Leo Strauss - Liberalism Ancient and Modern
Leo Strauss - Liberalism Ancient and Modern
Leo Strauss - Liberalism Ancient and Modern
3 122T¥Wf78451 /I
0
Modern
LEO STRAUSS
Foreword by Allan Bloom
LIBERALISM
ANCIENT and
MODERN
Leo Strauss
Foreword by Allan Bloom
Allan Bloom
Chicago, Illinois
November, 1988
Preface
vii
viii / Preface
foreign war; for revolutions backed by the sympathy, or at least the inter¬
ests, of the majority of the people concerned are not necessarily rejected
by liberals. There remains, however, one important difference between
liberalism and Communism regarding the goal itself. Liberals regard as
sacred the right of everyone, however humble, odd, or inarticulate, to
criticize the government, including the man at the top.
Someone might say that many liberals are much too pragmatic to aim
at the universal and homogeneous state: they would be fully satisfied with
a federation of all now existing or soon emerging states, with a truly
universal and greatly strengthened United Nations organization—an orga¬
nization that would include Communist China, the Federal Republic of
Germany, and Communist East Germany, although not necessarily Na¬
tionalist China. Still, this would mean that liberals aim at the greatest
possible approximation to the universal and homogeneous state or that
they are guided by the ideal of the universal and homogeneous state.
Some of them will object to the term “ideal” on the ground that the uni¬
versal and homogeneous state (or the greatest possible approximation to
it) is a requirement of hardheaded politics: that state has been rendered
necessary by economic and technological progress, which includes the ne¬
cessity of making thermonuclear war impossible for all the future, and by
ever increasing wealth of the advanced countries which are compelled by
sheer self-interest to develop the underdeveloped countries. As regards the
still existing tension between the liberal-democratic and the Communist
countries, liberals believe that this tension will be relaxed and will eventu¬
ally disappear as a consequence of the ever increasing welfarism of the
former and the ever increasing liberalism, due to the overwhelming de¬
mand for consumer goods of all kinds, of the latter.
Conservatives regard the universal and homogeneous state as either
undesirable, though possible, or as both undesirable and impossible. They
do not deny the necessity or desirability of larger political units than what
one may call the typical nation-state. For good or ill, they can indeed no
longer be imperialists. But there is no reason whatever why they should
be opposed to a United Free Europe, for instance. Yet they are likely to
understand such units differently from the liberals. An outstanding Euro¬
pean conservative has spoken of VEurope des patries. Conservatives look
with greater sympathy than liberals on the particular or particularist and
the heterogeneous; at least they are more willing than liberals to respect
and perpetuate a more fundamental diversity than the one ordinarily re¬
spected or taken for granted by liberals and even by Communists, that is,
the diversity regarding language, folk songs, pottery, and the like. Inasmuch
as the universalism in politics is founded on the universalism proceeding
from reason, conservativism is frequently characterized by distrust of reason
or by trust in tradition which as such is necessarily this or that tradition
and hence particular. Conservativism is therefore exposed to criticism that
Preface / i\
is guided by the notion of the unity of truth. Liberals, on the other hand,
especially those who know that their aspirations have their roots in the
Western tradition, are not sufficiently concerned with the fact that that
tradition is ever more being eroded by the very changes in the direction of
One World which they demand or applaud.
We remain closer to the surface by saying that the conservatives’ dis¬
trust of the universal and homogeneous state is rooted in their distrust of
change, in what is polemically called their “stand-patism,” whereas liberals
are more inclined than conservatives to be sanguine regarding change.
Liberals are inclined to believe that on the whole change is change for the
better, or progress. As a matter of fact, liberals frequently call themselves
progressives. Progressivism is indeed a better term than liberalism for the
opposite to conservativism. For if conservativism is, as its name indicates,
aversion to change or distrust of change, its opposite should be identified
with the opposite posture toward change, and not with something substan¬
tive like liberty or liberality.
The difficulty of defining the difference between liberalism and con¬
servativism with the necessary universality is particularly great in the
United States, since this country came into being through a revolution, a
violent change or break with the past. One of the most conservative groups
here calls itself Daughters of the American Revolution. The opposition
between conservativism and liberalism had a clear meaning at the time at
which and in the places in which it arose in these terms. Then and there
the conservatives stood for “throne and altar,” and the liberals stood for
popular sovereignty and the strictly nonpublic (private) character of re¬
ligion. Yet conservativism in this sense is no longer politically important.
The conservativism of our age is identical with what originally was liberal¬
ism, more or less modified by changes in the direction of present-day lib¬
eralism. One could go further and say that much of what goes now by the
name of conservativism has in the last analysis a common root with pres¬
ent-day liberalism and even with Communism. That this is the case would
appear most clearly if one were to go back to the origin of modernity, to
the break with the premodern tradition that took place in the seventeenth
century, or to the quarrel between the ancients and the moderns.
We are reminded of that quarrel immediately by the fact that the
term “liberal” is still used in its premodern sense, especially in the expres¬
sion “liberal education.” Liberal education is not the opposite of con¬
servative education, but of illiberal education. To be liberal in the original
sense means to practice the virtue of liberality. If it is true that all vir¬
tues in their perfection are inseparable from one another, the genuinely
liberal man is identical with the genuinely virtuous man. According to
the now prevailing usage, however, to be liberal means not to be con¬
servative. Hence it is no longer assumed that being liberal is the same as
being virtuous or even that being liberal has anything to do with being
x / Preface
posture toward liberalism. Even Jews who are politically conservative can
be observed to defer to contemporary Jewish “opinion leaders” who can
in no sense be described as politically conservative. This state of things
induces one to raise questions such as these: In what sense or to what
extent is Judaism one of the roots of liberalism? Are Jews compelled by
their heritage or their self-interest to be liberals? Is liberalism necessarily
friendly to Jews and Judaism? Can the liberal state claim to have solved
the Jewish problem? Can any state claim to have solved it? To these
questions I address myself in the two statements that conclude this
volume.
Leo Strauss
Claremont, California
Contents
Foreword v
Preface vii
4 / On the Minos 65
5 / Notes on Lucretius 76
8 / An Epilogue 203
Acknowledgments 273
3
4 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
But wisdom is inaccessible to man, and hence virtue and happiness will
always be imperfect. In spite of this, the philosopher, who, as such, is not
simply wise, is declared to be the only true king; he is declared to possess
all the excellences of which man’s mind is capable, to the highest degree.
From this we must draw the conclusion that we cannot be philosophers—
that we cannot acquire the highest form of education. We must not be
deceived by the fact that we meet many people who say that they are
philosophers. For those people employ a loose expression which is perhaps
necessitated by administrative convenience. Often they mean merely that
they are members of philosophy departments. And it is as absurd to expect
members of philosophy departments to be philosophers as it is to expect
members of art departments to be artists. We cannot be philosophers, but
we can love philosophy; we can try to philosophize. This philosophizing
consists at any rate primarily and in a way chiefly in listening to the conver¬
sation between the great philosophers or, more generally and more cau¬
tiously, between the greatest minds, and therefore in studying the great
books. The greatest minds to whom we ought to listen are by no means
exclusively the greatest minds of the West. It is merely an unfortunate
necessity which prevents us from listening to the greatest minds of India
and of China: we do not understand their languages, and we cannot learn
all languages.
To repeat: liberal education consists in listening to the conversation
among the greatest minds. But here we are confronted with the over¬
whelming difficulty that this conversation does not take place without our
help—that in fact we must bring about that conversation. The greatest
minds utter monologues. We must transform their monologues into a dia¬
logue, their side by side” into a “together.” The greatest minds utter
monologues even when they write dialogues. When we look at the Platonic
dialogues, we observe that there is never a dialogue among minds of the
highest order: all Platonic dialogues are dialogues between a superior man
and men inferior to him. Plato apparently felt that one could not write a
dialogue between two men of the highest order. We must then do some¬
thing which the greatest minds were unable to do. Let us face this
difficulty—a difficulty so great that it seems to condemn liberal education
as an absurdity. Since the greatest minds contradict one another regarding
the most important matters, they compel us to judge of their monologues;
we cannot take on trust what any one of them says. On the other hand, we
cannot but notice that we are not competent to be judges.
I his state of things is concealed from us by a number of facile delusions.
We somehow believe that our point of view is superior, higher than those
of the greatest minds—either because our point of view is that of our time,
and our time, being later than the time of the greatest minds, can be pre¬
sumed to be superior to their times; or else because we believe that each of
the greatest minds was right from his point of view but not, as he claims,
8 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
simply right: we know that there cannot be the simply true substantive
view, but only a simply true formal view; that formal view consists in the
insight that every comprehensive view is relative to a specific perspective,
or that all comprehensive views are mutually exclusive and none can be
simply true. The facile delusions which conceal from us our true situation
all amount to this: that we are, or can be, wiser than the wisest men of the
past. We are thus induced to play the part, not of attentive and docile lis¬
teners, but of impresarios or lion-tamers. Yet we must face our awesome
situation, created by the necessity that we try to be more than attentive
and docile listeners, namely, judges, and yet we are not competent to be
judges. As it seems to me, the cause of this situation is that we have lost all
simply authoritative traditions in which we could trust, the nomos which
gave us authoritative guidance, because our immediate teachers and
teachers’ teachers believed in the possibility of a simply rational society.
Each of us here is compelled to find his bearings by his own powers, how¬
ever defective they may be.
We have no comfort other than that inherent in this activity. Philoso¬
phy, we have learned, must be on its guard against the wish to be edifying
—philosophy can only be intrinsically edifying. We cannot exert our
understanding without from time to time understanding something of
importance; and this act of understanding may be accompanied by the
awareness of our understanding, by the understanding of understanding,
by noesis noeseos, and this is so high, so pure, so noble an experience that
Aristotle could ascribe it to his God. This experience is entirely independ¬
ent of whether what we understand primarily is pleasing or displeasing,
fair or ugly. It leads us to realize that all evils are in a sense necessary if
there is to be understanding. It enables us to accept all evils which befall us
and which may well break our hearts in the spirit of good citizens of the
city of God. By becoming aware of the dignity of the mind, we realize
the true ground of the dignity of man and therewith the goodness of the
world, whether we understand it as created or as uncreated, which is the
home of man because it is the home of the human mind.
Liberal education, which consists in the constant intercourse with the
greatest minds, is a training in the highest form of modesty, not to say of
humility. It is at the same time a training in boldness: it demands from us
the complete break with the noise, the rush, the thoughtlessness, the
cheapness of the Vanity Fair of the intellectuals as well as of their enemies.
It demands from us the boldness implied in the resolve to regard the
accepted views as mere opinions, or to regard the average opinions as ex¬
treme opinions which are at least as likely to be wrong as the most strange
or the least popular opinions. Liberal education is liberation from vulgarity.
The Greeks had a beautiful word for “vulgarity”; they called it apeirokalia,
lack of experience in things beautiful. Liberal education supplies us with
experience in things beautiful.
2/ Liberal Education
and Responsibility
When I was approached by The Fund for Adult Education with the sug¬
gestion that I prepare an essay on liberal education and responsibility, my
first reaction was not one of delight. While I am in many ways dependent
on the administration of education and hence on the organizations serving
education, I looked at these things, if I looked at them, with that awe
which arises from both gratitude and apprehension mixed with ignorance.
I thought that it was my job, my responsibility, to do my best in the class¬
room, in conversations with students wholly regardless of whether they are
registered or not, and last but not least in my study at home. I own that
education is in a sense the subject matter of my teaching and my research.
But I am almost solely concerned with the goal or end of education at its
best or highest—of the education of the perfect prince, as it were—and
very little with its conditions and its how. The most important conditions,
it seems to me, are the qualities of the educator and of the human being
who is to be educated; in the case of the highest form of education those
conditions are very rarely fulfilled, and one cannot do anything to produce
them; the only things we can do regarding them are not to interfere with
their interplay and to prevent such interference. As for the how, one knows
it once one knows what education is meant to do to a human being or once
one knows the end of education. Certainly, there are some rules of thumb.
Almost every year I meet once with the older students of my department
in order to discuss with them how to teach political theory in college. Once
on such an occasion a student asked me whether I could not give him a
general rule regarding teaching. I replied: “Always assume that there is one
silent student in your class who is by far superior to you in head and in
heart.” I meant by this: do not have too high an opinion of your impor¬
tance, and have the highest opinion of your duty, your responsibility.
There was another reason why I was somewhat bewildered when I first
9
10 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
began to prepare this essay. That reason has to do with the word “responsi¬
bility.” For clearly, liberal education and responsibility are not identical.
They may not be separable from each other. Before one could discuss their
relation, one would have to know what each of them is. As for the word
“responsibility,” it is now in common use, and I myself have used it from
time to time, for instance a very short while ago. In the sense in which it is
now frequently used, it is a neologism. It is, I believe, the fashionable sub¬
stitute for such words as “duty,” “conscience,” or “virtue.” We frequently
say of a man that he is a responsible man, where people of former genera¬
tions would have said that he is a just man or a conscientious man or a
virtuous man. Primarily, a man is responsible if he can be held accountable
for what he does—for example, for a murder; being responsible is so far
from being the same as being virtuous that it is merely the condition for
being either virtuous or vicious. By substituting responsibility for virtue, we
prove to be much more easily satisfied than our forefathers, or, more pre¬
cisely perhaps, we assume that by being responsible one is already virtuous
or that no vicious man is responsible for his viciousness. There is a kinship
between “responsibility” thus understood and “decency” as sometimes
used by the British: if a man ruins himself in order to save a complete
stranger, the stranger, if British, is supposed to thank him by saying, “It
was rather decent of you.” We seem to loathe the grand old words and
perhaps also the things which they indicate and to prefer more subdued
expressions out of delicacy or because they are more businesslike. However
this may be, my misgivings were caused by my awareness of my ignorance
as to what the substitution of responsibility for duty and for virtue means.
I certainly felt that I was particularly ill-prepared to address professional
educators on the subject “Education and Responsibility.” But then I learnt
to my relief that I was merely expected to explain two sentences occurring
in my speech “What is Liberal Education?” The sentences run as follows:
“Liberal education is the ladder by which we try to ascend from mass
democracy to democracy as originally meant. Liberal education is the nec¬
essary endeavor to found an aristocracy within democratic mass society.”
To begin at the beginning, the word “liberal” had at the beginning, just
as it has now, a political meaning, but its original political meaning is al¬
most the opposite of its present political meaning. Originally a liberal man
was a man who behaved in a manner becoming a free man, as distin¬
guished from a slave. “Liberality” referred then to slavery and presupposed
it. A slave is a human being who lives for another human being, his master;
he has in a sense no life of his own: he has no time for himself. The mas¬
ter, on the other hand, has all his time for himself, that is, for the pursuits
becoming him: politics and philosophy. Yet there are very many free men
who are almost like slaves since they have very little time for themselves,
because they have to work for their livelihood and to rest so that they can
work the next day. Those free men without leisure are the poor, the major-
Liberal Education and Responsibility /II
ity citizens. The truly free man who can live in a manner becoming a
free man is the man of leisure, the gentleman who must possess some
wealth—but wealth of a certain kind: a kind of wealth the administration
of which, to say nothing of its acquisition, does not take up much of his
time, but can be taken care of through his supervising of properly trained
supervisors; the gentleman will be a gentleman farmer and not a merchant
or entrepreneur. Yet if he spends much of his time in the country he will
not be available sufficiently for the pursuits becoming him; he must there¬
fore live in town. His way of life will be at the mercy of those of his fellow
citizens who are not gentlemen, if he and his like do not rule: the way of
life of the gentlemen is not secure if they are not the unquestioned rulers
of their city, if the regime of their city is not aristocratic.
One becomes a gentleman by education, by liberal education. The
Greek word for education is derived from the Greek word for child: educa¬
tion in general, and therefore liberal education in particular, is, then to say
the least, primarily not adult education. The Greek word for education is
akin to the Greek word for play, and the activity of the gentlemen is
emphatically earnest; in fact, the gentlemen are “the earnest ones.” They
are earnest because they are concerned with the most weighty matters,
with the only things which deserve to be taken seriously for their own sake’
with the good order of the soul and of the city. The education of the po¬
tential gentlemen is the playful anticipation of the life of gentlemen. It
consists above all in the formation of character and of taste. The fountains
of that education are the poets. It is hardly necessary to say that the gentle¬
man is in need of skills. To say nothing of reading, writing, counting,
reckoning, wrestling, throwing of spears, and horsemanship, he must pos¬
sess the skill of administering well and nobly the affairs of his household
and the affairs of his city by deed and by speech. He acquires that skill by
his familiar intercourse with older or more experienced gentlemen, pref¬
erably with elder statesmen, by receiving instruction from paid teachers in
the art of speaking, by reading histories and books of travel, by meditating
on the works of the poets, and, of course, by taking part in political life. All
this requires leisure on the part of the youths as well as on the part of their
elders; it is the preserve of a certain kind of wealthy people.
This fact gives rise to the question of the justice of a society which in the
best case would be ruled by gentlemen ruling in their own right. Just gov¬
ernment is government which rules in the interest of the whole society,
and not merely of a part. The gentlemen are therefore under an obligation
to show to themselves and to others that their rule is best for everyone in
the city or for the city as a whole. But justice requires that equal men be
treated equally, and there is no good reason for thinking that the gentle¬
men are by nature superior to the vulgar. The gentlemen are indeed supe¬
rior to the vulgar by their breeding, but the large majority of men are by
nature capable of the same breeding if they are caught young, in their
12 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
cradles; only the accident of birth decides whether a given individual has a
chance of becoming a gentleman or will necessarily become a villain; hence
aristocracy is unjust. The gentlemen replied as follows: the city as a whole
is much too poor to enable everyone to bring up his sons so that they can
become gentlemen; if you insist that the social order should correspond
with tolerable strictness to the natural order—that is, that men who are
more or less equal by nature should also be equal socially or by convention
—you will merely bring about a state of universal drabness. But only on the
ground of a narrow conception of justice, owing its evidence to the power
of the ignoble passion of envy, must one prefer a flat building which is
everywhere equally drab to a structure which from a broad base of drabness
rises to a narrow plateau of distinction and of grace and therefore gives
some grace and some distinction to its very base. There must then be a few
who are wealthy and well born and many who are poor and of obscure
origin. Yet there seems to be no good reason why this family is elected to
gentility and that family is condemned to indistinctness; that selection
seems to be arbitrary, to say the least. It would indeed be foolish to deny
that old wealth sometimes has its forgotten origins in crime. But it is more
noble to believe, and probably also truer, that the old families are the de¬
scendants from the first settlers and from leaders in war or counsel; and it
is certainly just that one be grateful.
Gentlemen may rule without being rulers in their own right; they may
rule on the basis of popular election. This arrangement was regarded as
unsatisfactory for the following reason. It would mean that the gentlemen
are, strictly speaking, responsible to the common people—that the higher
is responsible to the lower—and this would appear to be against nature.
The gentlemen regard virtue as choiceworthy for its own sake, whereas the
others praise virtue as a means for acquiring wealth and honor. The gentle¬
men and the others disagree, then, as regards the end of man or the highest
good; they disagree regarding first principles. Hence they cannot have gen¬
uinely common deliberations.1 The gentlemen cannot possibly give a suffi¬
cient or intelligible account of their way of life to the others. While being
responsible to themselves for the well-being of the vulgar, they cannot be
responsible to the vulgar.
But even if one rests satisfied with a less exacting notion of the rule of
gentlemen, the principle indicated necessarily leads one to reject democ¬
racy. Roughly speaking, democracy is the regime in which the majority of
adult free males living in a city rules, but only a minority of them are edu¬
cated. The principle of democracy is therefore not virtue, but freedom as
the right of every citizen to live as he likes. Democracy is rejected because
it is as such the rule of the uneducated. One illustration must here suffice.
The sophist Protagoras came to the democratic city of Athens in order to
educate human beings, or to teach for pay the art of administering well the
affairs of one’s household and of the city by deed and by speech—the polit-
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 13
vided it possesses a naturally good soul: it may then be lawful for Socrates
to become a good man in spite of his poverty. Since it is not necessary for
the philosopher to be wealthy, he does not need the entirely lawful arts by
which one defends one’s property, for example, forensically; nor does he
have to develop the habit of self-assertion in this or other respects—a habit
which necessarily enters into the gentleman’s virtue. Despite these differ¬
ences, the gentleman’s virtue is a reflection of the philosopher’s virtue; one
may say it is its political reflection.
This is the ultimate justification of the rule of gentlemen. The rule of
the gentlemen is only a reflection of the rule of the philosophers, who are
understood to be the men best by nature and best by education. Given the
fact that philosophy is more evidently quest for wisdom than possession of
wisdom, the education of the philosopher never ceases as long as he lives; it
is the adult education par excellence. For, to say nothing of other things,
the highest kind of knowledge which a man may have acquired can never
be simply at his disposal as other kinds of knowledge can; it is in constant
need of being acquired again from the start. This leads to the following
consequence. In the case of the gentleman, one can make a simple distinc¬
tion between the playful education of the potential gentleman and the
earnest work of the gentleman proper. In the case of the philosopher this
simple distinction between the playful and the serious no longer holds, not
in spite of the fact that his sole concern is with the weightiest matters, but
because of it. For this reason alone, to say nothing of others, the rule of
philosophers proves to be impossible. This leads to the difficulty that the
philosophers will be ruled by the gentlemen, that is, by their inferiors.
One can solve this difficulty by assuming that the philosophers are not
as such a constituent part of the city. In other words, the only teachers
who are as such a constituent part of the city are the priests. The end of
the city is then not the same as the end of philosophy. If the gentlemen
represent the city at its best, one must say that the end of the gentleman is
not the same as the end of the philosopher. What was observed regarding
the gentleman in his relation to the vulgar applies even more to the philos¬
opher in his relation to the gentlemen and a fortiori to all other nonphilos¬
ophers: the philosopher and the nonphilosophers cannot have genuinely
common deliberations. There is a fundamental disproportion between phi¬
losophy and the city. In political things it is a sound rule to let sleeping
dogs lie or to prefer the established to the nonestablished or to recognize
the right of the first occupier. Philosophy stands or falls by its intransigent
disregard of this rule and of anything which reminds of it. Philosophy can
then live only side by side with the city. As Plato put it in the Republic,
only in a city in which the philosophers rule and in which they therefore
owe their training in philosophy to the city is it just that the philosopher
be compelled to engage in political activity; in all other cities—that is, in
all actual cities—the philosopher does not owe his highest gift of human
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 15
origin to the city and therefore is not under an obligation to do the work of
the city. In entire agreement with this, Plato suggests in his Crito, where
he avoids the very term “philosophy,” that the philosopher owes indeed
very much to the city and therefore he is obliged to obey at least passively
even the unjust laws of the city and to die at the behest of the city. Yet he
is not obliged to engage in political activity. The philosopher as philoso¬
pher is responsible to the city only to the extent that by doing his own
work, by his own well-being, he contributes to the well-being of the city:
philosophy has necessarily a humanizing or civilizing effect. The city needs
philosophy, but only mediately or indirectly, not to say in a diluted form.
Plato has presented this state of things by comparing the city to a cave
from which only a rough and steep ascent leads to the light of the sun: the
city as city is more closed to philosophy than open to it.
The classics had no delusions regarding the probability of a genuine
aristocracy’s ever becoming actual. For all practical purposes they were sat¬
isfied with a regime in which the gentlemen share power with the people
in such a way that the people elect the magistrates and the council from
among the gentlemen and demand an account of them at the end of their
term of office. A variation of this thought is the notion of the mixed re¬
gime, in which the gentlemen form the senate and the senate occupies the
key position between the popular assembly and an elected or hereditary
monarch as head of the armed forces of society. There is a direct connec¬
tion between the notion of the mixed regime and modern republicanism.
Lest this be misunderstood, one must immediately stress the important
differences between the modem doctrine and its classic original. The mod¬
ern doctrine starts from the natural equality of all men, and it leads there¬
fore to the assertion that sovereignty belongs to the people; yet it under¬
stands that sovereignty in such a way as to guarantee the natural rights of
each; it achieves this result by distinguishing between the sovereign and
the government and by demanding that the fundamental governmental
powers be separated from one another. The spring of this regime was held
to be the desire of each to improve his material conditions. Accordingly the
commercial and industrial elite, rather than the landed gentry, pre¬
dominated.
The fully developed doctrine required that one man have one vote, that
the voting be secret, and that the right to vote be not abridged on account
of poverty, religion, or race. Governmental actions, on the other hand, are
to be open to public inspection to the highest degree possible, for govern¬
ment is only the representative of the people and responsible to the people.
The responsibility of the people, of the electors, does not permit of legal
definition and is therefore the most obvious crux of modern republicanism.
In the earlier stages the solution was sought in the religious education of
the people, in the education, based on the Bible, of everyone to regard
himself as responsible for his actions and for his thoughts to a God who
16 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
would judge him, for, in the words of Locke, rational ethics proper is as
much beyond the capacities of “day laborers and tradesmen, and spinsters
and dairy maids” as is mathematics. On the other hand, the same authority
advises the gentlemen of England to set their sons upon Puffendorfs Nat¬
ural Right “wherein (they) will be instructed in the natural rights of men,
and the origin and foundation of society, and the duties resulting from
thence.” Locke’s Some Thoughts Concerning Education is addressed to
the gentlemen, rather than to “those of the meaner sort,” for if the gentle¬
men “are by their education once set right, they will quickly bring all the
rest into order.” For, we may suppose, the gentlemen are those called upon
to act as representatives of the people, and they are to be prepared for this
calling by a liberal education which is, above all, an education in “good
breeding.” Locke takes his models from the ancient Romans and Greeks,
and the liberal education which he recommends consists to some extent in
acquiring an easy familiarity with classical literature: “Latin I look upon as
absolutely necessary to a gentleman.” 2
Not a few points which Locke meant are brought out clearly in the
Federalist Papers. These writings reveal their connection with the classics
simply enough by presenting themselves as the work of one Publius. This
eminently sober work considers chiefly that diversity and inequality in the
faculties of men which shows itself in the acquisition of property, but it is
very far from being blind to the difference between business and govern¬
ment. According to Alexander Hamilton, the mechanics and manufac¬
turers “know that the merchant is their natural patron and friend,” their
natural representative, for the merchant possesses “those acquired endow¬
ments without which, in a deliberative assembly, the greatest natural abili¬
ties are for the most part useless.” Similarly, the wealthier landlords are the
natural representatives of the landed interest. The natural arbiter between
the landed and the moneyed interests will be “the man of the learned
professions,” for “the learned professions . . . truly form no distinct in¬
terest in society” and therefore are more likely than others to think of “the
general interests of the society.” It is true that in order to become a repre¬
sentative of the people, it sometimes suffices that one practice “with suc¬
cess the vicious arts by which elections are too often carried,” but these
deplorable cases are the exception, the rule being that the representatives
will be respectable landlords, merchants, and members of the learned pro¬
fessions. If the electorate is not depraved, there is a fair chance that it will
elect as its representatives for deliberation as well as for execution those
among the three groups of men “who possess most wisdom to discern, and
most virtue to pursue, the common good of the society,” or those who are
most outstanding by ‘ merits and talents,” by “ability and virtue.” 3
Under the most favorable conditions, the men who will hold the balance
of power will then be the men of the learned professions. In the best case,
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 17
one may call disinterested contemplation of the eternal, but the relief of
man’s estate. Philosophy thus understood could be presented with some
plausibility as inspired by biblical charity, and accordingly philosophy in
the classic sense could be disparaged as pagan and as sustained by sinful
pride. One may doubt whether the claim to biblical inspiration was justi¬
fied and even whether it was always raised in entire sincerity. However this
may be, it is conducive to greater clarity, and at the same time in agree¬
ment with the spirit of the modern conception, to say that the moderns
opposed a “realistic,” earthly, not to say pedestrian conception to the
“idealistic,” heavenly, not to say visionary conception of the classics. Phi¬
losophy or science was no longer an end in itself, but in the service of
human power, of a power to be used for making human life longer, health¬
ier, and more abundant. The economy of scarcity, which is the tacit pre¬
supposition of all earlier social thought, was to be replaced by an economy
of plenty. The radical distinction between science and manual labor was to
be replaced by the smooth co-operation of the scientist and the engineer.
According to the original conception, the men in control of this stupen¬
dous enterprise were the philosopher-scientists. Everything was to be done
by them for the people, but, as it were, nothing by the people. For the
people were, to begin with, rather distrustful of the new gifts from the new
sort of sorcerers, for they remembered the commandment, “Thou shalt not
suffer a sorcerer to live.” In order to become the willing recipients of the
new gifts, the people had to be enlightened. This enlightenment is the core
of the new education. It is the same as the diffusion or popularization of
the new science. The addressees of the popularized science were in the first
stage countesses and duchesses, rather than spinsters and dairymaids, and
popularized science often surpassed science proper in elegance and charm
of diction. But the first step entailed all the further steps which were taken
in due order. The enlightenment was destined to become universal en¬
lightenment. It appeared that the difference of natural gifts did not have
the importance which the tradition had ascribed to it; method proved to
be the great equalizer of naturally unequal minds. While invention or dis¬
covery continued to remain the preserve of the few, the results could be
transmitted to all. The leaders in this great enterprise did not rely entirely
on the effects of formal education for weaning men away from concern
with the bliss of the next world to work for happiness in this. What study
did not do, and perhaps could not do, trade did: immensely facilitated and
encouraged by the new inventions and discoveries, trade which unites all
peoples, took precedence over religion, which divides the peoples.
But what was to be done to moral education? The identification of the
end of the gentlemen with the end of the nongentlemen meant that the
understanding of virtue as choiceworthy for its own sake gave way to an
instrumental understanding of virtue: honesty is nothing but the best
policy, the policy most conducive to commodious living or comfortable self-
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 21
preservation. Virtue took on a narrow meaning, with the final result that
the word “virtue" fell into desuetude. There was no longer a need for a
genuine conversion from the premoral if not immoral concern with worldly
goods to the concern with the goodness of the soul, but only for the calcu¬
lating transition from unenlightened to enlightened self-interest. Yet even
this was not entirely necessary. It was thought that at least the majority of
men will act sensibly and well if the alternative will be made unprofitable
by the right kind of institution, political and economic. The devising of the
right kind of institutions and their implementation came to be regarded as
more important than the formation of character by liberal education.
Yet let us not for one moment forget the other side of the picture. It is a
demand of justice that there should be a reasonable correspondence be¬
tween the social hierarchy and the natural hierarchy. The lack of such a
correspondence in the old scheme was defended by the fundamental fact
of scarcity. With the increasing abundance it became increasingly possible
to see and to admit the element of hypocrisy which had entered into the
traditional notion of aristocracy; the existing aristocracies proved to be oli¬
garchies, rather than aristocracies. In other words it became increasingly
easy to argue from the premise that natural inequality has very little to do
with social inequality, that practically or politically speaking one may safely
assume that all men are by nature equal, that all men have the same natu¬
ral rights, provided one uses this rule of thumb as the major premise for
reaching the conclusion that everyone should be given the same opportu¬
nity as everyone else: natural inequality has its rightful place in the use,
nonuse, or abuse of opportunity in the race as distinguished from at the
start. Thus it became possible to abolish many injustices or at least many
things which had become injustices. Thus was ushered in the age of toler¬
ance. Humanity, which was formerly rather the virtue appropriate in one’s
dealings with one’s inferiors—with the underdog—became the crowning
virtue. Goodness became identical with compassion.
Originally the philosopher-scientist was thought to be in control of the
progressive enterprise. Since he had no power, he had to work through
the princes. The control was then in fact in the hands of the princes, if of
enlightened princes. But with the progress of enlightenment, the tutelage
of the princes was no longer needed. Power could be entrusted to the peo¬
ple. It is true that the people did not always listen to the philosopher-
scientists. But apart from the fact that the same was true of princes, society
came to take on such a character that it was more and more compelled to
listen to the philosopher-scientists if it desired to survive. Still there re¬
mained a lag between the enlightenment coming from above and the way
in which the people exercised its freedom. One may even speak of a race:
will the people come into full possession of its freedom before it has be¬
come enlightened, and if so, what will it do with its freedom and even with
the imperfect enlightenment which it will already have received? An ap-
22 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
parent solution was found through an apparent revolt against the enlight¬
enment and through a genuine revolt against enlightened despotism. It
was said that every man has the right to political freedom, to being a
member of the sovereign, by virtue of the dignity which every man has as
man—the dignity of a moral being. The only thing which can be held to
be unqualifiedly good is not the contemplation of the eternal, not the cul¬
tivation of the mind, to say nothing of good breeding, but a good inten¬
tion, and of good intentions everyone is as capable as everyone else, wholly
independently of education. Accordingly, the uneducated could even ap¬
pear to have an advantage over the educated: the voice of nature or of the
moral law speaks in them perhaps more clearly and more decidedly than in
the sophisticated who may have sophisticated away their conscience. This
belief is not the only starting point and perhaps not the best starting point,
but it is for us now the most convenient starting point for understanding
the assertion which was made at that moment: the assertion that virtue is
the principle of democracy and only of democracy. One conclusion from
this assertion was Jacobin terror which punished not only actions and
speeches but intentions as well. Another conclusion was that one must re¬
spect every man merely because he is a man, regardless of how he uses his
will or his freedom, and this respect must be implemented by full political
rights for everyone who is not technically criminal or insane, regardless of
whether he is mature for the exercise of those rights or not. That reasoning
reminds one of a reasoning which was immortalized by Locke’s criticism
and which led to the conclusion that one may indeed behead a tyrannical
king, but only with reverence for that king. It remains then at the race be¬
tween the political freedom below and the enlightenment coming from
above.
Hitherto I have spoken of the philosopher-scientist. That is to say, I
have pretended that the original conception, the seventeenth-century con¬
ception, has retained its force. But in the meantime philosophy and science
have became divorced: a philosopher need not be a scientist, and a scien¬
tist need not be a philosopher. Only the title Ph.D. is left as a reminder of
the past. Of the two henceforth divorced faculties of the mind, science has
acquired supremacy; science is the only authority in our age of which one
can say that it enjoys universal recognition. This science has no longer any
essential connection with wisdom. It is a mere accident if a scientist, even a
great scientist, happens to be a wise man politically or privately. Instead of
the fruitful and ennobling tension between religious education and liberal
education, we now see the tension between the ethos of democracy and the
ethos of technocracy. During the last seventy years, it has become increas¬
ingly the accepted opinion that there is no possibility of scientific and
hence rational knowledge of “values,” that is, that science or reason is in¬
competent to distinguish between good and evil ends. It would be unfair
to deny that, thanks to the survival of utilitarian habits, scientists in gen-
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 23
eral and social scientists in particular still take it for granted in many cases
that health, a reasonably long life, and prosperity are good things and that
science must find means for securing or procuring them. But these ends
can no longer claim the evidence which they once possessed; they appear
now to be posited by certain desires which are not “objectively” superior to
the opposite desires. Since science is then unable to justify the ends for
which it seeks the means, it is in practice compelled to satisfy the ends
which are sought by its customers, by the society to which the individual
scientist happens to belong and hence in many cases by the mass. We must
disregard here the older traditions which fortunately still retain some of
their former power; we must disregard them because their power is
more and more corroded as time goes on. If we look then only at what is
peculiar to our age or characteristic of our age, we see hardly more than the
interplay of mass taste with high-grade but strictly speaking unprincipled
efficiency. The technicians are, if not responsible, at any rate responsive to
the demands of the mass; but a mass as mass cannot be responsible to any¬
one or to anything for anything. It is in this situation that we here, and
others in the country, raise the question concerning liberal education and
responsibility.
In this situation the insufficiently educated are bound to have an unrea¬
sonably strong influence on education—on the determination of both the
ends and the means of education. Furthermore, the very progress of sci¬
ence leads to an ever increasing specialization, with the result that a man’s
respectability becomes dependent on his being a specialist. Scientific edu¬
cation is in danger of losing its value for the broadening and the deepening
of the human being. The only universal science which is possible on this
basis—logic or methodology—becomes itself an affair of and for techni¬
cians. The remedy for specialization is therefore sought in a new kind of
universalism—a universalism which has been rendered almost inevitable by
the extension of our spatial and temporal horizons. We are trying to expel
the narrowness of specialization by the superficiality of such things as gen¬
eral civilization courses or by what has aptly been compared to the unend¬
ing cinema, as distinguished from a picture gallery, of the history of all na¬
tions in all respects: economic, scientific, artistic, religious, and political.
The gigantic spectacle thus provided is in the best case exciting and enter¬
taining; it is not instructive and educating. A hundred pages—no, ten
pages—of Herodotus introduce us immeasurably better into the mysterious
unity of oneness and variety in human things than many volumes written
in the spirit predominant in our age. Besides, human excellence or virtue
can no longer be regarded as the perfection of human nature toward which
man is by nature inclined or which is the goal of his eros. Since “values”
are regarded as in fact conventional, the place of moral education is taken
by conditioning, or more precisely by conditioning through symbols verbal
and other, or by adjustment to the society in question.
24 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
What then are the prospects for liberal education within mass democ¬
racy? What are the prospects for the liberally educated to become again a
power in democracy? We are not permitted to be flatterers of democracy
precisely because we are friends and allies of democracy. While we are not
permitted to remain silent on the dangers to which democracy exposes it¬
self as well as human excellence, we cannot forget the obvious fact that by
giving freedom to all, democracy also gives freedom to those who care for
human excellence. No one prevents us from cultivating our garden or from
setting up outposts which may come to be regarded by many citizens as
salutary to the republic and as deserving of giving to it its tone. Needless to
say, the utmost exertion is the necessary, although by no means the suffi¬
cient, condition for success. For “men can always hope and never need to
give up, in whatever fortune and in whatever travail they find themselves.”
We are indeed compelled to be specialists, but we can try to specialize in
the most weighty matters or, to speak more simply and more nobly, in the
one thing needful. As matters stand, we can expect more immediate help
from the humanities rightly understood than from the sciences, from the
spirit of perceptivity and delicacy than from the spirit of geometry. If I am
not mistaken, this is the reason why liberal education is now becoming
almost synonymous with the reading in common of the Great Books. No
better beginning could have been made.
We must not expect that liberal education can ever become universal
education. It will always remain the obligation and the privilege of a
minority. Nor can we expect that the liberally educated will become a po¬
litical power in their own right. For we cannot expect that liberal educa¬
tion will lead all who benefit from it to understand their civic responsibility
in the same way or to agree politically. Karl Marx, the father of commu¬
nism, and Friedrich Nietzsche, the stepgrandfather of fascism, were liber¬
ally educated on a level to which we cannot even hope to aspire. But per¬
haps one can say that their grandiose failures make it easier for us who
have experienced those failures to understand again the old saying that
wisdom cannot be separated from moderation and hence to understand
that wisdom requires unhesitating loyalty to a decent constitution and even
to the cause of constitutionalism. Moderation will protect us against the
twin dangers of visionary expectations from politics and unmanly contempt
for politics. Thus it may again become true that all liberally educated men
will be politically moderate men. It is in this way that the liberally edu¬
cated may again receive a hearing even in the market place.
No deliberation about remedies for our ills can be of any value if it is not
preceded by an honest diagnosis—by a diagnosis falsified neither by un¬
founded hopes nor by fear of the powers that be. We must realize that we
must hope almost against hope. I say this, abstracting entirely from the
dangers threatening us at the hands of a barbaric and cruel, narrow-minded
and cunning foreign enemy who is kept in check, if he is kept in check.
Liberal Education and Responsibility / 25
only by the justified fear that whatever would bury us would bury him too.
In thinking of remedies we may be compelled to rest satisfied with pallia¬
tives. But we must not mistake palliatives for cures. We must remember
that liberal education for adults is not merely an act of justice to those who
were in their youth deprived through their poverty of an education for
which they are fitted by nature. Liberal education of adults must now also
compensate for the defects of an education which is liberal only in name or
by courtesy. Last but not least, liberal education is concerned with the
souls of men and therefore has little or no use for machines. If it becomes
a machine or an industry, it becomes undistinguishable from the entertain¬
ment industry unless in respect to income and publicity, to tinsel and
glamour. But liberal education consists in learning to listen to still and
small voices and therefore in becoming deaf to lojid-speakers. Liberal edu¬
cation seeks light and therefore shuns the limelight.
NOTES
26
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy ( 27
According to positivism, the first premises are not evident and necessary,
but either purely factual or else conventional. According to existentialism,
they are in a sense necessary, but they are certainly not evident: all think¬
ing rests on unevident but nonarbitrary premises. Man is in the grip of
powers which he cannot master or comprehend, and these powers reveal
themselves differently in different historical epochs. Hence classical politi¬
cal philosophy is to be rejected as unhistorical or rationalistic. It was ra¬
tionalistic because it denied the fundamental dependence of reason on lan¬
guage, which is always this or that language, the language of a historical
community, of a community which has not been made, but has grown.
Classical political philosophy could not give to itself an account of its own
essential Greekness. Furthermore, by denying the dependence of man’s
thought on powers which he cannot comprehend, classical political philos¬
ophy was irreligious. It denied indeed the possibility of an areligious civil
society, but it subordinated the religious to the political. For instance, in
the Republic, Plato reduces the sacred to the useful; when Aristotle says
that the city is natural, he implies that it is not sacred, like the sacred Troy
in Homer; he reveals the precarious status of religion in his scheme by
enumerating the concern with the divine in the “fifth and first” place: only
the citizens who are too old for political activity ought to become priests.
Eric A. Havelock in his book The Liberal Temper in Greek Politics 1
approaches classical political philosophy from the positivistic point of view.
The doctrine to which he adheres is, however, a somewhat obsolete version
of positivism. Positivist study of society, as he understands it, is “descrip¬
tive” and opposed to “judgmental evaluation” (120, 368), but this does
not prevent his siding with those who understand “History as Progress.”
The social scientist cannot speak of progress unless value judgments can be
objective. The up-to-date or consistent positivist will therefore refrain from
speaking of progress, and instead speak of change. Similarly Havelock ap¬
pears to accept the distinction between primitive men or savages and civi¬
lized men (186-188), whereas the consistent positivist will speak not of
savages, but of preliterate men and assert that preliterate men have “civili¬
zations” or “cultures” neither superior nor inferior to those of literate men.
It would be wrong to believe that the up-to-date positivist is entirely con¬
sistent or that his careful avoidance of “evaluative” terms is entirely due to
his methodological puritanism; his heart tells him that once one admits the
inequality of “cultures,” one may not be able to condemn colonialism on
moral grounds. Havelock is therefore perhaps only more intelligent or more
frank than the consistent positivists when he describes his position as lib¬
eral, rather than as positivist. Yet this does not entirely dispose of the diffi¬
culty. “For the liberal man is to be taken as you find him and therefore his
present political institutions are to be taken as given also.” This means
that here and now the liberals will take American democracy as given and
will then “concentrate empirically and descriptively on this kind of politi-
28 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
process takes place and which limits the progress (cf. 253); this limit is not
set by man, and it surpasses everything man can bring about by his exer¬
tions and inventions; it is superhuman or divine. Moreover, one may grant
that progress is due entirely to man’s exertions and inventions and yet trace
progress primarily to rare and discontinuous acts of a few outstanding men;
"progressivism” is not necessarily identical with that "gradualism" which is
apparently essential to liberalism. Finally, liberalism is empirical or prag¬
matic; it is therefore unable to assert that the principle of causality (“noth¬
ing can come into being out of nothing and through nothing") is evidently
and necessarily true. On the other hand, it would seem that the Greek
anthropologists or rather "physiologists” did regard that principle as evi¬
dently true because they understood the relation of sense perception and
logos differently than do the liberals. It is no exaggeration to say that
Havelock never meets the issue of the possible fundamental difference be¬
tween the liberals and their Greek predecessors. For one cannot say that he
meets that issue by asserting that the Greeks who believed in progress
"may have retained this within the framework of a cosmic cycle” and that
"the issue as it affects a basic philosophy of human history and morals is
whether we at present are living in a regress or a progress” (405). It is ob¬
vious that this does not affect at all the considerations which have been
indicated. Besides, in order to prove that a given Greek thinker was a lib¬
eral, Havelock is now compelled to prove that the thinker in question
thought himself to live "in a progress.” Contrary to his inclination, he
cannot show this by showing that the thinker in question regarded his time
as superior to the barbaric beginnings, for any time prior to the final devas¬
tation is superior to the first age. Nor can he show it by showing that the
thinker in question believed himself to live at the peak of the process, for
this belief implies that there will be no further progress to speak of. All this
means that he cannot prove the existence of a single Greek liberal thinker.
Of one great obstacle to his undertaking Havelock is aware. To put it
conservatively, very little is known of the Greek liberals; at most only frag¬
ments of their writings and reports about their teachings as well as about
their deeds and sufferings survive. To overcome this difficulty, Havelock
must devise an appropriate procedure. He divides the bulk of his argument
into two parts, the first dealing with anthropology or philosophy of history
and the second with political doctrine. He subdivides the first part com¬
pletely and the second part to some extent in accordance with the require¬
ments of the subject matter. Liberalism being preceded by orthodoxy (73),
he presents first the orthodox or theological view, then the liberal or scien¬
tific view, and finally the compromise between the orthodox and the liberal
views which is in fact the metaphysical view (of Plato and Aristotle). He
thus tacitly replaces the Comtian scheme of the three stages by what would
seem to be a dialectical scheme which bodes as ill for the future of liberal¬
ism as did Comte’s. Given the great difficulty of interpreting fragments,
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 33
philosophy of history, at least before one has laid the proper foundation for
such an ascription. Havelock thinks or acts differently. Since his authors do
not speak of history in the derivative sense of the term, he makes them
speak of it and thus transforms them into modern thinkers, if not directly
into liberals. For instance, he translates “becoming” or “all human things”
by “History” and he inserts “history,” with brackets or without them, into
the ancient sayings (62, 94, 108, 115).
