stability of
character and power to decree natural laws—viz., God.
Peterson's (1996) argument mirrors Feser's Augustinian proof discussed above, only with natural laws instead
of abstracta, arriving at theism via elimination of competing views. Structurally similar but more sophisticated is
Foster (2001, 2004). Foster argues that the regularity of nature—and, as a consequence, the justification of induc-
tion—is best explained by the existence of nomically necessary laws. But prevailing realist accounts of laws (such
as Armstrong's) suffer from insuperable objections. The best explanation of laws is their being creations of a
supernatural being who then imposes them on the universe to ensure its regularity. Swinburne (2006) piles on,
contending that Armstrong's view, while plausibly accounting for event–event causation, cannot account for the
causal powers of intentional agents, which are substances. Rather than postulate two different kinds of causation,
it would be simpler to reduce the former to the latter, even simpler to reduce all causation to the causal power of
a single intentional agent, and even simpler still if that agent is God, who is, Swinburne maintains, the simplest
kind of person.
Interestingly, it seems to be the majority position in the literature that any realist view of laws is best explained by
theism. This is the verdict reached by Cartwright (2005), who therefore thinks reducing laws to dispositional powers
is the only position open to the naturalist. This is indeed a popular position, but Swinburne (2004), Dumsday (2011),
and Orr (2019) argue that even powers‐based analyses of laws is best explained by theism. Nontheistic analyses, for
instance, still leave unanswered questions like how there can be laws such as gravity that apply across objects of dif-
ferent natural kinds, and how dispositions get instantiated in objects in the first place.
Gordon (2018) thinks quantum theory requires a structural realism approach to laws; in particular, one according
to which reality is partly phenomenal in character. It is an indisputable result of quantum theory, he says, that there is
genuine ontic indeterminacy, which, contra naturalism, entails that physical reality is not sufficient unto itself. With-
out something more fundamental than matter to fill the gaps, material objects are radically ontologically incomplete.
But ontological incompleteness violates the principle of sufficient reason—the rejection of which destroys science
and leads to self‐defeating skepticism. The best explanation of what brings closure to reality is a kind of phenome-
nalism, which Gordan thinks is best attributed to the causal activity of God.8
MCINTOSH 5 of 14
3 | AXIOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS
Axiological arguments appeal to species of value unlike that in traditional moral arguments for theism.
A surprising number of philosophers have defended the seemingly counterintuitive view that the universe exists
because it should (Leslie, 1970, 1979; Rescher, 1984, 2010). Although the underlying axiarchic principle—that for all p,
if it ought to be the case that p, then p—has been used to motivate a variety of nonnaturalistic views (e.g., Leslie,
2001; Mander, 2016; Steinhart, 2012), it has also been used in arguments for theism. Hugh Rice (2000) agrees that
the principle explains why the universe exists but argues further that the principle itself is best understood as being a
reflection of God's will. Kordig (1989) and Vallicella (2018) advance a theistic argument based on a modal version of
the axiarchic principle: a maximally perfect being ought to exist. So, God ought to exist. Whatever ought to exist pos-
sibly exists. So, God possibly exists. Per S5, if God possibly exists, God exists. So, God exists. Something like this argu-
ment appears in nascent form in Ewing (1965).
More common in this category are appeals to beauty and aesthetics which, even by nontheist's lights, can serve as
powerful evidence for theism.9 Yet Swinburne (2004) appeals to beauty only as strengthening the design argument
(beauty in a designed universe is expected, but it isn't in an undesigned universe), and Howell (2006) argues that
mathematical theories' satisfaction of aesthetic criteria further supports theism as the explanation for their applica-
bility to the natural world.
There are stand‐alone arguments from beauty, however. Many harken back to F. R. Tennant (1930), who argues
that because things that are not the product of aesthetic intent are rarely beautiful, whereas the natural world, far
from being rarely beautiful, is in general beautiful, the natural world is likely the product of aesthetic intent (for
extended defense of Tennant, see Wynn, 1999). Forrest (1996) argues sensuous and nonsensuous beauty, like the
sublime (not to be confused as with what is merely pleasant), has the resilient impression of being a gift, pointing
to a transcendent, benevolent, infinitely beautiful giver. Similarly, West and Pelser (2015) argue that natural beauty
can serve as a Reidian “natural sign” that noninferentially justifies belief in God by perceiving Him through it. More
recent arguments from beauty (Geivett & Spiegel, 2019; Tallon, 2018) are simply framed: The objectivity of beauty
is best explained by theism. Defended at length are the central claims that beauty is, in fact, objective and that that
is improbable given naturalism.10 God, by contrast, as a being in whom all truth, beauty, and goodness reside, would
be an ideal ground and so the much better explanation.