The characteristic assertion of liberalism seems to be that man and
hence also morality is not “a fixed quantity”; that man’s nature and there¬
with morality are essentially changing; that this change constitutes History;
and that through History man has developed from most imperfect begin¬
nings into a civilized or humane being. The opponents of liberalism seem
to assert that man’s nature does not change, that morality is timeless or a
priori, and that man’s beginnings were perfect (27-29, 35, 40, 44-45).
But it is not clear, and it has not been made clear by Havelock, that there
is a necessary connection between the assertion that man’s nature does not
change and the assertion that man’s beginnings were perfect, that is, supe¬
rior to the present. The recollection, we do not say of Plato and Aristotle,
but merely of eighteenth-century progressivism would have dispelled the
confusion. Be this as it may, as is indicated by the titles of the pertinent
chapters in Havelock’s book, he is mainly concerned with the question re¬
garding the status of man in the beginning.
The preliberal or orthodox position must be understood by Havelock as
the belief that man’s beginnings were simply perfect, that man’s original
state was the garden of Eden or the golden age, a state in which men were
well provided for by God or gods and not in need of work and skills, and in
which nothing was required of them except childlike obedience: imperfec¬
tion or misery, and hence the need for work and the arts, arose through
man’s fault or guilt; but these merely human remedies are utterly insuffi¬
cient. The orthodox regard History as Regress. “The classic Greek state¬
ment of the Eden dream” occurs in Hesiod’s account of the golden age in
the Works and Days. According to Havelock, the comparison of the
golden age with the garden of Eden is not a loose analogy: “Hesiod’s nar¬
rative conveys the inevitable suggestion that Eden was lost through eating
of the fruit of the tree of knowledge” (36). Hesiod’s “famous account of
the five ages” contains “the story of three successive failures of three gen¬
erations of men” (37), of failures which culminate in the present, the
worst of all five ages. Havelock hears in Hesiod’s account “the tone of gen¬
uine social and moral critique.” Yet he cannot take him seriously: Hesiod’s
account of the fifth or present age “reads like the perennial and peevish
complaint of an ageing conservative whose hardening habits and faculties
cannot come to terms with youth or with changing conditions.” Accord¬
ingly, he apologizes for having “lingered over Plesiod” after having devoted
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 35
to him less than five pages, a considerable part of which is filled with a
mere enumeration of items mentioned by Hesiod (40).
Havelock suggests then that according to Hesiod man lost Eden through
his sin. Yet only three out of five successive races of men were “failures.”
The first and golden race was not a failure. There is no indication whatever
that it came to an end through man’s sin. The golden race lived under
Kronos; the next race, the silver race, was hidden away by Zeus; and the
three last races are explicitly said to have been “made” by Zeus. It would
seem then, as Havelock notes in a different context, that when Zeus “suc¬
ceeded to the throne of Kronos . . . human degeneration began” (53):
the destruction of the golden race was due to Zeus’s dethroning of Kronos.
Zeus apparently did not wish or was not able to make a golden race of his
own. It is, to say the least, not perfectly clear whether according to Hesiod
the failure of the silver, bronze, and iron races was not due in the last
analysis to Zeus’s whim or his defective workmanship, rather than to man’s
fault. “Hebrew analogies . . . can often mislead” (137). However, one of
the races made by Zeus, the fourth race, the race of the heroes or demi¬
gods, was by far superior to the three other races made or ruled by Zeus;
some of the men of the fourth race are so excellent that they are again
ruled by Kronos, if only after their death. Havelock does not explain why
Hesiod assigned to the demigods the place between the inferior bronze
race and the still more inferior iron race. When Plato adopted Hesiod’s
scheme in the Republic, he gave a reason why or intimated in what respect
the fourth race, or rather the fourth regime, is almost equal to the first
regime: the first regime is the rule of the philosophers, and the fourth re¬
gime is democracy, that is, the only regime apart from the first in which
philosophers can live or live freely (546 e-547 al, 557d 4, 558a8). For rea¬
sons which need not be stated, one cannot use the Platonic variation for
the understanding of the original. It is pertinent to say that according to
Hesiod the fifth or iron race is not necessarily the last race: the age suc¬
ceeding the iron age is likely to be superior to it or to the present age,
which itself is not at all deprived of every goodness (Works and Days
174-175, 179). Could Hesiod have thought that a more or less better race
is always succeeded by a more or less worse race which in its turn is always
succeeded by a more or less better race and so on until the age of Zeus (or
human life as we know it) comes to its end? On the basis of the evidence,
this suggestion is more “inevitable” than the accepted interpretation.
Under no circumstances is one entitled to say that Hesiod regarded “His¬
tory as Regress.”
How Hesiod’s account of the five races must be understood depends on
the context in which it occurs. As for its immediate context, it is the sec¬
ond of three stories; the first story is the account of Prometheus and
Pandora, and the third story is the tale of the hawk and the nightingale.
36 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Havelock refers in a few words to the first story, in which work may be said
to be presented as a curse, but he does not say anything about the third
story, although it is very pertinent to the history of Greek liberalism. The
hawk said to the nightingale while he carried her high up in the clouds,
having gripped her fast with his talons: “He is a fool who tries to with¬
stand the stronger, for he will never vanquish him and he suffers pain be¬
sides the disgrace.” The king believes that he disposes entirely of the fate
of the singer, but the singer or the poet has a power of his own—a power
surpassing that of the king (Theogony 94-103). As for the broad context
of this story as well as of the story of the five races, it is the Works and
Days as a whole. The poem as a whole tells when and how the various
“works,” especially of farming, must be done and which “days” are propi¬
tious and which not for various purposes; the account of the works and the
days is preceded by exhortations to work as the only proper thing for just
men and as a blessing, by answers to the question as to why the gods
compel men to work, and by the praise of Zeus the king, the guardian of
justice who blesses the just and crushes the proud if he wills (W.D. 267—
273). There are, it seems, two ways of life: that of the unjust idlers and
that of the just who work, especially as farmers. Closer inspection shows
that there are at least three ways of life corresponding to the three kinds of
men: those who understand by themselves, those who listen to the former
and obey them, and those who understand neither by themselves nor by
listening to others. The man who understands by himself and therefore
can speak well and with understanding and is best of all is, in the highest
case, the singer. The singer as singer neither works nor is idle. His deeds
belong to the night, rather than to the “days.” Song transcends the pri¬
mary antithesis which must be transcended because of the ambiguity of
work: work is both a curse and a blessing. Toil is the brother of Forgetting
(Theogony 226-227), while the Muses are the daughters of Memory.
Song transcends the primary antithesis because its highest theme—Zeus—
transcends it.
Havelock is not concerned with the context of Hesiod’s stories of the
perfect beginning because he is too certain of his answers to all questions.
“An early agricultural economy” combined with “disillusionment with sex”
finds “wish fulfillment by projecting backwards”; and the “backward vi¬
sion” combines “with an a priori epistemology” (36, 40). A psychology
and a sociology derived from the observation of present-day Western man,
or rather a certain type of present-day Western men, take the place of the
authentic context and are used as the key to the character of men and soci¬
eties of the past in such a way that phenomena, which are not allowed to
exist by the “a priori epistemology” of these present-day pursuits, can never
be noticed. The circle, being a circle, is necessarily closed. But the mind is
closed too. The attempt is made to catch a profound and subtle thought in
the meshes of a thought of unsurpassed shallowness and crudity.
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 37
except that he should not have spoken of Plato’s “skill.” From the fact
that inventions have been made, Plato infers that men lacked the invented
things at an earlier epoch; Havelock makes him “argue quite naively that
though new invention has been achieved by man ... it must come to a
stop sometime”: the notion of an “infinitely extended history’ or of
“human history as, so to speak, open at both ends is wholly alien to his
imagination” (49). Whatever may be true of the liberal imagination, the
liberal’s science tells him that invention must come to a stop sometime,
since the life of the human race will come to a stop sometime.
Following Havelock, we have completely disregarded the context of the
“archeology” of the third book of Plato’s Laws or the meaning of the work
as a whole. As we can here only assert, consideration of the whole work
would merely confirm what already appears from the passages used by
Havelock, namely, that it is wholly unwarranted to say that according to
Plato, man’s early life is “a wholly admirable and happy thing” (58).
Nevertheless Havelock is right in saying that “the net effect” of the pas¬
sages in question “upon the reader’s imagination” is the opposite. What
“necessity” drove Plato, whose “systematic mind was, to say the least, not
prone to contradiction” (100), to be “illogical”? Havelock suggests that
Plato was compelled grudgingly to make concessions to the Greek anthro¬
pologists, but that his prejudice always reasserted itself and especially when
he was old, that is, when he wrote the Laws in which “the Hesiodic nostal¬
gia is in control” (44, 47). This explanation rests on the untenable as¬
sumption that Plato believed in the age of Kronos. Havelock also suggests,
it seems, that Plato had to contradict himself because he could not contra¬
dict the Greek anthropologists “in open fight,” for in doing so he would
have been compelled to restate their doctrine and thus to contribute to the
spreading of a dangerous doctrine (87-88). This explanation rests on the
assumption, proved untenable by the tenth book of the Laws, for instance,
that Plato was afraid openly to set forth dangerous or subversive doctrines
to which he was opposed. Havelock might retort that the extreme view
openly set forth and openly attacked by Plato was less dangerous in his eyes
than the view of the Greek liberals; but until we know that there were
Greek liberals we must regard it as possible that Plato failed to set forth
the liberal view because the liberal view did not exist. We on our part sug¬
gest this explanation. Plato knew that most men read more with their
“imagination” than with open-minded care and are therefore much more
benefited by salutary myths than by the naked truth. Precisely the liberals
who hold that morality is historical or of merely human origin must go on
to say, with the sophist Protagoras as paraphrased by Havelock, that this
invaluable acquisition which for later men is a heritage “must never be
lost” or is “too precious to be gambled with” (187): the greatest enemies
of civilization in civilized countries are those who squander the heritage
because they look down on it or on the past; civilization is much less en-
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 41
dangered by narrow but loyal preservers than by the shallow and glib futur¬
ists who, being themselves rootless, try to destroy all roots and thus do
everything in their power in order to bring back the initial chaos and pro¬
miscuity. The first duty of civilized man is then to respect his past. This
respect finds its exaggerated but effective expression in the belief that the
ancestors the Founding Fathers—were simply superior to the present
generation and especially to the present youth, and mere “logic” leads
from this to the belief in perfect beginnings or in the age of Kronos.
coming from the very power of the arts? By dwelling on the ‘‘surface” of
the play, one becomes aware of the contrast between the arts and true wis¬
dom. Since the play presents the first men as most imperfect and since it
seems to suggest that the arts are less divine gifts than human inventions,
Havelock is certain that Aeschylus used a “scientific source” and as a con¬
sequence engages in speculations about the scientific anthropology which
illumined the poet (61-64). With perhaps greater right could not one
seek for the “scientific source” of the biblical account according to which
the city and the arts were originated by Cain and his race? The Bible leaves
much less doubt regarding the merely human origin of “civilization” than
does Aeschylus. Havelock does not prove and cannot prove from Aeschylus
the existence of “Greek liberalism.” Aeschylus’ changes of Hesiod’s story
are much more easily understood as the outcome of a somewhat different
meditation on things divine-human than as due to the influence of
science.
Havelock turns next to the choral song of the Antigone in which the
chorus expresses its trembling admiration for man as the being which is
supremely awful and supremely endangered: an awful crime against the
law of the city has just been discovered. In describing man’s awful or
wondrous character, the chorus enumerates man’s most outstanding inven¬
tions: “The figure of Prometheus has disappeared.” This would prove the
influence of science if it had been impossible for Greeks, or for men in
general, who were not scientists or influenced by science to be somehow
aware of the human origin of the human arts (cf. Laws 677d4). In two
pages Havelock proves, in accordance with his standards of proof, three
things. According to Havelock’s Sophocles, man taught himself “con¬
sciousness ; hence Havelock forces the reader to wonder how an uncon¬
scious being can teach itself anything and in particular consciousness. The
whole choral song in question expresses “flamboyant optimism.” “The
conclusion of the chorus carries us beyond the confines of anthropology to
the borders of a liberal theory of morals and politics” (68-70). With
equally “quick speech” he shows the influence of science as well as the
“theistic” or “pietistic” perversion of science in a passage of Euripides’
Suppliants. That passage is declared to be “a skillful rewrite” of a “scien¬
tific original” the existence of which we have by now learned to assume
since we have so frequently been told to do so. The only remark which
could possibly be stretched to be meant to be an attempt of a proof is the
assertion that Euripides becomes involved “in unconscious paradox”—in a
contradiction, since in theistically praising the kindness of heaven he
speaks nontheistically of its harshness. In fact, Euripides makes his
Theseus say that a god taught man to protect himself against a god, that is,
another god. Havelock, however, knows that Euripides speaks “in the per¬
son of Theseus” (72).
For Havelock s purpose Diodorus Siculus is much more important than
44 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
science and society, and hence of the character of both science and society
in entirely different terms from those of the liberals. On the other hand ii
is gratifying to see that “gradualism” does not necessarily excIude the crj
cial importance of gifted individuals” (93) and hence that "gradualism”
may make allowance for sudden changes. g uuaiism
Havmg arrived at this point we are in a position to pass final judgment
on Haveocks procedure. When speaking of Plato, he says: ’we have
spoken of his [scientific or naturalistic] source or sources. The case for their
of ‘ Wnt fi ' Sf' !?* With What right did he 3SSUme the existence
of scientific sources of the tragedians when he analyzed their plays? We
assume that in his opinion some people have justified his assumption but
cannot be certain that this is his opinion. We feel entitled to speak of
an involuntary satire on scientific method and on scientific progress.
sufficient for everyone, for, as he says, “the many do not, so to speak, no¬
tice anything” (316c 5—317c 1).
The third and final clue supplied by the speech of the Platonic Protagoras
is his assertion that there is a fundamental difference between the arts and
reverence or right: the latter are “universals,” that is, all men must partake
of them, while it is neither necessary nor desirable that everyone should be
a physician, a shoemaker, and so on. Havelock finds this assertion incom¬
patible with the assumed democratic creed of Protagoras (93). But does
democracy, as distinguished from Marxism, require that every man be a
jack of all trades? How does Havelock know that Protagoras’ assumed
theory of democracy demanded that everyone be a jack of all trades? The
Platonic Protagoras’ assertion that there is a fundamental difference be¬
tween the arts and “man’s moral sense” is meant to be the basis of democ¬
racy: all men are equal as regards that knowledge by which civil society as
such stands or falls. Yet Plato’s Protagoras describes reverence and right as
gifts of Zeus, and how can “a complete agnostic” give a religious account of
the origin and the validity of morality (93-94)? He explains his mythical
account of the origin and validity of morality in what one may call the
nonmythical part of his speech. The universal practice of mankind shows
that everyone “in some way or another” partakes of justice, as distin¬
guished from flute playing for instance; that is, that everyone must claim to
be just, regardless of whether he is just or not (323a 5-c 2). Justice has in
common with the arts that it is acquired by teaching and training; but the
difference between the teaching and training by which the arts are ac¬
quired and the teaching and training by which justice is acquired appears
from the fact that the latter consists chiefly in punishment: men become
just “in some way or another” chiefly by punishment, or the threat of it,
but also by praise, as distinguished from instruction proper (323d 6-324c
5, 324e 6-326a 4, 327d 1-2). What is mythically called a gift of Zeus is
nonmythically described as “social compulsion,” which as such cannot
produce, at any rate in the case of thinking men, more than conformism or
lip service. The assertion that morality rests on “social compulsion” or on
“conditioning” (178) and not on natural inclination nor on calculation
nor on intellectual perception should satisfy every behaviorist. It certainly
satisfies Havelock after he has added a few touches of his own. When
Plato’s Protagoras says that the man who does not pretend to be just,
whether he is just or not, is insane, Havelock adds “unless, it is surely im¬
plied, in temporary repentance” (171; the italics are not in the original).
When the Platonic Protagoras is believed to have said that justice and
virtue are useful, Havelock makes him say that morality is “pleasant”
(185). Perhaps still more remarkable is his enthusiasm for what the Pla¬
tonic Protagoras says regarding the purpose of punishment, namely, “that
punishment only makes sense as a corrective or as a deterrent” (175). He
takes it for granted that this teaching is genuinely Protagorean. But how
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 49
does he know this? Because it is a liberal view? But the illiberal Plato held
the same view Besides, the same Platonic Protagoras teaches, just as Plato
himself did that there are incurable criminals who must be driven out of
the city or be killed. Why did Plato entrust the rational teaching regarding
punishment to Protagoras in particular? The context requires a praise of
433a). That city is not early society, but is the society according to nature
which is sufficient for satisfying men’s bodily needs without poverty, with¬
out compulsion (government), and without bloodshed of any kind; it is
not a commercial society because it is not a competitive society, a competi¬
tive society presupposing the existence of government. Plato makes this
experiment in order to show the essential limitations of society thus con¬
ceived. A society of this character may possess justice of some sort since its
members exchange goods and services; it cannot possess human excellence:
it is a city of pigs. Whereas its members sing hymns to the gods, they can¬
not sing the praises of excellent men because there cannot be excellent
men in their midst (cf. 371e 9-372b 8 and 607a 3-4).
After he has completed his attempt to prove the existence of Greek pro-
gressivist philosophers from their alleged use or adulteration by the trage¬
dians, Diodorus Siculus, and Plato, Havelock turns to the fragments of
these alleged progressivists. Three very late reports on Anaximander and
five fragments from Xenophanes are said to “hint at the presence in both
[thinkers] of a scheme of cosmology which found perhaps its climax in the
history of life and of man upon the earth. . . . The tentative conclusion
can be drawn that ... if the record of Anaximander guarantees the bio¬
logical naturalism of Greek anthropology, that of Xenophanes does the
same for its empirical pragmatic conception of the sources of human
knowledge” (106-107). The unusual restraint of Havelock perhaps re¬
flects the fact that according to a report to which he does not refer (21 A
49) Xenophanes regarded only reason itself, in contradistinction to sense
perception, as trustworthy. He admits that “against these tentative conclu¬
sions should be set what we know of Xenophanes’ ‘theology.’ ” By this he
does not mean Xenophanes’ verses on the one god, the greatest among
gods and men who does not resemble the mortals at all; he does not say a
word about Xenophanes’ Eleaticism or his denial of any coming into
being; he merely means his “critical attack on Greek polytheism.” To say
nothing of the facts that according to a fragment and a report quoted by
Havelock, Xenophanes did not limit his attack to the Greek popular no¬
tions of the gods and that he did not attack polytheism, Havelock wishes
to believe that that “critical attack” “was a part of [Xenophanes’] recon¬
struction of the history of human institutions.” Sympathizing with the
spirit of present-day anthropology, Havelock “plays down” Xenophanes’
concern with the question of the truth of what peoples believe.
As regards Anaxagoras, Havelock carefully avoids any reference to his
doctrine regarding the ordering Intelligence which rules all things, knows
all things, exists always and is unmixed, and is the cause of all things; he
does not even take the trouble to deny the relevance of that doctrine for
Anaxagoras’ anthropology (107-112). To assimilate the Greek anthro¬
pologists to the liberals, Havelock must impute to Archelaus the view that
“the historical process is ... a natural growing process” and therefore
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 51
tus’ statement according to which “for all men good and true are the same,
but pleasant differs from one man to another” (B 69; cf. A 166) “which no
complete account of his philosophy can afford to ignore” (142); this state¬
ment would make clear that Democritus is not a historicist or a relativist,
that for him the problem indicated by the distinction between factual and
value judgments does not arise, and that one cannot intelligently solve a
political problem by describing it if one does not know what is good for all
men. As for Democritus’ or Havelock’s “historical method,” we give two
examples. Democritus’ saying, “Faction within the tribe is bad for both
sides,” proves to Havelock that whereas Plato and Aristotle uncritically
accepted “the virtual identification of nomos and polis,” “Democritus true
to his genetic method sees law generated as a solution to the problem
which was already crystallizing ... in the clan of blood kindred.” Yet
“depending on the context,” “tribe” (phyle) “might refer [also] to all
members of a polis” (135-136). Since we do not know the context in
which the saying occurred, some modesty of assertion would be particularly
proper, to say nothing of the fact that Plato and Aristotle only “virtually”
“identified nomos and polis” (cf. Laws 681a-c and Republic 565e 4-7).
In another saying Democritus shows what good—compassion, fraternity,
concord, and so on—follows or rather is already present when the powerful
take heart to help the poor and to be kind to them. According to Have¬
lock, this saying “constitutes the most remarkable single utterance of a
political theorist of Hellas. Considering its epoch, it is as remarkable as
anything in the history of political theory. Neither in content nor in
temper has it a parallel in the better-known classical thinkers” (143). Ap¬
parently Havelock did not remember Plato’s Laws 736d 4-e 2 and 936b
3-8 or Aristotle’s Politics 1320a 35—b 11 (cf. Rhetoric II, 7-8). But for¬
getfulness does not explain the extraordinary assertion and the complete
absence of a sense of proportion which it exhibits. He is driven to asser¬
tions of this kind by an inordinately strong prejudice and the ferocity
which goes with such prejudices. When Democritus says that “poverty
under democracy is as much to be preferred to the so-called prosperity
which resides with lords or princes as freedom is to slavery,” Havelock
makes him say “poverty under democracy is better than any prosperity
under oligarchy,” takes him to prefer democracy to all other regimes, and
finds it “hard to avoid the conclusion that when Thucydides penned the
Funeral Speech of Pericles he was expressing an intellectual debt to
Democritus” (146-147). He has strange notions of what is required for
making a conclusion sound. Besides, the Funeral Speech does not strike
one as a praise of “poverty under democracy.” Havelock finds it unneces¬
sary to comment on Democritus’ relative praise of poverty, nor does he
even allude to other fragments of Democritus which depreciate wealth
(B 283-286). Those sayings would not confirm his contention that the
position taken by the Greek liberals, among whom he counts Democritus,
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 53
sophists had “their own specific integrity,” but he does not seem to make
much sense when he says that “the theories they taught and believed may
or may not be possible of reconstruction, but they were at least serious
theories, intellectually respectable” (160): how can one judge of the dig¬
nity of doctrines which become accessible only through reconstruction if
their reconstruction is not possible? Given Plato’s “fundamental hostility”
(162) to the political theories of the liberals, Havelock would be unable to
reconstruct them if he could not rely in his interpretation of the Platonic
passages on that “portrait” of liberalism which he has painted with the
assistance of a few fragments. But before connecting the Platonic evidence
with the non-Platonic vision, true or feigned, of Greek liberalism, one must
understand the Platonic evidence by itself. The Protagoras being the most
important source for Havelock, he is under an obligation to interpret that
dialogue. Hie Rhodus hie salta. Here is the occasion for displaying that
“philological discipline,” that “good deal of finesse,” that “critical intu¬
ition,” to say nothing of “the over-all judgment” to which he lays claim
in this very context (157, 171*).
Plato presents Protagoras as presenting his particular claim in a particu¬
lar setting: in the house of a very wealthy Athenian, in the presence of his
most formidable competitors, with a view to inducing a youth to become
his pupil. A “pragmatist” (166) like Protagoras cannot but be influenced
by this situation: we can only guess as to how he would have stated his
claim if he had been closeted with Socrates or, for that matter, with the
mathematician Theodorus. An author as much concerned with “logo-
graphic necessity” as Plato would not have prefaced the conversation be¬
tween Socrates and Protagoras with the fairly extensive conversation
between Socrates and young Hippocrates—to say nothing at all here of the
conversation between Socrates and an anonymous “comrade” with which
the dialogue opens—without a good reason. The conversation between
Socrates and Hippocrates shows in the first place how much Protagoras
appealed to a certain kind of young man and conversely how little Socrates
appealed to those people or how little they appealed to Socrates; it permits
us to size up Hippocrates. Protagoras is characterized by the fact that he is
willing to accept as his pupil a youth of whom he knows nothing except
what Socrates tells him in the youth’s presence, namely, that he comes
from a wealthy Athenian house, that as regards his nature he is thought to
be a match for those of his age, that he seems to Socrates to desire to be¬
come famous in the city, and that he believes that he will most likely get
what he wants if he joins Protagoras. “We know from Middle Comedy
that Plato’s Academy charged fees and high ones at that.” Hence “by Pla¬
tonic standards the sophists committed no offence” (162). The basis on
which Havelock establishes the Platonic standard is somewhat narrow, and
hence he misses the decisive point. For Protagoras it is sufficient to know
that his potential customer can pay for his services; Socrates is concerned
The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / 55
above everything else with whether his potential young friends have the
right kind of nature. ’ In other words, Protagoras is at liberty to accept
every wealthy young man as a pupil, whereas Socrates is not (cf. the
Theages and Memorabilia I 6.13). The place occupied in Socrates’ thought
by nature” is taken in Protagoras’ thought by “wealth.” Havelock is un¬
aware of this difference. According to Plato’s presentation, Protagoras was
insufficiently aware of it.
. !n h!f Havelock admits then that Plato’s presentation of Protagoras
is fair. While he believes that Plato gives a reasonably fair account of Pro¬
tagoras claim, he contends that Plato “transfers [that claim] into a non-
political context (165, 168). Let us then consider the context. In his
eagerness to acquire a new pupil of means, Protagoras was entirely uncon-
cerned with inspecting the nature of Hippocrates; in spite of the caution of
which he boasts, he did not stop to consider whether there was not a
serpent lurking behind Hippocrates’ alluring promise. Still less did he con¬
sider whether his claim did not bring him into conflict with the Athenian
democracy. Socrates tactfully draws his attention to the fact that in Athens
rich and poor” are equally supposed to possess that political skill which
rotagoras claims to teach (319c 8-el): Protagoras’ claim is incompatible
with democracy. Havelock sees here only “irony ... at the expense of
Athenian democratic practice” (168), although he observes when speaking
ot a term similar in meaning to “irony,” namely, “playfulness,” that it is “a
term convenient to critics who have not understood Plato’s mind” (100).
It would be unbecoming to comment on his claim to have “understood
Plato’s mind.” But we may say that strictly speaking every utterance of the
Platonic Socrates is ironical since Socrates is always mindful of the qualities
of his interlocutors and that for this reason Havelock is right when he
intimates that one does not explain any particular utterance of the Platonic
Socrates by describing it as ironical.
At any rate, Socrates forces Protagoras for the benefit of Protagoras (cf.
316c 5) to show that his claim is compatible with Athenian democracy. In
the mythical part of his speech he defends or justifies democracy with that
complete lack of qualification which is fitting in a mythical utterance; in
the nonmythical part he defends or justifies democracy in a more qualified
manner: he knows that some qualification of democracy is required if his
claim is to be respectable or reasonable. If Protagoras had not given the
unqualified justification of democracy, Socrates could not know and the
readers of the Protagoras could not know, whether Protagoras had under¬
stood the difficulty to which Socrates had alluded. According to Havelock,
the continuity [of the logos) with the myth is tenuous, simply because the
myth is a myth” (168). He thus unwittingly suggests that Plato presented
Protagoras as a very great blunderer; this suggestion is wrong. As for the
qualification of democracy which is required for reconciling Protagoras’
claim with democracy, Protagoras supplies it in a properly subdued manner
56 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
by referring to the fact that in a democracy there are, after all, wealthy
people who can afford to give their sons a rather expensive education and
therefore, we must add, the education in that political art which he claims
to supply. Havelock applauds the “pragmatic” wisdom “which any mem¬
ber of a liberal democracy is forced to accept: that educational opportunity
tends to be available in proportion to family means” or that “leadership
tends to fall into the hands of the privileged”; he applauds the sophists’
“acceptance of a measure of plutocracy.” But a democrat might well
wonder whether Havelock is right in suggesting that a practice which is
bound to increase the gulf between the rich and the poor “does not violate
the ethos of democracy” (182-183, 248): “if there is inequality [of legal or
social status], the function of amity is thereby inhibited” (397). All that
one can say of Havelock’s political theory is that if he is right, it is not for a
liberal to be right in this point. As for his thesis that Protagoras was a de¬
fender of democracy, and even of “a craftsman democracy” (187), it must
be restated so as to read that the Platonic Protagoras defended a mixture
of democracy and oligarchy or that he deviated from democracy pure and
simple in the direction of oligarchy. He might have defended oligarchy
pure and simple if he had not been compelled to adapt his doubtlessly
“negotiable” political convictions to a democracy. His criticism of democ¬
racy differs from Socrates’ criticism because he takes the side of the
wealthy, whereas Socrates takes the side of the gentlemen. We trust that
Havelock is aware of this difference when he does not happen to write on
“the Elder Sophists.”
One would be unfair to the Platonic Protagoras if one did not stress
more strongly than Havelock does that, according to him, the laws are, or
should be, “the inventions of good and ancient lawgivers” (326d 5-6) as
distinguished from the enactments of a chance multitude. However “radi¬
cal” he may have been regarding the gods, he knew too well that reverence
for antiquity and especially for the great “inventors” of antiquity is indis¬
pensable for society. But, as he says, “the many do not, so to speak, notice
anything.” It is due to the merit of those inventors that present-day man is
separated by a gulf from the original savages. Protagoras must have noticed
somehow that Socrates looked down on that political art which Protagoras
claims to teach and of which he claims that every man possesses it. At any
rate, he accuses Socrates of not properly appreciating that art or what one
may call the progress of civilization: Socrates seems not to know that in the
beginning human beings were worse than the worst criminals living in civi¬
lized society. “The reflection almost reads like a piece of Plato’s own self-
criticism; . . . here he lets the liberals have their say undiluted” (188).
There is undoubtedly some kinship between the modern liberal and the
ancient sophist. Both are unaware of the existence of a problem of civiliza¬
tion, although to different degrees. For Protagoras supplies his assertions
with important qualifications which do not come out in Havelock’s para-
TTze Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy / SI
phrases. It would be painful and in no way helpful if we were to follow
Havelock s analysis of the conversation between Socrates and Protagoras.
As one would expect from his claim to have understood Plato’s thought he
interprets Socrates’ questions as dictated by Plato’s “system” without'lis¬
tening patiently to what Socrates actually says in the context. Similarly he
interprets Protagoras’ answers as dictated by a pragmatist or behaviorist
epistemology or sociology. The utmost one can say about his whole discus¬
sion is that it may shed some light on present-day liberalism. Two examples
must suffice. F
The question discussed by Socrates and Protagoras is whether virtue is
one or many. Common speech assumes that virtue is one: we speak of
good men At the same time common speech assumes that there are many
virtues and that a man may possess one virtue while lacking all others. For
instance, as Protagoras says, a man may be courageous and yet unjust or he
may be just and not be wise. When Protagoras’ attention is first drawn to
the difficulty, he suggests immediately that the one virtue has many quali¬
tatively different parts. Socrates seems to be surprised that Protagoras re¬
gards courage and wisdom too as parts of the one virtue. Protagoras replies
emphatically in the affirmative and adds that wisdom is the greatest of all
parts of virtue (329e 6-330a 2). Socrates’ difficulty is not hard to under¬
stand: in his long speech Protagoras had been rather reticent regarding
wisdom and especially reticent regarding courage; his emphasis had been
on justice, moderation, and piety; for his chief subject had been “political
T£ ^22e 27^a ^23a 6-7), which is a special kind of virtue (323c
. °ne wishes to understand Protagoras, one must therefore make
explicit what he implied by putting different emphases on justice, modera¬
tion, and piety on the one hand and wisdom and courage on the other. We
suspect that one cannot achieve this if one does not reflect on the Platonic
distinction between political virtue and genuine virtue. Who knows prior
to investigation whether Protagoras did not admit the soundness of this
distinction? Prior to further investigation it is clear that according to him
only political virtue is a gift of Zeus, and yet there is also a virtue which is a
gift of Prometheus (321d). Havelock carefully avoids this kind of reflec¬
tion which would certainly complicate matters and might shake his confi¬
dence that Protagoras’ thoughts about truth were thoughts about “the
parliamentary process” or “the crystallization of public opinion.”
At a certain point in the discussion Protagoras elaborates the obvious but
not unimportant truth that different things are good for different beings or
for different parts of those beings. Havelock finds therein a “pragmatic
epistemology,” a “pragmatic classification,” a “sophistic economics,” and a
pragmatic programme.” He is therefore shocked by “the Socratic context.”
Socrates virtually concludes ‘Here is mere relativism ” and “Plato
next resorts to an artifice as unfair as anything anywhere in his dialogues.
Socrates figuratively throws up his hands exclaiming: ‘I cannot deal with
58 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Havelock’s book culminates in, although it does not end with, his
account of Antiphon. The account is based on “the mutilated record”’sup¬
plied by two papyrus fragments which are now held to stem from the
sophist Antiphon (256, 289, 416-418). Antiphon asserts that by nature all
men, regardless of whether they are Greeks or barbarians, are alike in all
respects and that the denial of this likeness is barbaric; he proves this like¬
ness by the fact that as regards the things which are by nature necessary to
all men, such as breathing through mouth and nose, there is no difference
among men. Havelock admires Antiphon’s “breathless logic” in which the
distinction between “natural barbarians” and “‘the natural free man’
(that is, Greeks)” “dissolves like smoke” (257-258). He thus implies that
Antiphon’s liberal assertion is opposed to the view of the classics. His im¬
plicit criticism proceeds from a superficial understanding of certain pas¬
sages in the first book of the Politics (351-352) and from a complete dis-
60 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
his dissatisfaction with Plato’s suggestions regarding the use of that antith¬
esis by certain individuals. He abstains from discussing the pertinent Pla¬
tonic passages, and he does not even begin to consider whether Plato’s own
questioning of law—especially in the Statesman—as well as his simile of the
Cave does not imply the same antithesis, although differently understood.
He who had praised the sophists as “communication men” and blamed
Plato for despising “discourse [as] a vehicle of group or collective opinion
and decision” has the hardihood, and in a sense the consistency, to lump
him together with the “group thinkers” for whom the polis is “the mistress
adored” (194, 270). Fiat liberalismus pereat Plato.
All these lapses, however, fade into insignificance when compared with
the great merit of an observation which, to the best of our knowledge,
Havelock is the first classical scholar to make. “Any subject of a totalitarian
state—and the city-state had its totalitarian aspects—and indeed the citi¬
zens of a democracy, in this present age of war and anxiety, know what
Antiphon meant” (271). We dismiss the reference to “democracy in this
age of war and anxiety” as out of place and even misleading. But in the
main point Havelock is right. The polis, and even the celebrated Athens of
Pericles, was not liberal or limited by a First Amendment, and Antiphon
explicitly says that the law determines “for the eyes what they ought to see
and what they may not see, and for the ears what they ought to hear and
what they may not hear, and for the tongue what it ought to say and what
it may not say.” It is perhaps a pity that Havelock did not go on to wonder
in the first place whether Antiphon’s “candor,” however praiseworthy on
other grounds, does not have the disadvantage of being inconsistent with
his insight because remarks like those quoted “fight” the law of the city in
the presence of witnesses; and to wonder in the second place whether
Antiphon’s manner of writing was not perhaps affected by his insight or
whether the obscurity of his style was not perhaps intentional—whether he
appears to us as extraordinarily candid because a lucky or unlucky accident
has saved for us a most shocking saying of his in isolation, while in the
complete work it was perhaps hidden away in the middle of an innocent
exposition or not presented by the author in his own name but entrusted
to other people—whether therefore one should not read his fragments with
a corresponding lack of innocence; and to wonder finally whether other
Greek writers did not have the same insight (which after all is not of
transcendent profundity) and hence composed their writings accordingly
and hence must be read with much greater care and much less innocence
than that with which they are usually read. A scholar who would have
given these questions ever so little serious and unbiased consideration
would have written an entirely different book—not a liberal book in the
present-day sense, but a liberal book in the original sense.
To return to Havelock, he takes Antiphon’s antithesis of law and nature
to imply that law is not “framed by the virtue of inspired lawgivers,” but
62 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
to bespeak “reverence for life” (280). In fact Antiphon explains what the
good by nature is as distinguished from the good by convention: the good
by nature is that which is conducive to life, and therefore the good by
nature is ultimately the pleasant. “The human organism” is violable in par¬
ticular by other “human organisms”; the laws claim to protect the inno¬
cent; Antiphon questions the truth of this claim. Havelock admits that
Antiphon’s statement on this subject could “easily” be understood to mean
that it is according to nature “to adopt the initiative in aggression” in order
not to become the helpless victim of aggression. He rejects this possibility
on the ground that according to Antiphon “nature does not seek to create
enemies” (284), although he also says that Antiphon questioned the be¬
nign character of “nature’s rule” (294). Antiphon merely says that what is
just must be universally beneficent; he does not say that justice thus under¬
stood is possible, and he certainly does not say that justice thus understood
is implied in “the laws of nature.” He also appears to have pointed out the
essential inconveniences of marriage, and he may very well have questioned
the natural character of marriage. Havelock interprets the passage in ques¬
tion, after having excised portions of it “which better reflect the tradition”
than they reflect Antiphon (293), in the same spirit in which he interprets
his questioning the laws of the city. “The twentieth-century note in his
teaching is there. It sounds almost uncanny. Was he an apostle of the new
education? Would he have approved a progressive school? Is it possible
that in his Greek we catch, across the centuries, the accents of Sigmund
Freud?” (294.) The “almost” is inspired not by reasonable restraint, but
by the liberal temper: Sigmund Freud can be relied upon a priori to show
in each case that what appears to be uncanny is not truly uncanny.
Some readers may blame us for having devoted so much time and space
to the examination of an unusually poor book. We do not believe that
their judgment of the book is fair. Books like Havelock’s are becoming ever
more typical. Scholarship, which is meant to be a bulwark of civilization
against barbarism, is ever more frequently turned into an instrument of
rebarbarization. As history suggests, scholarship is, as such, exposed to that
degradation. But this time the danger is greater than ever before. For this
time the danger stems from the inspiration of scholarship by what is called
a philosophy. Through that philosophy the humane desire for tolerance is
pushed to the extreme where tolerance becomes perverted into the aban¬
donment of all standards and hence of all discipline, including philological
discipline. But absolute tolerance is altogether impossible; the allegedly
absolute tolerance turns into ferocious hatred of those who have stated
most clearly and most forcefully that there are unchangeable standards
founded in the nature of man and the nature of things. In other words, the
humane desire for making education accessible to everyone leads to an ever
increasing neglect of the quality of education. No great harm is done, or at
least there is no new reason for alarm, if this happens in disciplines of re-
64 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
cent origin; but the situation is altogether different if the very discipline
which is responsible for the transmission of the classical heritage is
affected. True liberals today have no more pressing duty than to counteract
the perverted liberalism which contends “that just to live, securely and
happily, and protected but otherwise unregulated, is man’s simple but su¬
preme goal” (374) and which forgets quality, excellence, or virtue.
NOTE
65
66 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
the name which is mentioned in the title is the name of a man of the re¬
mote past who is only spoken about in the conversation.
While the question with which Socrates opens the conversation is
abrupt, it cannot be said to be unambiguous. It is not clear whether he asks
the companion, “What in our opinion is law?” or “What is the law to
which we [we Athenians (?)] are subject?” The first question might be
called universal or theoretical, and the second question might be called
practical or particular. The practical question is again ambiguous; it may
refer to a whole legal order or to any particular law. While being distinct,
the theoretical and the practical questions are inseparable from each other.
One cannot know to which law one is subject without having some knowl¬
edge, however vague and dim, of law as such; one cannot know what law as
such is without possessing at least a directive toward the law to which one
is subject. For the time being Socrates makes his initial question unambig¬
uous by limiting the conversation to the theoretical question. But the prac¬
tical question is only driven underground: the dialogue ends with the sug¬
gestion that the law deserving the highest respect is the law, not of Athens,
but of Crete.
Socrates illustrates the question “What is law?” first by the question
“What is gold?” and then by the question “What is stone?” Gold is
most valuable, and a stone may be entirely worthless. “Gold” is never used
in the plural, whereas “stone” is; one cannot say “a gold” as one can say “a
stone”: there are wholes each part of which is a whole or complete, and
there are wholes no part of which is complete. We are thus induced to
wonder whether law, properly understood, is more like gold or more like
stone. But regardless of whether any particular law or even any particular
code can be said to be a whole, Socrates’ question is concerned with a
whole—the whole comprising all laws. Just as gold does not differ from
gold in respect of being gold and stone does not differ from stone in re¬
spect of being stone, law does not differ from law in respect of being law.
Does this mean that a bad law is as much law as a good law?
The companion’s first answer to Socrates’ comprehensive question is to
the effect that the law is the whole consisting of whatever is “held” or
whatever is established by law. Socrates convinces him by suitable parallels
that just as in other cases what we may call the acts of the human soul are
not the same as the things in which these acts issue, law as an act of the
soul is not the same as that in which that act issues. Law is then so far
from being something inanimate (like gold or stone) that it is an act of
the soul: is it manifestation or science or is it finding (invention) or art? In
his answer (the second and central answer to Socrates’ comprehensive
question) the companion does not meet the issue. He says that law is the
decision of the city. He means by this that the law is not an act of the soul,
but something in which certain acts of the soul issue. Yet it is now clear to
him that law is the outcome of some act of the soul, whereas his first an-
On the Minos / 67
swer would have been compatible with the view that law is custom of
which no one knows whence it came or, as one might say, which is not
“made” but has “grown.” Socrates rephrases the second answer in such a
way as to make it an answer to the particular question which he had ad¬
dressed to the companion: the act of the soul which is law has the charac¬
ter, neither of science nor of art, but of opinion; it is the city’s opining
about the affairs of the city.
A simple consideration suffices to show that this answer is insufficient.
We assume that there is a connection between law and justice. Perhaps a
man may be law-abiding without being just, but surely a lawless man is
unjust. In a way law and justice seem to be interchangeable; hence law will
be something high. But a city’s opinions may be low. We are then con¬
fronted with a contradiction between two most audible opinions which are
so audible because they are opinions of the city: the opinion that the law is
the opinion of the city and the opinion that the law is something high.
Socrates, without any hesitation and without giving any reason, chooses the
second opinion and therewith tacitly rejects the opinion that the law is the
opinion of the city. Since the opinions of the city are self-contradicting,
even the best of citizens cannot simply bow to them. Law is indeed an
opinion, according to Socrates; but he does not yet say whose opinion it is;
for the time being he only says that it is a high opinion, hence a true opin¬
ion, and hence the finding out of what is. “Finding out,” and hence law,
appears to be between “finding” or art on the one hand and “manifesta¬
tion” or science on the other.
Only one more step is needed in order to bring us to the third and final
definition of law, the only definition proposed by Socrates: the law wishes
to be the finding out of what is. The last step is a step back. Socrates
qualifies the apparent result according to which the law is the finding out
of what is. He does not give a reason for his qualification, but the compel¬
ling reason comes to sight immediately afterward: if the law were the
finding out (the having found out) of what is, and what is (what is with¬
out any admixture of nonbeing) is always the same, law would be simply
unchangeable, and hence all or most of the things which we call laws and
which differ from time to time and from place to place would not be laws
at all. But if law only wishes, or tends, to be the finding out of what is, if
no law is necessarily the finding out of what is, there can be an infinite
variety of laws which all receive their legitimation from their end: The
Truth. The companion fails to grasp the qualification; he believes that Soc¬
rates has left it at suggesting that law is the finding out of what is. Given
the fact, he argues, that we constantly find out the same things as things
which are (sun, moon, stars, men, dogs, and so on), all men should always
use the same laws, and they manifestly do not. Socrates replies to the effect
that the variety in question is due to the defects of human beings and does
not affect the law itself. The implied distinction between the infallible law
68 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
and the fallible human beings suggests to us that law is indeed an act of
the soul, but perhaps not necessarily of the human soul. Besides, Socrates
regards it as an open question whether human beings do use different laws
at different places and in different times. He thus compels the companion
to prove the fact that laws vary. But when he has completed that proof,
Socrates seems to reject it as an irrelevant “long speech." In brief, Socrates
tries to be silent about the variety of laws—about a fact which had induced
him to say that the law wishes to be—that is, is not necessarily—the find¬
ing out of what is.
The companion proves the variety of laws by the examples of laws con¬
cerning sacrifices and burials; the examples concern sacred things. They
confirm to some extent Socrates’ definition of law; they show that at any
rate the most awe-inspiring laws are based on more or less successful at¬
tempts to find out what is in the highest sense, namely, the gods and the
soul and hence what the gods demand from men and what death means.
The examples show the great difference between present Athenian practice
and the practice of the earliest past, of the age of Kronos, as it were. They
seem to show that in the beginning men were savage, whereas in present-
day Athens they are gentle; hence present-day Athenian laws will be supe¬
rior to the oldest laws, Greek or barbarian. This finding obviously presup¬
poses that laws differ temporally and locally. Perhaps Socrates treats the
changeability of law in so gingerly a manner because it is the premise of
the finding mentioned—of a finding with which he is not satisfied.
Socrates attempts now to bring about a meeting of minds with the com¬
panion by means of short speeches, or short questions and answers. The
companion prefers to answer Socrates’ questions rather than to question
Socrates. He grants to Socrates that people everywhere and always hold
that the just things are just, the noble things are noble, the unjust things
are unjust, and the base things are base—just as all people, regardless of
whether they hold it lawful or impious to bring human sacrifices, hold that
the things that weigh more are heavier and the things that weigh less are
lighter. The final result of this reasoning confirms the unqualified defini¬
tion of law according to which law does not merely wish but is the finding
out of what is. The companion, who through his own fault is compelled to
give short and rather quick answers and cannot, as we can, read and reread
Socrates’ questions, is unable to lay bare the sophism to which Socrates
draws our attention while committing it: the universal agreement regard¬
ing the opposition of the just or noble things to the unjust or base things
does not establish universal agreement as to the content of “the just and
the noble.” Nevertheless, the companion remains entirely unconvinced, for
Socrates’ result manifestly contradicts what the companion himself ob¬
serves with his own eyes in Athens every day, namely, that “we" (that is,
we Athenians) unceasingly change the laws.
What one may call Socrates’ second proof of his definition of law is not
On the Minos / 69
a mere repetition of the first. In the second proof Socrates tactily contrasts
“the just things” and “the heavier things”; he thus draws our attention to
two questions: (1) Can justice be a matter of degree as is weight? (2) Is
disagreement regarding weight as widespread and as profound as disagree¬
ment regarding justice? Besides, the first proof was still related to the opin¬
ion that law is the opinion of the city; that opinion plays no role in the
second proof. We are thus being prepared for the suggestion that law is
the mental act, not of the city (that is, of the assembly of the citizens) or
of the citizen, but of men of a different description.
Reading on, we observe that what we have called Socrates’ second proof
of his definition of law is in fact the first section of his tripartite defense of
his definition of law; that tripartite defense forms the second or central
part of the dialogue. At the beginning of the central section of the central
part, Socrates abruptly turns to the writings of men who possess an art. We
can discern the reason for the apparent change of the subject. Socrates had
raised the question whether law is a science or an art. He assumes now that
law is an art. He seems to justify this assumption as follows. Laws are pre¬
scriptive writings; but the arts, being a kind of perfect, final, fixed knowl¬
edge which is the same for all, necessarily find their appropriate expression
in prescriptive writings; hence laws belong to the same genus as the arts.
This reasoning suffers from an obvious flaw: it is not necessary for either
arts or laws to present themselves in writings. For instance, the farmers,
that is, the experts in farming, do not necessarily compile or even read writ¬
ings on farming.
If laws belong to the same genus as the arts and are therefore prescrip¬
tive writings composed by experts of a certain kind, namely, the kings (or
statesmen), there is no reason why laws should be the work of the city or
of Greeks: neither citizens nor Greeks are, as such, experts in the kingly
art. The prescriptions ordinarily called “laws” may differ from place to
place; but regarding things of which men possess knowledge, all knowers
agree, as Socrates asserts, regardless of where they live or whether they are
Greeks or barbarians. When the companion emphatically assents to this
assertion, Socrates praises him for the first time. Furthermore, the prescrip¬
tions ordinarily called “laws” may differ from time to time; but where
there is knowledge, there is no change of thought; or vice versa, where
there is change of thought, there is no knowledge; the frequent change of
“laws” for which Athens was so notorious is then a clear proof that the
Athenian legislature is ignorant, and hence its findings or decisions do not
deserve to be called laws or to be respected as laws; in fact those “laws”
must be particularly bad. The companion does not object to this tacit re¬
sult; in other words, he has now become convinced of the truth of Soc¬
rates’ definition of law or, more precisely, of the fact that law is an art. It
looks as if Socrates has succeeded in appealing from his pro-Athenian prej¬
udice to his antidemocratic prejudice. We on our part realize that the
70 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
certain kind—not indeed the unwritten laws of unknown origin which say
the same things always and everywhere, but certain acts of a wise soul.
Socrates had opened the central part of the dialogue with the suggestion
that there is universal agreement regarding the just and the noble things.
This suggestion taken by itself could be thought to refer to the unwritten
laws which are always and everywhere acknowledged to be laws and which
for this reason cannot be the work of human legislators (Xenophon,
Memorabilia IV. 4. 19). But the Minos is silent about the unwritten laws
thus understood. One may say that in this dialogue Socrates turns from
unwritten laws of unknown origin first to written laws and then to unwrit¬
ten laws of known origin, viz. the distributing by the king of the proper
food and toil to each man’s soul.
The third and last part of the Minos deals with the laws of Minos. The
transition is not explained and is therefore abrupt. We are supposed to
have learned what law is and what makes a law good; we must then seek
the best laws. What we have learned may have made us doubtful whether
the best laws can be of human origin. The lesson conveyed through the last
part of the dialogue may provisionally be said to be that the best laws are
the laws of Minos because Minos received them from the highest god, his
father Zeus. What must surprise us is that the laws of Zeus do not consist
in assigning to each man’s soul the food and toil best fitted for him, and
besides that Zeus did not communicate his laws to all men: he communi¬
cated them only to a single privileged man, to Minos, whom he appointed
also as the highest judge of the dead (Gorgias 523e-524a). Perhaps Zeus
did not wish to rule directly so that man, within certain limits left to him¬
self, would be compelled or enabled to choose as long as he lives. Further¬
more, if Zeus had communicated his law to men directly, men would nec¬
essarily be able to know the thoughts of Zeus, that is, soothsaying would
necessarily be a genuine art; but there is no need for soothsaying if there is
an intermediary between Zeus and men, an intermediary like Minos who,
as participating in divinity, does not need a human art to be aware of the
thoughts of his father and as participating in humanity can communicate
his father’s thoughts to men just as human legislators communicate their
laws to men.
Socrates leads up to the laws of Zeus by speaking first not simply of the
best laws but of laws (prescriptive and distributive acts) both good and an¬
cient regarding flute playing. As we could have learned from the compan¬
ion’s long speech, the good is in no wise the same as the ancient: certain
ancient laws commanded human sacrifices to the then highest god. But an
ancient law which is now still in force approximates the unchangeability
which appeared to be a mark of goodness. Law must be not only good or
wise but also stable: could the best laws be laws which are both wise and
stable? The example of flute playing—of an art which reminds most forci¬
bly of speech and yet which cannot be practiced while one speaks—draws
72 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
our attention to the quality of the divine as distinguished from the ancient
and the good. The flute songs invented by certain ancient barbarians are
most divine because they alone move and bring to light those who are in
need of the gods; yet the divine character of those flute songs explains why
they still retain their force. Not everything ancient is divine, but perhaps
everything divine necessarily lasts for a very long time. Could the stability
of the best laws be due to the unspeakable or mysterious power of the
divine which rules chance and may rule it in favor of the good? We are
thus prepared for Socrates’ suggestion that the oldest Greek laws—the laws
which Minos gave to his fellow Cretans, rather than, for instance, the
Egyptian laws or the Lacedaemonian laws which were popularly traced to
Apollo, the victor over Marsyas and his art of flute playing—combine the
qualities of oldness, goodness, and divinity.
The companion, who has been brought to admit that law is an art and
hence that the Athenian laws are either not laws at all or in the best case
only bad laws, refuses to bow to the Cretan laws. He does not deny that
Minos was an ancient king of divine origin, but he denies that he was a
good king. Socrates tells him that he is under the spell of an Athenian
myth; he sets out to liberate him from the spell of the Athenian myth as
he has liberated him from the spell of the Athenian laws. In a speech
whose length surpasses by far the length of the companion’s long speech,
Socrates appeals from the Athenian tragic poets who had originated the
myth, according to which Minos was bad, to Homer and Hesiod, the most
ancient poets, and thus proves that Minos and hence his laws are good.’
From Homer, Socrates has learned that Minos was the only one of the
children of Zeus educated by Zeus in his art, the noble art of sophistry,
which may be identical with the legislative art and certainly is identical
with the kingly art; the education took place in a cave, if in the cave of
Zeus. Law is so far from being the opinion of the city that it is, or is based
upon, an art, the highest art, the art of the highest god. In order to judge
of Socrates’ contention, one would have to consider in their contexts the
few Homeric verses to which he appeals; one would have to see whether
they express the view of Homer or of a Homeric character; in the latter
case one would have to consider whether that character can be presumed
to possess both the knowledge and the truthfulness required in a matter of
such importance. As Socrates indicates, the decisive Homeric passage could
be thought to mean that Minos associated with his father Zeus, not in
speeches devoted to education in virtue, but in drinking and playing. He
disposes of the suggestion that Minos associated with Zeus in drinking to
the point of drunkenness by a consideration which, it must be admitted, is
not free from begging the question. He does not dispose of the suggestion
that Zeus and Minos associated for other purposes which have nothing in
common with education to virtue. It is not advisable to speculate on the
alternatives which are not mentioned. It suffices to say that, as Socrates
On the Minos / 73
makes clear at the very end, the whole conversation is based on ignorance
of the function of the good legislator: the whole praise of Minos’ laws
must be reconsidered, as it is in the Laws.
The audible proof of Minos’ goodness is balanced by an inaudible doubt
of that goodness. The difference between proof and doubt corresponds to
the difference between two Socratic exhortations. The proof is preceded by
an exhortation to piety, for Socrates challenges the Athenian myth regard¬
ing Minos in the name of piety: it is impious for a human being to speak
ill of Minos, that is, a hero who was the son of Zeus; the god may resent
this more than if one speaks ill of him. The proof is followed by an ac¬
count of how the myth of Minos’ badness arose: Minos waged a just war
against Athens, defeated Athens, and compelled the Athenians to pay
that famous ransom : to send fourteen young Athenians at regular inter¬
vals to Crete as a kind of human sacrifice; hence Minos became hateful to
“us,” the Athenians, and we take our revenge on him through the tragic
poets who present him as bad; this revenge is effective because tragedy is in
its way as pleasing to the people and as apt to lead the soul as flute playing
itself. While stating these things, Socrates addresses his second exhortation
to the companion—the exhortation to be on his guard, not against acts of
impiety, but against incurring the hatred of any patriotic poet. As is shown
by the example of Minos, one cannot comply in all cases with both exhor¬
tations, although each exhortation demands compliance in all cases. While
complying with his first exhortation Socrates was compelled to praise most
highly the most ancient enemy of Athens to whom he will owe, if indi¬
rectly, the postponement of his execution decreed by the city of Athens
(cf. Phaedo 58a-c).
The end of the dialogue renders doubtful its chief result. This ending is
not entirely unexpected, for the suggestion that Minos’ laws are the best
laws implies the view that law can be the finding out of what is and hence
can be unchangeable, whereas Socrates’ definition of law implies the view
that law can never be more than the attempt to find out what is and hence
is necessarily changeable. According to the first view, men can be experts
—can possess full knowledge—regarding the matter with which law is con¬
cerned; according to the second view, men are ignorant regarding that
matter. One can resolve this difficulty by suggesting that while men cannot
be experts regarding that matter, they necessarily are knowers of it. The
fundamental difficulty can also be stated as follows: law is always and
everywhere the same and therefore one; law must be as variable as the
needs of individuals and therefore infinitely many. If one accepts the sec¬
ond view, one reaches this conclusion: whereas in the case of man, justice,
dog, the one (man as such, justice as such, dog as such) is of higher dignity
than the many (the individual men, just things, dogs); in the case of law
the one (the universal rule) is of lower dignity than the many (the assign¬
ment of the proper food and toil to each man’s soul) and in fact spurious.
74 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
We could touch only on some of the things which the reader of the
Minos must consider much more carefully than we have been able to do
here. For instance, we did not speak of the circumstances in which Socrates
and the companion address each other by name or in other ways. The
companion addresses Socrates eight times by name and never in any other
way. Socrates never addresses the companion by name (which does not
necessarily mean that he does not know his name), but addresses him
three times by an expression which we may render “you excellent one.” In
conversations between two men one uses the name of the other especially
in two cases: when the other says something apparently absurd and one
tries to call him back to his senses, and when one is pushed to the wall by
the other and begs for mercy. Socrates addresses the companion twice as
“you excellent one” immediately after the companion has addressed him as
“O Socrates”; the first time the companion was dissatisfied with Socrates’
praise of Minos, and the second time the companion failed to understand
how the good Minos could have acquired the reputation of being bad. As
for the character of the companion, we suspect that he was no longer quite
young, that he was concerned with civic fame, that he was what one might
call free from prejudices, and that he believed that one can be just while
being savage and unaccommodating.
The Minos raises more questions than it answers. In order to see how
the thoughts suggested by the Minos are best continued, one must turn to
the other dialogues. It is of little use to look up parallels in the other dia¬
logues to this or that passage of the Minos, for the meaning of the parallels
depends on their contexts, that is, on the whole dialogues within which
they occur. One must then study the other dialogues. With every other
dialogue a new land comes to sight; the experience resembles that of one's
becoming aware of an unexpected turn of the road at what seemed to be
the end of the road. The dialogue most akin to the Minos is the Hippar¬
chus. The Minos and the Hipparchus are the only dialogues between Soc¬
rates and a single nameless companion. They are the only dialogues whose
titles consist of the name of someone who is not present at the conversa¬
tion but was dead a long time before the conversation; their titles resemble
the titles of tragedies. They are the only dialogues which open with Soc¬
rates’ raising a “what is” question. While the Minos begins with the ques¬
tion “What is law?”, the Hipparchus begins with the question “What is
the quality of gain-loving? Who are the gain-loving ones?” If the beginning
of the Minos corresponded strictly to the beginning of the Hipparchus, it
would read: “What is the quality of lawful? Who are the law-abiding
ones?” If not law itself, surely law-abidingness is generally praised, while
love of gain is generally blamed: the Minos need not vindicate law-
abidingness and law, while the Hipparchus is devoted to vindicating love
of gain. While the Minos may be said to end in the praise of the Cretan
legislator Minos, the Hipparchus may be said to culminate in the praise of
On the Minos / 75
the Athenian tyrant Hipparchus. The vindication of the love of gain is the
vindication of tyranny, if the tyrant is the most outstanding lover of gain
(cf. Aristotle, Politics 1311a 4—11). Tyranny is the opposite of law or rule
of law; the Minos and the Hipparchus together deal with the two funda¬
mental alternatives. The connection which we indicated between “love of
gain” and “Hipparchus” is not made explicit in the Hipparchus. Hippar¬
chus is mentioned there because a saying of Hipparchus throws light on
the conversational situation. Socrates charges the companion with trying to
deceive him, and the companion charges Socrates with in fact deceiving
him. (No such charge is made in the Minos.) Thereupon Socrates quotes,
after proper preparation, the saying of Hipparchus “Do not deceive a
friend. The saying does not disapprove of deceiving people who are not
friends. From the context it would appear that not deceiving friends is a
part of justice or, in other words, that justice consists in helping one’s
friends and hurting one’s enemies. Love of gain is generally despised be¬
cause it seems inseparable from deception. However this may be, Socrates
praises the Athenian tyrant Hipparchus as a good and wise man, the great
educator of the Athenians in wisdom, whose reign resembled the age of
Zeus s father Kronos. If we put the Minos and the Hipparchus together,
we become haunted by the suggestion that an Athenian tyrant rather than
the Athenian law (and even than the Cretan law) was good and wise.
Accordingly, just as in the Minos Socrates explicitly rejects the Athenian
myth regarding Minos, in the Hipparchus he takes issue with what “the
many” in Athens say about Hipparchus: Harmodios and Aristogeiton, who
were magnified as liberators by the people of Athens, murdered Hippar¬
chus for no other reason than because they were envious of his wisdom and
his effect on the young; the nonlegal murder of Hipparchus foreshadows
the legal murder of Socrates.
The Hipparchus questions the view that love of gain is simply bad, just
as the Minos may be said to question the view that law is simply good: a
law may be bad just as gain may be good. These facts recommend the view
that both law and gain by themselves are neutral just as man may be said
to be neutral: a high-class man is not more nor less a man than a low-class
man (Hipparchus 230c). But just as the Minos leads up to the view that a
bad law is not a law, the Hipparchus leads up to the view that a bad gain is
not a gain. With what right do we then say of a low-class human being
that he is nevertheless a human being?
Notes on Lucretius
I. Ascent
76
Notes on Lucretius / 77
tween Rome and all living beings; through Venus, and only through
Venus, does one ascend from Romanism to Epicureanism.
Lucretius’ praise of Venus also serves the more obvious purpose of mak¬
ing her willing to grant him two favors. Since nothing glad and lovely
emerges without her, the poet asks her to help him in writing his poem by
granting abiding charm to what he will say. He tries to induce her to grant
him this favor by telling her that his poem will deal with the nature of
things, that is, her mighty empire, and that it is to benefit Memmius, who
has always been her favorite (21-28). He further asks Venus to grant
peace everywhere, to all mortals; she alone can restore peace since Mars,
the god of war, can be subdued only by his desire for Venus; when his de¬
sire will have been fully aroused, he will not be able to refuse her request
to grant peace to the Romans; for as long as the fatherland is in the grip of
war, Lucretius will lack the equanimity needed for writing his poem as per¬
fectly as he wishes and Memmius, compelled to come to the assistance of
the common weal, will lack the leisure needed for listening to the poet’s
verses (29-43). Only Venus can give charm to Lucretius’ poem, and only
Venus can restore the peace which is required for writing and enjoying
that poem. This is the reason that Lucretius, although he speaks of Mars,
is silent about the fact that the Romans are descendants not only of Venus
but of Mars as well: Venus, not Mars, is the link between Romanism and
Epicureanism.
Lucretius concludes his invocation of Venus by supporting his prayer for
peace with a reminder of what she owes to herself not because she is Venus
but because she is a divine being: all gods enjoy deathless life in perfect
peace. By this he means in the first place that since all gods enjoy perfect
peace, they all are able and willing to grant peace to men. But he also
means something else: the gods enjoy perfect peace because they are self-
sufficient, free from all pain and all danger, in no wise in need of men and
therefore not to be swayed by men’s good or bad deeds; they are altogether
remote from the affairs of men (44-49). The six verses which conclude
the invocation of Venus must be understood as part of their pre-Epicurean
context. The poet will repeat them literally in an Epicurean context; there
he introduces them by stating explicitly that the view of the gods which
they convey contradicts the popular view (II 644-645). No such statement
accompanies the verses when they occur first. In their pre-Epicurean con¬
text they do not exclude the possibility that the gods, who do not need
men in any way and cannot be swayed by any human merits and demerits,
bestow blessings on some men from sheer kindness whenever it pleases
them, just as Venus has always willed to bestow the greatest blessings on
Memmius (26-27) and has succeeded in doing so. In asking Venus to
grant abiding charm to his verses and peace to the Romans, the poet is not
necessarily trying to arouse the goddess to action; he may merely wish to
guide her in the action which she herself spontaneously started, the action
78 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
The last Book of the poem is the only one that begins and ends with
Athens. It almost goes without saying that no Book begins and ends
with “Rome.” The beginning of the last Book shows Athens’ greatness,
flnd the end shows Athens’ misery. Athens of outstanding fame first gave
men corn, an elevated kind of life, and laws; she first gave men sweet solace
of life when she brought forth the highly gifted man who by teaching wis¬
dom and thus liberating men from anguish showed them the way to happi¬
ness. This praise of Athens must be read in the light of the beginning of
the preceding Book. There Lucretius has spoken of the story that Ceres has
taught men how to grow com and of the fact that the god Epicurus has
taught men how to become wise. By correcting himself in the parallel pas¬
sage the poet shows that he can, if with some difficulty, resist the tempta¬
tion to deify the greatest benefactor of the human race, the most venerable
among the departed.2 He is grateful, not to any god, but in the first place
to Athens and to no other city.
The last Book ends with a description of the plague which had struck
Athens and which had been rendered immortal by Thucydides. This is not
the ending which one would have expected, the happy ending. The poet
had promised a copious speech on the gods (V 155), a speech which would
have made a happy ending. For some reason he replaced the speech on the
gods, the only beings that are perfectly happy, by the description of ex¬
treme misery.
Lucretius description of the plague differs most strikingly from its
Thucydidean model in being completely silent about the fact that the
plague occurred during a war and even owed its extremely destructive char¬
acter to that war:3 the plague was altogether a natural phenomenon, the
work of nature. As a consequence the plague as presented by Lucretius is
not less but more terrible than it is according to Thucydides. Since Lucre¬
tius does not present the plague in its context—in what we would call its
historical context—since he does not present the events preceding it and
following it, but describes it in isolation at the end of his poem, he pre¬
sents it as if it were the end of the world; he is silent on the cessation of
the plague. He presents to his readers in fact a recorded experience which
could give them a notion of the unrecordable end of the world. He is less
explicit than Thucydides about the fact that there were many who survived
the plague.4 He dwells more than Thucydides does on the fear of death
which gripped those exposed to the plague—their fear of death, not of
what might happen to them after death—and he is silent about their (not
necessarily unsuccessful) attempts, emphasized by Thucydides, to snatch
some pleasures without any regard to law before it was too late.5 He does
follow Thucydides’ description of the breakdown of fear of the gods and of
82 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
respect for the sacred laws regarding burial. Yet this description takes on a
somewhat different meaning in the Lucretian context; one cannot say of
Thucydides’ work what one can say of Lucretius’ work: that its most im¬
portant purpose is to liberate men from religion.
In order to reveal the magnitude of his enterprise, the poet returns at
the end of his poem for a moment to a still more pre-Epicurean view than
the one from which he started. He says that those who, from too great a
desire for life and fear of death, failed to take care of their sick were pun¬
ished afterward with a shameful death since they themselves were ne¬
glected and left without help when they fell sick; although he does not
speak of divine punishment, he suggests it. Yet he corrects himself imme¬
diately thereafter: those who from a sense of shame did take care of their
sick died no less miserably than the shameless.6 As a consequence of the
misery everywhere, neither the rites thought to be of divine origin nor the
gods themselves counted for much: they did not count for nothing. For
while the Athenians disregarded the customs of burial which they had
always observed, they did not desert the bodies of their dead kinsmen.7 At
any rate, the breakdown of religion is presented by Lucretius, as it is by
Thucydides, as a sign of extreme misery: there is something worse, much
worse, than religion.8 In the Lucretian context this means that the plague
which occurred in the heyday of Athenian civilization was more terrible
than the sacrifice of Iphigenia which occurred far from Athens in the ob¬
scure past: the witnesses of Iphigenia’s slaughter were sad and terrified;
they were not in a state of utter despondency; they could hope that Diana
would be appeased, and to the best of their knowledge this hope was ful¬
filled. And while the story of Iphigenia’s sacrifice may or may not be true,
the truth of the account of the plague in Athens is vouched for by one of
the most sober observers that ever was—by a man who was singularly free
from religious fear. The fact that Thucydides observed and described the
plague which struck him down could seem to show that philosophy, the
study of nature, is possible under the most unfavorable circumstances. Lu¬
cretius’ description of the plague, however, taken by itself, is far from sug¬
gesting this. It rather suggests that the mind of the philosopher stricken by
the plague would lose all its powers, become filled with anguish, pain, and
fear, and disintegrate before he died.9 The plague occurred prior to Epi¬
curus’ birth, but Lucretius does not in the slightest degree suggest that
Epicurus or an Epicurean would have withstood it better than anybody
else.
By contrasting directly the opening of the poem with its ending we gain
the impression that the poem moves from the sweetest natural phenome¬
non to the saddest and ugliest or that at the beginning the poet abstracts
entirely from the evils in order to accumulate them at the end. At the be¬
ginning he praises Venus, the giver of joy, charm, and peace, as the ruler of
nature; at the end he speaks, not even of Mars, but of the plague. Near the
Notes on Lucretius / 83
benefit and do not sense the bitterness of the drink which heals them.
The potential Epicurean whom Lucretius addresses may be a man of
rare worth according to ordinary standards, and he may have an excellent
mind; in the most important respect he is, to begin with, quite immature.
Therefore the poet must deceive him by adding something to the doctrine
which he expounds, something which is alien to the doctrine and which is
meant to conceal the sad, repulsive, and horrible character of the doctrine.
The comparison of honey and wormwood on the one hand with the poetry
and the doctrine on the other does not hold in every respect: children do
not necessarily learn that it was the bitter medicine which cured them,
whereas those readers of Lucretius’ work who grasp its meaning necessarily
learn that it is the doctrine which makes them sound and happy. The
comparison surely holds in that in both cases the patient tastes the sweet
first: thanks to the poetry, what the reader tastes first is sweet. But does the
reader ever taste the repulsive? Is what is primarily repulsive, if tasted by
itself, noticed only after it is no longer repulsive? Will its taste eventually
even be sweet? The example of Venus at the beginning and of the plague
at the end would seem to show that whereas the sweet is sensed first, the
repulsive or sad is sensed even at the end, but in such a way that it is more
bearable for the sensitive reader after he has digested the doctrine than
before. Furthermore, the child may take the honeyed wormwood merely
for the sake of the honey, or he may take it because he is uncomfortable;
he surely is not so uncomfortable as to be willing to take the bitter potion
by itself. Similarly, the potential Epicurean may be attracted to the Epicu¬
rean doctrine only because of the sweetness of Lucretius’ poetry, or he may
be attracted by it because he suffers from the terrors of religion; surely
those terrors are not so great as to make him willing to swallow the naked
truth. After all, he does not live in the age in which Agamemnon sacrificed
his beloved daughter. We conclude that poetry is the link or the mediation
between religion and philosophy.
How can religion be more attractive than philosophy if religion is noth¬
ing but terrifying? To answer this question, one must reconsider what the
poet says at the beginning in the light of what he says later on how men
lived before the emergence of philosophy; one must consider the function
of religion. Originally men lived like wild beasts, depending entirely on the
spontaneous gifts of the earth, without fire and the arts as well as without
laws and language, unable to conceive of a common good. They feared
death because they clung to the sweet light of life, but apparently not be¬
cause they feared what might happen to them after death. Nor did they
fear that the sun might not rise again after it had set; the thought that sun
and earth might be destructible had not occurred to them.12 That thought
occurred to them only after they had acquired language and the arts and
established society and laws; then they began to doubt whether the sun
would always rise and set and whether the earth would last forever:
Notes on Lucretius / 85
whether the world would come to an end and hence whether it did not
have a beginning. There is only one protection against the fear that the
walls of the world will someday crumble: the will of gods. Religion thus
serves as a refuge from the fear of the end or the death of the world; it has
its root in man s attachment to the world. Lucretius himself wishes, not to
say prays, that the day on which the huge machine of the world will fall
down with a dreadful sound will not come soon. The world to which man
is attached is not the boundless whole but the visible whole—heaven and
earth and what belongs to them—which is only an infinitesimal part of the
boundless whole: there are infinitely many worlds both simultaneously and
successively; everything to which a man can be attached—his life, his
friends, his fatherland, his fame, his work—implies attachment to the
world to which he belongs and which makes possible the primary objects of
his attachment.13 The recourse to the gods of religion and the fear of
them is already a remedy for a more fundamental pain: the pain stemming
from the divination that the lovable is not sempiternal or that the sempi¬
ternal is not lovable. Philosophy transforms the divination into a certainty.
One may therefore say that philosophy is productive of the deepest pain.
Man has to choose between peace of mind deriving from a pleasing delu¬
sion and peace of mind deriving from the unpleasing truth. Philosophy
which, anticipating the collapse of the walls of the world, breaks through
the walls of the world, abandons the attachment to the world; this aban¬
donment is most painful. Poetry on the other hand is, like religion, rooted
in that attachment, but unlike religion, it can be put into the service of
detachment. Because poetry is rooted in the prephilosophic attachment,
because it enhances and deepens that attachment, the philosophic poet is
the perfect mediator between the attachment to the world and the attach¬
ment to detachment from the world. The joy or pleasure which Lucretius’
poem arouses is therefore austere, reminding of the pleasure aroused by the
work of Thucydides.14
In giving an account of things “we” refer them to the first bodies (I 59).
The first bodies are not immediately known; they become known only
through an ascent (or descent). Prior to the ascent people render an
account of things, or at least of many things, by tracing them to gods.
What we have indicated regarding the first stage of the ascent can be
stated in general terms as follows. Primarily men are under the spell of
ancestral opinion; they act on the assumption that the true and the good is
the ancestral. A flexible man who by traveling has become aware of the
thought of many peoples will have become doubtful of the equation of the
true and good with the ancestral. Yet since all peoples trace at least some
86 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
things to gods, he will still believe in active gods. The second stage of the
ascent consists then in an insight which cannot be acquired by traveling,
but only while sitting or standing still; it is the realization that activity is
incompatible with the bliss of gods. For some reason Lucretius does not
use this theological insight at the beginning of his exposition of the truth.
Lucretius opens his account of nature with the assertion that nothing
ever comes into being out of nothing through gods. He thus opposes the
opinion of “all mortals” who trace to gods the numerous happenings of
which they cannot see the causes. He does not establish the principle that
nothing happens without a cause; all men take that principle for granted as
they take it for granted that there are things. The question concerns exclu¬
sively the causality of gods, or, more precisely, the question is exclusively
whether one is entitled to identify the invisible causes with the gods. To
refute the opinion primarily held by all mortals, he will show that nothing
ever comes into being out of nothing; by showing this he shows that noth¬
ing ever comes into being out of nothing through gods. He seems to dis¬
miss without argument the possibility that the gods create things from
something: is coming into being through gods the same as coming into
being through nothing? He cannot be said to presuppose the true view of
the gods according to which activity is incompatible with their bliss, for, as
we have seen, the verses in the proem (44-49) which intimate this view
do not in their context exclude the possibility that the self-sufficient gods
bestow their favors from kindness or whim, without any effort, as it were
playfully, on beings which are not self-sufficient. Lucretius says that when
we have seen that nothing can be created out of nothing, we shall under¬
stand whence each thing can be created and how all things come to be
without the labor of gods: he will prove that all things come into being
from something in such a way that there is no room for any divine activity
or interference (149-158); this proof makes unnecessary the inference
from the gods’ bliss; it makes unnecessary the assertion of the gods’ bliss.
Lucretius establishes the view that nothing can come into being out of
nothing as follows. If things could come into being out of nothing, they
could a fortiori come into being out of anything: things of every kind could
come into being out of things of every other kind; at any season, suddenly,
they could be born full-grown; their coming into being would not require
the fulfillment of any specific conditions; the various kinds of things would
not have peculiar sizes and powers; human art would not have any rhyme
or reason. As it is, however, it is manifest that things come into being from
fixed seeds and the like; hence, they cannot come into being out of noth¬
ing (159-214). Lucretius achieves the transition from “they do not” to
“they cannot” by starting from this disjunction: things come into be¬
ing either from nothing (or anything) or else from fixed seeds; but they
come into being only from fixed seeds; hence they cannot come into
being from nothing. One could say that his argument is defective because
Notes on Lucretius / 87
he gives only a few examples; he would probably ask the objector to pro¬
duce a single example of coming into being out of nothing or even of
metamorphoses which are not natural processes, for such metamorphoses
would be in the decisive respect emergences out of nothing. Still, his selec¬
tion of examples is in need of an explanation.
All examples adduced by him in support of the six arguments which are
meant to prove that nothing comes into being out of nothing are taken
from animals and plants. In the fifth argument he uses as sole example the
size and power of men; he could as well have chosen the size and power of
lions, cows, or mice; he chooses man in order to prepare the transition
from natural beings15 to art. But why does he limit his choice in the
whole passage to living beings (animals and plants)? 16 Let us consider the
context or rather the immediate sequel. After having proved that nothing
comes into being out of nothing, he proves in four arguments that nothing
perishes into nothing (215-264); the examples by which he supports these
arguments are taken from animate and inanimate things (such as earth
and sea) alike. Furthermore, he now speaks of Venus as well as of Father
Ether and Mother Earth; no reference of this kind had occurred in his
speech about coming into being. Finally, the second half of the fundamen¬
tal reasoning is adorned by the sketch of a pleasing rural spectacle, a sketch
which fills one-third of the fourth argument; there is no parallel to this in
the first half. We suggest this explanation. In the first half Lucretius deals
with birth, and in the second he deals with death. Birth is more pleasing,
more beautiful, than death. One way of mitigating or concealing the repul¬
sive is by generalization: inanimate things perish, but do not die. The poet
speaks of Venus in that argument in which he speaks of what time re¬
moves through old age and what is brought back in a manner by Venus:
Venus compensates and comforts for death; it is indeed no longer possible
to speak of Venus as the sole ruler of the nature of things (21). The poet
speaks of Father Ether and Mother Earth, and he draws a pleasing picture
in the argument in which he speaks of the consequences of a certain “pass¬
ing away, namely, the passing away of rain; these consequences are alto¬
gether exhilarating: a rich vegetation which nourishes the animals and
which renders possible the generation of offspring and the healthy growth
of the young animals. Death—be it only the death of rain—loses its sting if
it is seen to lead to life or to the only possible eternity. We have not yet
learned that there will be an end of the cycle of births and deaths on our
earth. At any rate, in presenting his fundamental reasoning Lucretius fol¬
lows the rule that the sweet must precede the sad and that the sad must be
sweetened.
Lucretius fears that his addressee or reader might “begin” to distrust
what he is told since the causes to which he is led (the eternal and inde¬
structible first bodies) are invisible; his teacher reminds him therefore of
invisible bodies of which he cannot help admitting that they are. His first
88 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
the second occurring in the poem, the first being the comparison of devas¬
tating storms to devastating floods (280-290).
There is no nature, nothing self-subsisting, apart from bodies and the
void; for whatever is by itself must either be susceptible of being sensed by
the common sense” (or, perhaps more precisely, it must touch and be
touched), and then it is body, or it cannot be touched, and then it is the
void; or, whatever is by itself is either able to act and to be acted upon, and
then it is body, or it is that within which or through which acting and
being acted upon take place, and then it is the void (418-448). What is,
but is not by itself, is either the property of a body or the void, that is,
cannot be separated from the body in question or the void without the
body in question or the void being destroyed, or it is an accident of body or
of the void. Among the examples of properties which Lucretius gives there
is none that is peculiar to man and even to living beings; but the examples
which he gives of accidents are all peculiar to men: “the human things”
are all accidents. He mentions slavery and freedom, poverty and wealth,
war and peace. He does not mention life, for it is a property of living
beings. He throws no light on the status of death. Regarding time, he
makes clear that it is not self-subsisting. Past events—his examples are
Paris desire for Helen, the rape of Helen, the Greeks’ nocturnal conquest
of Troy with the help of the wooden horse, and their destruction of
Troy were accidents of the human beings in question; they are now as
little as those human beings themselves are (449—482). The poem opens
with a presentation of Venus as the life-giving goddess who bends Mars to
her will. The present examples correct that presentation. Paris was the
favorite of Venus then, just as Memmius is her favorite now. Paris brought
about the ruin of his city or the victory of the Greeks; Memmius is to con¬
tribute to the victory of Greek wisdom in Rome. Could Lucretius’ poem
be comparable to the Trojan horse? This much is certain: the whole
dimension of things Greek and Roman qua Greek and Roman is a small
part of the sphere of accidents. We are at the opposite pole of the thought,
stated in the proem, that the Romans and only the Romans are akin to
that deity who is the only guide of the nature of things.
Lucretius proceeds to show that the first bodies whose character he has
left hitherto undetermined are atoms. They are absolutely solid, that is,
they do not include any void, and hence are eternal and indestructible,
whereas all other bodies are perishable: everything we see is more quickly
destroyed than built up, as the poet here observes in passing (556-557).
The atoms are indivisible; the fact that there is a limit to the division of
bodies is at the bottom of every finiteness and fixedness such as the specific
limitations of the growth and the life span of the various kinds of living
beings and of what each kind can and cannot do by virtue of the “cove¬
nants or laws’ of nature (551-598). Finiteness is meant to be a source
of comfort.17 In accordance with this Lucretius does not yet make clear
90 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
mentioned by name—were great men since they found many things di¬
vinely, in a more holy manner, and by a much more certain reasoning than
Apollo s Pythia ever does (734-739). In accordance with this he does not
criticize Heraclitus, Empedocles, and Anaxagoras on the ground that their
doctrines support or do not destroy the terrors of religion. To wonder how
this can be reconciled with what we know through the fragments especially
of Empedocles means to wonder how Lucretius read Empedocles but one
cannot begin to study how Lucretius read Empedocles before one knows
how Lucretius wrote. We have seen earlier that according to Lucretius one
can overcome the terrors of religion without becoming an Epicurean Per¬
haps his amazing silence about Plato and Aristotle (as distinguished from
Heraclitus, Empedocles, and Anaxagoras) signifies that they are not help¬
ful in the fight against religion.
The central argument of Lucretius against all nonatomists is this: all
things which we perceive are changeable and hence perishable bodies;
hence the indestructible first bodies cannot be perceptible; but the four
elements (fire, earth, water, air) and the characteristics of the homo-
eomeria (bones, flesh, blood, gold, earth, fire, water, and so on) are per¬
ceptible. In other words, the first bodies must have a different nature from
that of “the things”; they must have a secret and unseen nature; only if the
nature of the first things differs from that of “the things” can the character
of the things” as changeable and perishable be preserved.23 There re¬
mains the difficulty not discussed by Lucretius that size and shape-
characters of both the atoms and the things—are as such sensible and
hence destructible. Be this as it may, Lucretius does not say that the alter¬
natives to atomism must be rejected because they favor religion and its
terrors; his objection to them is purely theoretical; but by making
Memmius defend them in direct speech,24 the poet presents him as mak
ing a last-ditch stand in defense of the ultimate dignity of “the things ”
“the world,” “the walls of the world,” after he has failed to rise in defense
of Romanism. But Memmius succumbs to Lucretius’ powerful assault.
This is the situation in which the poet, taking breath, speaks about his
art and its function by comparing himself to a physician who has to give a
bitter potion to children and deceives them for their benefit by sweetening
the repulsive drink. He speaks about what he is doing after he has been
doing it, and after the reader has been exposed to it, for a considerable
time. The critique of the nonatomistic doctrines has in fact shown that
atomism is the most bitter or sad of all doctrines; the completion of that
critique is therefore a kind of climax, surely a place for rest and reflection
The poet introduces the verses which deal with his art and its function by
proudly proclaiming the novelty of his undertaking: he is the first to write
a poem openly devoted to the liberation of the mind from the bonds of
religion, and he wishes to be the first; he is spurred by a great hope of
praise; he goes so far as to say that that great hope has made him love the
92 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
inflicting blows on the worlds from outside. The examples which Lucretius
gives of the things that are created by the mindless meeting of the mind¬
less atoms and that could not last for ever so short a time if the atoms were
not replaced constantly from without are the sea, the earth, the sky, the
race of mortals, and the sacred bodies of the gods (1014-1016). The gods
are then not strictly speaking self-sufficient. The context (1019-1020,
1027-1031) suggests that the gods have come into being like all things
other than the atoms and the void. The gods being created by the atoms in
the same manner as the world (heaven and earth and what belongs to
them) or the worlds, one cannot resort to the gods for assurance that the
world is everlasting. It is perhaps more important to note that Lucretius
still fails to make clear that the human race or the world will not last for¬
ever; since he mentions the human race together not only with heaven and
earth but with the gods as well, he would have seemed to deny the imper¬
ishability of the gods by asserting the perishability of the world. This is to
say nothing of the fact that if the worlds are perishable, it is hard to see
how the intermundia—the places where the gods are asserted to live in eter¬
nal security—can be imperishable.
Lucretius does not fear that these or similar implications might induce
Memmius to rebel against the doctrine of infinity. He fears that Memmius,
whom he now addresses by name for the second time,27 might be attracted
by the view of “some” according to which the stability of the world is
brought about, not by any blows by atoms from the outside, but by the
desire of everything for the center of the world. There cannot be a center
of the world, that is, of the universe, if the universe is infinite (1052—
1082). What makes this view attractive would seem to be the horror in-
finiti or, perhaps more precisely, man’s need for regarding himself and his
world as the center of the universe. In trying to reduce that view ad ab-
surdum, Lucretius points out that, as a consequence of its implications, the
whole world would perish, that is, nothing would remain but space and the
atoms (1083-1113): he does not say here that this is the inevitable fate of
the world precisely on the basis of Epicureanism; he does not say here that
the gate of death is not shut on the world.28
III. On Book II
The First Book opens with the praise of Venus as both the ancestress of
the Romans and the sole guide of the nature of things; the Second Book
opens with a praise of that life of man as man which is in accordance with
nature. Nature calls for nothing but that the body be free from pain and
that the mind, freed from care and fear, enjoy pleasure. Bodily nature can
be gratified at little cost; it does not require luxury, wealth, noble birth, or
regal power. Nor are things of this kind needed or useful for the well-being
94 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
of the mind. What the mind needs is freedom from the terrors of religion
and from fear of death—evils which are removed, not by political and mili¬
tary power,29 but only by reason; reason alone, the study of nature, can
give man tranquillity of mind (14-61). Nature and the study of nature
are the sole sources of happiness.
In the first thirteen verses Lucretius speaks of a great boon about which
he is silent in the rest of the proem; we must not forget that gratification
while listening to his description of human happiness. It is sweet or gratify¬
ing, he says, to behold others in the grip of evils from which oneself is free.
He gives three examples: the man on land who sees another struggling in
the wind-tossed sea, the man in safety who watches armies in battle, and
the pupil of wise men who from his heights looks down on the unwise
struggling for superiority with one another. Of these spectacles the last is
the most gratifying; in fact it is second to nothing else in sweetness. Lucre¬
tius does not speak of a man in bodily health who sees others suffering from
disease. He says that it is not the distress of others which is pleasant, but
only the beholding of evils from which one is free. Yet he does not speak
of evils from which oneself has suffered before, for one cannot strictly
speaking behold those evils; hence one must admit that our pleasure or
happiness is enhanced by our seeing the pains and dangers of others. The
sad is necessary as a foil for the sweet, for sensing the sweet. Does the gods’
supreme happiness—their complete freedom from pain and danger (I
47)—require that they behold the misery of men? Is it desirable or even
possible that all men should be happy, that is, philosophers? We have seen
how much Lucretius is concerned with receiving praise for being the first,
with superiority: his happiness requires the inferiority of others. We can¬
not say whether he regards this kind of pleasure as natural, for he speaks of
nature only afterward (II 17, 20, 23). Certainly nature will not be the
source of happiness if it is not also the source of unhappiness. Man’s hap¬
piness requires that he be free from “the blind night” in which he finds
himself prior to philosophy; yet philosophy discovers the roots of all things
in empty space and the “blind” atoms (I 1110, 1115-1116).30 Nothing is
more alien to wisdom than that with which wisdom is above everything
else concerned: the atoms and the void. The first things are in no way a
model for man.
Lucretius turns at once to the questions concerning the movement by
which the atoms generate the various things and dissolve them again, con¬
cerning the force which compels them to do this, and concerning the speed
with which they move in the void. He asks for the reader’s attention in a
commanding tone. That the atoms are in motion is shown by the fact that
“we” see that “all” things decay and disappear and other things of the
same kind take their place (II 62-79). Lucretius obviously thinks, not of
the sun and the species of animals, but of individual animals and nations.
While he now mentions destruction first, he sees it only as a stage in the
Notes on Lucretius / 95
cycle through which the sum of things [the present world] always renews
itself.”31 Nor does he mention death. He goes on to show how the atoms,
moving in the boundless void, never come to rest, how some of them
colliding with one another either bounce back or unite with one another,
how by uniting in different ways they produce different kinds of things. He
illustrates the process by an explicit likeness and image: the movement of
minute bodies in the sun’s rays when those rays enter a dark room; those
bodies mingle in many ways and, as it were having formed troops, engage
in everlasting battle. It goes without saying that the atoms’ clashes do not
take place in the light of the sun; the likeness sweetens the likened. The
clashes of the atoms are fights in the dark, blind fights of blind atoms,
blind blows which the blind atoms inflict on one another (80-141). The
fundamental movements resemble less the deeds of Venus than those of
Mars.32 We see once more how one-sided, how misleading is the invoca¬
tion of Venus at the beginning of the work despite or because of its neces¬
sity. We also see how appropriate it is that the central example at the be¬
ginning of Book II is a man not engaged in fighting who watches
fighting.
Lucretius underlines the importance of his general characterization of
the atomic movements by what he does immediately afterward. Both near
the beginning of the next section (142-183) and near its end he addresses
Memmius by name. He has addressed him by name twice in Book I (411,
1052). The section thus distinguished consists of two parts. The first part
is devoted to the speed with which the atoms move in the void. How great
that speed is one can gather by considering the speed with which the light
of the sun travels; since it does not travel in the void, the speed of the
atomic motions must be much, much greater than the speed of the light of
the sun. The poet stresses the contrast between the movement of the sun’s
light and that of the atoms by alluding to the birds’ celebration of sunrise.
It is reasonable to think that it is the enormous speed with which the
atoms travel that accounts for the full fury and violence of their clashes; it
is then that fury and violence which contributes to, or rather accounts for,
the emergence of the “things.” According to the diametrically opposite
view the world is the work of the greatest awakeness, circumspection, and
care. It is this view against which Lucretius turns in the second part of the
section. According to “some,” 33 we are told, only beings of superhuman
wisdom and power, only gods, can have formed the world out of matter,
atomic or nonatomic: only through the activity of gods can the world
possess that perfect harmony with the needs of man which it is seen to
possess; only in this way can it be understood that nature prevents the
death of the human race by inducing men through divine pleasure,
through the deeds of Venus, to generate offspring—this wonderful har¬
mony between the individual’s sweetest pleasure and the most common
good. Lucretius rejects this view as utterly false. The reason is not that he
96 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
is an Epicurean: even if he did not know what the origins of the things are,
that is, if he did not know that they are the atoms and the void, he would
dare to assert from the very manner of working of heaven as well as from
many other things that the nature of the world is not created for our bene¬
fit by divine power; by nature the world abounds in defects (167-182).
Not wise gods or gods of wisdom, not even Venus, are at the helm or are
the originators; at the origin there is the fury and violence of the blind
atoms’ blind fights. There is a radical disharmony between the atomic
movements and even the rationes caeli on the one hand and the rationes
humanae or the rationes vitae on the other.34 The theological view tries to
establish a harmony between the rationes caeli and the rationes humanae-,
it wishes to be comforting. Lucretius fights religion less on account of its
terrors and crimes than of the defective character of the world; he does not
fight religion primarily because he holds Epicureanism and in particular
Epicurean theology to be true. What the poet tacitly suggested at the be¬
ginning of his argument (see pages 85-86 above) he now says almost ex¬
plicitly: there is no need for recourse to the fundamental theologoumenon
in order to refute the theological account. It goes without saying that the
realization of the badness of the world does not induce Lucretius for a
moment to think of rebellion or conquest: misery is as necessary to human
life as happiness.