The objectivity of beauty may not, however, be an essential ingredient in theistic arguments from aesthetics. As
many of the argument's defenders also emphasize, the fact that we have aesthetic sensibilities at all is better
explained by theism than naturalism. What we find beautiful goes far beyond, and sometimes contrary to, what might
have once had survival value. This otherwise gratuitous and overdeveloped sense of the aesthetic would be expected
if our cognitive faculties are the product of a being who himself has a taste for the aesthetic.11
4 | N O O L O G I C A L A R G U M EN T S
Noological (from noûs, mind or intellect) arguments are arguments for theism based on a variety of mind‐related phe-
nomena such as consciousness, reason, and knowledge.12
Let's begin with consciousness. The core idea, expressed by ancients and moderns alike, is that the seeming
implausibility of matter producing mind justifies a theological alternative. The argument's most prominent contempo-
rary defender is Richard Swinburne (2004, 2018). We know from experience that there are mental events (sensations
of color, pains, beliefs, thoughts, and feelings) distinct from physical (brain) events, yet they are obviously connected
in some law‐like way. A naturalistic explanation for how this could be is very improbable for several reasons. First,
psycho‐physical laws are not generalizable the way physical laws are because the former incorporate fundamentally
different kinds of things. So, second, there must be an enormous number of separate laws, and each could state only
that some particular brain event is connected to some particular mental event, not why (a point emphasized by
6 of 14 MCINTOSH
Adams, 1987).13 Theism explains both: God, given that he has good reason to create embodied persons, also has
good reason to ensure the relevant connections between persons and their bodies.14 Moreland (2008, 2009) focuses
on the existence of nonphysical mental states rather than their connection to physical states. Naturalistic theories
cannot get genuine, nonphysical mental states from their base ingredients of matter. Nontheistic alternatives, such
as panpsychism, fare no better on account of not being able to explain how base material ingredients could be
infused with consciousness, or why. Together, then, theism is thought to better explain the existence of mental states
as well as their connection to brain states.
According to Hasker (1999, 2013), Reppert (2009), and Goetz (2013), reason points to the existence of a primor-
dial rational intellect.15 Consider first how reasoning seems incompatible with naturalism. Reasoning requires inten-
tionality of thought, which is notoriously difficult to give physicalist accounts of. But more importantly, reasoning
requires mental causation—e.g., the propositional content of a thought causing another in a chain of logical infer-
ences—which violates the causal closure of nature. Now if reasoning cannot be explained in terms of prior, nonratio-
nal (naturalistic) processes, a theistic explanation in terms of a fundamental rational being naturally suggests itself,
even over other nontheistic views such as panpsychism and idealism, given that it is reason, and not just conscious-
ness as such, that is to be explained.
The argument from reason has noted similarities to Plantingian‐style arguments from proper function (Anderson,
2005; Barrett, 2018; Koons, 2018). On a Plantingian view, we come to know things when, roughly speaking, our cog-
nitive faculties function properly. But the notion of proper function requires a design plan, and hence, a designer, and
only the Judeo‐Christian God (or one very similar, argues McNabb, 2019) seems to fit the bill of a suitable designer of
cognitive faculties whose proper function is to aim at acquiring true beliefs.
A different route from knowledge to God lies in some version of the time‐worn Berkeleyan thesis that esse est
percipi, where it is God's mind that constitutes reality (see Mander, 2013 for a historical sampling of this argu-
ment). The idea that there's no such thing as a “view from nowhere”—an observer‐independent reality—has, of
course, been grist in the mill for anti‐realists like Rorty and Putnam. If reality were truly independent of our
knowledge of it, then we, or even an ideally rational knower, can never discount the possibility that we're radically
mistaken. But that seems less plausible than simply saying “truth” is not independent of our noetic activity. Such
anti‐realist arguments have in turn been grist in the mill for theists like Plantinga (1982), Alston (1996), Rea (2000),
and Dummett (2006), who can agree that truth is indeed not independent of noetic activity, but avoid the man-
ifest absurdities of eschewing the possibility of objective knowledge by grounding truth in the mind of God
instead of finite knowers. Thus, if realism is true, and knowledge and truth are somehow coextensive, then theism
is true.
More direct are arguments similar in spirit to Fitch's well‐known proof that if all truths are knowable then all
truths are in fact known (on which see Bigelow, 2005). Emanuel Rutten (2014), for example, argues that all possible
truths are knowable, and yet the proposition “God does not exist” is not knowable; hence, God exists.
5 | LINGUISTIC ARGUMENTS
A more recent category of theistic arguments appeals to certain facts of language and semantics.
Haldane and Smart (2003) argues for God from a Wittgensteinian linguistic‐communitarian view of concept for-
mation as a via media between nativist and abstractionist views. Contra the nativist, we are not born with concepts
like “cat”; we learn them. But contra the abstractionist, we learn them not from abstracting “cat” from our ostensive
experiences with cats, but from others in our linguistic community. But then where did they get the concept? The
regress is satisfactorily halted, thinks Haldane, if there is a being with intrinsic conceptual power. Perhaps Haldane's
argument can be strengthened if supplemented with Johnson and Potter's (2005), according to which God's having
endowed humans with an innate ability to acquire and use language better explains the empirical data on the origin
of language than naturalism.
MCINTOSH 7 of 14
In order to avoid epistemological skepticism, Bonevac (2018) argues that semantic content must be a certain way
—i.e., independent of finite minds, modally and temporally stable, infinitary, normative, and objective—to serve as an
anchor for successful reference, and hence, knowledge. But content can be that way only if it has a transcendent
ground. God is not only the perfect candidate for being the transcendent ground of content thus conceived but could
also ensure our epistemic access to it.