Lucretius continues his account of the atomic movements by showing
first that the atoms move downward and then that they swerve. The atoms
are of different weight, but in the void they all fall with equal speed; they
would never clash and thus bring about the emergence of compounds but
for the fact that they spontaneously swerve a little at times and in places
which are in no way fixed: the movement after the swerve does not in a
fixed manner arise from the movement before it. Atoms are so little attrac¬
tive that they do not even attract one another. The alternative to the
swerve would be that everything is determined by fate, and this is incom¬
patible with the freedom with which every living being on earth follows
“the will of [its] mind,” that is, where pleasure leads it, or originates
motion (216-293). When Epicurus takes issue with the physicists who
assert that everything is determined by fate or necessity, he says that the
belief in fate is worse than the belief in the tale of the gods since fate is
inexorable, whereas the gods of the tale are not.35 Lucretius does not fol¬
low his master in this point. His statement on the swerve of the atoms does
not read as if it were directed against any school of thought (cf. 225). He
does not wish to present the Epicurean teaching as pleasing or comforting,
as more pleasing and comforting than other teachings set forth by students
of nature. The doctrine of the swerve as Lucretius presents it is not meant
to bring the rationes of the atoms into harmony with the rationes
humanae. A sign of this is that the “freedom” which he tries to vindicate
by that doctrine is not peculiar to man, but is common to all animals.
Notes on Lucretius / 97
The swerve of the atoms might cast doubt on the fixedness of the natu¬
ral order. To dispel that doubt Lucretius asserts that while the atoms are
always in motion, the universe is in a sense at rest. No atom comes into
being or perishes, nor do the kinds of their movements change, hence also
not the outcome of those movements, that is, the production of the things
of various kinds. Lucretius is again silent about the destruction of the kinds
of things or of the world. The fact that the whole is seen to be at rest while
all its parts are in motion is strange. To remove that strangeness, Lucretius
adduces two gratifying (“white” or “glimmering”) examples: a herd of
grazing sheep and their lambs running around on a faraway hill, and mili¬
tary units engaged in a war game—not in war proper—on a plain as seen
from high mountains (299-332).
There are infinitely many things and infinitely many atoms. Yet the
things are related to the atoms as the infinitely many words or combina¬
tions of words are to the small numbers of letters (cf. I 823-829): the infi¬
nitely many atoms fall into classes of which there are not infinitely many.
Lucretius starts from the infinitely many natural things, both animate and
inanimate, each of which differs in shape from the others of its kind He
speaks at the greatest length of animals, especially of the fact that a mother
can tell its offspring from any other young animal of its kind and the off¬
spring its mother, and still more especially of the sad spectacle of a cow
vainly seeking its calf which has been slaughtered before the altars of the
gods. He thus prepares the reader for the detailed discussion (in II 398 ff.)
of the atomic causes of the painful things on the one hand and of the pleas¬
ant on the other. He infers from the infinite variety of shapes of things
that there must be a great variety of shapes of atoms: uniformity is the
outcome of purposeful action, of human production that is guided by a
single model (because it is guided by a single end), rather than of nature
The variety of atomic shapes is shown in a more precise
manner especially by the different ways in which different things affect us
with pleasure or pain; pleasure and pain are due to the different shapes of
atoms. Lucretius is thus led to exclaim that “touch, yea touch, o holy maj¬
esties of the gods, is the sense of body” (434-435). The reference here to
the gods needs an explanation. The poet had spoken earlier (I 1015) of
the holy bodies of the gods” (cf. I 38). In the present context he men¬
tions a deity by name. He speaks of the pleasant feelings which go with the
discharge of the semen bom in the body” “through the generative acts of
Venus ; he does not yet refer to a deity when speaking in the same context
of feelings of pain (II 435-439). The reference to Venus barely reminds
us of the praise of Venus as “the joy of men and gods” at the beginning of
the poem; we are more than sufficiently prepared for any weakening of that
praise (cf. 172-173). Can we still believe that the gods enjoy the deeds of
Venus? Above all, only twenty-five verses later Lucretius speaks of the
bitter or nauseous body of Neptune, that is, of sea water—of the body of a
98 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
god which can be dissolved into its ingredients even by human means
(471-477). Certain it is that our awareness of the gods must be under¬
stood in the last analysis in terms of our sense of touch.
One cannot help wondering regarding the size and shape especially of
those atoms which compose the bodies of the gods. We learn from Lucre¬
tius that the number of atomic shapes or forms is limited, that the sizes of
the atoms keep within unchangeable and rather narrow bounds, and that
therefore there cannot be atoms of gigantic, not to say boundless, size. Sim¬
ilarly, none of the things created by the clash of atoms can surpass others
of those things infinitely in beauty and splendor.36 What this means re¬
garding the gods is obvious. On the other hand, as we hear again, there are
infinitely many atoms of each form. This is compatible with the fact that
there are many fewer individuals of some kinds of things than of others.
Even if there were a terrestrial species of which there is only one individ¬
ual, infinitely many atoms of the appropriate shapes would be needed so
that that individual could be formed and preserved, given the fact that the
atoms move in what the poet now calls that vast and faithless sea. In fact,
the movement of the atoms in the infinite void is comparable to that of
the parts of a wrecked ship in the sea: as little as those parts, which are
small in number, could ever be put together again through being tossed
hither and thither by the waves, so little could atoms of a finite number
ever be brought together and kept together to form a thing (522-568). All
the terrors of the ocean, which after all has limits, are as nothing compared
with the terrors of the void. Infinity achieves what wise gods could not
have achieved: the production of a world of very deficient goodness. In
particular, the balance between birth and death is due to the war which
the atoms carry on with one another from infinite time. This balance is
least perfect in the case of man with whom wise gods would be especially
concerned: man begins his life crying, and laments accompany him to his
grave.37
Lucretius is still silent about the death of the world—about the death of
the species as distinguished from the death of individuals. He goes on to
speak about the atomic composition of the earth without drawing the ob¬
vious conclusion that, being a compound, the earth is bound to perish
sooner or later. He starts from the facts that nothing whose nature is mani¬
festly seen consists only of one kind of atom and that the larger the
number of powers a thing possesses within itself, the larger the number of
kinds of atoms of which it will consist. The earth possesses within itself the
greatest variety of powers; it gives rise to water, fire, and vegetation and it
sustains man as well as wild beasts. Hence the earth alone has been called
the Great Mother of the gods, of the wild beasts, and of our body (581-
599).38 Lucretius draws our attention to beings whose nature is not mani¬
festly seen and which may consist of one kind of atoms only; one wonders
whether the gods are beings of that kind, although (or because) this would
Notes on Lucretius / 99
imply that the gods are the least powerful beings in the universe. The
sequel surely suggests that the earth has much greater powers, or at least a
much larger number of powers, than the gods and that the gods are terres¬
trial beings. At any rate, the earth understood as a goddess seems to be the
clearest case of a terrestrial animal species of which there is only one mem¬
ber (cf. 541-543).
Of all these questions Lucretius answers immediately and explicitly only
one; he denies the divinity of the earth. He prefaces this denial with a
rather detailed description of the terror-inspiring, savage, and exotic proces¬
sion of the Great Mother. That procession had been described by the an¬
cient and learned poets of the Greeks who explained the meaning of its
various features. Lucretius mentions seven items. The central one is the
fact that the Great Mother is called the Mother of Mount Ida and that
she is given as companions Phrygian bands, because, “as they say ” corn
was first produced in that part of the earth. The Trojans, from whom the
Romans are derived, were Phrygians (I 474), but the Romans owe their
knowledge of the remarkable Phrygian cult in question to the Greeks. It is
in accordance with this that Lucretius traces the growing of corn to Athens
(VI 1-2). The second item conveys encouragement to parents regarding
the education of their children; the fifth conveys a condemnation of, and
severe threat to, people who have violated the majesty of the mother and
have been found ungrateful to their parents.39 The sixth item serves the
purpose of filling with fear the ungrateful minds and the impious hearts of
the multitude through the divine majesty of the goddess; the context leaves
it m doubt whether this goal is achieved. Lucretius himself is doubtful re¬
garding the last feature of the procession which he mentions; it may refer
to the tale told of the salvation of the infant Jupiter from the danger that
his father Saturnus might devour him, to the everlasting grief 40 of the
Great Mother, or it may intimate the goddess' proclaiming that men
should defend their fatherland (their paternal earth) and protect and
adorn their parents (600-643). Lucretius bestows high praise, if not on
the procession itself, at least on the thoughts which the Greek poets found
in some of its features. Yet he rejects those thoughts as quite wrong. His
reason is that the gods are free from all pain and danger and that they are
wholly unconcerned with men, with their merits or crimes (644-651)
We may add that if the gods are bom, they also will die.
The reason stated by Lucretius had been stated by him in the same
words near the beginning of the poem (I 44-49), but the second state¬
ment, despite its being literally identical with the first, has a different
meaning from that of the first. In the first place, the second statement is
much richer in meaning than the first by virtue of what we have learned
from Lucretius m the meantime; above all, the first statement concludes
the invocation of Venus and does not call into question the divinity of
Venus, whereas the second statement concludes the speech on the Great
100 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Mother and is meant to justify the denial of her divinity. Yet the funda¬
mental theologoumenon is not the sole reason why Lucretius denies the
divinity of the Great Mother, or, if you wish, that theologoumenon implies
a verity which the poet has not yet made explicit. The fundamental
theologoumenon articulates the perfection, the happiness of the gods with¬
out making explicit that perfect happiness is not possible without percep¬
tion or feeling. Lucretius denies the divinity of the earth on the ground
that the earth lacks perception or feeling at all times (II 652). He thus
makes us wonder whether a being ceases to be a god if it lacks perception
or feeling from time to time as in sleep. Be this as it may, Lucretius rejects
the deification of the earth (or of the sea, of corn, and of wine) with much
less asperity than he rejects religion in general (655-660). To understand
this, one must compare the present section with its parallels.
The statement on the Great Mother is closely connected with the attack
on the theologico-teleological account of nature in II 165-182. The con¬
nection is indicated by the fact that no explicit polemic occurs between
these two polemical passages. As we have observed, the problem of the
gods is present in the whole discussion between the two passages, that is, in
the discussion of the atomic composition of all things and hence also of the
gods. Lucretius rejects the theologico-teleological account of nature as
wrong, as a theoretical error, without saying anything about its roots in
human life and its effect on it. When he speaks of the deification of the
earth, however, he indicates clearly the function of that error; he thus
throws new light on religion. The terror which the cult of the Great
Mother causes is meant to be salutary. Lucretius does not say that it is not
salutary. Religion thus appears to be a human invention which serves the
purpose of counteracting the indifference of the whole to man’s moral and
political needs, for not all men are or can be philosophers; this is to say
nothing of the question as to whether philosophy, that is, Epicurean phi¬
losophy as Lucretius understood it, enjoins patriotism and gratitude to par¬
ents. The section on the Great Mother also reminds one of the section on
Venus at the beginning of the poem; to say the least, Venus, who is not
mentioned in the section on the Great Mother, is not as obviously a god¬
dess concerned with political morality as is the Great Mother; the unquali¬
fied rejection of religion which follows the invocation of Venus (I 62 ff.) is
therefore less surprising than an unqualified rejection of religion following
the speech on the Great Mother would be. The section on the Great
Mother surely leaves us with the sting of the question as to how the un-
philosophic multitude will conduct itself if it ceases to believe in gods who
punish lack of patriotism and of filial piety. One wonders in particular
what will happen to Memmius’ patriotism or concern with the common
weal (I 41-43) if Lucretius should succeed in converting him to Epicu¬
reanism.
Despite the fact that there is only a limited, if large, number of shapes of
Notes on Lucretius / 101
atoms, their number (and especially the still larger number of combina¬
tions of atoms of various shapes) is sufficient to account for the enormous
variety of the things which are produced by the atoms. Yet not every
combination which one might imagine is possible; there are no monsters
like Chimaeras, for instance. Lucretius does not speak in this section (II
661-729) of the gods, but the question of the atomic composition of the
gods is present in it since he speaks here of the composition of all species of
living beings: the variety of shapes of atoms must be such as to account for
the fact that “all things” are born of fixed seeds, preserve their kinds, and
are m need of specific food. The application to the conceit of children
stemming from the intercourse of gods and men like Aeneas is obvious.
One might think that the gods are not living beings. The force of this ob¬
jection is destroyed by Lucretius’ declaring that “these laws,” which obtain
regarding the coming into being and the preservation of living beings,
obtain mutatis mutandis regarding inanimate things as well.
Lucretius turns next to the qualities which the atoms lack. They lack
colors, sounds, tastes, smells, as well as hot and cold. All these qualities are
changeable and perishable and cannot therefore belong to the unchange¬
able and imperishable atoms (749-756, 862-864). The exposition of this
doctrine continues and deepens the critique of the nonatomistic doctrines
which was presented in Book I, but the poet no longer engages in explicit
polemics against actual or potential opponents: there is no longer any sign
of resistance on the part of Memmius. The discussion of colors is far more
extensive than that of all the other qualities in question taken together; in
the case of colors the contrast between the things and the atoms is particu-
(a795S798)ng: n° COl°rS With°Ut Hght’ and the atoms exist in blind darkness
Ibe next step requires a somewhat greater effort.41 The reader must
now be brought to admit that the atoms, which are the origins of all living
beings, lack sense or feeling—are lifeless. That animate beings emerge
under certain conditions out of inanimate ones is shown by experience:
worms emerge from stinking dung. In this context the poet remarks that
just as inanimate things (of a not noisome character) serve as food for cat¬
tle and thus change into cattle, and the cattle into human bodies, our
bodies frequently serve as food for wild beasts and birds (871-878)/It is
not clear whether he refers here to wild beasts and birds killing men or
merely, as is more likely, to their feeding on human corpses.42 The atoms
must be lifeless in order to be deathless: to be a living being and to be
mortal is the same (919). The teaching according to which the causes of
all things are lifeless is sweetened to some extent in the verses with which
the poet ends his speech about the qualities which the atoms lack. He
draws the somewhat unexpected conclusion that we all are of heavenly
origin: we all—plants, men, and wild beasts—owe our being to the rain
which is sent down from the regions of the ether and which fertilizes the
102 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
earth. Ether is our common father, and Earth is our common mother.
Lucretius shows that the earth is deservedly called mother: thanks to the
earth, the wild beasts, to say nothing of human beings, feed their bodies,
pass a sweet life, and propagate their kinds; he does not show that heaven
is deservedly called father (991-1001). When we compare these verses
with the Euripidean verses of which they remind us,43 we see that Lucre¬
tius does not, as Euripides does, call Ether the progenitor of men and gods
in contradistinction to the Earth who gives birth to the mortals: through¬
out his poem Lucretius puts a stronger emphasis on Earth than on Ether
because he does not wish to speak explicitly of the origin of the gods. As
father and mother, Ether and Earth would be living beings, hence mortal;
hence they could not be the ultimate origins of “us all”: the ultimate
origin is matter, that is, the atoms; not Ether and Earth, but the atoms are
the origins of everything, as Lucretius states again in the immediate sequel
in which he ascribes to heaven and earth no higher status than to the sea,
the rivers, the sun, the crops, the trees, and living beings (1002-1022). In
his earlier speech on Mother Earth he had made clear that the earth,
which lacks sense or feeling, is not a divine being (641-652). But the same
is true of the ether.44 If heaven and earth were gods, the things brought
forth by them would not be as defective as they are (180-181). In other
words, the world, nay, the boundless whole, grounded in nothing but the
atoms and the void, is not divine. Only some parts of the whole can possi¬
bly be divine: the gods. Whatever Lucretius’ doctrine of the gods may
mean, it surely means that the whole or the world is not divine.45
The last section of Book II deals, like the last section of Book I, with the
infinity of the whole. Accordingly, it is introduced by a statement (1023-
1047) which is comparable to the “wormwood and honey” passage in Book
I (921-950). In both introductions the poet speaks of a special effort
which the reader must make in order to understand the immediate sequel.
In all other respects the two introductions differ profoundly. In the second
introduction the poet mentions the subject which he is about to discuss,
whereas he had failed to do this in the first one. In the first introduction he
had spoken of his innovation through which the harsh doctrine will be
sweetened; he had spoken of a gratifying novelty without speaking of the
novelty of the doctrine. Now he speaks of the novelty of the doctrine to be
set forth, a repulsive novelty. Novelty as such, we are told, is disconcerting;
a doctrine may even be frightening merely because it is new and as long as
it is new. Lucretius urges the addressee not to reject the doctrine to be
expounded merely because he is frightened by its novelty; he ought to
examine it and accept it if it appears to him to be true or reject it if it is
false. He seems to be less concerned with making him an Epicurean than
with liberating him from fear of the new as new.46 He creates the impres¬
sion that the doctrine to be expounded can be repulsive only because it is
Notes on Lucretius / 103
knows this better than the aged plowman who can compare the present
with the past and who sees the decay of the soil going hand in hand with
the decay of piety: the latifundia have ruined Italy; everything passes to
the grave (1105-1174). What every old peasant knows to some extent
cannot be frightening because of its novelty. By generalizing the observa¬
tions of old peasants about the decay of agriculture and piety into the doc¬
trine of the decay of the world, Lucretius may even be said to sweeten the
sad doctrine in accordance with the feelings of the true Roman: the decay
or end of Rome is the decay or end of the world. When he repeats the
doctrine of the future destruction of the world at much greater length later
on, in a more advanced stage of Memmius’ education, Lucretius takes away
this scaffolding: in his opinion our world is still in its youth (V 330-337).
The decay of Italian agriculture and piety does not announce the speedy
end of the world. Lucretius does not deny that piety and Italian agriculture
are no longer what they were; but surely some of the arts are still progress¬
ing; philosophy is of recent origin, and it enters Rome only now, through
Lucretius’ poem.
This Book is the only one in which the poet addresses Epicurus. He does
this in the proem (1-30) and nowhere else. It is also the only Book in which
he mentions the name of Epicurus (1042): he never addresses Epicurus by
name. One may say that throughout the work Epicurus remains the name¬
less Graius homo (I 66), or rather the nameless “glory of the Greek race”
(III 3), if not a nameless god (V 8). In the present proem Lucretius apos¬
trophizes Epicurus with the vocative inclute (I 10); in the proem to
Book I he has apostrophized Venus in the same way (40), and in the
proem to Book V he will do the same to Memmius (8); the movement
from Venus to Epicurus is an ascent, and the movement from Epicurus to
Memmius is a descent; the whole movement is an ascent followed by a de¬
scent. If one counts I 925-950 as the second proem,49 the proem to Book
III will be the central proem. The peak is in the center.
The praise of Epicurus at the beginning of Book III serves in the first
place the purpose of bringing out the difference of rank between Epicurus
and Lucretius. Lucretius is a follower, an imitator of Epicurus; he could as
little rival Epicurus as a swallow could rival swans or kids a horse; as re¬
gards both beauty and force Lucretius’ work belongs to a different species,
to a lower species than Epicurus’ work. Yet “thou art the father, the dis¬
coverer of the things.” Lucretius merely profits from the discovery; Epi¬
curus’ mind is divine, whereas Lucretius receives through the master’s
teaching “some divine pleasure and a dread or horror.” 60 Thanks to Epi-
Notes on Lucretius / 105
curus’ complete discovery of the nature of things, the terrors of the mind
are dispelled and the walls of the world part asunder. Thus the majesty of
the gods comes to sight; they are seen to dwell in tranquil and beautiful
abodes, of which those of the Homeric gods on Olympus give an inkling,
beyond the walls of the worlds; nature is seen to supply the gods with
everything. Whereas Epicurus’ discovery reveals the perfect bliss of the
gods, it reveals the nonexistence of Hades. As for the nonexistence of
Hades, of a miserable life after death, Lucretius is going to prove it in Book
III. He does not say that, and where, he will prove the existence of the
gods. He surely has not proved it before; he merely has proved, or at¬
tempted to prove, that the nature of things does not leave room for divine
action on the world and its ingredients. We observe that nature is said to
supply the gods with everything: nature does not supply men with every¬
thing.
In order to drive out the fear of Hades which utterly confounds human
life and spoils all pleasures, Lucretius will lay bare the nature of the soul on
the basis of the principles set forth in the first two Books. Men frequently
say that there are things worse than hell and that they know the nature of
the soul without having engaged in studies, so that they do not need Epi¬
curean philosophy. But this is an idle boast. As soon as they have com¬
mitted a crime and as a consequence suffered the disgrace of which they
formerly said that it is worse than death, they cling to life and sacrifice to
the dead and the gods of the dead, that is, turn to religion (31-58).
Lucretius did not take issue with people who deny that they need Epicu¬
rean philosophy in order to get rid of fear of the gods: common experience
seems to show that one fate befalls the just and the unjust, or that the gods
do not rule the human race; but this does not exclude the possibility that
the fates of the just and the unjust will be greatly different after death or
that only through fear of punishment after death does the fear of the gods
reach its full power. Memmius at any rate seems to be more threatened by
fear of hell than by fear of the gods as such (page 80 above).
Lucretius speaks with special emphasis of the criminals’ religious fear.
He thus makes us wonder again whether by attempting to take away that
fear he does not weaken a salutary restraint. He answers this objection as
well as he can in the immediate sequel. He comes close to suggesting that
the primary phenomenon is not the fear of hell, but the fear of death, and
that crimes which seem to be a cause of the fear of hell are in fact a conse¬
quence of the fear of death (59-86).1B1 That is to say, by freeing men
from the fear of death, one does not emancipate crime from a powerful
restraint; one rather contributes to the abolition of crime. We are left with
the suspicion that prior to Epicurus, and in Rome even prior to Lucretius,
religion served a good purpose. Given the fact that many men, nay, almost
all men, will always refuse to listen to the Epicurean teaching, religion will
always serve a good purpose. Lucretius concludes his statement of the sub-
106 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
ject of Book III with the same seven verses with which in Books II and VI
he concludes the proems as distinguished from the statements of the sub¬
jects of those Books: just as children fear everything in the dark, “we”
sometimes fear in the light things which are no whit more dreadful than
what children tremble at in the dark and imagine that it will happen; this
terror must be dispelled, not by the rays of the sun, but by nature coming
to sight and being penetrated. Book III is the Book devoted to the over¬
coming of “our” childish fear.
Lucretius tells his reader that the soul is a part of man like the hand and
therefore located in a determinate part of the body. It is not, as some
Greeks have asserted, a harmony of the whole body (94-135). It is not
Lucretius’ manner as we have hitherto had occasion to observe it to begin
his presentation of a teaching with polemics against philosophic doctrines.
The polemic against “harmonism” is firm, but free from harshness or sar¬
casm: harmonism is as good for establishing the mortality of the soul as
Epicureanism; 62 it is the first doctrine explicitly discussed which is rejected
merely because it is wrong and not at the same time with a view to its effect
on man’s feelings. If any doubt were left, the discussion of harmonism
would show that Epicureanism is not needed for liberating the mind from
the terrors of religion.
The soul is a single nature consisting of the animus and the anima. The
animus, or the mind, is located in the breast, is the ruler of the whole
body, and is at the same time that through which we suffer fear, joy, and
the like; the understanding and the passions belong together. The anima is
spread through the whole body and obeys the animus. The distinction is
meant to explain that there is what one may call a particular freedom of
man. The animus alone and by itself can understand and can feel pleasures
and pains which are not pleasures and pains of the body (136-160). Both
parts of the soul must be bodily, as is shown by the fact that they affect our
body and are affected by it, for nothing can affect a body and be affected
by it without touch, and nothing can touch or be touched except body
(161-176). Since the acts of the animus are capable of unrivaled swiftness
and nimbleness, it must consist of very round, very smooth, and very tiny
parts. This insight into the nature of the animus is of very great impor¬
tance, as the poet indicates both explicitly and by addressing the reader in
a unique way (o bone). Things which consist of such parts are more easily
dissolved than things consisting of parts of the opposite description. The
fact that the animus through which we can sense or feel is of such a fine
texture and can be contained in a very small place explains why the con¬
tours and the weight of a man immediately after his death do not differ
from his contours and weight immediately before it. The same fact proves
that the anima too consists of very tiny particles. The poet compares the
soul in this respect to the flavor of wine, or as he puts it here, of Bacchus;
this is the first time that he mentions a god or a pseudo god by name in the
Notes on Lucretius / 107
The section with which Lucretius concludes his exposition of the nature
of the soul consists of three parts. He shows first that the soul cannot be
without the body and vice versa. Body and soul come into being together
and perish together. No sensation or feeling is possible without the co¬
operation of body and soul. It is true that the soul is the immediate cause
of sensing, but it is an error to hold that only the soul senses while using
the body merely as an instrument (323-369). In the central part Lucretius
takes issue with the view of Democritus regarding the local order of the
body atoms and the soul atoms. The treatment of the Democritean doc¬
trine near the end of the discussion of the nature of the soul reminds of
the treatment of harmonism at its beginning: the Democritean doctrine
would not render questionable the mortality of the soul. Lucretius indeed
treats Democritus or his doctrine with much greater respect than har¬
monism; he applies to him or to his doctrine the epithet “sacred”; Democ¬
ritus is the only human being to whom or to whose doctrine he ever ap¬
plies that epithet unqualifiedly;55 he never applies it to Epicurus. He
fails to apply it to Democritus in the central reference to him (III 1037)
where Democritus’ inferiority to Epicurus is clearly brought out. This
throws light on his calling “sacred” the gods’ bodies, their numina, and so
on. Finally, the poet restates the supremacy of the animus over the anima
and the body (396-416). While he is primarily concerned with the
mortality of the soul, he is very much concerned with its being the ruling
part in man, nay, in all living beings. Since he holds the soul to be as cor¬
poreal as the body, he is not compelled to regard the acts of the soul as
mere epiphenomena of the body; he can leave intact the “common-
sensical” distinction between soul and body.
The center of Book III (417-829) is devoted to the proof that the souls
are born and die. That proof consists of a large number of arguments
which are more or less independent of one another. In no other case does
Lucretius devote so many verses and so many arguments to the proof of a
single proposition. One could think that the coming into being and perish¬
ing of the souls is sufficiently established by the fact that they are com¬
pounds of atoms. Yet the gods are also compounds of atoms and never¬
theless supposed to be immortal. It is true that the Epicurean gods do not
live within the world or worlds, while the souls do. But could the souls not
live within the world and then, if they have lived piously here, withdraw to
the intermundia in which the gods dwell, to Islands of the Blessed, as it
were? Lucretius turns therefore to reasonings based on the specific char¬
acters of the soul which, after all, are better known to him than those of
the gods. In introducing these reasonings he reminds us that his verses are
to be worthy of Memmius’ “life” (420) without, however, mentioning
Memmius’ name; he reminds us of his esteem for Memmius. The first ar¬
gument makes clear that the soul is mortal because it is a compound of
particularly small and mobile atoms which are kept together by the body;
Notes on Lucretius / 109
but the body is manifestly mortal. In what looks at first glance like an ex¬
cursus, Lucretius illustrates the mobility of the soul by the ease with which
it is moved through slender causes; it is moved not only by smoke and
clouds but even by images of smoke and clouds; for instance, when asleep
we see high altars breathing steam and sending up their smoke (425-444).
When attempting to prove the mortality of the soul, Lucretius cannot
help presenting to us vividly the sad spectacles of men’s sudden or slow
deaths, of their diseases and decay, although he never comes near to that
accumulation of horrors which he has reserved for the end of his work. He
makes no attempt to sweeten the sad; the sweetening thought is the con¬
sideration, which now indeed remains unexpressed, that death, however
slow and painful, is preferable to the terrors of Hades. This thought re¬
mains so little expressed that Lucretius now uses men’s great unwillingness
to die, their eagerness to clutch at the last tie of life, as a proof of the mor¬
tality of the soul: if our souls were immortal, we would not mind dying
(597-614). However unreasonable the fear of death may be, it seems to
be quite natural.56 We may note some slight signs of resistance on the part
of the addressee,57 but the poet does not engage in explicit polemics
against other schools of thought while proving the mortality of the soul
(425-669); he engages in such polemics while attempting to refute the be¬
lief in the pre-existence of the soul (670 ff.).58 The reason is that he does
not take seriously the belief in the immortality of the soul if it is not ac¬
companied by the belief in its pre-existence: only an eternal soul can be
immortal (cf. 670-673).
The reference to men’s revulsion from death as a proof or sign of the
mortality of the soul occurs shortly before the end of the section that deals
with the soul’s immortality as distinguished from its pre-existence. It is fol¬
lowed by three more arguments in support of mortality. The two last of
these arguments refer in very different ways to hearsay. According to Lu¬
cretius, one cannot assert the immortality of the soul without asserting the
immortality of the five senses and hence of their organs; the painters and
writers of old presented the souls in Acheron as endowed with the senses;
but the senses cannot exist without the whole body (624-633). The im¬
plication is that the painters and writers of old acted more reasonably than
the more recent philosophers who assert the immortality of the soul bereft
of the senses. Lucretius is silent here about the ancient writers’ presenting
the souls as undergoing eternal punishment in Hades (I 111). In the last
argument (634-669) he uses his knowledge through hearsay of the maim¬
ing and killing caused by scythe-bearing chariots. We do not know whether
Memmius had firsthand knowledge of battles in which such chariots were
used; Lucretius surely had not. This is not to deny that the poet may have
observed other kinds of battles from afar (II 5-6).
The antepenultimate argument in support of mortality (615-623) is
repeated and enlarged in the argument that concludes the central part of
110 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Book III (784-829). The thought which Lucretius repeats is that every¬
thing has its place outside of which it cannot be; the mind cannot be in
the shoulders or in the heels, for instance; still less can it be outside the
whole body. He enlarges this thought by the consideration that the eternal
or immortal cannot be linked with the mortal. He then raises the question
as to what kinds of things are immortal and finds that the soul does not
belong to them. He identifies three kinds of immortal things: the atoms,
the void, and the universe. He does not mention the gods. But he compels
us to think of the gods by raising the question as to what kinds of things
are, or can be, immortal. He may allude to the gods by saying that things
may be eternal if there is no place without into which their parts may scat¬
ter or if there are no bodies which could assault them; for this condition
could be thought to be fulfilled in the intermundia in which the gods are
said to dwell. At any rate, the central part of Book III begins and ends with
allusions not so much to the gods as to the problem of the gods.
In the last part of Book III Lucretius draws the practical conclusion
from his proof of the soul’s mortality: death is nothing to us. The conclu¬
sion does not follow from the proof since we naturally recoil from death as
from a very great evil. Lucretius must therefore show in addition that our
revulsion from death is due to a delusion. It could be thought that by lib¬
erating us from this delusion he weakens our concern with preserving our
lives. Besides, the brutes too recoil from death; are they too under the spell
of a delusion? Yet Lucretius both as an atomist and as a human being
knows the power of death or the eagerness with which men cling to “the
sweet light of life” (V 989). He shows that he has considered the objec¬
tions to his thesis by the way in which he concludes the passage under dis¬
cussion; he concludes it by opposing “immortal death” to “mortal life.”
The delusion is said to consist in our believing that we are still alive and
feeling while we no longer are. We can be as little affected by what hap¬
pens after our death as we were affected by what happened before we were
born: we were not affected by the Punic Wars when the rule over all men
was at stake between the Carthaginians and the other side (830-869).
Lucretius opens the last part of Book III with a somewhat subdued reasser¬
tion of Romanism.69 In the same context he touches briefly on the possi¬
bility that the same atomic compound which is a given man was frequently
produced long before his time. He disposes of it by the consideration that
the same atomic compound was not the same man since no memory links
the earlier and the later. He does not speak of the possibility of a return
of the same compound.
Lucretius next shows us a man who pities himself by imagining the ter¬
rible or disgraceful things which will happen to him, that is, to his body,
after his death; that man imagines that he himself can stand by his corpse
and look at it; he imputes to his corpse the feelings which he, a living man,
has (870-893). Lucretius next presents to us living men addressing a man
Notes on Lucretius / 111
who just died, pitying him for what he has lost. They do not add, Lucretius
observes, that the dead man no longer yearns for what he has lost; Lucre¬
tius states in their direct speech what they ought to say to the dead man,
just as he has stated in their direct speech what they do say to him. He
then makes them say to the dead man what they would say if they were to
consider that he is not aware of anything: thou hast no reason to grieve,
but we have reason for everlasting grief. He finds fault with what he makes
them, or rather one of them, say—no one has reason for everlasting grief
—but he does not address this reproach to them; he never speaks to them.
Instead he makes them state another of their untutored speeches, and he
again refutes it without addressing them. At the end of this refutation he
calls death “the chill stopping of life” (894-930). His next action is still
more extraordinary than the one which we just described: he makes the
nature of things speak to any one of us, to whom she applies the vocatives
“thou mortal” and “thou fool” (933, 939). Nature herself is made to pro¬
claim how unreasonable it is to regard death as a great evil, regardless of
whether one has lived hitherto happily or miserably. Lucretius, having
listened together with his reader to Nature’s speech, finds that the only an¬
swer which “we” can give to Nature is that she is right. He then makes
Nature address an oldish man who fears death more than it is just to do;
she naturally deals more harshly with him than with the younger men; she
applies to him the vocative “thou criminal” (955). Having listened to
Nature’s second and last speech, Lucretius finds again that Nature would
be right in making her reproaches. He then gives the reader or addressee
additional reasons why Nature’s verdict and action are sound: the old must
give way to the new; if we look at death in the light of Nature, death ceases
to be terrible. Neither Lucretius nor the addressee or reader speaks to Na¬
ture—which does not mean that Nature does not speak to the addressee.
There is a noteworthy contrast between the central section of the last
part of Book III—the section in which Nature is made to speak and Lucre¬
tius comments on her speeches (931-977)—and the next section, which is
altogether undramatic, that is, in which not even the second person is ever
used (978-1023). The poet speaks now of the terrors of hell, the denial of
which seemed to be the primary reason for denying the possibility of a life
after death; these terrors have proved to be of secondary importance.
While it is true that only through the fear of hell does the fear of the gods
acquire its full power, and hence Memmius is threatened by the fear of
hell rather than by the fear of the gods as such (see page 105 above), it
appears that not the fear of hell, but the fear of death, is the enemy of our
happiness; the fear of hell threatens, not man as man, but the unjust. This
means that Lucretius ascribes some importance to the tenors of hell: he
does not even take the trouble to deny in so many words that a blessed life
after death is reserved for the just; he wishes to remain silent about religion
as a possibly pleasant and salutary delusion. He need not give a special
112 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
proof in order to deny that there is a hell after he has proved the mortality
of the souls. He limits himself therefore to explaining the stories of hell in
terms of the evils of human life. To cite only the central example, the true
Sisyphus is the man who runs for public office, for he wishes to lay hold on
a power which always eludes him, that is, which always remains precarious.
After the interlude on the terrors of hell, which was necessary in order to
bring out the peculiarity regarding both subject matter and manner of
treatment of the surrounding sections, Lucretius turns to telling the reader
something which he should tell himself from time to time: the reader is to
play the role previously played by men in general and, above all, by Nature.
Yet what he is to tell himself reads as if Lucretius were telling it to him, as
if Lucretius were addressing him. It is then Lucretius who tells his address¬
ee, whom he apostrophizes now as “thou knave,” that much better men
than he have died and that therefore he should not make any fuss about
his dying. The language which he uses is stronger than the language previ¬
ously used by Nature. He reminds the reader of six men who have died.
The first three are political men: the Roman king Ancus, the Persian king
Xerxes, whose name and country are not mentioned, and Scipio, the terror
of Carthage. The last three men are philosophers and poets: Homer, De¬
mocritus, and Epicurus; Epicurus’ genius surpassed that of all other men.
The men of outstanding minds are all Greeks (1024-1052). The political
men are all non-Greeks: they are all barbarians. Romanism is a kind of
barbarism. It is proper that Lucretius should make some effort to entrust
this speech to somebody else.
The sequel—the end of Book III—is as undramatic or nearly so as the
interlude that deals with the terrors of hell; it tacitly takes up the theme
that hell is the life of the fools here. Men live in the way they do because
they suffer from a burden the causes of which they do not know; hence no
one knows what he wants and changes from one thing or place to another;
everyone runs away from himself, but he cannot escape from himself; he is
sick without knowing the cause of his sickness; if he knew that cause, he
would leave everything else and first attempt to know the nature of things,
for what is at stake is his condition in eternity—the “eternal death” from
which he cannot escape and from which he foolishly attempts to escape.
The flight from oneself is the flight from one’s death (1053-1094). To
study nature means to learn to accept one’s death without delusion or
rebellion and hence to live well.
The last part of Book III tells us what the right posture toward death is.
In this context Lucretius presents seven utterances of beings other than the
poet in direct speech. Direct speech of beings other than Lucretius occurs
only here and twice in Book I (803-808, 897-900), but in Book I the
speaker in question is the addressee, and he speaks in defense of philo¬
sophic doctrines, that is, within the context of Lucretius’ polemics against
philosophic doctrines; whereas in Book III the polemic is directed against
Notes on Lucretius / 113
common, nay universal, opinion, and the speakers are men in general, Na¬
ture, and the addressee as a mask for Lucretius. In the speeches of Nature
and of the addressee as a mask for Lucretius there occurs an unusually large
number of vocatives; those speakers apostrophize their addressee as “thou
mortal,” “thou fool,” “thou criminal,” and “thou knave.” Lucretius him¬
self has apostrophized his addressee earlier in Book III (206) as “thou
good one.” It so happens that Lucretius apostrophizes the addressee after
Book III only in Book V, where he apostrophizes him five times “o Mem-
mius.” (He apostrophizes him “o Memmius” altogether nine times in the
poem.) The difference between the manner in which Lucretius, speaking
in his own name on the one hand and speaking through a mask on the
other, apostrophizes his addressee deserves notice, although it is not sur¬
prising.60
V. On Book IV
given in Book III are not quite sufficient to establish the mortality of the
souls. But how could this be? The belief in punishment after death pre¬
supposes not only the immortality of the souls but the existence of punish¬
ing gods as well. Perhaps the explanation of the likenesses throws light on
the belief in such gods or in gods in general. In the proem (6-7) Lucre¬
tius has reminded us of his purpose to liberate the mind from the bondage
of religion. The only way in which we can know, according to the Epicu¬
rean doctrine, of the gods being and their nature is through their likenesses
or images which reach us after they have passed through the flaming walls
of the world. Someone might say that Lucretius’ discussion of the like¬
nesses or images in Book IV has no relation whatever to his teaching re¬
garding, the gods since the very terms “likenesses” (simulacra) and
images (imagines) do not occur in his statement about how men have
come to know of the gods.62 This objection could at least as well be used
in support of the opposite assertion. Paintings and statues of the gods are
also called likenesses and images.” 63 The difficulty which we have in¬
dicated may explain why Lucretius gives a second justification of his pres¬
ent theme by linking the subject “the likenesses of things,” not to the doc¬
trine of the soul, but to the atomistic doctrine in general (45-53).
The likenesses or images are minute bodies on the surface of the things;
they are hurled forward by pressure from within the things; each likeness is
propelled immediately by the succeeding one; the succession never ceases;
the likenesses are carried away with incredible speed in all directions; they
are so tiny that they cannot be seen. Streaming from the surfaces of the
things, they preserve the things’ shapes and colors without alteration. If
certain conditions are fulfilled, they literally transmit to us faithful images
or copies of the shape and color of the thing in question. Yet not all like¬
nesses stream directly from things. Some likenesses are formed in the air;
they can be compared to the shapes which clouds sometimes take on like
those of giants and other fear-inspiring things. Besides, genuine likenesses
are deformed by the air on their way from the things to our eyes. Our
shadows seem to walk and to gesticulate, whereas, being lifeless, they are
incapable of walking and gesticulating (129-142, 168-175, 352-378).
A square tower seen from afar looks round; this means that the likeness
of the tower has become round on its way from the tower to our eyes; it is
as genuine as the square likeness which hits us when we are near the tower.
This is to say that not the eyes are deceived, but the mind, for it is the
reasoning of the mind, not the eyes, through which we can know the na¬
ture of the things. In a sense we see everything (462) which appears to us
as visible, regardless of whether we are awake or asleep at the time, and this
fact can easily shake our trust in the senses. Yet it is not the fault of the
senses if we do not distinguish between the things manifest—the likenesses
as such—and the things dubious—what the mind adds of its own. This
fault is indeed hard to avoid since nothing is harder than to make that dis-
Notes on Lucretius / 115
cupies the center of the section devoted to the senses other than sight. Lu¬
cretius is particularly concerned with the fact that the same food tastes
sweet or bitter to different kinds of beings, that is, to different kinds of
atomic compounds. He opens his discussion of this subject by another un¬
usual expression; his discussion serves the purpose, he says, “that we may
see how and why for different beings there is different food" (633-634);65
it looks as if the poet himself were listening to his own instruction or as if
he were still learning while teaching.66 Things taste differently to different
kinds of beings, that is, the tastes are not copies of the qualities of the
things; when one sees the things, their shapes and colors are preserved; but
one destroys the things when tasting them. As for smells, they come from
the interior of the things smelled and not, as the likenesses, from their sur¬
face; the same kinds of smells attract or repel different species of living be¬
ings. In addition, the species differ in regard to the keenness of their power
of smelling. Men are less apt to discern wholesome food by their sense of
smell than are wild beasts, while in other respects men’s senses are superior
to those of other animals.
Lucretius turns next to the question as to by what and whence the mind
(mens) is moved. This section too is opened by an unusual expression.67
We understand this section better if we look forward to the fact that “the
nature of the gods is subtle and far removed from our senses" (V 148_
149). “The subtle nature of the mind" is moved to the perception peculiar
to it by “subtle” likenesses of things which wander in the air and become
linked with one another; those combined likenesses are more subtle than
the likenesses which cause the vision of the eyes. In this way we “see” Cen¬
taurs, Scyllas, Cerberus, and the likenesses of the dead. We recall that the
explanation of such sights is the guiding purpose of the discussion of like¬
nesses in general (IV 29 ff.). The expression “we see” is justified to the ex¬
tent that the awareness of beings like the Centaurs is caused by likenesses
just as the awareness of ordinary things is. Needless to say, there are no
Centaurs and the like; the likenesses of Centaurs are produced by chance
meetings of the likenesses of horses with those of men. A single image of
this kind is sufficient to stir our mind, which is exceedingly subtle and
mobile. The mind’s “seeing" is more powerful when we are asleep than
when we are awake: it is in our dreams that “we seem to behold,” or that
“our mind believes it sees,” the dead (722-776). All this does not mean
that there are no likenesses affecting the mind which copy things that are
as they are; without such likenesses true thinking would be impossible.
Up to this point the chief subject of Book IV is the likenesses or images.
What the chief subject of the second half of the Book is, is not easy to say.
The first half may be said to consist of three parts: (1) the likenesses and
vision, (2) the three other senses discussed, (3) thought. The second half
also consists of three parts: (1) critique of the teleological view (823—
857); (2) explanation (<z) of the need for food, (b) of how we are able to
Notes on Lucretius / 117
move our limbs in various ways, (c) of sleep and dreams (858-1036); and
(3) explanation and critique of love (1037-1287). Lucretius first attacks
the view that the parts of the body were brought into being for their use
(the eyes for the sake of seeing, for instance); according to him their use¬
fulness and the awareness of it are consequent upon their having come into
being; only in the case of artifacts does awareness of usefulness precede the
coming into being. This criticism does not present itself as directed against
a philosophic school. More important, it is the only criticism of teleology
occurring in the work which contains no reference whatever to the gods.
The poet desires to remain silent on the gods in the present context. But
not to mention the gods is not the same as not to think of them. We have
stated earlier that in no other Book are gods as rarely mentioned with or
without name as in Book III. We must now correct this statement with a
view to the fact that the poet speaks very frequently in the last section of
Book IV of Venus, meaning by this word not the goddess, but simply sex¬
ual love.
Let us now consider the central part of the last half of Book IV. “Food”
had already been discussed from a different point of view in the central
part of the first half of Book IV, namely, when the sense of taste was being
considered. But then “food” occupied the central place, a place taken in
the second half by “movement of the limbs.” Movement of the limbs is
the action most emphatically ascribed to the gods in the section par excel¬
lence devoted to the gods: “men ascribed sense to the gods because the
gods were seen to move their limbs” (V 1172-1173); the gods’ moving
their limbs is the ratio cognoscendi of the gods’ sensing (and perhaps
thinking), or of the gods' being living beings. There is no difficulty in rec¬
onciling this with the facts that the likenesses of the dead seem to move
their limbs when they appear to us in our dreams and that our shadows
seem to walk (IV 364-369, 756-770). The difficulty is this. Our voluntary
movements are preceded by images or likenesses of those movements; these
images are very small bodies, and yet they set in motion the whole large
bulk of our bodies. Lucretius disposes of this difficulty with ease. For all we
know, he explained the gods’ moving their bodies, which are of wondrous
bulk (V 1171), in the same manner, but he is silent as to how the gods can
move their limbs. As for food, all living beings need food in order to repair
the losses which they incur especially through their exertions. The gods are
seen in our dreams to accomplish many wondrous things without under¬
going any toil (V 1181-1182); hence they would not seem to be in need
of food; Lucretius is silent on this subject.
Dreams were first discussed in connection with thinking; in the repeti¬
tion they are discussed in connection with sleep. The discussion of sleep is
introduced with nine verses in which Lucretius speaks of how he will treat
that subject—he will treat it in sweet verses rather than in many—and
urges his reader, who is again assumed to possess a keen mind, to listen
118 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
carefully and thus to accept the true teaching. Sleep, we are told, liberates
the mind from its cares. Thus one might think that it is a most desirable
state. Lucretius does not draw this conclusion. Sleep is due to a disor¬
dering of the positions of the body atoms and the mind atoms (IV 943—
944). This disordering brings about a disturbance of the soul and hence in
particular the suspension of sensing. Lucretius speaks here in all cases but
one (944) of the anima, and not of the animus, thus permitting us to
imagine that the animus can perceive the gods (V 1170-1171) while the
anima is dormant. Surely in his first discussion of dreams (IV 722-822),
in which he has spoken of our seeing Centaurs and the like, he has spoken
only of animus and mens. In the second discussion he gives seventeen ex¬
amples of dreams or kinds of dreams; in the ninth example (1008) there
occurs the only mention of “gods” or of “divine” that occurs between
verses 591 and 1233. He now states that we mostly dream of the thing with
which we were preoccupied while we were awake or that the likenesses
which enter the mind when we are asleep are the same as those which we
previously apprehended with the senses. What we dream depends on “in¬
terest and will.” The same is true of the beasts. Dogs, for instance, dream
of hunting wild beasts, and after they have been awakened by such dreams
they still pursue “the empty likenesses of stags”; puppies behave in their
dreams “as if they beheld unknown forms and faces.” Other examples
show that what living beings dream of depends on their fears. Sometimes
the likenesses believed to be seen do not precede the emotions or the
movements of the limbs, but are called forth by them. The likenesses of
every body which appear to males ripe for the discharge of the semen seem
to announce “a glorious face and a beautiful color” and thus to facilitate
that discharge (962-1036). One is tempted to say that it is not only fear
but love too which gives rise to visions of superhuman beings, of beings of
superhuman beauty and splendor; but it is wise to resist such temptations.
Certain it is that both Lucretian discussions of dreams do not in any way
suggest that through dreams we have an access (or a superior access) to
beings that are and to which we have no access (or only an inferior access)
while we are awake.
The last part of Book IV is devoted to Venus, who, according to the
beginning of the poem, is the deity par excellence. We have learned in the
meantime that Venus, so far from being a deity, is nothing but a personifi¬
cation of sexual love (cf. II 655-657 and 437). We also have learned what
to think of favorites of Venus like Paris. We learn now that sexual love, so
far from being divine, is a great threat to our happiness, although perhaps
not as great a threat as fear of death. The attack on love in the last section
of Book IV corresponds to the attack on the fear of death in the last sec¬
tion of Book III, and the deepest reason for this correspondence might
well be the fact that both fear and love are roots of the belief in gods. The
fate of Venus in the poem indicates the fate of all gods in it; Venus is re-
Notes on Lucretius / 119
lated to the true gods as the true gods are to the truth about the true gods.
Love is a wound of the mind, the beloved like a mortal enemy. Love prom¬
ises pleasure, but the pleasure which it gives is followed by chilly care. From
this we draw the conclusion that the gods cannot feel love, just as they do
not need food or sleep; Lucretius does not draw this conclusion. Love is
love of one, boy or woman; in order to enjoy the fruit of Venus without
suffering from the cares which she brings with her, one must separate sexual
pleasure from love. The ingredient of enmity in love reveals itself in the
very act of embrace. The lovers hope that by their embrace their desire
will be stilled, but this hope cannot be fulfilled, for the beauty which
arouses the love is only a delicate likeness which cannot enter the body like
food or drink; the lovers are mocked by images just as the thirsty man who
dreams of drinking (1048-1120). The sufferings of lovers are aggravated
by their self-deception; the lover ascribes to his beloved more than it is
right to ascribe to any mortal; he regards her as Venus herself or as some
other entirely flawless being which has nothing whatever to conceal. Hence
one frees oneself from the fetters of love best by thinking of the defects of
mind and body which the beloved is bound to have (1153-1191). All this
does not mean that venereal desire and pleasure is not natural; brutes have
no less a share in it than men (1192-1208). We may say that it is as natu¬
ral as the fear of death. Sterility is not due to divine action and therefore
cannot be counteracted by sacrifices to the gods (1233-1247). Nor is it
due to divine action that sometimes a woman of indifferent attractiveness
comes to be loved (1278-1287). Philosophy counteracts love as it counter¬
acts fear. There is no link between philosophy and eros.
VI. On Book V
The proem to Book V is devoted, as is the proem to Book III, to the
praise of Epicurus. But in the proem to Book V Lucretius does not address
Epicurus; he praises Epicurus while addressing Memmius by name. He
indicates’again that his work is inferior to that of Epicurus: no poem can
match “the grandeur of the things and the discoveries” of Epicurus; surely
no one formed of a mortal body can produce a poem which fits Epicurus’
deserts. It would seem that only a god could chant Epicurus’ praises ade¬
quately, for is not Epicurus himself a god? If one must speak in accordance
with what the known grandeur of the things itself demands, one must say
that Epicurus was a god, for he was the greatest benefactor of men that ever
was. In order to see that Epicurus was a god, it suffices that one compare
his discoveries with the divine discoveries of others which were made in
antiquity, with the discoveries said to have been made by Ceres and Liber.
Those discoveries are not necessary for life; there are said to be peoples
which live without bread and wine. Epicurus’ discovery, however, is neces-
120 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
sary for living well; it makes possible happiness amidst great peoples. It is
safe to assume that those great peoples include not only the Greeks but the
Romans as well. In accordance with this Lucretius indicates here that the
Romans are not barbarians and in Book V, as distinguished from the two
preceding Books, addresses Memmius by name. Lucretius then compares
Epicurus’ benefactions with the famous deeds of Heracles. By killing the
famous monsters Heracles and others have not disposed of the wild beasts
and other terrors with which the earth still abounds. Epicurus, however,
has taught men how to cleanse their hearts from desires and fears, from the
vices of all kinds. Therefore he deserves to be ranked among the gods. He
deserves this rank above all since he was wont to utter well and divinely
many sayings about the immortal gods themselves and to reveal in his say¬
ings the whole nature of things (1-54). Epicurus was then a god, if we
understand by a god not a being which is deathless, but a supreme bene¬
factor of men. He is, or was, not the only god: he deserves to be ranked
among the gods. But are those gods, the immortal gods, also benefactors of
the human race? Does the notion underlying the praise of Epicurus as a
god not render doubtful the notion underlying the Epicurean conception
of the gods? Is the praise of Epicurus as a god not tantamount to saying
that Epicurus was a god because he denied the godness of the gods? Why
does Lucretius praise here most highly, not Epicurus’ revealing the whole
nature of things, but his speeches about the immortal gods? 68
Lucretius follows Epicurus to the extent that he teaches by what law
everything has been created; he does not say here that he will reproduce
his master’s well and divinely framed sayings about the immortal gods. He
has shown before that the mind is mortal because it is inseparable from a
body which has come into being. He must show now that the world is
mortal because it has come into being; he must show how all its parts have
come into being. The human things belong to those parts; of the human
things Lucretius mentions here only speech and religion; the genesis, the
atomic composition, of reason has been not indeed discussed but intimated
before, in Book III; reason and religion are the most important human
phenomena. He will also explain how nature steers the courses of sun and
moon lest we think that those bodies move of their own will in order to
favor the crops and the living beings or that those bodies are moved by
gods. That the heavenly bodies cannnot be moved by gods follows indeed
from the fundamental theologoumenon, but if one does not know precisely
how they are moved, one is tempted time and again to relapse into the
ancient fears of harsh, omnipotent lords (55—90). Epicurus’ divine sayings
about the immortal gods are less useful for the liberation from religion
than his astronomy.
Lucretius begins to fulfill his promise that he will prove the mortality of
the world by telling Memmius, whom he again addresses by name, that
sea, earth, and heaven, those three bodies so different from each other, will
Notes on Lucretius / 121
perish on a single day. That heaven and earth will perish is a novel and
hence incredible assertion; it is not supported by Memmius’ experience.
Yet perhaps he will soon be a witness of an earthquake which will shake his
confidence in the stability of the world. The doctrine of the mortality of
the world is frightening not only because it is novel but because the de¬
struction of the world is terrible in itself (91-109).69 The teaching that the
soul is mortal is gratifying because it relieves us from the fear of hell. The
teaching that the world is mortal is not gratifying because, so far from re¬
lieving us from any fear, it adds to our fears. Yet can the world be im¬
mortal if it is not the work of gods, and will these gods not be harsh lords?
Yet as preservers of the world will they not also be beneficent?
Before taking on this difficulty Lucretius makes two more promises. He
promises to prove the mortality of the world, or rather to reveal the future
destiny of mankind in a more sacred and in a much more certain manner
than the Pythia. But before he will proclaim this superior revelation, he
will supply the reader with many solaces (110-114). That is to say, he
promises to show that the mortality of the world is preferable to its immor¬
tality, just as the mortality of the soul is more desirable than its immortal¬
ity. Yet the reader needs first some comfort against his fear that by denying
the immortality and hence the divinity of the world or of its most conspic¬
uous parts he will commit a monstrous crime and be punished like the
giants of old. Lucretius, who is not averse to repeating himself, no longer
retorts that religion rather than its rejection is a crime or responsible for
crimes.70 He limits himself to proving that religion is based on untruth.
Heaven, sea, and earth, sun, moon, and stars are not divine because they
lack vital motion and sense or mind. By gods we understand beings which
possess vital motion and sense or mind, and such beings must possess ap¬
propriate bodies such as none of those parts of the world possess (114-
145). This argument would prove that the gods must have bodies resem¬
bling human bodies, if Lucretius did not ascribe mind (mens) also to
brutes.71 He goes on to assert that no part of the world can be an abode of
the gods; the world is in no sense divine. The abodes of the gods must fit
the gods' subtle nature, which is not accessible to our senses, but is barely
seen by the mind. Lucretius promises the reader to prove in a copious
speech what he has said about the nature and the abodes of the gods
(146-155); he does not promise that he will prove the existence of the
gods. Nor does he keep his promise, although he had said that the speeches
about the immortal gods are his master’s greatest achievement (52-54).
Not only is the world not divine; it is not even the work of gods. People
say that the gods have willed to fashion the glorious nature of the world for
the sake of man and hence that the world is immortal. Lucretius again
takes issue with the view that it is sinful to deny the immortality of the
world, and he again fails to counter it by referring to the crimes caused by
religion. But in discussing the divine origin of the world as distinguished
122 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
is, by the destruction of the world. According to the stories, there was once
a time when fire won out and another when water won out (the deluge).
The ancient Greek poets presented the temporary victory of fire in the
story of Phaethon, according to which the omnipotent father (Jupiter)
prevented the destruction of the world by his timely intervention. Lucre¬
tius rejects as untrue this story and its implication that the death of the
world can or will be prevented by the gods. The omnipotent father himself
would be mortal (cf. 318-323 and 258-260).
The second argument in support of the mortality of the world (324-
350) is likewise not based on specifically Epicurean premises. The world
and hence also the human race are mortal because each had a beginning,
and that the world had a beginning is shown by the fact that the past
which men remember does not go beyond the Theban and Trojan wars. In
fact, the world is young as is shown by the recent origin of some of the arts
and especially of philosophy. One cannot explain these facts by cataclysms
which left the world itself (heaven, earth, and the species of animals) in¬
tact, for if all the works of men and almost all men could be destroyed by a
weaker cause, a more grievous cause can destroy all men and the world it¬
self. The third argument (351-379) proves the mortality of the world by
showing that the world does not belong to the beings which are necessarily
immortal. Lucretius’ enumeration of the immortal beings agrees almost lit¬
erally with the one which he had given when proving the mortality of the
soul (III 806-818). The immortal beings are the atoms, the void, and the
infinite universe (as distinguished from the world or worlds). But the
world does not possess the perfect solidity of the atoms, nor is it void, nor
is it the universe; hence the gate of death is not shut on the world, but
stands open and looks toward the world with huge wide-gaping maw. This
argument would imply that the mortality of the world can be established
only on the basis of atomism and therefore that atomism, or rather Epicu¬
reanism, is the indispensable basis for denying the divine origin of the
world or divine intervention in the world, that is, for liberating the mind
from the terrors of religion.
Since the world is mortal, it must have come into being (V 373-376).
The proof of the mortality is followed by an exposition of how the world
came into being. This exposition seems to complete the proof of the Epi¬
curean doctrine; the infinitely many atoms moving in infinite time through
the infinite void explain the world as we know it, since they explain how it
came into being: the world is one of the many arrangements of atoms
which in a very long time came about through the furious clashes of the
blind atoms without the intervention of an ordering mind or a peaceful
agreement between the atoms; and once it has come about, it preserves it¬
self for a long time. Order comes out of disorder, discord, war—a war due
to the dissimilarity of the atoms and their mutual repulsion (416-448).
Owing to its specific atomic composition the earth emerged first and came
124 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
to occupy the lowest place in the center of the visible world. As a conse¬
quence of its emergence those atoms or atomic compounds which were to
form the stars and the ether were driven from the earth and began to form
those upper bodies; this change in its turn led to the emergence of the sea
and thus to the earth s taking on its final shape. Lucretius speaks in this
context of the living bodies of sun and moon, but he means by this no
more than that they are not stationary in contrast to the earth which is
stationary (449-494; cf. 125). The temporary quasi divinization of sun
and moon serves the purpose of bringing out the low estate of the earth,
allegedly the Great Mother, the place of man who is allegedly the favorite
of the creating gods: the defects of nature, which prove that it is not the
work of gods, are above all the defects of the earth.74
After having sketched the coming into being of the main parts of the
world, Lucretius turns to the heavenly bodies. He begins his discussion of
them with the words, “Now let us sing what is the cause of the motions of
the stars.” The expression “let us sing” occurs nowhere else in the poem.
On the only other occasion on which Lucretius speaks of his “singing” (VI
84), he means his exposition of other phenomena aloft.76 Since he “sings”
of the motions of the stars, he is entitled to speak of “the stars of the eter¬
nal world” and shortly thereafter even of the earth as “living” (V 509, 514,
538; cf. 476). Singing means magnifying and embellishing. Yet beyond the
two examples mentioned Lucretius cannot be said to magnify or embellish
the heavenly bodies or their motions. He does not hesitate to speak of
Matuta’s spreading rosy dawn (656-657), of the moon’s beholding the
sun setting (709), of Venus or Cupid (737), of Mother Flora (739), and
of Ceres and Bacchus (741-742), but the exercise of this poetic license is
in no way peculiar to the astronomic part of the poem. One might say that
Lucretius exclaims, Let us sing,” when he “sings” least and therefore can
indicate in an inconspicuous manner what “singing” means.
What then is peculiar to the astronomic part? Lucretius does not give
“the cause” of the motions of the stars, but a variety of incompatible
causes; he gives a variety of possible causes since it is impossible to know
which is truly the cause (526-533). Strictly speaking, he does not know
“the cause of the motions of the stars.” Yet ignorance of that cause gives
rise to religion (1185-1186) or is the chief justification of religion. Hence
it would seem that the human mind is insufficient in the decisive respect.
One is therefore tempted to say that one “sings” when one does not know.
But the insufficiency mentioned is not peculiar to our knowledge of things
aloft (VI 703-711). It would be better to say that Lucretius does not dis¬
cuss in detail the genesis of the heavenly bodies and their motions, but
speaks of them as they are after their genesis has been completed, whereas,
as regards the terrestrial beings, he presents their genesis in detail. But why
does he proceed so differently in the two cases? The heavenly bodies and
their motions are one of the chief reasons, nay, the chief reason, why men
Notes on Lucretius / 125
believe that there are gods acting on the world or in the world, and to de¬
stroy that belief is one of the two primary purposes of the whole poem.76
It is therefore all the more remarkable that the astronomic part of the
poem is completely free from the attacks on religion in which the poet en¬
gages so often. Or, to speak more generally, in the astronomic part Lucre¬
tius is completely silent about the nonexistence of the vulgar gods or the
existence of the true gods. Lucretius’ “singing” means here his complete
silence about the problem of the gods. This leaves us with the question
with what right singing thus understood can still be described as mag¬
nification or embellishment.
After the completion of the astronomic part Lucretius “returns to the
youth of the world” (780) in order to give an account of how the terres¬
trial things came into being. This is the only occasion on which the poet
speaks of his “returning” to something; the uniqueness of “I return” cor¬
responds to the uniqueness of “let us sing”; he returns now to nonsinging.
The astronomic part is a digression within the context of a Book devoted
to the coming into being of the world and its parts. The coming into being
of the world and its parts, we recall, is the reverse side of the mortality of
the world. The mortality of the world seemed to be incredible because of
the belief in gods who created the world. This belief is refuted long before
the beginning of the astronomic part and independently of any peculiarly
Epicurean assumptions (195-234). The “digression” has the subordinate
function of counteracting the impression made by the visible (and com¬
pleted) heavenly bodies and their motions—an impression which leads to
the belief in the gods of religion. Precisely because the “digression” has this
subordinate function, it is all the more remarkable that it is more emphati¬
cally a “song” than any other part of the first five Books.
The earth brought forth first the plants and then the animals. Even now
the earth brings forth some small animals; it is therefore not surprising that
in the spring of the world, when the earth was of youthful fertility, that is,
when heat and moisture abounded everywhere and yet a mild climate pre¬
vailed everywhere, the earth should have brought forth all kinds of animals
(783-820). The earth is therefore deservedly called the mother of all liv¬
ing beings; in her youth she was almost literally their mother; through ag¬
ing she lost her primeval power. In her youth she gave birth to many kinds
of monsters or freaks which proved to be unable to procreate and even to
live for any length of time; those kinds perished. Only those kinds survived
which from the beginning were able to live and to propagate. Some of
those kinds survived through their own powers, others because they were
entrusted to the protection of man, who preserves them since they are use¬
ful to him. When speaking of the species which are entrusted to man’s tu¬
telage, Lucretius addresses Memmius for the fourth time in this Book by
name (821-877). In the three preceding cases, as well as in the two cases
occurring in Book II, he had addressed Memmius by name in antitheolog-
126 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
gods and the marvelous sizes of their bodies. This much and not more is
unambiguously said to have been “seen” and still to be “seen” of the gods
by men awake. The beautiful forms and the great bulk do not by them¬
selves prove that their owners are living beings; gods must be capable of
feeling or sensing. Men did not “see” that the gods sense, but they “attrib¬
uted” sense to the gods because they “saw” the gods moving their limbs.
Yet this inference is of questionable validity. Men see the gods chiefly in
sleep; in sleep they also “see” dead men moving their limbs, that is, they
seem to see this or they believe they see it (IV 757-772). Accordingly Lu¬
cretius does not unambiguously say that the gods were seen to move their
limbs; the expression which he uses (videbantur) can as well mean that
the gods seemed to move their limbs. The whole sentence reads as follows:
“They attributed sense to the gods because they seemed to move their
limbs and to utter haughty sounds befitting their resplendent form and
their ample strength.” The gods’ sensing, that is, living, is not experienced,
but a human “addition” to the experienced (cf. V 1195 and IV 462-468);
the experience in itself is in fact not more than a seeming.
What is true of the gods’ sensing is also true of their eternal life: men
“gave” them eternal life, and “they believed” that gods possessing such
great strength could “not easily” be overcome by any force; beings which
are not easily overcome by any force are not necessarily eternal. “They be¬
lieved” the gods to be outstanding in good fortune because none of the
gods was ever troubled by fear of death, and “in sleep they saw them
achieve many wondrous things without undergoing any toil” (V 1169—
1182). One is curious to know whether men saw while awake that the gods
were never troubled by fear of death, and which wondrous things the gods
were seen to do; there is no suggestion that they were seen to think or to
understand or in any other way to know the truth. There is also no sug¬
gestion that they were seen to be simply self-sufficient and hence unable to
act on the world and within it and in particular to act on men. On the
contrary, since the first cause of religion as presented by Lucretius consists
to a considerable extent of human additions to what was genuinely seen or
experienced, there is no reason why men should not have imagined also
that the beings possessing beautiful faces and enormous sizes, which ap¬
peared to them in their dreams and seemed to utter haughty sounds, were
not also their haughty lords threatening them with terrible punishments.
This may be the reason why Lucretius declares that he will set forth “the
cause,” that is, a single cause, of religion. However this may be, he is con¬
cerned with pointing to a cause which has nothing whatever to do with
men’s dreams; therefore he adduces the following cause: men were in¬
duced by their beholding the celestial phenomena, of which they do not
know the causes, to trace those phenomena to the gods. In particular,
frightening and nocturnal phenomena of this kind were held to be threats
on the part of the gods or proofs of their anger. In the light of “the longest
130 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
and fullest treatment of the nature of the gods and the causes and function
of religion in the poem” as well as of our previous observations,87 we shall
say that the fundamental theologoumenon is meant to articulate in the
most adequate manner our notion of the gods as entia perfectissima: the
most perfect beings cannot possibly act on the world or in the world; the
fundamental theologoumenon, in contradistinction to the ontological
proof, is not meant to prove the existence of gods; their existence is not
known.
This result is not contradicted by those writings of Epicurus that have
come down to us in nonfragmentary form. In the case of fragments we
cannot know how the thoughts expressed in them would appear in the
light of the whole to which they belonged. The Principal Opinions never
speaks of gods or of the divine.88 According to the first of those Opinions,
that which is blessed and indestructible suffers no trouble nor does it
cause trouble to any other; hence it is not affected by fear or favor; for
everything of this kind occurs only in what is weak.” This statement is
ordinarily taken as an assertion of the fundamental theologoumenon; but
there are “immortal goods” which wise men can enjoy.89 The Letter to
Herodotus, which is an epitome of Epicurus’ teaching on nature, never
speaks of gods or of the divine; it does say that “in the indestructible and
blessed nature there can in no way be anything which can bring about
dissolution or confusion” (78); this statement could be made by a mon¬
otheist as well as by an atheist. The Letter to Herodotus also teaches that
one must not believe that the same things are blessed and indestructible
and at the same time will or do or cause things that are incompatible with
bliss and indestructibility (81). The Letter to Pythocles, which is a sum¬
mary of Epicurus’ teaching about the things aloft, warns its reader against
having recourse to “the divine nature” in order to explain celestial
phenomena: one must leave the divine nature unmolested in its complete
bliss (97; cf. 113 and 115-116). The utmost one can say is that the Letter
to Pythocles uses the fundamental theologoumenon as a bulwark against
mythical explanations, but those explanations are known to be impossible
independently of the fundamental theologoumenon (cf. 104). The Letter
to Pythocles refers once to the intermundia (89) without even alluding to
their being the abodes of the gods. Epicurus sets forth his teaching regard-
mg the gods and especially their existence in his Letter to Menoeceus
(123-124), which is in fact devoted to ethics; he has found no place for it
in his physics, that is, his teaching regarding the whole. No one in his right
mind will say that the Epicurean gods are postulated by practical reason:
Epicurus did not “find it necessary to deny knowledge in order to make
room for faith.”
To return to Lucretius, according to what one may call his official teach¬
ing the truth is sad because the world is not divine nor of divine origin, but
the truth is attractive or comforting above all because the most lovable is
Notes on Lucretius / 131
sempiternal since there are gods, blessed and immortal beings that are akin
to man rather than to any other beings. Yet if the gods are not, the most
divine being, the being most resplendent, most beneficent, and most high
in rank is the wise man with his frail happiness. The frailty of human
happiness cannot be overcome by any conquest of nature, by the subjec¬
tion of the whole to human use, for this would require among other things
the emancipation of the desires for unnecessary things and therefore the
certainty of human misery, of the fate of Sisyphus. Besides, the Epicurean
sage has as little incentive to charity—to feeding the hungry and clothing
the naked—as the Epicurean gods; like the Epicurean gods he is beneficent
by being what he is rather than by doing anything. It is in agreement with
this that Lucretius’ “political philosophy” is only an account of the coming
into being of political society; it does not deal with the question of the best
regime: no regime deserves to be called good; philosophy cannot trans¬
form, or contribute toward transforming, political society.
Religion is presented by Lucretius as belonging to political society (V
1161-1162, 1222; cf. 1174 and 1111), which does not mean that it does
not have ingredients antedating political society. It belongs to political so¬
ciety because laws, punishment, and fear of punishment belong to political
society (1136-1151). Fear of punishment and fear of the gods belong
together; fear of the gods is fear of divine punishment. Fear of the gods
leads to men’s despising themselves; Lucretius no longer says that it leads to
crimes;00 he says now that it leads to the sacrifice of beasts; he no longer
speaks, as he did at the beginning, of human sacrifices. Ignorance of the
causes of the motions of the heavenly bodies is not the sole or sufficient
cause of men’s believing in angry gods. (Hence astronomy is not suffi¬
cient for liberating men from the fear of the gods.) At least as important
in this respect is men’s bad conscience; for instance, the awareness of
haughty kings that they have done or said haughty things which deserve
punishment (1194-1240). We see again that religion may exert a salutary
restraint. It is surely greatly preferable that the restraint be exerted by
philosophy, which restrains the desires while it takes away the fear of the
gods. This implies, however, that philosophy belongs to political society no
less than religion does or that philosophy is impossible in prepolitical soci¬
ety: philosophy presupposes a high development of the arts. In prepolitical
society Venus alone held sway. In political society, just as in nature. Mars
rather than Venus holds sway.01 Prepolitical society is in one sense more
natural than political society; but it cannot be “the state of nature” since
man lives according to nature only by virtue of philosophizing. The same
man who in prepolitical society would have been a member of his tribe,
like everybody else, may in political society lead the strictly private life of
the philosopher.
At the beginning of his account of the genesis of the arts Lucretius
speaks of the discovery of copper, gold, and iron as well as of silver and
132 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
lead. The discovery of gold was an important step in the transition from
the rule of those by nature superior to the rule of the rich (1113-1114).
Through trial and error men learned to prefer copper to gold and silver
because of its greater usefulness; the now prevailing preference for gold
emerged at a later date (1241-1280). The use of iron was discovered last.
When speaking of the discovery of the nature of iron Lucretius apostro¬
phizes Memmius by name for the last time in the poem. He says: “It is
easy for you to know by yourself, Memmius, how the nature of iron was
discovered” (1281-1282). The poet had not used the second person since
verse 1091. No such rarity of the use of the second person occurs anywhere
else in the poem.92 The present use of the second person is emphasized by
the simultaneous use of the vocative of Memmius. The poet had apos¬
trophized Memmius by name after Book I only in antitheological contexts;
the present context is even less visibly antitheological than the preceding
one (cf. pages 125-126 above). But between the present use of the vocative
of Memmius and of the second person and the preceding use of the vocative
of Memmius or of the second person there occurred the statement par ex¬
cellence on the gods: Lucretius saw no need for emphasizing the impor¬
tance of that statement. Lucretius mentions Memmius for the last time
when speaking of the discovery of iron; iron is particularly useful in war;
the connection between Memmius and war was indicated near the begin¬
ning of the poem (I 40-43). How much Lucretius is concerned with
opening his account of the genesis of the arts with the theme “war” is
shown by the fact that the sequel to what he says on the discovery of the
metals deals with the various stages in which beasts were employed in war.
Lucretius uses this occasion to indicate how much the progress of the arts
takes place through error and trial; he makes us imagine for a moment that
men foolishly tried to use bulls, boars, and even lions against their enemies,
perhaps because, despairing of victory, they wished to harm their enemies
while committing suicide (1281-1349).
Lucretius turns from the progress of the art or arts of war to weaving. By
this he does not mean to turn from a man’s art to a woman’s art—the
superior sex invented even the art of weaving, which is thought to be a
preserve of the inferior sex—but from the arts of war to the arts of peace.
Still, the peaceful art exercised commonly by men and hence higher in
rank than weaving is agriculture, which is the next subject of the poet. The
first teacher of agriculture and arboriculture was indeed nature herself, but
men improved on the first lessons. Nature also taught men the rudiments
of music, and reason raised the rustic Muse to its height. Lucretius presents
the emergence of the various arts in accordance with the order of their
rank. He therefore turns from music to knowledge of the seasons, that is,
of one of the most visible signs of the sure order of nature; this knowledge
is the last discovery discussed by him in any detail. In discussing music (as
distinguished from knowledge of the seasons) he alludes to the fact that
Notes on Lucretius / 133
the enjoyments of the rustic Muse, despite their rudeness, embody some of
the purest subphilosophic enjoyments of present-day men.93 While this
kind of music survives into the present in an improved form, present-day
men are not happier than the earthbom men at the beginning who could
not suffer from the lack of pleasures which they did not know. Progress
within many arts is due to the desire for novel or even greater pleasures,
that is, by the ignorance of the term of true pleasure. Hence this kind of
progress goes hand in hand with the progress of war. This is not to deny
that the progress of the arts is on the whole a progress of knowledge, a
progress which culminates in Epicurus’ work. The order of the arts as pre¬
sented at the end of Book V follows the same principle as the order of
outstanding men which occurred near the end of Book III (1024-1044).94
VII. On Book VI
this is true. Book VI makes us forget the coming into being, and therewith
the death, of the world. Lucretius has reminded us of that sad truth even
in the latter part of Book V, which is so single-mindedly devoted to com¬
ing into being as distinguished from perishing, by speaking of the ambigu¬
ity of the progress of the arts. Yet at the very end of Book V (1440-1457)
he has become silent about that ambiguity. But it suffices to compare the
last verses of Book V with the last verses of Book VI in order to see that
the poet’s use of honey is judicious; he does not permit the honey to make
us insensitive to the wormwood.
The phenomena to be dealt with in Book VI are traced by men to the
gods whom they believe to be their dreadful masters. It is undoubtedly
true that the gods lead a life free from all care and that fear of the gods is
incompatible with pure worship or perception of the gods. Yet it is also
true that the error which leads to fear of the gods is uprooted only by the
verissima ratio, that is, by the natural explanation of the phenomena which
induce ignorant men to believe in divine wrath. The expression verissima
ratio occurs nowhere else in the poem. One of the things which Lucretius
must therefore do is to “sing” of the true causes and effects of storms and
lightnings. He invokes the Muse Calliope, who is “rest to men and joy to
gods,” to be his leader (51-95). Calliope now takes the place of Venus;
Venus is not even mentioned any more in Book VI. Calliope had been the
Muse invoked by Empedocles. Empedocles was both a philosopher and a
poet. He was surpassed by Democritus and above all by Epicurus. Yet in
surpassing Empedocles, Democritus and Epicurus had separated philos¬
ophy entirely from poetry. Poetry became at best the handmaid of philos¬
ophy. Yet the poet possesses insights which Epicurus may have lacked,
above all the understanding of men’s attachment to the world and what
this implies. By restoring the union of philosophy and poetry, by pre¬
senting the true and final philosophic teaching poetically, Lucretius may be
said to surpass Epicurus; the Lucretian presentation of the truth is superior
to the Epicurean presentation. Yet if we consider the crucial importance of
the Epicurean gods in the Epicurean presentation of the truth, are we not
driven to say that in the decisive respect Epicurus too is a poet? Do the
Epicurean gods not magnify or embellish the whole?
Lucretius explains thunder (96-159) and lightning (160-218) in order
to explain the thunderbolt (219-378), for the thunderbolt, being the
strongest of all fires, is together with its concomitants the most frightening
thing coming from heaven. The explanation of the thunderbolt naturally
leads up to an attack on the Tyrrhenian kind of divination (which had
been taken over by the Romans) and, more generally, on the theological
view: thunderbolts strike the innocent as well as the guilty; nay, they strike
the likenesses and images of the gods (379-422). One need not be an
atomist in order to be impressed by arguments of this kind. Lucretius
explains thereafter at some length three phenomena akin to thunder-
Notes on Lucretius / 135
NOTES
1. Cf. Hesiod, Theogony 11—21: Ares is not explicitly mentioned among the gods
praised by the Muses. Cf. Works and Days 145-146.
2. Cf. the virum in VI 5 with the deus ille fuit, deus in V 8.
3. Cf. especially 1259-1263.
4. Cf. 1197-1204, 1210-1211, 1226-1229 with Thucydides II 49.8 and 51.6.
5. 1183, 1212; cf. 1208-1212 with Thucydides II 49.8; consider the fact that there
is no passage in Lucretius which corresponds to II 53.
6. Cf. 1239-1246 with Thucydides II 51.5.
7. Cf. 1278-1286 (consider especially the last words of the poem) with Thucydides
II 53.4, beginning and 52.4. Cf. Epicurus’ unconcern with his burial: Diogenes
Laertius X 118.
8. In his letter to Menoeceus (134) Epicurus says that there is something worse than
the tale of the gods: the fate or necessity of which the physikoi speak.
9. Cf. 1156-1162, 1182-1185, 1212.
10. Ill 1-30.
11. Cf. I 117-119, 121, 124, 136-137, 143-145.
12. V 925-1010, 1087-1090; cf. VI 601-602.
13. V 1211-1217, 1236-1240, 91-109, 114-121, 373-375, 1186-1187; VI 565-567,
597-607, 650-652, 677-679.
14. Cf. Thucydides I 22.4.
15. Hence the conclusion of the whole reasoning in 205-207. The fourth argument is
the only one which shows that many first bodies are common to many things as
letters ("elements”) are common to words, that is, that there is something more
common than the heterogeneous seeds of the various kinds of animals and plants.
16. Lucretius does not regard plants as living beings: I 774 (cf. 821 and II 702-703).
17. Cf. I 107-108. Cf. the emphasis on numbers, that is, on small numbers, in 419—
420, 432, 445-446, 449-450, 503.
18. I 803-808, 897-900. Cf. 770.
19. Cf. II 185-190.
20. I 28, 136-145, 933-934.
21. Cicero, De republica III 26; De finibus II 15.
22. I 716-725; cf. VI 680 ff.
23. I 675-678, 684-689, 778-781, 848-856, 915-920.
24. I 803—808 and 897-900. In I 803-808 the addressee tries to prove that without
the four elements there could not be growth of plants and animals; Lucretius
strengthens this argument by stating that without the four elements there could
not be human life. In the parallels in IV 633-672 and VI 769—780 he also speaks
of diseases and death.
25. Cf. the evolvamus and pervideamus in I 954 and 956.
26. I 1021-1022; cf. 328 and 1110.
27. I 1052.
28. Cf. I 1112 with V 373-375.
29. Only in this context does Lucretius refer to things Roman in the proem to Book
II. He no longer refers to things Roman in the proems to the following Books.
30. Cf. also the implicit contrast between the wandering or restless atoms and the
wandering mind in II 82-83. Cf. also the contrast between the fall of the atoms
Notes on Lucretius / 137
and the fall of certain philosophers (I 741). The void is motionless or quiet (II
238); yet this quietness has no kinship with the quietness which the mind needs
(cf. I 639).
31. Cf. also the emphasis on generating in II 62-64. Cf. the semper in II 76 with the
nunc in V 194.
32. Cf. I 1025; II 573-576, V 380-381, 391-392.
33. In the two cases in which the poet addressed Memmius by name in Book I he also
did this while polemicizing against “some," that is, while indicating Memmius’
likely resistance to Epicureanism. The same is true of the two cases in Book I
(803-808, 897-900) in which he presents Memmius as opposing Epicureanism in
direct speech.
34. II 169, 178, I 105. Consider again the initial statement about the theme of the
whole poem in I 54-55. Cf. Spinoza, Tr. theol.-pol. XVI 10-11 (Bruder).
35. Letter to Menoeceus 134.
36. II 481—482, 496—507; cf. V 1171, and 1177 (auctos.). Consider the unusual
section-beginnings in II 478-479 and 522-523.
37. II 569-580; cf. 174-181 and V 220-234.
38. Cf. IV 761: the dead are held by “death and earth.”
39. As for the difference between the second and the fifth items, cf. Democritus (Diels)
B 278.
40. Literally, “the everlasting wound”; cf. “the everlasting wound” of Mars in I 34,
that is, shortly before the first statement of the fundamental theologoumenon.
41. Cf. II 886-888, 902-903, 931, 983.
42. Cf. Ill 879-889.
43. Cf. Bailey’s edition and commentary (Oxford: 1947), p. 956.
44. Cf. V 115-125, 144-145.
45. Cf. Cicero, De natura deorum I 52.
46. Note the contrast with I 398-417, the conclusion of the section dealing with the
void.
47. Cf. I 1052-1053 in the parallel.
48. He does not invoke the gods in order to confirm a theologoumenon; cf. the parallel
case in II 434 (pro divom numina sancta). No other reference to the hearts of the
gods occurs in the poem.
49. Cf. Bailey, op. cit., p. 761.
50. “Lucretius is a poet not to be suspected of giving way to superstitious terrors; yet
when he supposes the whole mechanism of nature laid open by the master of his
philosophy, his transport on this magnificent view, which he has represented in
the colours of such bold and lively poetry, is overcast with a shade of secret dread
and horror.” Burke, The Sublime and Beautiful, II sect. 5.
51. Reconsider from this point of view I 80-83.
52. Cf. Plato, Phaedo 86c2-d4 (Simmias). Cf. the sarcasm in Lucretius’ critique of
pre-existence (the premise of Cebes’ argument) in III 776-783.
53. Just as “we all” who “stem from heavenly seed” (II 991) are not merely “all we
human beings.” Cf. also page 96 above.
54. Cf. Ill 753.
55. Ill 371, V 622. Of Empedocles he says that Sicily does not seem to have possessed
something more sacred than him (I 729-730).
56. Cf. V 177-178.
57. Expressions like fateare necessest, cur credis, quod si forte putas, quid dubitas, quod
si forte credis do not occur in the first part of Book III (31—424), but occur in the
second part.
58. Cf. 754, 760, 765-766.
59. Note the contrast between the avoidance of the first person plural in the verses
138 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
dealing with the Punic Wars (833-837) and the frequency of the first person
plural (“we,” that is, we human beings, not we Romans) in the rest of the pas¬
sage.
60. Compare the procedure of the Xenophontic Socrates who apostrophizes Xenophon
and no one else as “you wretch” and “you fool” (Memorabilia I 3.11,13). Cf.
Plato, Republic 595cl0-596al.
61. Cf. also I 130-135.
62. V 1161-1193. Cf. VI 76-77.
63. II 609; VI 419-420.
64. Passive forms of videre occur here seventeen times with the unambiguous meaning
of “to seem.” Cf. I 726 (videtur) and 727 (fertur).
65. Cf. the “we” in 37. Cf. VI 970-972.
66. Cf. IV 969-970.
67. Nunc age . . . accipe . . . percipe (722-723).
68. Cf. Ill 12-27.
69. Cf. II 1023-1047.
70. Cf. I 80 ff.
71. Ill 294-301. Cf. II 265-268 and V 1325.
72. Cf. II, 478-484.
73. Cf. II, 175-182. The promise there made to Memmius is fulfilled in the present
context.
74. Cf. especially 233-234 with 198. Cf. 495—505. This step is prepared by the transi¬
tion from 258-260 (the earth is the parent of all) to 318-323 (the sky is the
parent of all). Cf. II 598-599 with 991-998.
75. VI 84; cf. 255, 259, 376. Verbal forms of canere occur ten times; in nine cases the
word is applied to human singing or music. Cantus occurs four times and canor
twice.
76. V 1183-1193, 1205-1221, 83-87; cf. I 62-69.
77. Cf. pages 95-96, 119-120, 121-123 above.
78. This is so despite the fact that nature supplies everything to the gods (III 23).
79. Cf. pages 116-117 above.
80. Bailey, op. cit., p. 1474 note, refers to Empedocles (B 128, lines 1-3): “for those
men Ares was not god nor Kydoimos nor Zeus the king nor Kronos nor Poseidon
but only Kypris the queen.” Lucretius indicates the absence of Zeus, Ares, and
Poseidon in V 958-959 and 999-1006.
81. Letter to Herodotus 75-76.
82. Cf. Plato, Republic 365c6—dl. Cf. the plerumque in V 1153 and the ferantur in
1159.
83. Cf. Cicero, De finibus I 51.
84. Op cit., p. 1507.
85. Ibid., p. 67.
86. Cf. Xenophanes B 16.
87. See pages 99-100, 114-115, 117-118, 121-122 above. Cf. I 132-135.
88. The Gnomologium Vaticanum differs in this respect from the Principal Opinions-
cf. Nos. 24, 33, and 65.
89. Letter to Menoeceus, end; Gnomologium Vaticanum No. 78.
90. Cf. pages 121—122 above.
91. Cf. page 95 above.
92. If I am not mistaken, the second person is used in Book I (consisting of 1117
verses) 91 times; in Book II (1174), 122 times; in Book III (1094), 112 times;
in Book IV (1287), 89 times; in Book V (1457), 49 times; and in Book VI
(1286), 62 times. I disregarded the cases in which the second person is used of
Venus, Epicurus, or Calliope.
Notes on Lucretius / 139
93. Cf. 1392-1411 with II 29-33.
94. Cf. also the ascent from political life to poetry in 1440-1445; cf. also 1448-1451
and 332-337.
95. Cf. page 81 above.
96. Cf. V 95-109 and 1236-1240.
97. Cf. Aristotle, Metaphysics 1050b22—24; cf. On the Heaven 270M-16.
98. Cf. page 81 above.
How To Begin To Study
The Guide of the Perplexed
I believe that it will not be amiss if I simply present the plan of the Guide
as it has become clear to me in the course of about twenty-five years of
frequently interrupted but never abandoned study. In the following
scheme Roman (and Arabic) numerals at the beginning of a line indicate
the sections (and subsections) of the Guide, while the numbers given in
parentheses indicate the Parts and the chapters of the book.
140
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 141
1. Introductory (I 71-73)
2. Refutation of the Kalam demonstrations (I 74-76)
3. The philosophic demonstrations (II 1)
4. Maimonides’ demonstration (II 2)
5. The angels (II 3-12)
6. Creation of the world, i.e., defense of the belief in creation
out of nothing against the philosophers (II 13-24)
7. Creation and the Law (II 25-31)
in. Prophecy (II 32-48)
1. Natural endowment and training the prerequisites of proph¬
ecy (II 32-34)
2. The difference between the prophecy of Moses and that of
the other prophets (II 35)
3. The essence of prophecy (II 36-38)
4. The legislative prophecy (of Moses) and the Law (II 39-40)
5. Legal study of the prophecy of the prophets other than Moses
(II 41-44)
6. The degrees of prophecy (II 45)
7. How to understand the divine actions and works and the di¬
vinely commanded actions and works as presented by the
prophets (II 46-48)
iv. The account of the Chariot (III 1-7)
a". Views regarding bodily beings that come into being and perish,
AND IN PARTICULAR REGARDING MAN (III 8-54)
v. Providence (III 8-24)
1. Statement of the problem: matter is the ground of all evils
and yet matter is created by the absolutely good God (III
8-14)
2. The nature of the impossible or the meaning of omnipotence
(III 15)
3. The philosophic arguments against omniscience (III 16)
4. The views regarding providence (III 17-18)
5. Jewish views on omniscience and Maimonides’ discourse on
this subject (III 19-21)
6. The book of Job as the authoritative treatment of providence
(III 22-23)
7. The teaching of the Torah on omniscience (III 24)
terms, and its second purpose is to explain biblical similes. The Guide is
then devoted above all to biblical exegesis, although to biblical exegesis of a
particular kind. That kind of exegesis is required because many biblical
terms and all biblical similes have an apparent or outer and a hidden or
inner meaning; the gravest errors as well as the most tormenting perplex¬
ities arise from men’s understanding the Bible always according to its ap¬
parent or literal meaning. The Guide is then devoted to “the difficulties of
the Law’’ or to “the secrets of the Law.” The most important of those se¬
crets are the Account of the Beginning (the beginning of the Bible) and
the Account of the Chariot (Ezek. 1 and 10). The Guide is then devoted
primarily and chiefly to the explanation of the Account of the Beginning
and the Account of the Chariot.
Yet the Law whose secrets Maimonides intends to explain forbids that
they be explained in public, or to the public; they may only be explained in
private and only to such individuals as possess both theoretical and polit¬
ical wisdom as well as the capacity of both understanding and using allu¬
sive speech; for only “the chapter headings” of the secret teaching may be
transmitted even to those who belong to the natural elite. Since every
explanation given in writing, at any rate in a book, is a public explanation,
Maimonides seems to be compelled by his intention to transgress the Law.
There were other cases in which he was under such a compulsion. The Law
also forbids one to study the books of idolaters on idolatry, for the first in¬
tention of the Law as a whole is to destroy every vestige of idolatry; and yet
Maimonides, as he openly admits and even emphasizes, has studied all the
available idolatrous books of this kind with the utmost thoroughness. Nor
is this all. He goes so far as to encourage the reader of the Guide to study
those books by himself (III 29-30, 32, 37; Mishneh Torah, H. ‘Abodah
Zarah II 2 and III 2). The Law also forbids one to speculate about the
date of the coming of the Messiah; yet Maimonides presents such a specu¬
lation or at least its equivalent in order to comfort his contemporaries
(Epistle to Yemen, 62, 16 ff., and 80, 17 ff. Halkin; cf. Halkin’s Introduc¬
tion, pp. xii-xiii; M.T., H. Melakhim XII 2). Above all, the Law forbids
one to seek for the reasons of the commandments; yet Maimonides devotes
almost twenty-six chapters of the Guide to such seeking (III 26; cf. II 25).
All these irregularities have one and the same justification. Maimonides
transgresses the Law “for the sake of heaven,” that is, in order to uphold or
to fulfill the Law (I Introd. and III Introd.). Still, in the most important
case he does not, strictly speaking, transgress the Law, for his written
explanation of the secrets of the Law is not a public but a secret explana¬
tion. The secrecy is achieved in three ways. First, every word of the Guide
is chosen with exceeding care; since very few men are able or willing to
read with exceeding care, most men will fail to perceive the secret teaching.
Second, Maimonides deliberately contradicts himself, and if a man declares
both that a is b and that a is not b, he cannot be said to declare anything.
144 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Lastly, the “chapter headings” of the secret teaching are not presented in
an orderly fashion, but are scattered throughout the book. This permits us
to understand why the plan of the Guide is so obscure. Maimonides suc¬
ceeds immediately in obscuring the plan by failing to divide the book ex¬
plicitly into sections and subsections or by dividing it explicitly only into
three Parts and each Part into chapters without supplying the Parts and
the chapters with headings indicating the subject matter of the Parts or of
the chapters.
The plan of the Guide is not entirely obscure. No one can reasonably
doubt, for instance, that II 32-48, III 1-7, and III 25-50 form sections.
The plan is most obscure at the beginning, and it becomes clearer as one
proceeds; generally speaking, it is clearer in the second half (II 13-end)
than in the first half. The Guide is then not entirely devoted to secretly
transmitting chapter headings of the secret teaching. This does not mean
that the book is not in its entirety devoted to the true science of the Law.