Pruss (2018) argues that theism provides a satisfying solution to problems of semantic indeterminism, such as
cases where the meaning of certain counterfactuals, knowledge attributions, and vague terms is context sensitive.
A good theory will allow us to maintain that (a) there are objectively correct answers to all such cases, even if we can't
know them; (b) the semantic facts are objective yet mind dependent and not brute; and (c) the meaning of many of
our terms are determined by use and behavior. Unlike nontheistic solutions, the view that our communicative prac-
tices ultimately derive from a supernatural language institutor in whom is hidden the fully precise semantic facts
delivers all the goods. The availability of a theistic solution with such explanatory power is evidence for theism.
6 | ANTHROPOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS
Anthropological arguments are based on existential (in the French sense) and social aspects characteristic of human
beings.
Beginning with the existential, many have expressed a kind of deep, soul‐stabbing desire for something beyond
this world, such as God. C. S. Lewis famously thought this was a good indication that there is something like God,
for, in our experience, natural desires (generally, if not always) imply the existence of what can satisfy them.16 Tallon
(2018) extends the idea to include the desire for unending play and enjoyment. The argument may strike analytic phi-
losophers as facile, but it has been deftly defended against the most obvious objections (see Holyer, 1988; Lee,
2017). For instance, desire for impossible things like, say, morphing into a dragon, are hardly natural desires—i.e.,
common and nonpathological. Besides, if stated inductively, even a handful of legitimate counterexamples, if there
be any, would not significantly deflate the argument so long as the majority of our natural desires do in fact have real
satisfiers. In a modal twist to the argument, Pruss (2010a) appeals to “visceral” desires (def: A visceral desire D is for x
if and only if x is possible to get, and, necessarily, when an agent y who has D gets x, y's desire D is satisfied by x), such
as hunger and thirst, which do not imply their intentional objects do exist, only that they can. But then a visceral
desire for God implies God can exist. Per S5, if God can exist, God does exist. Continuing with the modal theme,
Buras and Cantrell (2018) argue that our desire for a certain kind of happiness only God could satisfy is evidence that
God can (and so does) exist, and Pruss (2010b) argues the fact that so many of us take God to be the motivational
center of our lives is evidence that God can (and so does) exist.
To our deepest desires and motivations, Walls (2018) adds that our richest and most profound displays of love
point to something beyond what can be explained as evolutionary byproducts of kin selection or reciprocal altruism.
Were we created in the image of a God whose nature is love, however, it would be no surprise that our lives seem to
have “a depth of meaning that vastly exceeds the severe limits imposed by naturalism” (Walls, 2018, p. 318).
Theists and naturalists alike have contended that life can have objective meaning only if a being like God exists to
give it meaning (one of the better arguments is Morris, 1993). Arguments for objective meaning, then, would be argu-
ments for theism. In this respect, Dougherty (2016) argues the fact that belief that life has objective meaning comes
so naturally to us is evidence of its truth. Given that naturalism gives us no reason to expect to have true beliefs
about the meaning of life, but theism does (God would want for people to have true beliefs about that), belief that
life has objective meaning confirms theism over naturalism.17
Moving on to more social aspects, Neill and McNabb (2019) have recently argued that theism provides the best
account of the justification for political authority. They agree with Heumer (2013) that the most prominent secular
justifications are inadequate: Contractarian theories are unjustly coercive, and consequentialist theories can only jus-
tify states far too minimal than is necessary. But rather than see all political authority as illegitimate as Heumer does,
8 of 14 MCINTOSH
they (drawing on Wolterstorff, 2012) propose a theistic account: God delegates to mundane rulers the authority has
over us in virtue of being our morally perfect creator, and that authority remains legitimate insofar as it reflects God's
moral nature and the ideal of Shalom. God, therefore, is the best explanation of how exactly that amount of political
authority requisite for the common good is justified.18
It is a sociological fact that most people believe in God.19 Is this (defeasible) evidence for the truth of theism?
Basic insights in epistemology, such as the evidential value of testimony, make it hard to resist an affirmative answer
here, despite argumentum ad populum concerns (on which see Meierding, 1998; Réhault, 2015). Thomas Kelly (2011)
agrees, pointing out that it is demonstrably the case that we commonly treat the beliefs of others as evidence of their
truth, and properly so. Zagzebski's (2011) view explains why: The reasons we have for trusting ourselves to form true
beliefs are reasons for likewise trusting others to. Further, one's credence in a belief increases the more widespread it
is. The evident naturalness of belief in God, which some argue is itself evidence of theism (e.g., Barrett & Church,
2013), strongly suggests we shouldn't expect major sociological shifts in this regard. Widespread belief in God, there-
fore, is a prima facie reason to believe God exists. The ultimate value of the argument, as its expositors point out,
depends on whether there are better explanations of widespread belief in God other than that it's being probably
true. Interestingly, Dobrzeniecki (2018) thinks the argument need not depend on the prevalence of belief at all. A
more modest version can be run by restricting it to just the consensus of those whom we regard as epistemic author-
ities on the question.
7 | META‐ARGUMENTS
That there are so many arguments for theism is a remarkable phenomenon, especially considering that most substan-
tive philosophical theses hang on epicycles of just one or two main arguments. Theism can therefore benefit from
cumulative case arguments in ways most other views cannot. If we take each individual argument for theism—or
rather, the explanandum of each argument—as independent pieces of evidence, even if each only modestly confirms
theism, their cumulative force could result in significant confirmation of theism (i.e., raise the intrinsic probability of
theism to well above .5). But even if that's not the case, their cumulative force could still significantly confirm theism
over naturalism. These are the kinds of broad meta‐arguments for theism we're most familiar with (e.g., Swinburne,
2006). According to Poston (2018), we can be more precise by estimating likelihood ratios for each independent
argument, then sum them up—the sum being their approximate cumulative evidential force. Doing so shows that
even a handful of modestly good arguments can cumulatively amount to very strong evidence, indeed.20
Briefly, here are two further ways one might advance a meta‐argument for theism. First, if a theory were true, we
should expect there to be multiple, independent lines of evidence supporting it. Since we do have multiple, indepen-
dent lines of evidence supporting theism, that is itself evidence for theism. Second, arguments that God exists are
ipso facto arguments that God possibly exists. Having so many theistic arguments, then, should significantly raise
one's credence in the main premise of the ontological argument (Arbour, 2019). And per S5, if we're justified in
believing God can exist, we're justified in God does exist.
CO NCLUSIO N
I would like to conclude with two general observations about contemporary theistic arguments. First, it is striking
how many of them have as a premise some form of realism—about abstracta, unities, laws, morality, beauty, and
so on. Second, it is also striking how many exploit the convenient fiction that theism and naturalism are the only live
options. Taking these observations together, we should expect theistic arguments—to the extent that they have any
force—to push nontheists in one of two directions.
In one direction is the wholesale denial of all realisms thought to support theism, affirming instead the hardcore
reductionism and eliminitivism theists argue naturalism entails (Baker, 2013; Craig & Moreland, 2000; Rea, 2002;
MCINTOSH 9 of 14
Smith, 2012). Few, however, seem to have taken this route (exceptions are Ladymann & Ross, 2007; Rosenberg,
2011), though I suspect this is because naturalists tend have their heads in the sand. At any rate, theists should work
on developing more arguments that do not depend on realisms.
Academic winds seem to be blowing more in the other direction: Rejecting the convenient fiction that theism and
naturalism are the only live options. Philosophers who are not ostrich naturalists are exploring alternatives to theism
such as panpsychism (e.g., Nagel, 2012; Alter & Nagasawa, 2015; Buckareff & Nagasawa, 2016; Goff, 2017; Bruntrup
& Jaskolla, 2017). In response, besides directly critiquing such views, theists should work on strengthening the tie
between the explanandum and theism as the explanans in their arguments. Doing so would also address the specter
of God‐of‐the‐gaps reasoning that haunts many of the arguments discussed in this article.21
ENDNOTES
1
By “theistic argument” I mean an argument for existence of, or for the rationality of belief in, God. By “God,” I mean a
supernatural personal being with one or more attributes traditionally associated with divinity, such as maximal knowledge,
power, goodness, necessity, transcendent creator, designer, etc.
2
Obviously, the arguments to be discussed should also be distinguished from those that no rational person would take seri-
ously. For instance, suppose I offer the following novel, nontraditional argument for God's existence: the Dixie argument.
(1) Either my cat is named Lucifer or God exists. (2) My cat is not named Lucifer. (3) Therefore, God exists. The argument is
valid, and I believe sound (my cat is named Dixie, and I accept (3)). Plantinga says of a similarly structured argument that it
“is in some way question begging, or at least dialectically deficient.” See The Nature of Necessity (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1974), 217‐218. I'm not sure it begs the question, but I am sure no rational person would take it seriously. The ques-
tion of what distinguishes any argument, even a sound one, from a good argument is difficult, and of course not unique to
theistic arguments. Suffice it to say that the arguments of concern here have the distinction of being taken seriously by
rational people, unlike the Dixie argument.
3
Nor will I discuss arguments of so‐called ramified natural theology: arguments intended to point to a specifically Christian
conception of God. Further, it should also go without saying that there is not the space here to cover rejoinders, surrejoin-
ders, etc.
4
Menzel does with set theory what Richard Otte does with epistemic probability. See Otte's “A Theistic Conception of
Probability,” in Michael Beaty (ed.), Christian Theism and the Problems of Philosophy (Notre Dame, 1990), pp. 92‐117. Unfor-
tunately I remembered Otte's article as this one was in its final stages, so could not incorporate its insights.
5
Interestingly, according to a former student of his, Smith said he is “51% theist” due to considerations about abstract
objects.
6
The characteristic modal axiom of S5, ◇p ⊃ □◇p, is logically equivalent to our ubiquitous theistic modal inference ◇□p ⊃
□p. In fact, ◇□p ⊃ p is provable from the much weaker modal system B, so technically theists don't need S5 to license the
ubiquitous inference. That said, S5 is the favored system among modal logicians and metaphysicians as regards to the
question of what best captures our intuitions about metaphysics of modality. For defenses of S5 as the correct system
of absolute or metaphysical modality, see Alexander Pruss, Actuality, Possibility, and Worlds (Continuum, 2011), pp. 13‐
17; Bob Hale, Necessary Beings: An essay on Ontology, Modality, & the Relations Between Them (Oxford, 2013), pp. 127ff;
Timothy Williamson, “Modal Science,” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 46(4‐5), pp. 453‐492; and Alexander Pruss and
Joshua Rasmussen, Necessary Existence (Oxford, 2018), ch. 2.