It means that the true science of the Law is partly public. This is not sur¬
prising, for the teaching of the Law itself is of necessity partly public. Ac¬
cording to one statement, the core of the public teaching consists of the
assertions that God is one, that He alone is to be worshiped, that He is
incorporeal, that He is incomparable to any of His creatures, and that He
suffers from no defect and no passion (I 35). From other statements it
would appear that the acceptance of the Law on every level of compre¬
hension presupposes belief in God, in angels, and in prophecy (III 45) or
that the basic beliefs are those in God’s unity and in creation (II 13). In
brief one may say that the public teaching of the Law, insofar as it refers to
beliefs or to “views,” can be reduced to the thirteen “roots” (or dogmas)
which Maimonides had put together in his Commentary on the Mishnah.
That part of the true science of the Law which is devoted to the public
teaching of the Law or which is itself public has the task of demonstrating
the roots to the extent to which this is possible or of establishing the roots
by means of speculation (III 51 and 54). Being speculative, that part of the
true science of the Law is not exegetic; it is not necessarily in need of sup¬
port by biblical or talmudic texts (cf. II 45 beginning). Accordingly, about
20 per cent of the chapters of the Guide contain no biblical quotations,
and about 9 per cent of them contain no Hebrew or Aramaic expressions
whatever. It is not very difficult to see (especially on the basis of III 7 end,
23, and 28) that the Guide as devoted to speculation on the roots of the
Law or to the public teaching consists of sections II—III and V-VI as in¬
dicated in our scheme and that the sequence of these sections is rational;
but one cannot understand in this manner why the book is divided into
three Parts, or what sections I, IV, and VII and most, not to say all, sub¬
sections mean. The teaching of the Guide is then neither entirely public or
speculative nor entirely secret or exegetic. For this reason the plan of the
Guide is neither entirely obscure nor entirely clear.
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 145
Yet the Guide is a single whole. What then is the bond uniting its
exegetic and its speculative ingredients? One might imagine that while
speculation demonstrates the roots of the Law, exegesis proves that those
roots as demonstrated by speculation are in fact taught by the Law. But in
that case the Guide would open with chapters devoted to speculation; yet
the opposite is manifestly true. In addition, if the exegesis dealt with the
same subject matter as that speculation which demonstrates the public
teaching par excellence, namely, the roots of the Law, there would be no
reason why the exegesis should be secret. Maimonides does say that the
Account of the Beginning is the same as natural science and the Account
of the Chariot is the same as divine science (that is, the science of the in¬
corporeal beings or of God and the angels). This might lead one to think
that the public teaching is identical with what the philosophers teach,
while the secret teaching makes one understand the identity of the teach¬
ing of the philosophers with the secret teaching of the Law. One can safely
say that this thought proves to be untenable on almost every level of one’s
comprehending the Guide: the nonidentity of the teaching of the philos¬
ophers as a whole and the thirteen roots of the Law as a whole are the first
word and the last word of Maimonides. What he means by identifying the
core of philosophy (natural science and divine science) with the highest
secrets of the Law (the Account of the Beginning and the Account of the
Chariot) and therewith by somehow identifying the subject matter of
speculation with the subject matter of exegesis may be said to be the secret
par excellence of the Guide.
Let us then retrace our steps. The Guide contains a public teaching and
a secret teaching. The public teaching is addressed to every Jew, including
the vulgar; the secret teaching is addressed to the elite. The secret teaching
is of no use to the vulgar, and the elite does not need the Guide for being
apprised of the public teaching. To the extent to which the Guide is a
whole, or one work, it is addressed neither to the vulgar nor to the elite. To
whom then is it addressed? How legitimate and important this question is
appears from Maimonides’ remark that the chief purpose of the Guide is
to explain as far as possible the Account of the Beginning and the Account
of the Chariot “with a view to him for whom (the book) has been com¬
posed” (III beginning). Maimonides answers our question both explicitly
and implicitly. He answers it explicitly in two ways; he says on the one
hand that the Guide is addressed to believing Jews who are perfect in their
religion and in their character, have studied the sciences of the philoso¬
phers, and are perplexed by the literal meaning of the Law; he says on the
other hand that the book is addressed to such perfect human beings as are
Law students and perplexed. He answers our question more simply by
dedicating the book to his disciple Joseph and by stating that it has been
composed for Joseph and his like. Joseph had come to him “from the ends
of the earth” and had studied under him for a while; the interruption of
146 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
the oral instruction through Joseph’s departure, which “God had decreed,”
induced Maimonides to write the Guide for Joseph and his like. In the
Epistle Dedicatory addressed to Joseph, Maimonides extols Joseph's virtues
and indicates his limitation. Joseph had a passionate desire for things spec¬
ulative and especially for mathematics. When he studied astronomy,
mathematics, and logic under Maimonides, the teacher saw that Joseph
had an excellent mind and a quick grasp; he thought him therefore fit to
have revealed to him allusively the secrets of the books of the prophets,
and he began to make such revelations. This stimulated Joseph’s interest in
things divine as well as in an appraisal of the Kalam; his desire for knowl¬
edge about these subjects became so great that Maimonides was compelled
to warn him unceasingly to proceed in an orderly manner. It appears that
Joseph was inclined to proceed impatiently or unmethodically in his study
and that this defect had not been cured when he left Maimonides. The
most important consequence of Joseph’s defect is the fact, brought out by
Maimonides’ silence, that Joseph turned to divine science without having
studied natural science under Maimonides or before, although natural
science necessarily precedes divine science in the order of study.
The impression derived from the Epistle Dedicatory is confirmed by the
book itself. Maimonides frequently addresses the reader by using expres¬
sions like “know” or “you know already.” Expressions of the latter kind
indicate what the typical addressee knows, and expressions of the former
kind indicate what he does not know. One thus learns that Joseph has
some knowledge of both the content and the character of divine science.
He knows, for example, that divine science in contradistinction to mathe¬
matics and medicine requires an extreme of rectitude and moral perfec¬
tion, and in particular of humility, but he apparently does not yet know
how ascetic Judaism is in matters of sex (I 34, III 52). He had learned from
Maimonides’ “speech” that the orthodox “views” do not last in a man if
he does not confirm them by the corresponding “actions” (II 31). It goes
without saying that while his knowledge of the Jewish sources is extensive,
it is not comparable in extent and thoroughness to Maimonides’ (II 26,
33). At the beginning of the book he does not know that both according
to the Jewish view and according to demonstration, angels have no bodies
(I 43, 49), and he certainly does not know, strictly speaking, that God has
no body (I 9). In this respect as well as in other respects his understanding
necessarily progresses while he advances in his study of the Guide (cf. I 65
beginning). As for natural science, he has studied astronomy, but is not
aware of the conflict between the astronomical principles and the prin¬
ciples of natural science (II 24), because he has not studied natural sci¬
ence. He knows a number of things that are made clear in natural science,
but this does not mean that he knows them through having studied natural
science (cf. I 17, 28; III 10). From the ninety-first chapter (II 15) it
appears that while he knows Aristotle’s Topics and Farabi’s commentary
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 147
on that work, he does not know the Physics and On the Heaven (cf. II 8).
Nor will he acquire the science of nature as he acquires the science of God
and the angels while he advances in the study of the Guide. For the Guide,
which is addressed to a reader not conversant with natural science, does
not itself transmit natural science (II 2). The following remark occurring
in the twenty-sixth chapter is particularly revealing: “It has been demon¬
strated that everything moved undoubtedly possesses a magnitude and is
divisible; and it will be demonstrated that God possesses no magnitude and
hence possesses no motion.” What “has been demonstrated” has been
demonstrated in the Physics and is simply presupposed in the Guide; what
“will be demonstrated” belongs to divine science and not to natural sci¬
ence; but that which “will be demonstrated” is built on what “has been
demonstrated.” The student of the Guide acquires knowledge of divine
science, but not of natural science. The author of the Guide in contradis¬
tinction to its addressee is thoroughly versed in natural science. Still, the
addressee needs some awareness of the whole in order to be able to ascend
from the whole to God, for there is no way to knowledge of God except
through such ascent (I 71 toward the end); he acquires that awareness
through a report of some kind (I 70) that Maimonides has inserted into
the Guide. It is characteristic of that report that it does not contain a
single mention of philosophy in general and of natural science in partic¬
ular. The serious student cannot rest satisfied with that report; he must
turn from it to natural science itself, which demonstrates what the report
merely asserts. Maimonides cannot but leave it to his reader whether he
will turn to genuine speculation or whether he will be satisfied with ac¬
cepting the report on the authority of Maimonides and with building on
that report theological conclusions. The addressee of the Guide is a man
regarding whom it is still undecided whether he will become a genuine
man of speculation or whether he will remain a follower of authority, if of
Maimonides’ authority (cf. I 72 end). He stands at the point of the road
where speculation branches off from acceptance of authority.
Why did Maimonides choose an addressee of this description? What is
the virtue of not being trained in natural science? We learn from the
seventeenth chapter that natural science had already been treated as a
secret doctrine by the pagan philosophers “upon whom the charge of cor¬
ruption would not be laid if they exposed natural science clearly”: all the
more is the community of the Law-adherents obliged to treat natural sci¬
ence as a secret science. The reason why natural science is dangerous and is
kept secret “with all kinds of artifices” is not that it undermines the
Law—only the ignorant believe that (I 33), and Maimonides’ whole life as
well as the life of his successors refutes this suspicion. Yet it is also true
that natural science has this corrupting effect on all men who are not per¬
fect (cf. I 62). For natural science surely affects the understanding of the
meaning of the Law, of the grounds on which it is to be obeyed, and of the
148 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
but not to the rejection of the worship of other gods: all gods may be in¬
corporeal. Only if the belief in God’s incorporeality is based on the belief
in His unity, as Maimonides’ argument indeed assumes, does the belief in
God's incorporeality appear to be the necessary and sufficient ground for
rejecting “forbidden worship” in every form, that is, the worship of other
gods as well as the worship of both natural things and artificial things. This
would mean that the prohibition against idolatry in the widest sense is as
much a dictate of reason as the belief in God’s unity and incorporeality.
Yet Maimonides indicates that only the theoretical truths pronounced in
the Decalogue (God’s existence and His unity), in contradistinction to the
rest of the Decalogue, are rational. This is in agreement with his denying
the existence of rational commandments or prohibitions as such (II 33; cf.
I 54, II 31 beginning, III 28; Eight Chapters VI). Given the fact that Aris¬
totle believed in God’s unity and incorporeality and yet was an idolater (I
71, III 29), Maimonides’ admiration for him would be incomprehensible if
the rejection of idolatry were the simple consequence of that belief. Ac¬
cording to Maimonides, the Law agrees with Aristotle in holding that the
heavenly bodies are endowed with life and intelligence and that they are
superior to man in dignity; one could say that he agrees with Aristotle in
implying that those holy bodies deserve more than man to be called images
of God. But unlike the philosophers he does not go so far as to call those
bodies “divine bodies” (II 4-6; cf. Letter to Ibn Tibbon). The true
ground of the rejection of “forbidden worship” is the belief in creation out
of nothing, which implies that creation is an absolutely free act of God or
that God alone is the complete good that is in no way increased by cre¬
ation. But creation is according to Maimonides not demonstrable, whereas
God’s unity and incorporeality are demonstrable. The reasoning underlying
the determination of the initial theme of the Guide can then be described
as follows: it conceals the difference of cognitive status between the belief
in God’s unity and incorporeality on the one hand and the belief in crea¬
tion on the other; it is in accordance with the opinion of the Kalam. In
accordance with this, Maimonides brings his disagreement with Ka¬
lam into the open only after he has concluded his thematic discussion of
God’s incorporeality; in that discussion he does not even mention the
Kalam.
It is necessary that we understand as clearly as possible the situation in
which Maimonides and his addressee find themselves at the beginning of
the book, if not throughout the book. Maimonides knows that God is in¬
corporeal; he knows this by a demonstration that is at least partly based on
natural science. The addressee does not know that God is incorporeal; nor
does he learn it yet from Maimonides: he accepts the fact that God’s in-
corporeality is demonstrated, on Maimonides’ authority. Both Maimonides
and the addressee know that the Law is a source of knowledge of God;
only the Law can establish God’s incorporeality for the addressee in a man-
152 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
ner that does not depend on Maimonides’ authority. But both know that
the literal meaning of the Law is not always its true meaning and that the
literal meaning is certainly not the true meaning when it contradicts rea¬
son, for otherwise the Law could not be “your wisdom and your under¬
standing in the sight of the nations” (Deut. 4:6). Both know, in other
words, that exegesis does not simply precede speculation. Yet only Mai¬
monides knows that the corporealistic expressions of the Law are against
reason and must therefore be taken as figurative. The addressee does not
know and cannot know that Maimonides’ figurative interpretations of
those expressions are true: Maimonides does not adduce arguments based
on grammar. The addressee accepts Maimonides’ interpretations just as he
is in the habit of accepting the Aramaic translations as correct translations
or interpretations. Maimonides enters the ranks of the traditional Jewish
authorities: he simply tells the addressee what to believe regarding the
meaning of the biblical terms. Maimonides introduces reason in the guise
of authority. He takes on the garb of authority. He tells the addressee to
believe in God’s incorporeality because, as he tells him, contrary to appear¬
ance, the Law does not teach corporeality, because, as he tells him, corpo¬
reality is a demonstrably wrong belief.
But we must not forget the most important atypical addressee, the
reader who is critical and competent. He knows the demonstration of
God’s incorporeality and the problems connected with it as well as Mai¬
monides does. 4 herefore the exegetic discussion of God’s incorporeality
which is presented in the first forty-nine chapters of the Guide, and which
is prespeculative and hence simply public as far as the typical addressee is
concerned, is postspeculative and hence secret from the point of view of
the critical and competent reader. The latter will examine Maimonides’
explanations of biblical terms in the light of the principle that one cannot
establish the meanings of a term if one does not consider the contexts in
which they occur (II 29; cf. Epistle to Yemen 46, 7 ff.) or that while gram¬
mar is not a sufficient condition, it is surely the necessary condition of
interpretation. For while the competent reader will appreciate the advan¬
tages attendant upon a coherent discussion of the biblical terms in ques¬
tion as distinguished from a translation of the Bible, he will realize that
such a discussion may make one oblivious of the contexts in which the
terms occur. He will also notice contradictions occurring in the Guide, re¬
member always that they are intentional, and ponder over them.
The readers of the Guide were told at the beginning that the first pur¬
pose of the book is the explanation of biblical terms. They will then in no
way be surprised to find that the book opens with the explanation of bib¬
lical terms in such a way that, roughly speaking, each chapter is devoted to
the explanation of one or several biblical terms. They will soon become
habituated to this procedure: they become engrossed by the subject mat¬
ter, the What, and will not observe the How. The critical reader, however.
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 153
will find many reasons for becoming amazed. To say nothing of other con¬
siderations, he will wonder why almost the only terms explained are those
suggesting corporeality. It is perhaps not a matter of surprise that one
chapter is devoted to the explanation of “place” and another to the expla¬
nation of “to dwell.” But why is there no chapter devoted to “one,” none
to “merciful,” none to “good,” none to “intelligence,” none to “eternity”?
Why is there a chapter devoted to “grief” and none to “laughter”? Why is
there a chapter devoted to “foot” and another to “wing,” but none to
“hand” nor to “arm”? Assuming that one has understood Maimonides’
selection of terms, one still has to understand the order in which he dis¬
cusses them. To what extent the explanation of terms is limited to terms
suggesting corporeality appears with particular clarity when one considers
especially those chapters that are most visibly devoted to the explanation of
terms, the lexicographic chapters. By a lexicographic chapter I understand
a chapter that opens with the Hebrew term or terms to be explained in the
chapter regardless of whether these terms precede the first sentence or
form the beginning of the first sentence and regardless of whether these
terms are supplied with the Arabic article al- or not. The lexicographic
chapter may be said to be the normal or typical chapter in the discussion of
God’s incorporeality (I 1-49); thirty out of the forty-nine chapters in
question are lexicographic, whereas in the whole rest of the book there oc¬
cur at most two such chapters (I 66 and 70). All these thirty chapters oc¬
cur in I 1-45: two-thirds of the chapters in I 1-45 are lexicographic. Thus
the question arises why nineteen chapters of the discussion of God’s incor¬
poreality—and just the nineteen chapters having both the subject matters
and the places that they do—are not lexicographic. Why do ten of these
thirty lexicographic chapters begin with Hebrew terms preceding the first
sentence and twenty of them begin with Hebrew terms forming part of the
first sentence? Thirteen of the terms in question are nouns, twelve are
verbs, and five are verbal nouns: why does Maimonides in some cases use
the verbs and in other cases the verbal nouns? Within the chapters, gener¬
ally speaking, he discusses the term that is the subject of the chapter in
question, first in regard to the various meanings it has when it is not ap¬
plied to God and then in regard to the various meanings it has when ap¬
plied to God; he proves the existence of each of these meanings in most
cases by quoting one or more biblical passages; those quotations are some¬
times explicitly incomplete (ending in “and so on”) and more frequently
not; the quotations used to illustrate a particular meaning of a particular
term do not always follow the biblical order; they are frequently introduced
by “he said,” but sometimes they are ascribed to individual biblical authors
or speakers; in most cases he does not add to the name of the biblical au¬
thor or speaker the formula “may he rest in peace,” but in some cases he
does; sometimes “the Hebrew language” or “the language” is referred to.
In a book as carefully worded as is the Guide according to Maimonides'
154 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
emphatic declaration, all these varieties, and others that we forgo men¬
tioning, deserve careful consideration. It goes without saying that there is
not necessarily only one answer to each of the questions implied in each of
these varieties; the same device—for example, the distinction between lexi¬
cographic and nonlexicographic chapters or the tracing of a biblical quota¬
tion to an individual biblical author—may fulfill different functions in
different contexts. In order to understand the Guide, one must be fully
awake and as it were take nothing for granted. In order to become enabled
to raise the proper questions, one does well to consider the possibility that
there exists the typical chapter or else to construct the typical chapter, that
is, to find out which of the varieties indicated are most in accordance with
the primary function of the chapters devoted to the explanation of biblical
terms: only the other varieties are in need of a special reason.
The first chapter of the Guide is devoted to “image and likeness." The
selection of these terms was necessitated by a single biblical passage: “And
God said, Let us make man in our image, after our likeness. ... So God
created man in his image, in the image of God created he him, male and
female created he them" (Gen. 1:26-27). The selection of these terms for
explanation in the first chapter is due to the unique significance of the pas¬
sage quoted. That passage suggests to the vulgar mind more strongly than
any other biblical passage that God is corporeal in the crudest sense: God
has the shape of a human being, has a face, lips, and hands, but is bigger
and more resplendent than man since He does not consist of flesh and
blood, and is therefore in need, not of food and drink, but of odors; His
place is in Heaven from which He descends to the earth, especially to high
mountains, in order to guide men and to find out what they do, and to
which He ascends again with incredible swiftness; He is moved, as men
are, by passions, especially by anger, jealousy, and hate, and thus makes
men frightened and sad; His essence is Will rather than Intellect. (Cf. I
10, 20, 36-37, 39, 43, 46, 47, 68.) Maimonides tells his addressee that
$elem (the Hebrew term which is rendered by “image”) does not mean, if
not exactly in any case, but certainly in the present case, a visible shape; it
means the natural form, the specific form, the essence of a being: “God
created man in his image” means that God created man as a being en¬
dowed with intellect or that the divine intellect links itself with man.
Similar considerations apply to the Hebrew term rendered by “likeness."
The Hebrew term designating form in the sense of visible shape is to’ar,
which is never applied to God. After having dispelled the confusion regard¬
ing image” Maimonides says: “We have explained to thee the difference
between selem and to’ar and we have explained the meaning of $elem.”
He thus alludes to the twofold character of his explanation here as well as
elsewhere: one explanation is given to “thee," that is, to the typical
addressee, and another is given to indeterminate readers; the latter expla¬
nation comes to sight only when one considers, among other things, the
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 155
context of all biblical passages quoted. To mention only one example, the
second of the three quotations illustrating the meaning of to’ar is “What
form is he of?” (I Sam. 28:14). The quotation is taken from the account
of King Saul’s conversation with the witch of Endor, whom the king had
asked to bring up to him the dead prophet Samuel; when the woman saw
Samuel and became frightened and the king asked her what she saw, she
said: “I saw gods (elohim) ascending out of the earth.” The account con¬
tinues as follows: “And he said unto her, What form is he of? And she
said: an old man cometh up; and he is covered with a mantle.” Mai-
monides himself tells us in the next chapter that elohim is an equivocal
term that may mean angels and rulers of cities as well as God; but this does
not explain why that term is also applied to the shades of the venerable
departed—beings without flesh and blood—which frighten men either be¬
cause those shades do not wish to be “disquieted,” that is, they wish to rest
in peace, or for other reasons. To say nothing of other reasons, the rational
beings inhabiting the lowest depth are in truth not men who have died,
but all living men, the Adamites, that is, the descendants of Adam, who
lack Adam’s pristine intellectuality (cf. I 2 with I 10). It looks as if Mai-
monides wished to draw our attention to the fact that the Bible contains
idolatrous, pagan, or “Sabian” relics. If this suspicion should prove to be
justified, we would have to assume that his fight against “forbidden wor¬
ship” and hence against corporealism is more radical than one would be in¬
clined to believe or that the recovery of Sabian relics in the Bible with the
help of Sabian literature is one of the tasks of his secret teaching.
However this may be, his interpretation of Genesis 1:26 seems to be
contradicted by the fact that the Torah speaks shortly afterward of the di¬
vine prohibition addressed to man against eating of the fruit of the tree of
knowledge: if man was created as an intellectual being and hence destined
for the life of the intellect, his Creator could not well have forbidden him
to strive for knowledge. In other words, the biblical account implies that
man’s intellectuality is not identical with man's being created in the image
of God, but is a consequence of his disobedience to God or of God’s pun¬
ishing him for that sin. As we are told in the second chapter, this objection
was raised, not by the addressee of the Guide, but by another acquaintance
of Maimonides, a nameless scientist of whom we do not even know
whether he was of Jewish extraction and who was apparently not very
temperate in regard to drink and to sex. (Compare the parallel in III 19.)
Maimonides tells his addressee that he replied to his objector as follows:
the knowledge that was forbidden to man was the knowledge of “good and
evil,” that is, of the noble and base, and the noble and base are objects not
of the intellect, but of opinion; strictly speaking they are not objects of
knowledge at all. To mention only the most important example, in man’s
perfect state, in which he was unaware of the noble and base, although he
was aware of the naturally good and bad, that is, of the pleasant and pain-
156 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
may very well be threats to Israel’s enemies. A talmudic passage that con¬
firms Maimonides’ public explanation and in which “sitting” is mentioned
together, not with “rising,” but with “standing up” naturally leads to the
discussion of “standing up” (I 13), which term, according to Maimonides,
means, if applied to God, His unchangeability—an unchangeability not
contradicted, as he indicates, by God’s threats to destroy Israel.
Having arrived at this point, Maimonides interrupts his discussion of
verbs or of other terms that refer to place and turns to the explanation of
“man” (I 14). A similar interruption occurs shortly afterward when he
turns from “standing” and “rock” (I 15 and 16) to an explanation of the
prohibition against the public teaching of natural science (I 17). Although
these chapters are subtly interwoven with the chapters preceding and fol¬
lowing them, at first glance they strikingly interrupt the continuity of the
argument. By this irregularity our attention is drawn to a certain numerical
symbolism that is of assistance to the serious reader of the Guide: 14
stands for man or the human things and 17 stands for nature. The connec¬
tion between “nature” and “change of place” (or, more generally, mo¬
tion), and therewith the connection between the theme of I 17 and the
subsection to which that chapter belongs, has been indicated before. The
connection between “14” and the context cannot become clear before we
have reached a better understanding of the relation between nature and
convention; at present it must suffice to say that I 7 deals with “to gener¬
ate.” Although I 26 obviously deals with terms referring to place, it also
fulfills a numerological function: the immediate theme of that chapter is
the universal principle governing the interpretation of the Torah (“the
Torah speaks according to the language of human beings”); 26 is the
numerical equivalent of the secret name of the Lord, the God of Israel; 26
may therefore also stand for His Torah. Incidentally, it may be remarked
that 14 is the numerical equivalent of the Hebrew for “hand”; I 28 is de¬
voted to “foot”: no chapter of the Guide is devoted to “hand,” the char¬
acteristically human organ, whereas Maimonides devotes a chapter, the
central chapter of the fourth subsection, to “wing,” the organ used for
swift descent and ascent. In all these matters one can derive great help
from studying Joseph Albo’s Roots. Albo was a favorite companion living
at the court of a great king.
Of the twenty-one chapters of the second subsection sixteen are lexico¬
graphic and five (I 10, 14, 17, 26, 27) are not. Of these sixteen chapters
two begin with Hebrew terms supplied with the Arabic article (I 23 and
24). Thus only seven of the twenty-one chapters may be said to vary from
the norm. In seven of the fourteen chapters beginning with a pure Hebrew
term, tnat term precedes the first sentence, and in the seven others the
Hebrew term forms part of the first sentence. Seven of these chapters be¬
gin with a verb and seven with a noun or a verbal noun. It is one thing to
observe these regularities and another thing to understand them. The dis-
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 159
tinction between the verbs and the verbal nouns is particularly striking,
since lexicographic chapters beginning with verbal nouns occur only in one
subsection. Furthermore, of the three lexicographic chapters of the first
subsection, one opens with nouns preceding the first sentence, one with
nouns forming part of the first sentence, and one with a verb preceding the
first sentence; orderliness would seem to require that there be a chapter
opening with a verb that forms part of the first sentence. One of the chap¬
ters of the second subsection (I 22) begins with a verb preceding the first
sentence, but the first sentence opens with the verbal noun (supplied with
the Arabic article) of the same verb; there occurs no other case of this kind
in the whole book. If we count this ambiguous chapter among the chapters
beginning with a verbal noun forming part of the first sentence, we reach
this conclusion: the second subsection contains four chapters beginning
with verbs or verbal nouns preceding the first sentence and eight chapters
beginning with verbs or verbal nouns forming part of the first sentence.
Furthermore, the second subsection contains six chapters beginning with
verbs and six chapters beginning with verbal nouns; of the latter six chap¬
ters three begin with pure verbal nouns and three begin with verbal nouns
supplied with the Arabic article. The second subsection surpasses the first
subsection in regularity especially if I 22 is properly subsumed. From all
this we are led to regard it as possible that I 22 somehow holds the key to
the mystery of the second subsection.
The first chapter of the second subsection (18) is devoted to “place,” a
term that in postbiblical Hebrew is used for designating God Himself. To
our great amazement Maimonides is completely silent about this meaning
of “place.” His silence is all the more eloquent since he quotes in this very
chapter postbiblical Hebrew expressions containing “place,” since he ad¬
monishes the readers in this very chapter to consult regarding his explana¬
tion of any term not only “the books of prophecy” but also other
“compilations of men of science”—Talmud and Midrash are such compila¬
tions—and since he has concluded the preceding chapter with a quotation
from the Midrash. In the only other lexicographic chapter devoted to a
term used for designating God Himself—in I 16, which is devoted to
“rock”—he does not hesitate to say that that term is also used for desig¬
nating God, for that meaning of “rock” is biblical. We see then how liter¬
ally he meant his declaration that the first intention of the Guide is to
explain terms occurring in “the books of prophecy,” that is, primarily in
the Bible: he is primarily concerned with the theology of the Bible in
contradistinction to postbiblical Jewish theology. He is alive to the ques¬
tion raised by the Karaites. As he puts it, not only does criticism of the
talmudic Sages do no harm to them—it does not even do any harm to the
critic or rather to the foundations of belief (I Introd., 5 end, 19 end, 46
end; cf. Resurrection 29, 10-30, 15 Finkel). This observation enables us to
solve the difficulty presented by I 22.
160 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
The reason why progress beyond the teaching of the Torah is possible or
even necessary is twofold. In the first place, the Torah is the law par excel¬
lence. The supremacy of Moses' prophecy—the superiority of Moses’
knowledge even to that of the Patriarchs—is connected with its being the
only legislative prophecy (I 63, II 13, 39). But precisely because his
prophecy culminates in the Law, it reflects the limitations of law. Law is
more concerned with actions than with thoughts (III 27-28; I Introd.).
Mosaic theology reflects this orientation. According to the opinion of many
of our contemporaries, Maimonides’ theological doctrine proper is his doc¬
trine of the divine attributes (I 50-60). In that subsection he quotes pas¬
sages from the Torah only in that single chapter (I 54) in which he dis¬
cusses the thirteen divine attributes revealed to Moses (Exod. 34:5-7);
those attributes—all of them moral qualities—constitute the Mosaic theol¬
ogy; they express positively what in negative expression is called in the
same context “God’s back parts.” Although God’s goodness had been re¬
vealed to Moses in its entirety, the thirteen attributes articulate only that
part of God’s goodness which is relevant for the ruler of a city who is a
prophet. Such a ruler must imitate the divine attributes of wrath and
mercy, not as passions—for the incorporeal God is above all passion—but
because actions of mercy or wrath are appropriate in the circumstances,
and he must imitate God’s mercy and wrath in due proportion. The ruler
of a city, on the other hand, must be more merciful than full of anger, for
extreme punitiveness is required only because of the necessity, based on
“human opinion,” to exterminate the idolaters by fire and sword (I 54).
Following another suggestion of Maimonides (I 61-63) one could say
that the adequate statement of Mosaic theology is contained in the divine
name YHVH—a name by which God revealed Himself for the first time
to Moses as distinguished from the Patriarchs: “I appeared unto Abraham,
unto Isaac, and unto Jacob, by the name of God Almighty, but by my
name YHVH was I not known to them” (Exod. 6:3). Maimonides recog¬
nizes that this verse asserts or establishes the superiority of Moses’
prophecy to that of the Patriarchs (II 35), but he does not explain that
verse: he does not explain, at least not clearly, which theological verities
other than the thirteen attributes were revealed to Moses, but were un¬
known to the Patriarchs. Only this much may be said to emerge: Abraham
was a man of speculation who instructed his subjects or followers, rather
than a prophet who convinced by miracles and ruled by means of promises
and threats, and this is somehow connected with the fact that he called
“on the name of YHVH, the God of the world” (Gen. 21:33) (I 63, II
13), that is, the God of the transmoral whole rather than the law-giving
God. It is this Abrahamitic expression that opens each Part of the Guide as
well as other writings of Maimonides. Considering all these things, one will
find it wise to limit oneself to saying that the Mosaic theology par excel¬
lence is the doctrine of the thirteen moral attributes.
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 163
Second, the Mosaic legislation was contemporary with the yet unbroken
and universal rule of Sabianism. Therefore the situation in the time of
Moses was not different from the situation in the time of Abraham, who
disagreed with all men, all men having the same Sabian religion or belong¬
ing to the same religious community. The innovation was naturally re¬
sisted, even with violence, although it was not a principle of Sabianism to
exterminate unbelievers. Yet the Torah has only one purpose: to destroy
Sabianism or idolatry. But the resistance by the Sabians proper was less
important than the inner Sabianism of the early adherents of the Torah. It
was primarily for this reason that Sabianism could be overcome only grad¬
ually: human nature does not permit the direct transition from one
opposite to the other. To mention only the most obvious example, our an¬
cestors had been habituated to sacrifice to natural or artificial creatures.
The sacrificial laws of the Torah are a concession to that habit. Since the
simple prohibition or cessation of sacrifices would have been as unintel¬
ligible or distasteful to our ancestors as the prohibition or cessation of
prayer would be now, God provided that henceforth all sacrifices be trans¬
ferred to Him and no longer be brought to any false gods or idols. The
sacrificial laws constitute a step in the gradual transition, in the progress
from Sabianism to pure worship, that is, pure knowledge, of God (cf. I 54,
64); the sacrificial laws were necessary only “at that time.” The Sabians
believed that success in agriculture depends on worship of the heavenly
bodies. In order to eradicate that belief, God teaches in the Torah that
worship of the heavenly bodies leads to disaster in agriculture, whereas
worship of God leads to prosperity. For the reason given, the open depre¬
cation of sacrifices as such occurs not yet in the Torah, but in the prophets
and in the Psalms. Conversely, the Torah is less explicit than the later doc¬
uments regarding the duty of prayer (III 29, 30, 32, 35-37).
No less important an adaptation to Sabian habits is the corporealism of
the Bible. For Sabianism is a form of corporealism; according to the Sabi¬
ans, the gods are the heavenly bodies or the heavenly bodies are the body
of which God is the spirit (III 29). As for the Bible, Maimonides’ teaching
on this subject is not free from ambiguity. The first impression we receive
from his teaching is that according to it the corporealistic understanding of
the Bible is a mere misunderstanding. For instance, selem simply does not
mean visible shape, but only natural form, and even if it should sometimes
mean visible shape, the term must be considered to be homonymous, and
it certainly does not mean visible shape, but natural form, in Genesis
1:26-27 (I 1; cf. I 49). In other cases, perhaps in most cases, the primary
meaning of the term—say, “sitting”—is corporealistic, but when it is ap¬
plied to God, it is used in a derivative or metaphoric sense; in those cases
the meaning of the text, the literal meaning, is metaphoric. Generally
stated, the literal meaning of the Bible is not corporealistic. But there are
also cases in which the literal meaning is corporealistic, for instance, in the
164 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
many cases in which the Bible speaks of God’s anger (cf. I 29). One must
go beyond this and say that generally speaking the literal meaning of the
Bible is corporealistic because “the Torah speaks in accordance with the
language of the children of Man,” that is, in accordance with “the imag¬
ination of the vulgar,” and the vulgar mind does not admit, at least to
being with, the existence of any being that is not bodily; the Torah there¬
fore describes God in corporealistic terms in order to indicate that He is (I
26, 47, 51 end). The Bible contains indeed innumerable passages directed
against idolatry (I 36), but, as we have seen, idolatry is one thing and cor-
porealism is another. The corporealistic meaning is not the only meaning,
it is not the deepest meaning, it is not the true meaning, but it is as much
intended as the true meaning; it is intended because of the need to educate
and to guide the vulgar and, we may add, a vulgar that originally was alto¬
gether under the spell of Sabianism. What is true of the biblical similes is
true also of the metaphoric biblical terms. According to the talmudic
Sages, the outer of the similes is nothing, while the inner is a pearl; ac¬
cording to King Solomon, who was “wiser than all men” (I Kings 5:11),
the outer is like silver, that is, it is useful for the ordering of human society,
and the inner is like gold: it conveys true beliefs (I Introd.). Hence it is
not without danger to the vulgar that one explains the similes or indicates
the metaphoric character of expressions (I 33). For such biblical teachings
as the assertions that God is angry, compassionate, or in other ways
changeable, while not true, yet serve a political purpose or are necessary
beliefs (III 28).
A third possibility emerges through Maimonides’ thematic discussion of
providence. There he makes a distinction between the view of the Law re¬
garding providence and the true view (III 17, 23). He could well have said
that the true view is the secret teaching of the Law. Instead he says that
the true view is conveyed through the book of Job, thus implying that the
book of Job, a nonprophetic book whose characters are not Jews and that is
composed by an unknown author (II 45; Epistle to Yemen 50, 19-52, 1
Halkin), marks a progress beyond the Torah and even beyond the
prophets (cf. Ill 19). We recall that the simple co-ordination, taught by
the Torah, of the worship of the Lord with agricultural and other pros¬
perity was merely a restatement of the corresponding Sabian doctrine. As
Maimonides indicates when explaining the account of the revelation on
Mount Sinai, the beautiful consideration of the texts is the consideration
of their outer meaning (II 36 end, 37). This remark occurs within the sec¬
tion on prophecy in which he makes for the first time an explicit distinc¬
tion between the legal (or exegetic) and the speculative discussion of the
same subject (cf. II 45 beginning). Accordingly, he speaks in his explana¬
tion of the Account of the Chariot, at any rate apparently, only of the lit¬
eral meaning of this most secret text (III Introd.). Or to state the matter
as succinctly as Maimonides does in the last chapter, the science of the
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 165
11); but God Himself cannot explain clearly the deepest secrets of the
Torah to flesh and blood (I Introd., 31 beginning); He “speaks in ac¬
cordance with the language of the children of man” (I 26); things that
might have been made clear in the Torah are not made clear in it (I 29);
God makes use of ruses and of silence, for only “a fool will reveal all his
purpose and his will” (I 40; cf. Ill 32, 45 and 54); and, last but not least,
as Maimonides explains in the Guide, God does not use speech in any
sense (I 23), and this fact entails infinite consequences. One is therefore
tempted to say that the infrarational in the Bible is distinguished from the
suprarational by the fact that the former is impossible, whereas the latter is
possible: biblical utterances that contradict what has been demonstrated
by natural science or by reason in any other form cannot be literally true,
but must have an inner meaning; on the other hand, one must not reject
views the contrary of which has not been demonstrated, that is, which are
possible—for instance, creation out of nothing—lest one become thor¬
oughly indecent (I 32, II 25).
Yet this solution does not satisfy Maimonides. Whereas he had orig¬
inally declared that the human faculty that distinguishes between the pos¬
sible and the impossible is the intellect, and not the imagination, he is
compelled, especially in his chapters on providence, to question this verdict
and to leave it open whether it is not rather the imagination that ought to
have the last word (I 49, 73, III 15). He is therefore induced to say that
the certainty of belief is one’s awareness of the impossibility of the alterna¬
tive or that the very existence of God is doubtful if it is not demonstrated
or that man’s intellect can understand what any intelligent being under¬
stands (I 50 and 51 beginning, 71, III 17). This is acceptable if the
Account of the Beginning and the Account of the Chariot are indeed
identical with natural science and divine science and if these sciences are
demonstrative. But this enigmatic equation leaves obscure the place or the
status of the fact of God’s free creation of the world out of nothing: does
this fact belong to the Account of the Beginning or to the Account of the
Chariot or to both or to neither? (Cf. Commentary on the Mishnah,
Hagigah II 1.) According to the Guide, the Account of the Chariot deals
with God’s governance of the world, in contradistinction not only to His
providence (cf. I 44 on the one hand, and on the other I 40, where Mai¬
monides refers to III 2 and not, as most commentators believe, to the
chapters on providence, just as in III 2 he refers to I 40) but also to His
creation. By considering the relation of the Account of the Beginning and
the Account of the Chariot, one is enabled also to answer completely the
question that has led us to the present difficulty: the question concerning
the order of rank between the Mosaic theophany and the Isaian the-
ophany. The Account of the Beginning occurs in the Torah of Moses, but
the Account of the Chariot, which is identical with the divine science or
the apprehension of God (I 34), occurs in the book of Ezekiel and in its
168 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
highest form precisely in the sixth chapter of Isaiah (III 6; cf. also the
quotations from the Torah on the one hand and from other biblical books
on the other in III 54).
Once one has granted that there is an intrabiblical process beyond the
teaching of Moses, one will not be compelled to deny the possibility of a
postbiblical progress of this description. The fact of such a progress can be
proved only if there are characteristic differences between the Bible and
the postbiblical authoritative books. We could not help referring, for in¬
stance, to Maimonides’ tacit confrontation of the talmudic view according
to which the outer of the similes is “nothing” and of Solomon’s view ac¬
cording to which it is “silver,” that is, politically useful; taken by itself this
confrontation suggests that Solomon appreciated the political to a higher
degree than did the talmudic Sages. The differences in question are to
some extent concealed, since the postbiblical view ordinarily appears in the
guise of an explanation of a biblical text. Maimonides discusses this diffi¬
culty in regard to homiletic, rather than legal, explanations; he rejects both
the opinion that these explanations are genuine explanations of biblical
texts and the opinion that since they are not genuine explanations, they
ought not to be taken seriously; in fact the talmudic Sages used a poetic or
a charming device, playing as it were with the text of the Bible, in order to
introduce moral lessons not found in the Bible (III 43). He indicates that
he will not stress his critique of the talmudic Sages (III 14 end). Since the
emphasis on serious differences between the Bible and the Talmud could
appear in the eyes of the vulgar as a criticism of the talmudic Sages, he has
spoken on this subject with considerable, although not extraordinary, re¬
straint. Whenever he presents a view as a view of the Law, one must con¬
sider whether he supports his thesis at all by biblical passages and, if he
does so, whether the support is sufficient according to his standards as dis¬
tinguished from traditional Jewish standards. In other words, in studying a
given chapter or group of chapters one must observe whether he uses
therein any postbiblical Jewish quotations at all and what is the proportion
in both number and weight of postbiblical to biblical quotations.
In the first chapter explicitly dealing with providence (III 17), he speaks
of an addition” to the text of the Torah that occurs “in the discourse of
the Sages”; as one would expect, he disapproves of this particular “addi¬
tion. This statement is prepared by an immediately preceding cluster of
talmudic quotations that are in manifest agreement with the teaching of
the Torah and that strike us with particular force because of the almost
complete absence of talmudic quotations after the end of III 10. In this
twofold way he prepares his silence on the future life in his presentation of
the Torah view on providence: the solution of the problem of providence
by recourse to the future life is more characteristic of the postbiblical
teaching than of the Bible. According to the talmudic Sages, “in the future
life there is no eating, nor drinking” and this means that the future life is
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 169
not, it is even indispensable for the defense of the Law. Kalam entered
Judaism long after the talmudic period, in the Gaonic period (I 71, 73).
All the more must the introduction of philosophy into Judaism be re¬
garded as a great progress, if it is introduced in due subordination to the
Law or in the proper manner (that is, as Maimonides introduced it to
begin with in his legal works). One must also consider the considerable
scientific progress that was made by both Greeks and Muslims after Aris¬
totle’s time (II 4, 19). All this does not mean, however, that Maimonides
regarded his age as the peak of wisdom. He never forgot the power of what
one may call the inverted Sabianism that perpetuates corporealism through
unqualified submission to the literal meaning of the Bible and thus even
outdoes Sabianism proper (I 31); nor did he forget the disastrous effect of
the exile (I 71, II 11): “If the belief in the existence of God were not as
generally accepted as it is now in the religions [that is, Judaism, Christian¬
ity, and Islam], the darkness of our times would even be greater than the
darkness of the times of the sages of Babylon” (III 29). This is to say
nothing of the fact that Sabianism proper was not completely eradicated
and could be expected to have a future (cf. I 36). It goes without saying
that Maimonides also never forgot the Messianic future, a future that may
or may not be followed by the end of the world (cf. I 61 with II 27). In
spite of this, one is entitled to say that Maimonides regarded the step that
he took in the Guide as the ultimate step in the decisive respect, namely,
in the overcoming of Sabianism. As he modestly put it, no Jew had written
an extant book on the secrets of the Law “in these times of the exile” (I
Introd.). At the beginning, the power of Sabianism was broken only in a
limited part of the world through bloody wars and through concessions to
Sabian habits; those concessions were retracted almost completely by the
post-Mosaic prophets, by the Aramaic translators, and by the Talmud, to
say nothing of the cessation through violence of the sacrificial service and
the conversion of many pagans, which was assisted by military victories, to
Christianity or Islam. Now the time has come when even the vulgar must
be taught most explicitly that God is incorporeal. Since the Bible suggests
corporealism, the vulgar will thus become perplexed. The remedy for this
perplexity is the allegoric explanation of the corporealistic utterances or
terms that restores the faith in the truth of the Bible (I 35), that is, pre¬
cisely what Maimonides is doing in the Guide. But the progress in over¬
coming Sabianism was accompanied by an ever increasing oblivion of
Sabianism and thus by an ever increasing inability to remove the last, as it
were, fossilized concessions to Sabianism or relics of Sabianism. Maimon¬
ides marks a progress even beyond the post-Mosaic prophets insofar as he
combines the open depreciation of the sacrifices with a justification of the
sacrificial laws of the Torah, for his depreciation of the sacrifices does not
as such mean a denial of the obligatory character of the sacrificial laws. He
is the man who finally eradicates Sabianism, that is, corporealism as the
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 171
the Mishneh Torah, that is, Deuteronomy (cf. II 34-35 and III 24).
Maimonides link with the Torah is, to begin with, an iron bond; it gradu¬
ally becomes a fine thread. But however far what one may call his intellec-
tualization may go, it always remains the intellectualization of the Torah.
Our desire to give the readers some hints for the better understanding of
the second subsection compelled us to look beyond the immediate context.
Returning to that context, we observe that after Maimonides has con¬
cluded the second subsection, he again does something perplexing. The last
chapter of the second subsection dealt with “foot”; that passage of the
Torah on which the second subsection is based speaks emphatically of
God s face and His “back”; nothing would have been simpler for
Maimonides than to devote the third subsection to terms designating parts
of the animate body or of the animal. Instead he devotes the fourth sub¬
section to this subject; the first two chapters of the fourth subsection are
devoted precisely to “face” and to “back” (I 37 and 38). The third subsec¬
tion, which deals with an altogether different subject, thus seems to be out
of place or to be a disconcerting insertion. Furthermore, the third subsec¬
tion is the least exegetic or the most speculative among the subsections de¬
voted to incorporeality; six of its eight chapters are not lexicographic; five
of them are in no obvious sense devoted to the explanation of biblical
terms and do not contain a single quotation from the Torah; one of these
chapters (I 31) is the first chapter of the Guide that does not contain a
single Jewish (Hebrew or Aramaic) expression, and another (I 35) does
not contain a single quotation of Jewish (biblical or talmudic) passages.
One is tempted to believe that it would have been more in accordance
with the spirit of the book if the most speculative among the subsections
devoted to incorporeality had formed the end of the part devoted to that
subject.
In order to understand these apparent irregularities, it is best to start
from the consideration that, for the general reason indicated, Maimonides
desired to divide each of the seven sections of the Guide into seven subsec¬
tions and that for a more particular reason he decided to treat unity in
three subsections; hence incorporeality had to be treated in four subsec¬
tions. Furthermore, it was necessary to place almost all lexicographic chap¬
ters within the part treating incorporeality, or conversely it was necessary
that the majority of chapters dealing with incorporeality should be lexico¬
graphic. For the reasons given where they had to be given, it proved conve¬
nient that the majority of chapters of the first subsection should be non-
lexicographic and the majority of chapters of the second subsection should
be lexicographic. It is this proportion of the first two subsections that
Maimonides decided to imitate in the last two subsections devoted to
incorporeality: the majority of chapters of the third subsection became
nonlexicographic, and the majority of chapters of the fourth subsection
became lexicographic, but—for a reason to be indicated presently—in such
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 173
tion deals with the Hebrew term for “living”; that term is the only one
occurring in the lexicographic chapters of this subsection that is not said to
be homonymous; this silence is pregnant with grave implications regarding
“the living God” (cf. I 30 and 41).