7
Not to be confused with design arguments, which focus on what is empirically the case posterior to natural laws, such as
an intelligence‐friendly universe, irreducibly complex biological organisms, or whatever.
8
While writing this article, I overlooked Bradley Monton's fine contribution to Walls & Dougherty (2018), in which he gives
a new argument for theism based on thermodynamics and the nature of induction.
9
See quotations in Tallon, 2018. Paul Draper, for example: “I agree that beauty supports theism but maintain the overall
pattern of good and evil in the world is more probable on naturalism than on theism… So the ability of theism to explain
beauty and our enjoyment of it is a relatively small advantage for theism. Arguments from evil against theism are much
more powerful than the argument from beauty in favor of theism.”
10
Several authors lean heavily on Eddy Zamach, Real Beauty (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania University Press, 1997). I can-
not resist quoting this wonderful passage from Forrest (1996, 133‐134): “‘How ugly the stars are tonight! How trivial the
pounding of the waves on the beach! And is it not crass to be thrilled by mountains? The rain forest and the wild‐flowers
are quite repulsive. And as for sunsets...’. If a full‐blown relativism in aesthetics was correct, then those responses would be
unusual but not in any way improper. But my reaction is that anyone who fails to appreciate the beauty of this universe is
defective.”
10 of 14 MCINTOSH
11
Also relevant here are Nozick's (1981, 594‐610) arguments for a being of unlimited value and meaning. But his arguments
have not yet been formally massaged into arguments for theism explicitly.
I borrow the term “noological” from William Lane Craig, Philosophy of Religion: A Reader and Guide (New Jersey: Rutgers
12
University Press, 2002), which he uses to refer to the argument from consciousness. But the term seems more fitting
for this broader category of arguments, as it captures the variety well (e.g., better than “epistemological”), especially con-
sidering the full etymology of noûs and logos. Because arguments for theism from free will seem to ultimately appeal to
consciousness or the soul, I would include them in this category as well.
13
Adams (1987), and Swinburne (2018) following him refers to this aspect of the argument from consciousness as the argu-
ment from flavors and colors, which is really just the explanatory gap problem (on which see Jospeh Levine, Purple Haze:
The Puzzle of Consciousness (Oxford, 2001)) with a theistic solution. There is a different nontraditional theistic argument
properly from flavors and colors that is at once moral, noological, and aesthetic, the gist of which can be gathered from
this passage from William Paley, Natural Theology (Cambridge, 1803; ed. 2009), pp. 518‐519: “Assuming the necessity
of food for the support of animal life; it is requisite, that the animal be provided with organs, fitted for the procuring,
receiving, and digesting of its food. It may be also necessary, that the animal be impelled by its sensations to exert its
organs. But the pain of hunger would do all this. Why add pleasure to the act of eating; sweetness and relish to food?
Why a new and appropriate sense for the perception of the pleasure? Why should the juice of a peach, applied to the pal-
ate, affect the part so differently from what it does when rubbed upon the palm of the hand? This is a constitution which,
so far as appears to me, can be resolved into nothing but the pure benevolence of the Creator. Eating is necessary; but the
pleasure attending it is not necessary: and that this pleasure depends, not only upon our being in possession of the sense
of taste, which is different from every other, but upon a particular state of the organ in which it resides, a felicitous adap-
tation of the organ to the object, will be confessed by any one, who may happen to have experienced that vitiation of taste
which frequently occurs in fevers, when every taste is irregular, and every one bad.” Unfortunately I know of no contem-
porary defenses of this argument.
14
With Swinburne and Adams, Kimble, and O'Connor attack materialistic accounts of the correlation between physical and
mental states, but, contra Swinburne and Adams, see the unlikely emergence of consciousness as buttressing the fine‐
tuning argument rather than its own argument for theism. See their “The Argument from Consciousness Revisited,” in J.
L. Kvanvig (ed.), Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Religion, Vol. 3 (Oxford, 2011), 110‐141.
15
Reppert dithers on the argument's formulation as an argument just against naturalism or also one for theism. He also
doesn't distinguish, as I and others do, the argument from reason from other arguments (from consciousness, proper func-
tion, abstract objects, etc.). My exposition follows Goetz most closely.
16
The argument from desire, or at least the central sentiment, predates Lewis by centuries, going back at least to Augustine.
17
Nevermind the egregious gaffe in Dougherty's rendering of Bayes' theorem on p. 83.
18
Remarks made by Jay Richards in his Money, Greed, and God (New York: HarperOne, 2009), 217ff suggest the makings of a
different kind of political argument. From free markets emerge irreducible properties that have mystified economists for
centuries: order and harmony from chaos, general welfare from individual self‐interest, increasing amounts and kinds of
value (i.e., capital) created de novo just from the practice of free trade, etc. What best explains these irreducible emergent
properties of free markets? As economists like Hayek have pointed out, the problem parallels historic bemusement at how
random, chaotic naturalistic processes could produce such highly complex yet orderly functional systems we see in biolog-
ical organisms. Is there an economic equivalent of the explanatory mechanisms of natural selection and chance? Or was
Adam Smith's admiration at how the market seems to be guided by an “invisible hand” more than metaphorical? It is rather
remarkable that since many national economies and, to a large extent, the global economy began operating according to
free market principles, global abject poverty rates have fallen a staggering 80%. See Pinkovsky and Sala‐i‐Martin, “Para-
metric Estimations of the World Distribution of Income,” The National Bureau of Economic Research no. 15433 (2009).
See also Max Roser and Esteban Ortiz‐Ospina, “Global Extreme Poverty,” Our World in Data, March 27, 2017, https://
ourworldindata.org/extreme‐poverty/.
Thomas Kelly cites, probably with some amusement, Phil Zuckerman, “Atheism: Contemporary Rates and Patterns” in Martin
19
(Ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Atheism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006): “Zuckerman (a sociologist of
religion and an atheist, one of whose avowed purposes is to show that non‐belief is more common than is typically claims)
estimates that approximately 88% of the world's population believes in God.” See Kelly (2011), 146n18.
Poston uses Royall's case to illustrate the standard of “pretty strong” evidence: you have two urns, one containing only
20
white balls and the other half black, half white. Pick a ball, note its color, put it back, shake and stir. Successively drawing
three white balls is equivalent to a likelihood ratio (LR) of 8, or pretty strong evidence that you're drawing from the urn
with only white balls. By comparison, medical professionals routinely make diagnoses based on LRs within that range,
10 being uncommonly strong. If we had two dozen (or so) theistic arguments, as Plantinga suggested, each would need
only a meager LR of 1.1 (that is, barely any evidential value at all) to amount to pretty strong evidence for theism. But there
MCINTOSH 11 of 14
are actually much more than two dozen arguments for theism. Throughout the course of my article, some 50 (or so) non‐
traditional arguments for theism are cited. Suppose only half are independent. Now, assuming there are also at least 25
traditional theistic arguments, the cumulative effect of having 50 arguments each with the stingy LR of 1.1 puts their total
LR at a staggering 117. And the reality is that many, perhaps even most, of the arguments deserve a much higher LR than
1.1; yet even a slight increase to 1.25, evenly distributed across the lot, has dramatic results: 25 arguments = LR of 265,
and 50 = just over 70,000. It's hard to imagine what that evidential force practically amounts to if not certainty.
21
Thanks to Benjamin Arbour and Elizabeth McIntosh for many helpful discussions. Special thanks to William Vallicella for
kindly mailing me an off print of his article “From Facts to God,” and to the authors who confirmed with me that I have
summarized their arguments correctly. Finally, thanks to Yujin Nagasawa's commissioning and editorial guidance of this
article.
ORCID
Chad A. McIntosh https://orcid.org/0000-0002-3660-7061
RE FE R ENC E S
Adams, R. (1983). Divine necessity. Journal of Philosophy, 80(11), 741–752.
Adams, R. (1987). Colors, flavors, and God. In The virtue of faith and other essays in philosophical theology (pp. 243–262). New
York: Oxford University Press.
Adams, R. (1994). Leibniz: Determinist, theist, idealist. New York: Oxford University Press.
Alston, W. (1996). A realist conception of truth. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Alter, A., & Nagasawa, Y. (2015). Consciousness in the physical world: Perspectives on Russellian monism. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Anderson, J. (2005). If knowledge then God. Calvin Theological Journal, 40(1), 49–75.
Anderson, J., & Welty, G. (2011). The lord of non‐contradiction: An argument for God from logic. Philosophia Christi, 13(2),
321–338.
Arbour, B. (2019). Cumulative case arguments and Bayesian approaches to ontological arguments. Unpublished MS.
Baker, L. R. (2013). Naturalism and the first‐person perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.
Barrett, J. (2018). The argument from positive epistemic status. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two Dozen (or so) Arguments for
God (pp. 159–169). New York: Oxford University Press.
Barrett, J., & Church, I. (2013). Should SCR give atheists epistemic assurance? The Monist, 96(3), 311–324.
Bigelow, J. (2005). Omnificence. Analysis, 65(3), 187–196.
Bonevac, D. (2018). Arguments from knowledge, reference, and content. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) argu-
ments for God (pp. 214–237). New York: Oxford University Press.
Braine, D. (1988). The reality of time and the existence of God. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bruntrup, G., & Jaskolla, L. (2017). Panpsychism: Contemporary perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.
Buckareff, A., & Nagasawa, Y. (2016). Alternative concepts of God: Essays on the metaphysics of the divine. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Buras, T., & Cantrell, M. (2018). C. S. Lewis's argument from nostalgia: A new argument from desire. In Walls & Dougherty
(Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God (pp. 356–371). New York: Oxford University Press.
Cartwight, N. (2005). No God, no laws. Unpublished MS.
Craig, W. L. (2016). God over all: Divine aseity and the challenge of Platonism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Craig, W. L., & Moreland, J. P. (Eds.) (2000). Naturalism: A critical analysis. New York: Routledge.
Davis, R. B. (2008). God and modal concretism. Philosophia Christi, 10(1), 57–74.
Davis, R. B. (2011). God and the platonic horde: A defense of limited conceptualism. Philosophia Christi, 13(2), 289–303.