The last chapter of the fourth subsection is the only chapter of the
Guide that opens with the expression “The angels.” This chapter sets forth
the assertion that the angels are incorporeal, that is, it deals with the incor¬
poreality of something of which there is a plurality. Maimonides thus
makes clear that incorporeality, and not unity, is still the theme as it had
been from the beginning. The next chapter opens the discussion of unity.
Incorporeality has presented itself as a consequence of unity; unity has
been the presupposition, an unquestioned presupposition. Unity now
becomes the theme. We are told at the beginning that Unity must be
understood clearly, not, as it is understood by the Christians, to be compat¬
ible with God's trinity, or, more generally stated, with a multiplicity in
God (I 50). In the fifth subsection Maimonides effects the transformation
of the common, not to say traditional, understanding of unity, which
allowed a multiplicity of positive attributes describing God Himself, into
such an understanding as is in accordance with the requirements of specu¬
lation. The fifth subsection is the first subsection of the Guide that may be
said to be entirely speculative. Hence the discussion of unity, in contradis¬
tinction to the discussion of incorporeality, is characterized by a clear, if
implicit, distinction between the speculative and the exegetic discussion of
the subject. In the first four subsections there occurred only one chapter
without any Jewish expression; in the fifth subsection five such chapters
occur. In the first forty-nine chapters there occurred only nine chapters
without any quotation from the Torah; in the eleven chapters of the fifth
subsection ten such chapters occur. In spite of its speculative character the
fifth subsection does not demonstrate that God is one; it continues the
practice of the preceding subsections by presupposing that God is one (I
53, 58, 68). Yet from this presupposition it draws all conclusions and not
merely the conclusion that God is incorporeal: if God is one, one in every
possible respect, absolutely simple, there cannot be any positive attribute
of God except attributes describing His actions.
Maimonides knows by demonstration that God is one. The addressee,
being insufficiently trained in natural science (cf. I 55 with I 52), does not
know unity by demonstration, but through the Jewish tradition and ulti¬
mately through the Bible. The most important biblical text is “Hear, O
Israel, the Lord is our God, the Lord is one” (Deut. 6:4; cf. M.T., H.
Yesodei ha-Torah I 7). To our very great amazement, Maimonides does
not quote this verse a single time in any of the chapters devoted to unity.
He quotes it a single time in the Guide, imitating the Torah, which, as he
says, mentions the principle of unity, namely, this verse, only once (Resur-
rection 20, 1-2). He quotes the verse in III 45, that is, the 169th chapter.
176 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
quate or misleading but is the notion of something that simply does not
exist—of a merely imaginary being, the theme of deceived and deceiving
men (I 60). What is true of the ordinary believer is true at least to some
extent of the addressee of the Guide. The destruction of the old founda¬
tion forces him to seek for a new foundation: he is now compelled to be
passionately concerned with demonstration, with the demonstration not
only of God’s unity but of His very being in a sense of “being” that cannot
be entirely homonymous. For now he knows that the being of God is
doubtful as long as it is not established by demonstration (I 71). Now he
has been brought to the point where he must make up his mind whether
or not he will turn altogether to the way of demonstration. Maimonides
shows him three ways of demonstrating God’s being, unity, and incorpo¬
reality: the way of the Kalam, the way of the philosophers, and Maimoni¬
des’ own way (I 71 end, 76 end, II 1 end). While Maimonides cannot
simply accept the philosophers’ way, he prefers it to that of the Kalam for
the following reason. The Kalam begins, not from the world as we know it
through our senses or from the fact that things have determinate natures,
but from asserting that what the philosophers call the nature, say, of air is
only custom and hence of no inherent necessity: everything could be en¬
tirely different from what it is. The Kalam cannot live without reference
to what we know through our senses, for in contradistinction to simple be¬
lief whose first premise is the absolute will of God, it attempts to demon¬
strate that God is, and hence it must start from the given and at the same
time it must deny the authoritative character of the given. The philoso¬
phers on the other hand start from what is given or manifest to the senses
(171,73).
Maimonides turns first to the analysis and critique of the Kalam
demonstrations. He presents the premises of the Kalam (I 73) and then
the Kalam demonstrations that are based on those premises (I 74-76).
Maimonides’ critique does not limit itself to the technical Kalam reason¬
ing. For instance, the first proof of the createdness of the world and there¬
with of the being of the Creator assumes that the bodies that we see
around us have come into being through an artificer and infers from this
that the world as a whole is the work of an artificer. This proof, which does
not make any use of the premises peculiar to the Kalam, is based on in¬
ability, or at any rate failure, to distinguish between the artificial and the
natural. The second proof is based on the premise that no infinite what¬
ever is possible; it therefore first traces men to a first man, Adam, who
came out of dust, which in turn came out of water, and then traces water
itself to unqualified nothing out of which water could not have been
brought into being except by the act of the Creator (I 74; cf. Logic chaps.
7, 8, 11). It is not difficult to recognize in this proof elements of biblical
origin. Since the Kalam premises as stated by Maimonides are necessary
for the Kalam proofs (I 73 beginning and toward the end) and the
180 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Kalam proofs do not in all cases follow from those premises, those prem¬
ises while necessary are not sufficient. After all, the Kalam selected its
premises with a view to proving the roots of the Law: the premise of its
premises is those roots. While the First Part ends with the critique of the
Kalam, the Second Part opens with “The premises required for establish¬
ing the being of God and for demonstrating that He is not a body nor a
force in a body and that He is one,” that is, with the premises established
by the philosophers. Maimonides thus indicates that the seventy-six chap¬
ters of the First Part, which lead up to philosophy through a critique of the
popular notions of God as well as of theology, are negative and prephilo-
sophic, whereas the one hundred and two chapters of the Second and
Third Parts are positive or edifying. In other words, the First Part is chiefly
devoted to biblical exegesis and to the Kalam, that is, to the two translogi-
cal and transmathematical subjects mentioned even in the very Epistle
Dedicatory.
The Kalam proves that God as the Creator is, is one, and is incorporeal
by proving first that the world has been created; but it proves that premise
only by dialectical or sophistical arguments. The philosophers prove that
God is, is one, and is incorporeal by assuming that the world is eternal, but
they cannot demonstrate that assumption. Hence both ways are defective.
Maimonides way consists in a combination of these two defective ways.
For, he argues, “the world is eternal—the world is created” is a complete
disjunction; since God’s being, unity, and incorporeality necessarily follow
from either of the only two possible assumptions, the basic verities have
been demonstrated by this very fact (I 71, II 2). Yet the results from
opposed premises cannot be simply identical. For instance, someone might
have said prior to World War II that Germany would be prosperous re¬
gardless of whether she won or lost the war; if she won, her prosperity
would follow immediately; if she lost, her prosperity would be assured by
the United States of America who would need her as an ally against Soviet
Russia; but the predictor would have abstracted from the difference be¬
tween Germany as the greatest power which ruled tyrannically and was
ruled tyrannically, and Germany as a second-rank power ruled democrati¬
cally. The God whose being is proved on the assumption of eternity is the
unmoved mover, thought that thinks only itself and that as such is the
form or the life of the world. The God whose being is proved on the
assumption of creation is the biblical God who is characterized by Will
and whose knowledge has only the name in common with our knowledge.
If we consider the situation as outlined by Maimonides, we see that what is
demonstrated by his way is only what is common to the two different no¬
tions of God or what is neutral to the difference between God as pure In¬
tellect and God as Will or what is beyond that difference or what has only
the name in common with either Intellect or Will. But God thus under¬
stood is precisely God as presented in the doctrine of attributes: Maimoni-
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 181
with II 1). Besides, if there were such proofs, one is tempted to say that
there is no need whatever for provisionally granting the eternity of the
world in order to demonstrate God’s being, unity, and incorporeality; yet
Maimonides asserts most emphatically that there is such a need. None of
these or similar difficulties is, however, by any means the most serious
difficulty. For while the belief in God’s unity, being, and incorporeality is
required by the Law, that belief, being compatible with the belief in the
eternity of the world, is compatible with the unqualified rejection of the
Law: the Law stands or falls by the belief in the creation of the world. It is
therefore incumbent on Maimonides to show that Aristotle or Aristotelian-
ism is wrong in holding that the eternity of the world has been demon¬
strated: the eternity of the world which was the basis of the demonstration
of God s being, unity, and incorporeality is a dubious assumption. Yet it is
not sufficient to refute the claims of Aristotelianism in order to establish
the possibility of creation as the Law understands creation, for if the world
is not necessarily eternal it may still have been created out of eternal mat¬
ter. Maimonides is then compelled to abandon or at any rate to refine the
disjunction on which his original argument was based. The original dis¬
junction (the world is either eternal or created) is incomplete at least to
the extent that it blurs the difference between creation out of matter and
creation out of nothing. It brings out the opposition between Aristotle and
the Law, but it conceals the intermediate possibility presented in Plato’s
Timaeus. Plato s version of the doctrine of eternity is not inimical to the
Law, for while Aristotle’s version excludes the possibility of any miracle,
the Platonic version does not exclude all miracles as necessarily impossible.
Maimonides does not say which miracles are excluded by the Platonic
teaching. Two possible answers suggest themselves immediately. It is
according to nature that what has come into being will perish; but according
to the Law both Israel and the souls of the virtuous have come into being
and will not perish; hence their eternity a parte post is a miracle—a miracle
that is more in accordance with creation out of nothing than with creation
out of eternal matter. Second, God’s special providence for Israel, according
to which Israel prospers if it obeys and is miserable if it disobeys, is a
miracle not likely to be admitted by Plato, whose teaching on providence
seems to have been identical with that presented in the Book of Job: prov¬
idence follows naturally the intelligence of the individual human being. In
accordance with his judgment on the relation between the Aristotelian
doctrine and the doctrine of the Law, Maimonides proves by an extensive
argument that the Aristotelian doctrine is not demonstrated and is in addi¬
tion not probable. As for the Platonic doctrine, he explicitly refuses to pay
any attention to it on the additional ground that it has not been demon¬
strated (II 13, 25-27, 29, III 18; Yemen 24, 7-10; Resurrection 33, 16-36,
17; Letter on Astrology jj§ 19 ff. Marx). That ground is somewhat strange
because according to Maimonides the Aristotelian and the biblical alterna-
How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed / 183
fives have not been demonstrated either. In his critique of the Aristotelian
doctrine he makes use of the Kalam argument based on a premise that so
defines the possible that it might be either the imaginable or the nonself¬
contradictory or that regarding which we cannot make any definite asser¬
tions because of our lack of knowledge; the premise in question excludes
the view according to which the possible is what is capable of being or
what is in accordance with the nature of the thing in question or with
what possesses an available specific substratum (cf. I 75, II 14, III 15).
The reader must find out what the premises of the preferred premise are,
how Maimonides judges of those premises, and whether the argument
based on the premise in question renders improbable not only the eternity
of the visible universe but the eternity of matter as well.
At any rate, being compelled to question the Aristotelian doctrine,
Maimonides is compelled to question the adequacy of Aristotle's account
of heaven. That questioning culminates in the assertions that Aristotle had
indeed perfect knowledge of the sublunar things, but hardly any knowl¬
edge of the things of heaven, and ultimately that man as man has no such
knowledge: man has knowledge only of the earth and the earthly things,
that is, of beings that are bodies or in bodies. In the words of the Psalmist
(115:16): "The heavens, even the heavens, are the Lord’s; but the earth
hath he given to the children of Man.” Accordingly, Maimonides suggests
that the truth regarding providence, that is, that theological truth which is
of vital importance to human life, comes to sight by the observation of the
sublunar phenomena alone. Even the proof of the First Mover of heaven,
that is, the philosophic proof of God’s being, unity, and incorporeality, to
say nothing of the being of the other separate intelligences, becomes a
subject of perplexity (II 22, 24; cf. II 3, 19, III 23). And yet it was knowl¬
edge of heaven that was said to supply the best proof, not to say the only
proof, of the being of God (II 18). Maimonides has said earlier that very
little demonstration is possible regarding divine matters and much of it re¬
garding natural matters (I 31). Now he seems to suggest that the only
genuine science of beings is natural science or a part of it. It is obvious that
one cannot leave it at this apparent suggestion. The least that one would
have to add is that the strange remarks referred to occur within the context
in which Maimonides questions Aristotle’s account of heaven in the name
of astronomy or, more precisely, in which he sets forth the conflict between
philosophic cosmology and mathematical astronomy—that conflict which
he calls “the true perplexity”: the hypotheses on which astronomy rests
cannot be true, and yet they alone enable one to give an account of the
heavenly phenomena in terms of circular and uniform motions. Astronomy
shows the necessity of recurring for the purpose of calculation and predic¬
tion to what is possible in a philosophically inadmissible sense (II 24).
We have been compelled to put a greater emphasis on Maimonides’
perplexities than on his certainties, and in particular on his vigorous and
184 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
skillful defense of the Law, because the latter are more easily accessible
than the former. Besides, what at first glance seems to be merely negative is
negative only in the sense in which every liberation, being a liberation not
only to something but also from something, contains a negative ingredient.
So we may conclude with the words of Maimonides with which we began:
The Guide is "a key permitting one to enter places the gates to which were
locked. When those gates are opened and those places are entered, the
souls will find rest therein, the bodies will be eased of their toil, and the
eyes will be delighted.”
Marsilius of Padua
Marsilius, whose chief work is entitled Defender of the Peace (1324), was
a Christian Aristotelian. But both his Christianity and his Aristotelianism
differ profoundly from the beliefs of the most celebrated Christian Aristote¬
lian, Thomas Aquinas. Marsilius lives as it were in another world than
Thomas. In the whole Defender he refers to Thomas only once, but even
then, when he claims to quote Thomas, he in fact quotes only the state¬
ment of another authoritative Christian writer which Thomas had inserted
(with that writer’s name ) 1 in a compilation he had made. Thomas had
accepted the traditional ecclesiastical polity of the Roman Church. Marsil¬
ius admits that the Christian priesthood is divinely established as distinct
from the Christian laity, both being part of the Christian order; but he
denies that the ecclesiastical hierarchy is divinely established. According to
him all Christian priests are essentially equal in all respects as far as divine
right is concerned. He also denies that any priest, even if he be bishop or
pope, has by divine right any of the following powers: the power to com¬
mand or to coerce; the power to decide whether and how coercion is to be
exercised against apostates and heretics, be they subjects or princes; and the
power to determine in a legally binding way what is orthodox and what is
heretical. But we cannot go into Marsilius’ doctrine of the Church, al¬
though it was of the greatest political importance, especially during the
Reformation, for that doctrine belongs to political theology rather than to
political philosophy. By following this distinction, we do not distort Marsil¬
ius’ teaching, for he himself distinguishes throughout his work the political
teaching which is “demonstrated” by “human demonstration” from the
political teaching which is revealed by God immediately or mediately and
is therefore accepted by simple faith as distinguished from reason.2 This
is not to deny that the principle of his doctrine regarding the Christian
priesthood supplies the key to almost all the difficulties in which his work
185
186 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
abounds, for that principle explains his only explicit deviation from the
teaching of Aristotle.
As regards the principles of political philosophy, Marsilius presents him¬
self as a strict follower of Aristotle, “the divine philosopher” or “the pagan
sage.” 3 He explicitly agrees with Aristotle regarding the purpose of the
commonwealth: the commonwealth exists for the sake of the good life,
and the good life consists in being engaged in the activity becoming a free
man, that is, in the exercise of the virtues of the practical as well as of the
speculative soul. While practical or civic felicity “seems to be” the end of
human acts, in fact the activity of the metaphysician is more perfect than
the activity of the prince who is the active or political man par excellence.4
Marsilius explicitly agrees with Aristotle in regarding the purpose of the
commonwealth as the ground for the other kinds of causes (material,
formal, and moving) of the commonwealth and of its parts. He explicitly
agrees with him in very many other points. He has only one reservation
against Aristotle: Aristotle did not know one very grave disease of civil
society, an “evil thing, the common enemy of the human race” which must
be eradicated. This ignorance does not derogate from Aristotle’s supreme
wisdom. Aristotle did not know the “pestilence” in question because he
could not know it, for it was the accidental consequence of a miracle, and
it could have been even less foreseen by the wisest man than the miracle
itself. The miracle was the Christian revelation, and the grave disease arose
from the claims, in no way supported by Scripture, of the Christian
hierarchy—claims which culminate in the notion of papal plenitude of
power. Marsilius declares that this is the only political disease with which
he will deal, since the others have been properly dealt with by Aristotle.8
One ought therefore not even to expect to find a complete presentation of
political philosophy in the Defender. The work comes to sight as a kind of
appendix to that part of Aristotle’s Politics which may be said to deal with
the diseases of civil society.
Yet Aristotle’s unawareness of a single, if unusually grave, disease of civil
society is only the reverse side of his fundamental error: he was a pagan.
That error affects his political philosophy immediately only in one point,
however: in the teaching regarding the priesthood. He did not know the
true Christian priesthood, but only the false pagan priesthoods. This does
not mean that his teaching regarding the priesthood is entirely wrong. On
the contrary, within political philosophy that teaching is in the main cor¬
rect. He saw clearly that the priesthood forms a necessary part of the com¬
monwealth, even a noble part, but cannot be the ruling part: priests
cannot have the power to rule or to judge. He also saw clearly that it
cannot be left entirely to the individuals whether they become priests or
not; the number as well as the qualifications of the priests, and in particu¬
lar the admission of foreigners to priesthood in the commonwealth, is sub¬
ject to the decision of the government of the commonwealth. The Chris-
Marsilius of Padua / 187
quence of the fact that Aristotle was a pagan. It concerned political philos¬
ophy or the rational political teaching only accidentally. Still, according to
Aristotle, the best polity is the rule of gentlemen who rule their city, a
fairly small society, and are enabled to do so because they are men of
wealth. How can such men be thought to be rulers in a Christian society
where they would have to rule Christian priests and hence the Church?
For in a Christian society the activity of the priest is more noble than that
of the ruler. Furthermore, the Church is universal. Finally, the best men in
Christendom, that is, the best Christians, must live in evangelical poverty.
This was the problem which Marsilius believed he had to solve and that he
had solved.
The problem of how to reconcile the Aristotelian principle (the men
dedicated to the most noble practical activity ought to rule in their own
right) with the Christian principle (the activity of the priest is more noble
than that of the gentleman) could seem to have been solved in the clearest
and simplest manner by the doctrine of papal plenitude of power. Mar¬
silius avoids that conclusion within the confines of political philosophy by
teaching that in every commonwealth the fundamental political authority
is not the government or the ruling part, but the human legislator, and
that the human legislator is the people, the whole body of the citizens. To
express this in the language of Rousseau, Marsilius asserts that the only
legitimate sovereign is the people, but that the sovereign is to be distin¬
guished from the government. He thus succeeds in subordinating the
Christian priests to the Christian laity, the Christian aristocracy to the
Christian populus or demos. But in taking these steps he seems to deviate
flagrantly from the teaching of his revered master, who may be said to have
identified the sovereign with the government and, above all, to have pre¬
ferred the sovereignty or government of the gentlemen (aristocracy) to the
sovereignty or government of the people (democracy).
Marsilius does not dispose of the difficulty by accepting Aristotle’s asser¬
tions according to which democracy or the rule of the vulgar is a bad
regime and the farmers, artisans, and money-makers, who constitute the
vulgar, are not in the strictest sense parts of the commonwealth. He rather
increases the difficulty by ascribing to Aristotle himself the following teach¬
ing: the legislative power must be entirely in the hands of the whole citi¬
zen body; the government ought to be elected by the whole citizen body
and ought to be responsible to it; the government must rule in strict
adherence to the laws, and if it transgresses a law it is liable to punishment
by the whole citizen body. This teaching ascribed to Aristotle is much
more democratic than Aristotle's authentic teaching: in the whole body of
the citizens, as Marsilius understands it, the vulgar must play a very great,
not to say a decisive, role. The reasoning in favor of the vulgar by which
Marsilius supports his teaching is indeed almost identical with the argu¬
ment in favor of democracy which Aristotle had reported and considered in
190 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
the course of his ascent from the defective regimes to aristocracy (or king-
ship). And Marsilius does not tire of explicitly quoting Aristotle in this
context, although not without strange misinterpretations. Still stranger is
his complete silence in this context about Aristotle’s antidemocratic argu¬
ment. He reports the antidemocratic argument, but omits any reference to
Aristotle. He quotes only one authority for the antipopulist position: the
saying of the wise king Solomon according to which “the number of the
fools is infinite.” Marsilius has not quoted any biblical passage in his popu¬
list reasoning; he thus perplexes us for a moment by making us think that
the Bible, or at any rate Solomon, might favor aristocracy. Yet he disposes
of this possibility by suggesting that the sage meant perhaps by the fools
the infidels who, however wise in the worldly sciences, are nevertheless
absolutely foolish, since, according to Paul, the wisdom of this world is
foolishness with God. For from this it follows that the faithful man, and
hence all the more the faithful multitude, is truly wise and hence perfectly
competent to make laws and to elect kings or magistrates.
There is at least one other remark of Marsilius which shows that his
belief in the competence of the people at large originated in his concern,
not with authority as such, but with authority in Christendom. He says in
effect that the necessity of giving the multitude power to legislate and to
elect officials is less evident than the necessity of entrusting the multitude
with the power to elect priests and remove them from their priestly offices;
for error in the election of a priest can lead to eternal death and to very
great harm in this life. That harm consists in the seduction of women dur¬
ing the secret conversations in the course of which they confess their sins
to a priest. It is obvious that the simplest citizen, and surely therefore the
faithful multitude, is as able to judge the trustworthiness of any individual
priest in such matters as the most learned men could be; and the simple
multitude might even be better informed in such respects than the
learned. Marsilius also suggests that the whole body of all the faithful
which is guided in its deliberations by the Holy Spirit, as distinguished
from the whole body of citizens as mere citizens, is infallible.12 By far the
most important argument for popular government, however, is supplied by
the example of the Church in its purest form, in which there were not yet
Christian princes, and the Church consisted exclusively of priests and a
multitude of such laymen as were subjects. Precisely in that epoch
“Church” meant only the whole body of the faithful, and thus all Chris¬
tians were ecclesiastics. Hence the traditional distinction between the
people and the clergy must be radically revised in favor of the people. In
accordance with the practice of the early Church, the election to all
priestly offices belongs to the whole multitude of the faithful. This reason¬
ing is not weakened but strengthened by the fact that in the very early
Church the multitude was uncivilized and inexperienced: if even then the
bishops were frequently elected by the multitude, this procedure is all the
Marsilius of Padua / 191
more appropriate after the faith has taken root in both subjects and
princes.13
Let us return to the confines of political philosophy and consider
Marsilius doctrine of the human legislator somewhat more closely. He
devotes two whole chapters out of fifty-two to the statement, the proofs,
and the defense of that doctrine. He advances three proofs to which he
adds a fourth, but that fourth proof is, as he says, hardly more than a
summary of the first three. (1) The legislative power ought to belong to
those from whom alone the best laws can emerge, but this is the whole
citizen body; one reason is that no one harms himself knowingly and
hence, we may add, when each thinks of his interest, no one’s interest will
be neglected or the interest of all will be duly provided for. (2) The legis¬
lative power ought to belong only to those who can best guaranteee that
the laws made will be observed, but this is the whole citizen body, for each
citizen observes better a law, even if it is not good, “which he seems to
have imposed on himself”; the reason for this is that every citizen not only
is a free man, that is, not subject to a master, but desires to be a free man.
We may note that this argument causes a difficulty which Marsilius never
discusses regarding the God-given and hence not even apparently self-
imposed law. (3) What can benefit and harm each, and hence all, ought
to be known and heard by all so that all and each can attain the benefit
and repel the harm. The defense of the doctrine is stated in three argu¬
ments which are in the main taken from the populist reasoning reported by
Aristotle. In the second of the latter group of arguments, Marsilius illus¬
trates the danger of entrusting legislative power to a few or to one by re¬
ferring to the oligarchic or tyrannical character of the canon law.14 Marsil¬
ius’ populist thesis thus appears to be derived from his anticlericalism.
Marsilius ascribes the fundamental political power, the power of the
human legislator, not simply to the whole citizen body but to “the whole
citizen body or its stronger or superior part.” By the stronger or superior
part he certainly does not mean the unqualified majority. The stronger or
superior part, which as it were replaces the whole citizen body, must be
understood in terms of both number and quality, so that the vulgar may
not be entirely at the mercy of the better people nor the latter entirely at
the mercy of the former. The arrangement sketched by Marsilius might be
called a “polity”—a mean between oligarchy and democracy—were it not
for the fact that “polity” is a form of government, while Marsilius speaks
of the sovereign as distinguished from the government. Furthermore,
whereas in a democracy, in Aristotle’s sense, the common people partici¬
pate fully in deliberation and jurisdiction, Marsilius reserves these func¬
tions for the government or the ruling part as distinguished from the whole
citizen body or its stronger superior part.18 Above all, as Marsilius al¬
ready discloses in the chapters explicitly devoted to the definition of the
human legislator, the human legislator may delegate his legislative power
192 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
to one or to several men. Marsilius thus allows the sovereignty of the peo¬
ple to remain entirely dormant. In the same breath in which he proclaims
the transcendent virtue of everyone’s actually participating in legislation,
he dismisses that participation as irrelevant. One must go further and say
that he retracts the very principle of popular sovereignty. He compares the
position of the ruling part in the body politic to that of the heart in the
human body: it is that part which molds the other parts of the body poli¬
tic. But if this is so, the ruling part is not derivative from a pre-existing
sovereign, the human legislator, or the people, that is, the whole which
consists of all parts of the body politic in their proper proportion, but is
rather the cause of the alleged sovereign. In accordance with this Marsilius
compares the position of the ruling part in the commonwealth to that of
the prime mover in the universe, that is, of the Aristotelian God who
surely is not subject to laws made by the other parts of the universe. In a
word, Marsilius returns to the Aristotelian view according to which the
human legislator (the sovereign) is identical with the ruling part (the gov¬
ernment) or according to which the stronger or superior part is identical
with the ruling part; for in every stable political order, the ruling part,
whether it consists of one man or a few or the many, is as a matter of
course the stronger or superior part. Marsilius even explicitly identifies the
ruler with the legislator; for example, by calling the Roman emperors legis¬
lators. He does not leave it at saying that the human legislator can give the
ruler "plenitude of power.” He goes so far as to say that the ruler owes his
position to “the human legislator or any other human will”: the ruler may
owe his position to his own will.16
If the ruling part is the legislator it cannot be simply subject to the law.
Even in a republic, where no individual is the legislator and hence some¬
how above the law, it is sometimes necessary for an individual magistrate
to act illegally in order to save the republic, as Cicero did when quenching
the Catilinian conspiracy. When Marsilius suggests that the ruler is subject
only to the divine law, we must not forget that according to him the divine
law is not as such knowable to human reason nor does it as such have
coercive power in this world. Furthermore, if the ruling part (the govern¬
ment) is the legislator (the sovereign), the government is not subject to
punishment in case of misconduct for the same reason for which the sover¬
eign people in the populist hypothesis is not subject to punishment.17 To
sum up, in spite of its dogmatic tone, Marsilius’ populist teaching proves to
be, if in a different way, as provisional or as tentative as the democratic
argument in Aristotle’s Politics.
lar princes. It can therefore be assumed that his preference for elective
monarchy over hereditary monarchy belongs to his final or serious political
teaching. He certainly never contradicts this preference as he contradicts
the doctrine of popular sovereignty. His argument in favor of elective king-
ship can be reduced to a single consideration. The most important quality
of the ruler is prudence, for the infinite variety of human affairs does not
permit an adequate regulation by laws, and prudence does not come by
inheritance. Prudence, that is, practical wisdom in contradistinction to
mere cleverness, is not separable from moral virtue and vice versa. Pru¬
dence is also and especially required for the making of good and just laws.
While prudence is then of the utmost importance, it is rare; nature gen¬
erated only a part of the human race apt for prudence, and still fewer men
actualize that potentiality. The foregoing consideration does not imply that
hereditary kingship is illegitimate; it merely means that hereditary kingship
is as such inferior to elective kingship. Hereditary kingship may even be
preferable to elective kingship in most countries at all times and in all
countries at the beginning of their political life, when all men are still un¬
civilized. For in most countries at all times and in all countries at the be¬
ginning or in their decay, prudence is as it were at best the preserve of a
single family, and there are therefore no prudent electors. Elective kingship
is superior to hereditary kingship because the former is suitable to a perfect
and civilized commonwealth, whereas the latter is suitable to a still imper¬
fect or irremediably uncivilized society.10
Now, this very consideration leads to the conclusion that to a perfect or
civilized commonwealth the rule of a number of prudent men, that is, aris¬
tocracy, is still more suitable than even elective monarchy, for there is no
reason why, if there exists in a commonwealth a number of prudent men,
as will be the case in a perfect commonwealth, all except one should always
be deprived of the highest honor; those unjustly deprived of their fair share
in government would justly engage in sedition. Marsilius devotes a whole
chapter to the proof that the indispensable unity of government is in no
way impaired if the government consists of a number of men instead of
one man. Not only hereditary kingship but kingship as such is proper only
at times and in places where there is an extreme paucity of men who are fit
to rule a commonwealth as, for instance, perhaps in Rome at the end of
the republic. Monarchy is the proper kind of government in the household
rather than in the perfect civil society. That aristocracy as distinguished
from kingship is possible only under the most favorable conditions, and
hence very rarely, in no way contradicts the fact that it is the most natural
regime. If the priests were as they ought to be, Marsilius argues, the gen¬
eral council of the Church could consist only of priests, for the most
important requirement for participation in such an assembly is thorough
knowledge of the divine law, which is the highest form of wisdom; but the
priests are not as they ought to be. This amounts to saying that in principle
Marsilius of Padua / 195
aristocracy or the rule of the wise is preferable; only because the Church is
no longer an aristocracy, but, as Marsilius never tires of repeating, is now
an oligarchy, is it in need of correction by the best part of the laity; and the
laity is, in the Church, the popular element. Within his populist argument
Marsilius indicates that the devising and examining of the laws is the
proper business of the prudent men; the other members of society are of
little use in this matter and would only be disturbed in the performance of
their necessary work if they were called upon to do more than to act as
“formal” ratifiers. Such popular ratification of the laws would indeed seem
to be desirable, since it is likely to make the populace more willing to obey
the laws.20
Marsilius’ very vacillation between populism and absolute monarchy
may be said to point to aristocracy as the right mean between these two
faulty extremes. What speaks in favor of the legislative power of absolute
kings redounds also to the benefit of a sovereign government which con¬
sists of the prudent men of a city each of whom owes his position to co¬
optation by his peers rather than to popular election; and what speaks in
favor of the legislative power of “the stronger or superior part of the whole
citizen body” redounds to the benefit of what is in truth the stronger or
superior part in every city which is not either too young or small or else too
old or large for political excellence, namely, the most prudent and virtuous
citizens. Marsilius abstains from arguing in favor of kingship while he
argues emphatically in favor of popular sovereignty: the regime which he
favors is somewhat closer, not indeed to democracy, but to the “polity”
than to kingship. At the same time his populist argument points, through
its glaring defects, for instance, from the “polity” to an aristocracy which is
acceptable to the populace not only because of the inherent qualities of a
genuine aristocracy as the rule of the most prudent and virtuous citizens
but also because it respects the susceptibilities of the populace. Marsilius
presented the argument for aristocracy in the most subdued form because
that argument did not provide a sufficiently broad basis for the anticlerical
policy which he regarded as by far the most urgent task for his age. In
addition, the argument in favor of aristocracy would have redounded in the
opinion of the majority of his contemporaries to the benefit of the clergy,
for if political power is shown to belong by right to the wisest, it would
seem to follow that it belongs less to those wise in human wisdom than to
those wise in divine wisdom.
The strategy which Marsilius employed can then be explained by the
political impossibility which amounted to a physical impossibility of airing
the fundamental political issue. He could have an easy conscience in pro¬
ceeding as he did because he was satisfied that a government of priests was
impossible or undesirable. For according to him the New Testament not
only does not authorize government by priests, especially in secular mat¬
ters, but positively forbids it. In the Christian law, and only in the Chris-
196 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
tian law, the action of the priest as priest is the most perfect of all. But this
action requires a spirit and a way of life which are incompatible with ruler-
ship, for it requires contempt for the world and the utmost humility.
Christ excluded himself and the apostles from worldly rule in every form.
Paul forbade every priest to become entangled in any secular matter what¬
ever, since no one can serve two masters. The New Testament recognizes in
the strongest terms the duty of obedience to the human government
“which beareth not the sword in vain,” not so much for the defense of the
fatherland as for executing wrath upon the evildoers, and the New Testa¬
ment traces to sinful pride the view that bad rulers or masters may be dis¬
obeyed. Christian slaves are not permitted to demand that they be set free
after six years’ servitude as the Hebrew slaves are, for the Old Testament
law in question acquires in Christianity a purely mystical meaning.
Humility and contempt for the world can then go together perfectly with
sincere obedience to worldly masters.
Still, within the confines of political philosophy, Marsilius must put the
accents somewhat differently than the highest Christian authorities had
done. He almost goes so far as to defend the pagan rulers against the saying
of Christ that they “lord it over” their subjects. According to Paul, only
those that are “contemptible” in the Church, that is, those who possess
wisdom in things which are not spiritual, ought to be judges in worldly
matters. The demands of the Sermon on the Mount cannot be reconciled
with the status and the duties of governors and their lay subjects.21 The
perfect Christian community was the community of Christ and the apos¬
tles in which there was community of goods; but that community was
imperfect in other respects since it was meant to become universal, and yet
no provision was made for its unity in the future when it would have be¬
come a large society; it could become perfect only through the acts of
Christian princes. One is tempted to express Marsilius’ thought by saying
that it was nature which perfected grace rather than grace which perfected
nature. He even goes so far as to indicate that there is an opposition
between human government and divine providence, the former rewarding
in this world the just and the doers of good deeds and the latter inflicting
suffering on them in this world.22 Marsilius indicates the peculiarity of the
Christian law by saying that belief in God’s future judgment—a belief
which Christianity shares with all other religions—would induce the Chris¬
tian priests not to defraud the poor, while belief in the Christian religion
would induce the Christian priests to live in poverty. Evangelical poverty is
indeed according to him the inevitable concomitant of radical contempt
for this world or of radical humility. Within the confines of human reason,
however, wealth, just as honor, comes to sight as something good since it is
required for the exercise of moral virtue. But according to the Christian
teaching, voluntary poverty is so much required for perfection that those
who do' not live in voluntary poverty are bad Christians. In spite of this.
Marsilius of Padua / 197
Marsilius can complain that the popes did not show proper gratitude for
having been raised by the Roman emperors from extreme poverty to
abundance of temporal goods. He appears to assume that Christian moral¬
ity and the worldly morality of the gentleman contradict each other or that
revelation is not simply above reason but against reason. This may be one
reason why he regarded the New Testament law as especially difficult to
fulfill.23
Marsilius has sometimes been celebrated as a defender of religious free¬
dom. Yet he does not go beyond raising the question as to whether it is
permitted to coerce heretics or infidels, while stating in the same context
that he does not wish to say that such coercion is inappropriate. He does
deny that such coercion can be exercised in this world on the basis of di¬
vine law. For according to Marsilius, no divine law has as such any coercive
power in this world unless by virtue of a human law which makes it a
crime to transgress the divine law in question. In addition, according to
the Christian divine law, which, of course, condemns heresy and infi¬
delity and buttresses that condemnation by the threat of punishment in
the other life, a man who is coerced into belief is not truly a believer; be¬
sides, Christian priests have not been given by Christ any coercive power.
In spite of this, the Christian human legislator, not as Christian but as
human legislator, may use coercion against heretics and infidels in this
world. This right can be illustrated by the following parallel. The Christian
divine law forbids drunkenness, but does not as such require that coercion
be used in this world against drunkards; yet it does not forbid the human
legislator to prohibit drunkenness under penalties in this world. Similarly,
the human legislator may enforce religious sobriety, that is, orthodoxy.
Whether or not he does so will depend on his judgment on heresy, for
instance. He may be guided by the biblical comparison of heresy to fornica¬
tion and hence permit heresy as he permits fornication, although for¬
nication, too, is forbidden by the Christian divine law. Or he may be
guided by the biblical comparison of heresy to leprosy and hence take
coercive action against heretics in compliance with the advice of experts
(the priests), just as he takes coercive action against lepers in compliance
with the advice of experts (the physicians). He may also be guided by the
facts that the New Testament surely permits excommunication and that
excommunication is bound to affect the excommunicated in this life.24
But apart from any theological consideration, that is, from any consider¬
ation peculiar to the Christian divine law, it is clear that if belief in divine
judgment in the other world is conducive to virtuous conduct in this world,
as even pagan philosophers admitted, it is not inappropriate for the human
legislator to protect that belief and its corollaries by forbidding speech
which may subvert that belief. This conclusion is not contradicted by Mar¬
silius’ teaching that human government is concerned only with “transe-
unt” as distinguished from “immanent” acts. According to that distinc-
198 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
rational, and what is rational is not universally admitted. Among the rules
which can metaphorically be called “natural rights” Marsilius mentions the
rule that human offspring must be reared by the parents up to a certain
time; he may have regarded this rule as not unqualifiedly rational since
Aristotle had held that no deformed child should be reared. More gener¬
ally, if wars are by nature necessary in order to prevent overpopulation, the
distinction between just and unjust wars loses much of its force, and this
grave qualification of the rules of justice cannot but impair the rationality
of those rules of justice which are universally or generally admitted to ob¬
tain within the commonwealth. In other words, the universally admitted
rules of right are not rational since there exists a natural necessity to trans¬
gress them or since man does not possess freedom of will to the extent to
which both common opinion and the teaching of revelation assert it.28
One can understand Marsilius’ denial of natural law best if one starts
from the fact that he implicitly denies the existence of first principles of
practical reason. The cognitive status of the first principles of action in
Aristotle’s Ethics is obscure. One way of removing this obscurity—the way
preferred by Averroes and Dante—is to conceive of the first principles of
action and therefore also of politics as supplied by theoretical reason or
natural science: it is natural science which makes clear what the end of
man is. Let the end of man be the perfection of his mind, that is, the
actual thought of the metaphysician as metaphysician. The individual
human being who is capable of pursuing this end will then deliberate as to
how, given his circumstances, he can reach this end. This deliberation—an
act of practical reason—will in many points differ from individual to indi¬
vidual, but there are certain universal rules of conduct with which all men
must comply who wish to become perfect as men of speculation. Those
rules are, however, not universal strictly speaking since only a minority of
men is by nature capable of the contemplative life. But there is also an end
which all men are able to pursue; this is the perfection of their bodies. This
lower or first perfection requires among other things security in and
through political society. Here a profound ambiguity enters: political soci¬
ety is required, although in different ways, for the sake of both man’s first
and his ultimate (theoretical) perfection. However this may be, political
society in its turn requires a variety of “parts” (farmers, artisans, moneyed
men, soldiers, priests, governors, or judges) and a certain order of these
parts. It requires for its well-being that the legislators and the governors or
judges possess prudence and if not all at any rate some of the moral virtues,
especially justice. In agreement with Aristotle’s procedure in the Politics,
Marsilius deduces the necessity of those virtues from the purpose of civil
society, and the necessity of that purpose from the end or ends of man.
That is to say, deviating from the procedure which Aristotle had fol¬
lowed in his Ethics for educative or practical reasons, Marsilius does not
take those virtues as ultimates, as choiceworthy for their own sake. It is be-
Marsilius of Padua / 201
cause Marsilius treats prudence and the moral virtues less as choiceworthy
for their own sake than as subservient to the two natural ends indicated
that his political science is more obviously and more emphatically “demon¬
strative” than Aristotle’s political science.29
Marsilius says much less than Aristotle even in his Politics about the
highest end which is natural to man. For the reasons indicated above he
lowered his sights. His doctrine of the commonwealth is reminiscent of the
suggestion in Plato’s Republic according to which the city of pigs is the
true city. His doctrine of the human law is reminiscent of Maimonides'
suggestion according to which the human law serves no higher goal than
the perfection of man s body, whereas the divine law brings about
the perfection of both the body and the mind.30 But Maimonides held
that the divine law is essentially rational and not, as it is according to
Thomas, suprarational. One may say that Marsilius combines Maimonides’
view of the human law with Thomas’ view of the divine law and thus ar¬
rives, within the confines of political philosophy, at the conclusion that the
only law properly so called is the human law which is directed toward the
well-being of the body. Marsilius was driven to take this view to some ex¬
tent by his anticlericalism. When antitheological passion induced a thinker
to take the extreme step of questioning the supremacy of contemplation,
political philosophy broke with the classical tradition, and especially with
Aristotle, and took on an entirely new character. The thinker in question
was Machiavelli.
NOTES
9. Ibid., I 5.12; 19.4 (102, 22, ed. Previt6-Orton) and 5 beginning. II 6.10 end; 10.6-
20.13. Note that Marsilius does not quote Deut. 33:10.
10. Ibid., I 5.1, 13. II 13—14; 24.1 end; 30.4 (par. 1 end).
11. Ibid., I 1.1; 8.4; 10.4-5; 15.1; 17. II 4.5; 8.9; 28 end. Politics 1255b 13-15- 1276*
1-3; 1282b 7-13; 1324b 7-9; 1333b 5 ff. EN 1180* 24-35
12. Defender, I 5.1, 13; 8.3; 11 (esp. 11.6); 12.3, 4; 13.1, 3, 4. II 17.10-12; 21.3
and 9 end. Politics 1281* 40 ff. (esp. 1281b 23-25).
202 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
13. Defender, II 2.3; 15.8; 16.1 and 9 beginning; 17.5, 7-8, 10; 28.3, 17.
14. Ibid., I 12-13. II 23.9, 13 beginning; 24.11; 26.19; 28.29.
15. Ibid., I 5.1, 7; 8.1; 12.4. II 2.8; 4.8; 8.7.
16. Ibid., I 4.4 (13, 20); 8.5; 10.2; 12.3; 13 end; 14 heading and end; 15.5-6; 16.21;
17.9. II 5.4 (149 bottom); 8.6; 21.2; 30.4 (485, 19-21—one of the two central
parts of the chapter). Ill 2.13. Defensor Minor, chap. 3 beginning. Politics 1296b
14-16.
17. Defender, I 14.3; 15.4; 26.13. Cf. II 3.15 and 30.6.
18. Ibid., I 9.5-7; 15.3 end; 16. II 24.2.
19. Ibid., I 7.1; 9.4-7, 10; 11.3 (42, 14-15); 14.2-7, 10; 15.1; 16. 11-24 (esp.
16.17).
20. Ibid., I 2.2; 3.4; 9.10; 11.5 end; 12.2; 13.8; 14.9; 16.19, 21, 23; 17. II 20.2 end
and 13-14; cf. II 3.15 with 30.6. Alan Gewirth, Marsilius of Padua, trans. with
an introduction (New York: 1956), I 254. The use of regnum suggested in I 2
makes one expect a more monarchistic tendency than Marsilius actually has.
21. Ibid., I 10.3; 12.2. II 4.13; 5.1-2, 4-5, 8 (par. 1); 9.10, 12; 11.2, 7; 28.24
(462, 9); 30.4 par. 1 end.
22. Ibid., II 4.6; 13.28; 17.7-8; 22.1 beginning, 15-16; 24.4; 27.2 (426 par. 2).
Gewirth, op. cit., I 81.
23. Ibid., I 6.3, 6; 15.21; 16. II 11.4; 13.16, 23 end-24; 26.12 beginning.
24. Ibid., I 10.3-7. II 5.6, 7 (154, 23-26 and 157, 28); 6.11-13; 8.8; 9.2-5; 10.3,
7, 9; 13.2 end.
25. Ibid., I 5.4, 7. II 2.4 (3); 8.5; 9.11; 10.4, 9; 17.8 toward the end. Gewirth, op.
cit., I 284.
26. I 19.10. II 13.28; 17.2; 18.8 (pars. 1-2 and end); 19.1-3; 20.1-2; 21.11, 13;
22.6, 8, 10; 24.9, 12; 25.4-6, 9, 15-18; 28.27; 30.8. Defensor Minor, chaps. 7
and 12.
27. Defender, I 17.10. II 28.15.
28. Ibid., I 10.3-7; 12.2-3; 14.4; 15.6 end; 19.13. II 8.3; 12.7-8.
29. Ibid., I 6-9; 11.3; 14.2, 6-7. Dante, De Monarchia, I 14.
30. Republic, 372' 6-7; Guide of the Perplexed, II 40 and III 27.
An Epilogue
What one may call the new science of politics emerged shortly before
World War I; it became preponderant and at the same time reached its
mature or final form before, during, and after World War II. It need not
be a product or a symptom of the crisis of the modern Western world—of
a world which could boast of being distinguished by ever broadening free¬
dom and humanitarianism; it is surely contemporary with that crisis.
The new political science shares with the most familiar ingredients of
our world in its crisis the quality of being a mass phenomenon. That it is a
mass phenomenon is compatible with the fact that it possesses its heights
and its depths, the handful of opinion leaders, the men responsible for the
breakthroughs on the top, and the many who drive on the highways pro¬
jected by the former at the bottom. It wields very great authority in the
West, above all in this country. It controls whole departments of political
science in great and in large universities. It is supported by foundations of
immense wealth with unbounded faith and unbelievably large grants. In
spite of this one runs little risk in taking issue with it. For its devotees are
fettered by something like a Hippocratic oath to subordinate all consider¬
ations of safety, income, and deference to concern with the truth. The
difficulty lies elsewhere. It is not easy to free one’s mind from the impact of
any apparently beneficent authority, for such freeing requires that one st,ep
outside of the circle warmed and charmed by the authority to be
questioned.