Dobrzeniecki, M. (2018). Is the fact that other people believe in God a reason to believe? Remarks on the Consensus Gentium
Argument. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 10(3), 133–153.
Dougherty, T. (2016). Belief that life has meaning confirms that life has meaning: A Bayesian approach. In J. Seachris, & S.
Goetz (Eds.), God and Meaning: New Essays (pp. 81–98). New York: Bloomsbury Academic.
Dummett, M. (2006). Thought and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dumsday, T. (2011). Have the laws of nature been eliminated? In G. Butera (Ed.), Reading the cosmos: Nature, science and
wisdom (pp. 11–128). Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press.
12 of 14 MCINTOSH
Ewing, A. C. (1965). Two ‘proofs’ of God's existence. Religious Studies, 1(1), 29–45.
Feser, E. (2017). Five proofs of the existence of God. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.
Forrest, P. (1996). God without the supernatural: A defense of scientific theism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Foster, J. (2001). Regularities, laws of nature, and the existence of God. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 101(1),
145–161.
Foster, J. (2004). The divine lawmaker: Lectures on induction, laws of nature, and the existence of God. Oxford: Oxford Univer-
sity Press.
Geivett, R. G., & Spiegel, J. S. (2019). Beauty: A troubling reality for the scientific naturalist. In Copan & Taliaferro (Ed.), The
naturalness of belief: New essays on theism's rationality (pp. 141–157). New York: Lexington Books.
Goetz, S. (2013). The argument from reason. Philosophia Christi, 15(1), 47–62.
Goff, P. (2017). Consciousness and fundamental reality. New York: Oxford University Press.
Gordon, B. (2018). The argument from the incompleteness of nature. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments
for God (pp. 417–445). New York: Oxford University Press.
Haldane, J. J., & Smart, J. J. C. (2003). Atheism and theism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Hasker, W. (1999). The emergent self. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Hasker, W. (2013). What is naturalism? And should we be naturalists? Philosophia Christi, 15(1), 21–34.
Holyer, R. (1988). The argument from desire. Faith and Philosophy, 5(1), 61–71.
Howell, R. (2006). Does mathematical beauty pose problems for naturalism? Christian Scholar's Review, 35(4), 493–504.
Huemer, M. (2013). The problem of political authority: An examination of the right to coerce and the duty to obey. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Johnson, J., & Potter, J. (2005). The argument from language and the existence of God. Journal of Religion, 85(1), 83–93.
Juarez, P. (2017). From the unity of the world to God: A teleo‐cosmological argument for God's existence. Scientia et Fides,
5(2), 283–303.
Keller, L. (2017). Against naturalized cognitive propositions. Erkenntnis, 82(4), 929–946.
Keller, L. (2018). The argument from intentionality (or Aboutness): Propositions supernaturalized. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.),
Two Dozen (or so) Arguments for God (pp. 11–28). New York: Oxford University Press.
Kelly, T. (2011). Consensus Gentium: Reflections on the ‘common consent’ argument for the existence of God. In Clark &
VanArragon (Ed.), Evidence and Religious Belief (pp. 135–156). New York: Oxford University Press.
Koons, R. (2018). The general argument from intuition. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God (pp.
338–257). New York: Oxford University Press.
Koperski, J. (2017). Breaking the laws of nature. Philosophia Christi, 19(1), 83–101.
Kordig, C. (1989). A deontic argument for God's existence. Nous, 15(2), 207–208.
Kronen, J., & Menssen, S. (2013). The argument from wholes: A classical Hindu design argument for the existence of God.
Faith and Philosophy, 30(2), 138–158.
Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lee, R. S. (2017). As if swallowing life itself: C. S. Lewis's argument from desire II. In Baggett, et al. (Eds.), C. S. Lewis as phi-
losopher: Truth, goodness, and beauty (pp. 327–346). Lynchburg, VA: Liberty University Press.
Leftow, B. (2010). God and necessity. New York. Oxford University Press.
Leftow, B. (2018). The argument from Possibility. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God (pp.
406–416). New York: Oxford University Press.
Leslie, J. (1970). The theory that the world exists because it should. American Philosophical Quarterly, 7(4), 286–298.
Leslie, J. (1979). Value and existence. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.
Leslie, J. (2001). Infinite minds: A philosophical cosmology. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lowe, E. J. (2013). Naturalism, theism, and objects of reason. Philosophia Christi, 15(1), 35–45.
Mander, W. J. (2013). On arguing for the existence of God as a synthesis between realism and anti‐realism. International Jour-
nal for Philosophy of Religion, 74(1), 99–115.
Mander, W. J. (2016). Idealist ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.
McNabb, T. D. (2019). Religious epistemology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Meierding, L. (1998). The Consensus Gentium argument. Faith and Philosophy, 15(3), 271–297.
Menzel, C. (2018). The argument from collections. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God (pp.
29–58). New York: Oxford University Press.
MCINTOSH 13 of 14
Moreland, J. P. (2008). Consciousness and the existence of God: A theistic argument. New York: Routledge.
Moreland, J. P. (2009). The argument from consciousness. In Craig & Moreland (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to natural the-
ology (pp. 282–343). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Morris, T. V. (1993). Making sense of it all: Pascal and the meaning of life. Grand Rapids, MI: Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.
Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos. New York: Oxford University Press.
Neill, J., & McNabb, T. D. (2019). By whose authority? A political argument for God's existence. European Journal for Philos-
ophy of Religion. Forthcoming
Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Orr, J. (2019). No God, no powers. International Philosophical Quarterly, 59(4).
Peterson, J. (1996). Law and thomistic exemplarism. The Thomist, 60(1), 81–108.
Plantinga, A. (1982). How to be an anti‐realist. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Association, 56(1), 47–70.
Poston, T. (2018). The argument from so many arguments. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for God
(pp. 372–386). New York: Oxford University Press.
Pruss, A. (2010a). The ontological argument from desire. Alexander Pruss's Blog, http://alexanderpruss.blogspot.com/2010/
04/ontological‐argument‐from‐desire.html.
Pruss, A. (2010b). The ontological argument and the motivational centers of lives. Religious Studies, 46(2), 233–249.
Pruss, A. (2018). The argument from counterfactuals: Counterfactuals, vagueness, and God. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two
dozen (or so) Arguments for God (pp. 76–88). New York: Oxford University Press.
Rasmussen, J. (2019). How reason can lead to GodInterVarsity Press Academic.
Ratzsch, D. (1987). Nomo (theo)logical necessity. Faith and Philosophy, 4(3), 83–402.
Rea, M. (2000). Theism and epistemic truth‐equivalences. Nous, 34(2), 291–301.
Rea, M. (2002). A world without design: The ontological consequences of naturalism. New York: Oxford University Press.
Réhault, S. (2015). Can atheism be epistemically responsible when so many people believe in God? European Journal for Phi-
losophy of Religion, 7(1), 181–198.
Reppert, V. (2009). The argument from reason. In Craig & Moreland (2009).
Rescher, N. (1984). The riddle of existence: An essay in idealistic metaphysics. Washington: University Press of America.
Rescher, N. (2010). Axiogenesis: An essay in metaphysical optimalism. Plymouth, UK: Lexington Books.
Rice, H. (2000). God and goodness. New York: Oxford University Press.
Rosenberg, A. (2011). The atheist's guide to reality: Enjoying life without illusions. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.
Rutten, E. (2014). A modal‐epistemic argument for the existence of God. Faith and Philosophy, 31(4), 386–400.
Smith, Q. (1994). A conceptualist argument for God's existence. Faith and Philosophy, 11(1), 38–49.
Smith, R. S. (2012). Naturalism and our knowledge of reality. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Publishing Co.
Steiner, M. (1998). The applicability of mathematics as a philosophical problem. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Steinhart, E. (2012). Axiarchic polytheism. Unpublished MS.
Swinburne, R. (2004). The existence of god. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Swinburne, R. (2006). Relations between universals, or divine laws? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 84(2), 179–189.
Swinburne, R. (2018). The argument from colors and flavors: The argument from consciousness. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.),
Two dozen (or so) arguments for God (pp. 293–303). New York: Oxford University Press.
Tallon, P. (2018). The Mozart argument and the argument from play and enjoyment: The theistic argument from beauty and
play. In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two dozen (or so) arguments for god (pp. 321–340). New York: Oxford University Press.
Tennant, F. R. (1924). Theism and laws of nature. The Harvard Theological Review, 17(4), 375–391.
Tennant, F. R. (1930). Philosophical theology (Vol. 2)Cambridge University Press.
Vallicella, W. F. (2000). From facts to God: An onto‐cosmological argument. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion,
48(3), 157–181.
Vallicella, W. F. (2018). Does god exist because he ought to exist? In M. Szatkowski (Ed.), Ontology of theistic beliefs (pp.
205–212). Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter.
Walls, J. (2018). The argument form love and the argument from the meaning of life: The God of love and the meaning of life.
In Walls & Dougherty (Ed.), Two Dozen (or so) Arguments for God (pp. 304–320). New York: Oxford University Press.
Walls, J., & Dougherty, T. (Eds.) (2018). Two dozen (or so) arguments for God. New York: Oxford University Press.
West, R., & Pelser, A. C. (2015). Perceiving God through natural beauty. Faith and Philosophy, 32(3), 293–312.
14 of 14 MCINTOSH
Wigner, E. (1960). The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. Communications on Pure and
Applied Mathematics, 13(1), 1–14.
Wolterstorff, N. (2012). The mighty and the almighty: An essay in political theology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wynn, M. (1999). God and goodness: A natural theological perspective. New York: Routlegde.
Zagzebski, L. (2011). Epistemic self‐trust and the Consensus Gentium argument. In Clark & VanArragon (Ed.), Evidence and reli-
gious belief (pp. 22–36). New York: Oxford University Press.
AU THOR BIOGRAPHY
C. A. McIntosh earned his BA in philosophy from Calvin College and MA in philosophy from Cornell University,
where he is also finishing a PhD in metaphysics. He has forthcoming papers in the areas of political philosophy,
the meaning of life, and the ethics of lying. McIntosh currently works from his home in rural Ohio, where he
enjoys country living and being a stay‐at‐home dad.
How to cite this article: McIntosh CA. Nontraditional arguments for theism. Philosophy Compass. 2019;14:
e12590. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12590