Yet it is necessary to make the effort. The new political science itself
must demand it. One might say that precisely because it is an authority
operating within a democracy it owes an account of itself to those who are
subjected, or are to be subjected, to it. However sound it may be, it is a
novelty. That it emerged so late is probably no accident: deep-seated resist¬
ances had to be overcome step by step in a process of long duration.
203
204 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
hardly uses a term which did not originate in the market place and is not
in common use there; but the new political science cannot begin to speak
without having elaborated an extensive technical vocabulary.
Fourth, Aristotelian political science necessarily evaluates political
things; the knowledge in which it culminates has the character of categoric
advice and of exhortation. The new political science on the other hand
conceives of the principles of action as “values” which are merely “subjec¬
tive”; the knowledge which it conveys has the character of prediction and
only secondarily that of hypothetical advice.
Fifth, according to the Aristotelian view, man is a being sui generis, with
a dignity of its own: man is the rational and political animal. Man is the
only being which can be concerned with self-respect; man can respect him¬
self because he can despise himself; he is “the beast with red cheeks,” the
only being possessing a sense of shame. His dignity is then based on his
awareness of what he ought to be or how he should live. Since there is a
necessary connection between morality (how man should live) and law,
there is a necessary connection between the dignity of man and the dignity
of the public order: the political is sui generis and cannot be understood as
derivative from the subpolitical. The presupposition of all this is that man
is radically distinguished from nonman, from brutes as well as from gods,
and this presupposition is ratified by common sense, by the citizen’s under¬
standing of things; when the citizen demands or rejects, say, “freedom
from want for all,” he does not mean freedom from want for tigers, rats, or
lice. This presupposition points to a more fundamental presupposition
according to which the whole consists of essentially different parts. The
new political science on the other hand is based on the fundamental prem¬
ise that there are no essential or irreducible differences: there are only
differences of degree; in particular there is only a difference of degree be¬
tween men and brutes or between men and robots. In other words, accord¬
ing to the new political science, or the universal science of which the new
political science is a part, to understand a thing means to understand it in
terms of its genesis or its conditions and hence, humanly speaking, to
understand the higher in terms of the lower: the human in terms of the
subhuman, the rational in terms of the subrational, the political in terms
of the subpolitical. In particular the new political science cannot admit
that the common good is something that is.
Prior to the emergence of the new political science, political science had
already moved very far from Aristotelian political science in the general
direction of the new political science. Nevertheless it was accused of paying
too great attention to the law or to the Ought and of paying too little at¬
tention to the Is or to the actual behavior of men. For instance, it seemed
to be exclusively concerned with the legal arrangements regarding universal
suffrage and its justification and not to consider at all how the universal
right to vote is exercised; yet democracy, as it is, is characterized by the
208 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
manner in which that right is exercised. We may grant that not so long ago
there was a political science which was narrowly legalistic—which, for
example, took the written constitution of the U.S.S.R. very seriously—but
we must add immediately that that error had been corrected, as it were in
advance, by an older political science, the political science of Montesquieu,
of Machiavelli, or of Aristotle himself. Besides, the new political science, in
its justified protest against a merely legalistic political science, is in danger
of disregarding the important things known to those legalists: “voting be¬
havior as it is now studied would be impossible if there were not in the
first place the universal right to vote, and this right, even if not exercised
by a large minority for very long periods, must be taken into consideration
in any long-range prediction since it may be exercised by all in future elec¬
tions taking place in unprecedented and therefore particularly interesting
circumstances. That right is an essential ingredient of democratic “behav¬
ior,” for it partly explains “behavior” in democracies (for instance, the
prevention by force or fraud of certain people from voting). The new
political science does not simply deny these things, but it literally relegates
them to the background, to “the habit background”; in so doing it puts the
cart before the horse. Similar considerations apply, for instance, to the
alleged discovery by the new political science of the importance of “propa¬
ganda”; that discovery is in fact only a partial rediscovery of the need for
vulgar rhetoric, a need that had become somewhat obscured from a few
generations which were comforted by faith in universal enlightenment as
the inevitable by-product of the diffusion of science, which in its turn was
thought to be the inevitable by-product of science. Generally speaking, one
may wonder whether the new political science has brought to light any¬
thing of political importance which intelligent political practitioners with a
deep knowledge of history, nay, intelligent and educated journalists, to say
nothing of the old political science at its best, did not know at least as well
beforehand.
The main substantive reason, however, for the revolt against the old
political science would seem to be the consideration that our political situ¬
ation is entirely unprecedented and that it is unreasonable to expect earlier
political thought to be of any help in coping with our situation; the un¬
precedented political situation calls for an unprecedented political science,
perhaps for a judicious mating of dialectical materialism and psychoanalysis
to be consummated on a bed supplied by logical positivism. Just as classical
physics had to be superseded by nuclear physics so that the atomic age
could come in via the atomic bomb, the old political science has to be
superseded by a sort of nuclear political science so that we may be enabled
to cope with the extreme dangers threatening atomic man; the equivalent
in political science of the nuclei is probably the most minute events in the
smallest groups of humans if not in the life of infants; the small groups in
question are certainly not of the kind exemplified by the small group which
An Epilogue / 209
political situation. The incarnation of the empirical spirit is the man from
Missouri, who has to be shown. For he knows that he, as well as everyone
else who is of sound mind and whose sight is not defective, can see things
and people as they are with his eyes and that he is capable of knowing how
his neighbors feel; he takes it for granted that he lives with other human
beings of all descriptions in the same world and that because they are all
human beings, they all understand one another somehow; he knows that if
this were not so, political life would be altogether impossible. If someone
would offer him speculations based on extrasensory perception, he would
turn his back on him more or less politely. The old political science would
not quarrel in these respects with the man from Missouri. It did not claim
to know better or differently than he such things as that the Democratic
and Republican parties are now, and have been for some time, the prepon¬
derant parties in this country and that there are presidential elections every
fourth year. By admitting that facts of this kind are known independently
of political science, it admitted that empirical knowledge is not necessarily
scientific knowledge or that a statement can be true and known to be true
without being scientific, and, above all, that political science stands or falls
by the truth of the prescientific awareness of political things.
Yet one may raise the question as to how one can be certain of the truth
of empirical statements which are prescientific. If we call an elaborate
answer to this question an epistemology, we may say that an empiricist, in
contradistinction to an empirical, statement is based on the explicit
assumption of a specific epistemology. Yet every epistemology presupposes
the truth of empirical statements. Our perceiving things and people is
more manifest and more reliable than any “theory of knowledge”—any
explanation of how our perceiving things and people is possible—can be;
the truth of any “theory of knowledge” depends on its ability to give an
adequate account of this fundamental reliance. If a logical positivist tries to
give an account of “a thing” or a formula for “a thing” in terms of mere
sense data and their composition, he is looking, and bids us to look, at the
previously grasped “thing”; the previously grasped “thing” is the standard
by which we judge of his formula. If an epistemology—for example,
solipsism—manifestly fails to give an account of how empirical statements
as meant can be true, it fails to carry conviction. To be aware of the neces¬
sity of the fundamental reliance which underlies or pervades all empirical
statements means to recognize the fundamental riddle, not to have solved
it. But no man needs to be ashamed to admit that he does not possess a
solution to the fundamental riddle. Surely no man ought to let himself be
bullied into the acceptance of an alleged solution—for the denial of the
existence of a riddle is a kind of solution of the riddle—by the threat that
if he fails to do so he is a “metaphysician.” To sustain our weaker brethren
against that threat one might tell them that the belief accepted by the
empiricists, according to which science is in principle susceptible of infinite
212 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
merits about “the revolutionary” or “the conservative” which did not even
claim to have any basis other than observations made in the United States
at the present moment; if those statements had any relations to facts at all,
they might have some degree of truth regarding revolutionaries or conser¬
vatives in certain parts of the United States today, but they reveal them¬
selves immediately as patently wrong if taken as they were meant—namely,
as descriptions of the revolutionary or the conservative as such; the error in
question was due to the parochialism inevitably fostered by the new politi¬
cal science.
At the risk of some repetition we must say a few words about the lan¬
guage of the new political science. The break with the political understand¬
ing of political things necessitates the making of a language different from
the language used by political men. The new political science rejects the
latter language as ambiguous and imprecise and claims that its own lan¬
guage is unambiguous and precise. Yet this claim is not warranted. The
language of the new political science is not less vague, but more vague,
than the language used in political life. Political life would be altogether
impossible if its language were unqualifiedly vague; that language is capable
of the utmost unambiguity and precision as in a declaration of war or in an
order given to a firing squad. If available distinctions like that between
war, peace, and armistice prove to be insufficient, political life finds,
without the benefit of political science, the right new expression (Cold
War as distinguished from Hot or Shooting War) which designates the
new phenomenon with unfailing precision. The alleged vagueness of polit¬
ical language is primarily due to the fact that it corresponds to the com¬
plexity of political life or that it is nourished by long experience with polit¬
ical things in a great variety of circumstances. By simply condemning pre-
scientific language, instead of deviating from usage in particular cases be¬
cause of the proved inadequacy of usage in the cases in question, one
simply condemns oneself to irredeemable vagueness. No thoughtful citizen
would dream of equating politics with something as vague and empty as
“power” or “power relations.” The thinking men who are regarded as the
classic interpreters of power—Thucydides and Machiavelli—did not need
these expressions; these expressions as now used originate, not in political
life, but in the academic reaction to the understanding of political life in
terms of law alone: these expressions signify nothing but that academic
reaction.
Political language does not claim to be perfectly clear and distinct; it
does not claim that it is based on a full understanding of the things which
it designates unambiguously enough; it is suggestive: it leaves those things
in the penumbra in which they come to sight. The purge effected by “sci¬
entific” definitions of those things has the character of sterilization. The
language of the new political science claims to be perfectly clear and dis¬
tinct and at the same time entirely provisional; its terms are meant to
218 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
imply hypotheses about political life. But this claim to undogmatic open¬
ness is a mere ceremonial gesture. When one speaks of “conscience” one
does not claim that one has fathomed the phenomenon indicated by that
term. But when the new political scientist speaks of the “Super-Ego,” he is
certain that anything meant by “conscience” which is not covered by the
Super-Ego ’ is a superstition. As a consequence he cannot distinguish be¬
tween a bad conscience, which may induce a man to devote the rest of his
life to compensating another man to the best of his powers for an irrepara¬
ble damage, and “guilt feelings” which one ought to get rid of as fast and
as cheaply as possible. Similarly he is certain to have understood the trust
which induces people to vote for a candidate for high office by speaking of
the father image”; he does not have to inquire whether and to what ex¬
tent the candidate in question deserves that trust—a trust different from
the trust which children have in their father. The allegedly provisional or
hypothetical terms are never questioned in the process of research, for their
implications channel the research in such directions that the “data” which
might reveal the inadequacy of the hypotheses never turn up. We con¬
clude that to the extent to which the new political science is not formalis¬
tic, it is vulgarian. This vulgarianism shows itself particularly in the “value-
free manner in which it uses and thus debases terms that originally were
meant only for indicating things of a noble character—terms like “cul-
ture, personality,” “values,” “charismatic,” and “civilization.”
The most important example of the dogmatism to which we have
alluded is supplied by the treatment of religion in the new political or so¬
cial science. The new science uses sociological or psychological theories re¬
garding religion which exclude, without considering it, the possibility that
religion rests ultimately on God’s revealing Himself to man; hence those
theories are mere hypotheses which can never be confirmed. Those theories
are in fact the hidden basis of the new science. The new science rests on a
dogmatic atheism which presents itself as merely methodological or hypo¬
thetical. For a few years, logical positivism tried with much noise and little
thought to dispose of religion by asserting that religious assertions are
meaningless statements.” This trick seems to have been abandoned with¬
out noise. Some adherents of the new political science might rejoin with
some liveliness that their posture toward religion is imposed on them by
intellectual honesty: not being able to believe, they cannot accept belief as
the basis of their science. We gladly grant that, other things being equal, a
frank atheist is a better man than an alleged theist who conceives of God
as a symbol. But we must add that intellectual honesty is not enough. In¬
tellectual honesty is not love of truth. Intellectual honesty, a kind of self-
denial, has taken the place of love of truth because truth has come to be
believed to be repulsive, and one cannot love the repulsive. Yet just as our
opponents refuse respect to unreasoned belief, we on our part, with at least
An Epilogue / 219
equal right, must refuse respect to unreasoned unbelief; honesty with one¬
self regarding one’s unbelief is in itself not more than unreasoned unbelief,
probably accompanied by a vague confidence that the issue of unbelief ver¬
sus belief has long since been settled once and for all. It is hardly necessary
to add that the dogmatic exclusion of religious awareness proper renders
questionable all long-range predictions concerning the future of societies.
The reduction of the political to the subpolitical is the reduction of pri¬
marily given wholes to elements which are relatively simple, that is, suffi¬
ciently simple for the research purpose at hand, yet necessarily susceptible
of being analyzed into still simpler elements in infinitum. It implies that
there cannot be genuine wholes. Hence it implies that there cannot be a
common good. According to the old political science, there is necessarily a
common good, and the common good in its fullness is the good society and
what is required for the good society. The consistent denial of the common
good is as impossible as every other consistent manifestation of the break
with common sense. The empiricists who reject the notion of wholes are
compelled to speak sooner or later of such things as “the open society,”
which is their definition of the good society. The alternative (if it is an
alternative) is to deny the possibility of a substantive public interest, but
to admit the possibility of substantive group interests; yet it is not difficult
to see that what is granted to the goose “group” cannot be consistently
denied to the gander “country.” In accordance with this, the new political
science surreptitiously reintroduces the common good in the form of “the
rules of the game” with which all conflicting groups are supposed to com¬
ply because those rules reasonably fair to every group can reasonably be
admitted by every group. The “group politics” approach is a relic of Marx¬
ism, which more reasonably denied that there can be a common good in a
society consisting of classes that are locked in a life-and-death struggle,
overt or hidden, and therefore found the common good in a classless and
hence stateless society comprising the whole human race or the surviving
part of it. The consistent denial of the common good requires a radical
“individualism.” In fact, the new political science appears to teach that
there cannot be a substantive public interest because there is not, and
cannot be, a single objective which is approved by all members of society:
murderers show by their action that not even the prohibition against
murder is strictly speaking to the public interest. We are not so sure
whether the murderer wishes that murder cease to be a punishable action
and not rather that he himself get away with murder. Be this as it may, this
denial of the common good is based on the premise that even if an objec¬
tive is to the interest of the overwhelming majority, it is not to the interest
of all: no minority, however small, no individual, however perverse, must
be left out. More precisely, even if an objective is to the interest of all, but
not believed by all to be to the interest of all, it is not to the public inter-
220 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
est: everyone is by nature the sole judge of what is to his interest; his judg¬
ment regarding his interest is not subject to anybody else’s examination on
the issue whether his judgment is sound.
This premise is not the discovery or invention of the new political sci¬
ence; it was stated with the greatest vigor by Hobbes, who opposed it to
the opposite premise which had been the basis of the old political science
proper. But Hobbes still saw that his premise entails the war of everybody
against everybody and hence drew the conclusion that everyone must cease
to be the sole judge of what is to his interest if there is to be human life;
the individual's reason must give way to the public reason. The new politi¬
cal science denies in a way that there is a public reason: government may
be a broker, if a broker possessing “the monopoly of violence,” but it surely
is not the public reason. The true public reason is the new political science
which judges in a universally valid, or objective, manner of what is to the
interest of each, for it shows to everyone what means he must choose in
order to attain his attainable ends, whatever those ends may be. It has been
shown earlier in this volume what becomes of the new political science, or
of the only kind of rationality which the new political science still admits,
if its Hobbesian premise is not conveniently forgotten: the new form of
public reason goes the way of the old.
The denial of the common good presents itself today as a direct conse¬
quence of the distinction between facts and values according to which only
factual judgments, not value judgments, can be true or objective. The new
political science leaves the justification of values or of preferences to “polit¬
ical philosophy” or more precisely to ideology on the ground that any jus¬
tification of preferences would have to derive values from facts, and such
derivation is not legitimately possible. Preferences are not strictly speaking
opinions and hence cannot be true or false, whereas ideologies are opinions
and, for the reason given, false opinions. Whereas acting man has neces¬
sarily chosen values, the new political scientist as pure spectator is not
committed to any value; in particular, he is neutral in the conflict between
liberal democracy and its enemies. The traditional value systems antedate
the awareness of the difference between facts and values; they claimed to
be derived from facts—from Divine Revelation or from similar sources—in
general from superior or perfect beings which as such unite in themselves
fact and value; the discovery of the difference between facts and values
amounts therefore to a refutation of the traditional value systems as origi¬
nally meant. It is at least doubtful whether those value systems can be
divorced from what present themselves as their factual bases. At any rate, it
follows from the difference between facts and values that men can live
without ideology: they can adopt, posit, or proclaim values without making
the illegitimate attempt to derive their values from facts or without relying
on false or at least unevident assertions regarding what is. One thus arrives
at the notion of the rational society or of the nonideological regime: a soci-
An Epilogue / 221
against what one may call the democratic orthodoxy of the immediate past.
It had learned certain lessons which were hard for that orthodoxy to
swallow regarding the irrationality of the masses and the necessity of elites;
if it had been wise, it would have learned those lessons from the galaxy of
antidemocratic thinkers of the remote past. It believed, in other words, it
had learned that contrary to the belief of the orthodox democrats, no com¬
pelling case can be made for liberalism (for example, for the unqualified
freedom of such speech as does not constitute a clear and present danger)
nor for democracy (free elections based on universal suffrage). But it suc¬
ceeded in reconciling those doubts with the unfaltering commitment to
liberal democracy by the simple device of declaring that no value judg¬
ments, including those supporting liberal democracy, are rational and
hence that an ironclad argument in favor of liberal democracy ought in
reason not even to be expected. The very complex pros and cons regarding
liberal democracy have thus become entirely obliterated by the poorest
formalism. The crisis of liberal democracy has become concealed by a ritual
which calls itself methodology or logic. This almost willful blindness to the
crisis of liberal democracy is part of that crisis. No wonder then that the
new political science has nothing to say against those who unhesitatingly
prefer surrender, that is, the abandonment of liberal democracy, to war.
Only a great fool would call the new political science diabolic: it has no
attributes peculiar to fallen angels. It is not even Machiavellian, for
Machiavelli’s teaching was graceful, subtle, and colorful. Nor is it
Neronian. Nevertheless one may say of it that it fiddles while Rome burns.
It is excused by two facts: it does not know that it fiddles, and it does not
know that Rome burns.
9/ Preface to Spinoza’s
Critique of Religion
224
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 225
moment; that moment was to come within a few years. The weakness of
the Weimar Republic made certain its speedy destruction. It did not make
certain the victory of National Socialism. The victory of National Socialism
became necessary in Germany for the same reason for which the victory of
Communism had become necessary in Russia: the man who had by far the
strongest will or single-mindedness, the greatest ruthlessness, daring, and
power over his following, and the best judgment about the strength of the
various forces in the immediately relevant political field was the leader of
the revolution.1
Half-Marxists trace the weakness of the Weimar Republic to the power
of monopoly capitalism and the economic crisis of 1929, but there were
other liberal democracies which were and remained strong although they
had to contend with the same difficulties. It is more reasonable to refer to
the fact that the Weimar Republic had come into being through the de¬
feat of Germany in World War I, although this answer merely leads to the
further question as to why Germany had not succeeded in becoming a lib¬
eral democracy under more auspicious circumstances (for instance, in
1848), that is, why liberal democracy had always been weak in Germany. It
is true that the Bismarckian regime as managed by William II had become
discredited already prior to World War I and still more through that war
and its outcome, and correspondingly liberal democracy had become ever
more attractive; but at the crucial moment the victorious liberal democra¬
cies discredited liberal democracy in the eyes of Germany by the betrayal
of their principles through the Treaty of Versailles.
It is safer to try to understand the low in the light of the high than the
high in the light of the low. In doing the latter one necessarily distorts the
high, whereas in doing the former one does not deprive the low of the
freedom to reveal itself fully as what it is. By its name the Weimar Repub¬
lic refers one to the greatest epoch of German thought and letters, to the
epoch extending from the last third of the eighteenth century to the first
third of the nineteenth century. No one can say that classical Germany
spoke clearly and distinctly in favor of liberal democracy. This is true de¬
spite the fact that classical Germany had been initiated by Rousseau. In
the first place Rousseau was the first modem critic of the fundamental
modern project (man’s conquest of nature for the sake of the relief of
man’s estate) who therewith laid the foundation for the distinction, so
fateful for German thought, between civilization and culture. Above all,
the radicalization and deepening of Rousseau’s thought by classical Ger¬
man philosophy culminated in Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, the legitima¬
tion of that kind of constitutional monarchy which is based on the recogni¬
tion of the rights of man and in which government is in the hands of
highly educated civil servants appointed by a hereditary king. It has been
said, not without reason, that Hegel’s rule over Germany came to an end
only on the day that Hitler came to power. But Rousseau prepared not
226 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
only the French Revolution and classical German philosophy but also that
extreme reaction to the French Revolution which is German romanticism.
To speak politically and crudely, “the romantic school in Germany . . .
was nothing other than the resurrection of medieval poetry as it had
manifested itself ... in art and in life.” 2 The longing for the Middle
Ages began in Germany in the same moment in which the actual
Middle Ages—the Holy Roman Empire ruled by a German—ended,
in what was then thought to be the moment of Germany’s deepest
humiliation. In Germany, and only there, did the end of the Middle Ages
coincide with the beginning of the longing for the Middle Ages. Compared
with the medieval Reich, which had lasted for almost a millennium until
1806, Bismarck’s Reich (to say nothing of Hegel’s Prussia) revealed itself
as a little Germany not only in size. All profound German longings—for
those for the Middle Ages were not the only ones nor even the most pro¬
found ones—all these longings for the origins or, negatively expressed, all
German dissatisfactions with modernity pointed toward a third Reich, for
Germany was to be the core even of Nietzsche’s Europe ruling the planet.8
The weakness of liberal democracy in Germany explains why the situa¬
tion of the indigenous Jews was more precarious in Germany than in any
other Western country. Liberal democracy had originally defined itself in
theologico-political treatises as the opposite, less of the more or less en¬
lightened despotism of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, than of
“the kingdom of darkness,” that is, of medieval society. According to lib¬
eral democracy, the bond of society is universal human morality, whereas
religion (positive religion) is a private affair; in the Middle Ages religion,
that is, Catholic Christianity, was the bond of society. The action most
characteristic of the Middle Ages is the Crusades; it may be said to have
culminated not accidentally in the murder of whole Jewish communities.
The German Jews owed their emancipation to the French Revolution or
its effects. They were given full political rights for the first time by the
Weimar Republic. The Weimar Republic was succeeded by the only
German regime—by the only regime that ever was anywhere—which had
no other clear principle except murderous hatred of the Jews, for “Aryan”
had no clear meaning other than “non-Jewish.” One must keep in mind
the fact that Hitler did not come from Prussia, nor even from Bismarck’s
Reich.
While the German Jews were politically in a more precarious situation
than the Jews in any other Western country, they originated “the science
of Judaism,” the historical-critical study by Jews of the Jewish heritage.
The emancipation of the Jews in Germany coincided with the greatest
epoch of German thought and poetry, with the epoch in which Germany
was the foremost country in thought and poetry. One cannot help compar¬
ing the period of German Jewry with the period of Spanish Jewry. The
greatest achievements of Jews during the Spanish period were partly ren-
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 227
dered possible by the fact that Jews became open to the influx of Greek
thought which was understood to be Greek only accidentally. During the
German period, however, the Jews became open to the influx of
German thought, of the thought of the particular nation in the midst of
which they lived—of a thought which was understood to be German
essentially: the political dependence was also spiritual dependence. This
was the core of the predicament of German Jewry.
Three quotations may serve to illustrate the precarious situation of the
Jews in Germany. Goethe, the greatest among the cosmopolitan Germans,
a “decided non-Christian,” summarizes the results of a conversation about
a new society to be founded, between his Wilhelm Meister and “the gay
Friedrich,” without providing his summary with quotation marks, as
follows:
To this religion [the Christian religion] we hold on, but in a particular man¬
ner; we instruct our children from their youth on in the great advantages
which [that religion] has brought to us; but of its author, of its course we
speak to them only at the end. Then only does the author become dear and
cherished, and all reports regarding him become sacred. Drawing a conclu¬
sion which one may perhaps call pedantic, but of which one must at any
rate admit that it follows from the premise, we do not tolerate any Jew
among us; for how could we grant him a share in the highest culture, the
origin and tradition of which he denies? 4
Two generations later Nietzsche could say: “I have not yet met a German
who was favorably disposed toward the Jews.” 5 One might try to trace
Nietzsche’s judgment to the narrowness of his circle of acquaintances: no
one would expect to find people favorably disposed toward Jews among the
German Lutheran pastors among whom Nietzsche grew up, to say nothing
of Jakob Burckhardt in Basel. Nietzsche has chosen his words carefully; he
surely excluded himself when making the judgment quoted, as appears, in
addition, from the context. But he does not say something trivial. While his
circle of acquaintances was limited—perhaps unusually limited—he was of
unusual perspicacity. Besides, being favorably disposed toward this or that
man or woman of Jewish origin does not mean being favorably disposed
toward Jews. Two generations later, in 1953, Heidegger could speak of “the
inner truth and greatness of National Socialism.” 6
In the course of the nineteenth century many Western men had come
to conceive of many, if not all, sufferings as problems which as such were
held to be soluble as a matter of course. Thus they had come to speak also
of the Jewish problem. The German-Jewish problem was never solved. It
was annihilated by the annihilation of the German Jews. Prior to Hitler’s
rise to power most German Jews believed that their problem had been
solved in principle by liberalism: the German Jews were Germans of the
Jewish faith, that is, they were no less German than the Germans of the
228 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
Christian faith or of no faith. They assumed that the German state (to say
nothing of German society or culture) was or ought to be neutral to the
difference between Christians and Jews or betw'een non-Jews and Jews.
This assumption was not accepted by the strongest part of Germany and
hence by Germany. In the words of Herzl: “Who belongs and who does
not belong, is decided by the majority; it is a question of power.” At any
rate it could seem that in the absence of a superior recognized equally by
both parties the natural judge on the Germanness of the German Jews was
the non-Jewish Germans. As a consequence a small minority of the
German Jews, but a considerable minority of the German-Jewish youth
studying at the universities, had turned to Zionism. Zionism was almost
never wholly divorced from the traditional Jewish hopes. On the, other
hand, Zionism never intended to bring about a restoration like the one
achieved in the days of Ezra and Nehemiah: the return to the land of
Israel was not thought to culminate in the building of the third temple
and in the restoration of the sacrificial service.
The peculiarity of Zionism as a modern movement comes out most
clearly in the strictly political Zionism as presented in the first place by
Leon Pinsker in his Autoemancipation and then by Theodor Herzl in The
Jews’ State. Pinsker and Herzl started from the failure of the liberal solu¬
tion but continued to see the problem to be solved as it had begun to be
seen by liberalism, that is, as a merely human problem. They radicalized
this purely human understanding. The terrible fate of the Jews was in no
sense to be understood any longer as connected with divine punishment
for the sins of our fathers or with the providential mission of the chosen
people and hence to be borne with the meek fortitude of martyrs. It was to
be understood in merely human terms: as constituting a purely political
problem which as such cannot be solved by appealing to the justice or
generosity of other nations, to say nothing of a league of all nations.
Accordingly, political Zionism was concerned primarily with nothing but
the cleansing of the Jews from millennial degradation or with the recovery
of Jewish dignity, honor, or pride. The failure of the liberal solution meant
that the Jews could not regain their honor by assimilating themselves as
individuals to the nations among which they lived or by becoming citizens
like all other citizens of the liberal states: the liberal solution brought at
best legal equality, but not social equality; as a demand of reason it had no
effect on the feelings of the non-Jews. To quote Herzl again: “We are a
nation—the enemy makes us a nation whether we like it or not.” In the
last analysis this is nothing to be deplored, for “the enemy is necessary for
the highest effort of the personality.” Only through securing the honor of
the Jewish nation could the individual Jew’s honor be secured. The true
solution of the Jewish problem requires that the Jews become “like all the
nations” (I Sam. 8), that the Jewish nation assimilate itself to the nations
of the world or that it establish a modern, liberal, secular (but not neces-
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 229
sarily democratic) state. Political Zionism strictly understood was then the
movement of an elite on behalf of a community constituted by common
descent and common degradation for the restoration of their honor
through the acquisition of statehood and therefore of a country—of any
country: the land which the strictly political Zionism promised to the Jews
was not necessarily the land of Israel.
This project implied a profound modification of the traditional Jewish
hopes—a modification arrived at through a break with these hopes. For the
motto of his pamphlet Pinsker chose these words of Hillel: “If I am not
for myself, who will be for me? And if not now, when?’' He omitted the
sentence which forms the center of Hillel’s statement: “And if I am only
for myself, what am I?” He saw the Jewish people as a herd without a
shepherd who protects and gathers it; he did not long for a shepherd, but
for the transformation of the herd into a nation which can take care of
itself. He regarded the Jewish situation as a natural sickness which can be
cured only by natural means. What the change effected by strictly political
Zionism means, one sees most clearly when, returning to the origin, one
ponders over this sentence of Spinoza: “If the foundations of their religion
did not effeminate the minds of the Jews, I would absolutely believe that
they will at some time, given the occasion (for human things are mutable),
establish their state again.”
Strictly political Zionism became effective only through becoming an
ingredient, not to say the backbone, of Zionism at large, that is, by making
its peace with traditional Jewish thought. Through this alliance or fusion it
brought about the establishment of the state of Israel and therewith that
cleansing which it had primarily intended; it thus procured a blessing for
all Jews everywhere regardless of whether they admit it or not.7 It did not,
however, solve the Jewish problem. It could not solve the Jewish problem
because of the narrowness of its original conception, however noble. This
narrowness was pointed out most effectively by cultural Zionism: strictly
political Zionism, concerned only with the present emergency and resolve,
lacks historical perspective; the community of descent, of the blood, must
also be a community of the mind, of the national mind; the Jewish state
will be an empty shell without a Jewish culture which has its roots in the
Jewish heritage. One could not have taken this step unless one had previ¬
ously interpreted the Jewish heritage itself as a culture, that is, as a product
of the national mind, of the national genius.8 Yet the foundation, the
authoritative layer, of the Jewish heritage presents itself, not as a product
of the human mind, but as a divine gift, as divine revelation. Did one not
completely distort the meaning of the heritage to which one claimed to be
loyal by interpreting it as a culture like any other high culture? Cultural
Zionism believed to have found a safe middle ground between politics
(power politics) and divine revelation, between the subcultural and the
supracultural, but it lacked the sternness of the two extremes. When cul-
230 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
tural Zionism understands itself, it turns into religious Zionism. But when
religious Zionism understands itself, it is in the first place Jewish faith and
only secondarily Zionism. It must regard as blasphemous the notion of a
human solution to the Jewish problem. It may go so far as to regard the
establishment of the state of Israel as the most important event in Jewish
history since the completion of the Talmud, but it cannot regard it as the
arrival of the Messianic age, of the redemption of Israel and all men. The
establishment of the state of Israel is the most profound modification of
the Galuth which has occurred, but it is not the end of the Galuth: in the
religious sense, and perhaps not only in the religious sense, the state of
Israel is a part of the Galuth. Finite, relative problems can be solved;
infinite, absolute problems cannot be solved. In other words, human
beings will never create a society which is free from contradictions. From
every point of view it looks as if the Jewish people were the chosen people,
at least in the sense that the Jewish problem is the most manifest symbol
of the human problem insofar as it is a social or political problem.
To realize that the Jewish problem is insoluble means never to forget the
truth proclaimed by Zionism regarding the limitations of liberalism. Lib¬
eralism stands and falls by the distinction between state and society or by
the recognition of a private sphere, protected by the law but impervious to
the law, with the understanding that, above all, religion as particular reli¬
gion belongs to the private sphere. As certainly as the liberal state will not
“discriminate” against its Jewish citizens, as certainly is it constitutionally
unable and even unwilling to prevent “discrimination” against Jews on the
part of individuals or groups. To recognize a private sphere in the sense
indicated means to permit private “discrimination,” to protect it, and thus
in fact to foster it. The liberal state cannot provide a solution to the Jewish
problem, for such a solution would require the legal prohibition against
every kind of “discrimination,” that is, the abolition of the private sphere,
the denial of the difference between state and society, the destruction of
the liberal state. Such a destruction would not by any means solve the Jew¬
ish problem, as is shown in our days by the anti-Jewish policy of the
U.S.S.R. It is foolish to say that that policy contradicts the principles of
Communism, for it contradicts the principles of Communism to separate
the principles of Communism from the Communist movement. The
U.S.S.R. owes its survival to Stalin’s decision not to wait for the revolution
of the Western proletariat, that is, for what others would do for the
U.S.S.R., but to build up socialism in a single country where his word was
the law, by the use of any means, however bestial, and these means could
include, as a matter of course, means successfully used before, not to say
invented, by Hitler: the large-scale murder of party members and anti-
Jewish measures. This is not to deny that Communism has not become
what National Socialism always was, the prisoner of an anti-Jewish ideol¬
ogy, but makes use of anti-Jewish measures in an unprincipled manner.
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 231
God’s declaring these teachings and rules could have that certainty only
through a reliable tradition which also vouches for the reliable transmission
of the very words of God, and through miracles. The self-misunderstanding
is removed when the content of revelation is seen to be rational, which
does not necessarily mean that everything hitherto thought to be revealed
is rational. The need for external credentials of revelation (tradition and
miracles) disappears as its internal credentials come to abound. The truth
of traditional Judaism is the religion of reason, or the religion of reason is
secularized Judaism. But the same claim could be made for Christianity,
and however close secularized Judaism and secularized Christianity might
come to each other, they are not identical, and as purely rational they
ought to be identical. Above all, if the truth of Judaism is the religion of
reason, then what was formerly believed to be revelation by the transcend¬
ent God must now be understood as the work of the human imagination
in which human reason was effective to some extent; what has now become
a clear and distant idea was originally a confused idea.11 What, except
demonstrations of the existence of God by theoretical reason or postu¬
lations of His existence by practical reason which were becoming ever
more incredible, could prevent one from taking the last step, that is, to
assert that God Himself is a product of the human mind, at best “an
idea of reason”?
These and similar denials or interpretations suddenly lost all their force
by the simple observation that they contradict not merely inherited opin¬
ions but present experience. At first hearing one may be reminded of what
Leibniz had said when overcoming Bayle’s doubt regarding revelation:
“Toutes ces difficultes invincibles, ces combats pr^tendus de la raison
contre la foi s’evanouissent.
God’s revealing Himself to man, His addressing man, is not merely known
through traditions going back to the remote past and is therefore now
“merely believed” but is genuinely known through present experience
which every human being can have if he does not refuse himself to it. This
experience is not a kind of self-experience, of the actualization of a human
potentiality, of the human mind coming into its own, into what it desires
or is naturally inclined to, but of something undesired, coming from the
outside, going against man’s grain; it is the only awareness of something
absolute which cannot be relativized in any way as everything else, rational
or nonrational, can; it is the experience of God as the Thou, the father and
king of all men; it is the experience of an unequivocal command addressed
to me here and now as distinguished from general laws or ideas which are
always disputable and permitting of exceptions; only by surrendering to
God’s experienced call which calls for one’s loving Him with all one’s
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 233
heart, with all one’s soul, and with all one’s might can one come to see the
other human being as his brother and love him as himself. The absolute
experience will not lead back to Judaism—for instance, to the details of
what the Christians call the ceremonial law—if it does not recognize itself
in the Bible and clarify itself through the Bible and if it is not linked up
with considerations of how traditional Judaism understands itself and with
meditations about the mysterious fate of the Jewish people. The return to
Judaism also requires today the overcoming of what one may call the per¬
ennial obstacle to the Jewish faith: of traditional philosophy, which is of
Greek, pagan origin. For the respectable, impressive, or specious alterna¬
tives to the acceptance of revelation, to the surrender to God’s will, have
always presented themselves and still present themselves as based on what
man knows by himself, by his reason. Reason has reached its perfection in
Hegel’s system; the essential limitations of Hegel’s system show the essen¬
tial limitations of reason and therewith the radical inadequacy of all ra¬
tional objections to revelation. With the final collapse of rationalism the
perennial battle between reason and revelation, between unbelief and belief,
has been decided in principle, even on the plane of human thought, in
favor of revelation. Reason knows only of subjects and objects, but surely
the living and loving God is infinitely more than a subject and can never
be an object, something at which one can look in detachment or indiffer¬
ence. Philosophy as hitherto known, the old thinking, so far from starting
from the experience of God, abstracted from such experience or excluded
it; hence, if it was theistic, it was compelled to have recourse to demonstra¬
tions of the existence of God as a thinking or a thinking and willing being.
The new thinking as unqualified empiricism speaks of God, man, and the
world as actually experienced, as realities irreducible to one another,
whereas all traditional philosophy was reductionist. For if it did not assert
that the world and man are eternal, that is, deny the creator-God, it sought
for the reality preceding world and man as it precedes world and man and
as it succeeds world and man, that is, for what cannot be experienced by
man, by the whole man, but only be inferred or thought by him. Un¬
qualified empiricism does not recognize any such Without or Beyond as a
reality, but only as unreal forms, essences, or concepts which can never be
more than objects, that is, objects of mere thought.13
The new thinking had been originated, above all, by Franz Rosenzweig,
who is thought to be the greatest Jewish thinker whom German Jewry has
brought forth. It was counteracted by another form of the new thinking,
the form originated by Heidegger.14 It was obvious that Heidegger’s new
thinking led far away from any charity as well as from any humanity. On
the other hand, it could not be denied that he had a deeper understanding
than Rosenzweig of what was implied in the insight or demand that the
traditional philosophy which rested on Greek foundations must be super¬
seded by a new thinking. He would never have said as Rosenzweig did that
234 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
“we know in the most precise manner, we know it with the intuitional
knowledge of experience, what God taken by Himself, what man taken by
himself, what the world taken by itself ‘is/ ” Nor did he assume, as
Rosenzweig assumed, that we possess without further ado an adequate
understanding of Greek philosophy, of the basic stratum of that old think¬
ing which has to be overcome: with the questioning of traditional philoso¬
phy the traditional understanding of the tradition becomes questionable.
For this reason alone he could not have said as Rosenzweig did that most
Platonic dialogues are “boring.” 15 This difference between Rosenzweig
and Heidegger, about which much more could be said, was not uncon¬
nected with their difference regarding revelation. At that time Heidegger
expressed his thought about revelation by silence or deed rather than by
speech. Rosenzweig’s friend Martin Buber quotes a much later utterance
of Heidegger which gives one, I believe, an inkling of Heidegger’s
argument—especially if it is taken in conjunction with well-known utter¬
ances of Nietzsche whom Heidegger evidently follows in this matter.
“The ‘prophets’ of these religions [sc. Judaism and Christianity],” says
Heidegger according to Buber, “do not begin by foretelling the word of the
Holy. They announce immediately the God upon whom the certainty of
salvation is a supernatural blessedness reckons.” 16 Buber comments on
this statement as follows:
Heidegger does not speak of the prophets’ “hearers,” but he clearly means
that the prophets themselves were concerned with security.17 This asser¬
tion is not refuted by the well-known facts which Buber points out—by the
fact, in a word, that for the prophets there is no refuge and fortress except
God: the security afforded by the temple of God is nothing, but the secu¬
rity afforded by God is everything. As Buber says seventeen pages earlier in
the same publication, “He who loves God only as a moral ideal, can easily
arrive at despairing of the guidance of a world the appearance of which
contradicts, hour after hour, all principles of his moral ideality.” 18 Surely
the Bible teaches that in spite of all appearances to the contrary the world
is guided by God or, to use the traditional term, that there is particular
providence, that man is protected by God if he does not put his trust in
flesh and blood but in God alone, that he is not completely exposed or for¬
saken, that he is not alone, that he has been created by a being which is, to
Preface to Spinoza's Critique of Religion / 235
of the utmost importance to that Church that its father was not a Chris¬
tian, but a Jew who had informally embraced a Christianity without
dogmas and sacraments. The millennial antagonism between Judaism and
Christianity was about to disappear. The new Church would transform
Jews and Christians into human beings—into human beings of a certain
kind: cultured human beings, human beings who, because they possessed
science and art, did not need religion in addition. The new society, consti¬
tuted by the aspiration common to all its members toward the True, the
Good, and the Beautiful, emancipated the Jews in Germany. Spinoza be¬
came the symbol of that emancipation which was to be not only emancipa¬
tion but secular redemption. In Spinoza, a thinker and a saint who was
both a Jew and a Christian and hence neither, all cultured families of the
earth, it was hoped, would be blessed. In a word, the non-Jewish world,
having been molded to a considerable extent by Spinoza, had become re¬
ceptive to Jews who were willing to assimilate themselves to it.
The celebration of Spinoza had become equally necessary on purely
Jewish grounds. As we have seen, the emphasis had shifted from the Torah
to the Jewish nation, and the Jewish nation could not be considered the
source of the Torah if it was not understood as an organism with a soul of
its own; that soul had expressed itself originally and classically in the Bible,
although not in all parts of the Bible equally. From the days of the Bible
on, there was always the conflict between prophet and priest, between the
inspired and the uninspired, between profound subterraneous Judaism and
official Judaism. Official Judaism was legalistic and hence rationalistic. Its
rationalism had received most powerful support from the philosophic ra¬
tionalism of alien origin which had found its perfect expression in the
Platonic conception of God as an artificer who makes the universe by look¬
ing up to the unchangeable, lifeless ideas. In accordance with this, official
Judaism asserted that God has created the world and governs it sub ratione
boni. Precisely because he believed in the profoundly understood divinity
of the Bible, Spinoza revolted against this official assertion in the name of
the absolutely free or sovereign God of the Bible—of the God who will be
what He will be, who will be gracious to whom He will be gracious and
will show mercy to whom He will show mercy. Moved by the same spirit,
he embraced with enthusiasm Paul’s doctrine of predestination. The bibli¬
cal God has created man in His image: male and female did He create
them. The male and the female, form and matter, cogitation and exten¬
sion, are then equally attributes of God; Spinoza rejects both Greek ideal¬
ism and Christian spiritualism. The biblical God forms light and creates
darkness, makes peace and creates evil; Spinoza’s God is simply beyond
good and evil. God’s might is His right, and therefore the power of every
being is as such its right; Spinoza lifts Machiavellianism to theological
heights. Good and evil differ only from a merely human point of view;
theologically the distinction is meaningless. The evil passions are evil only
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 243
with a view to human utility; in themselves they show forth the might and
the right of God no less than other things which we admire and by the
contemplation of which we are delighted. In the state of nature, that is,
independently of human convention, there is nothing just and unjust, no
duty and no guilt, and the state of nature does not simply vanish when
civil society is established: pangs of conscience are nothing but feelings of
displeasure which arise when a plan has gone wrong. Hence there are no
vestiges of divine justice to be found except where just men reign. All
human acts are modes of the one God who possesses infinitely many at¬
tributes each of which is infinite and only two of which are known to us,
who is therefore a mysterious God, whose mysterious love reveals itself in
eternally and necessarily bringing forth love and hatred, nobility and
baseness, saintliness and depravity, and who is infinitely lovable not in
spite but because of His infinite power beyond good and evil.
Compared with the fantastic flights of the Spinoza enthusiasts in the
two camps, of the moralists and the immoralists, Cohen’s understanding of
Spinoza is sobriety itself. All the more impressive is his severe indictment
of Spinoza.36 He shows first that in his Theologico-political Treatise Spi¬
noza speaks from a Christian point of view and accordingly accepts the
entire Christian critique of Judaism, but goes much even beyond that
Christian critique in his own critique. He accepts against his better knowl¬
edge the assertion of Jesus that Judaism commands the hatred of the
enemy. He opposes spiritual and universalistic Christianity to carnal and
particularistic Judaism: the core of Judaism is the Mosaic law as a particu¬
laristic, not to say tribal, law which serves no other end than the earthly or
political felicity of the Jewish nation; the Torah does not teach morality,
that is, universal morality; the Mosaic religion is merely national; Moses’
God is a tribal and in addition a corporeal God. By denying that the God
of Israel is the God of all mankind Spinoza has blasphemed the God of
Israel. He reduces Jewish religion to a doctrine of the Jewish state. For
him, the Torah is of merely human origin.
Cohen shows next that the Christianity in the light of which Spinoza
condemns Judaism is not historical or actual Christianity, but an idealized
Christianity and hence that while he idealizes Christianity, he denigrates
Judaism. He shows then that Spinoza admits the universalistic character of
the Old Testament prophecy, thus contradicting himself grossly. This con¬
tradiction clearly proves his lack of good faith.37 Nor is this all. While tak¬
ing the side of spiritual and transpolitical Christianity against carnal and
political Judaism, Spinoza contradicts this whole argument by taking the
side of the state not only against all churches but against all religion as
well. “He put religion altogether,” that is, not merely Judaism, “outside
the sphere of truth.” Starting like all other sophists from the equation of
right and might, he conceives of the state entirely in terms of power poli¬
tics, that is, as divorced from religion and morality, and he puts the state
244 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
thus conceived above religion. This does not mean that he deifies the state.
On the contrary, he is concerned above everything else with what he calls
philosophy, which he assumes to be wholly inaccessible directly or indi¬
rectly to the large majority of men. He has no compunction whatever
about affirming the radical and unmodifiable inequality of men without
ever wondering “how can nature, how can God answer for this difference
among men?” Hence his sympathy for democracy is suspect. He is com¬
pelled to erect an eternal barrier between popular education and science or
philosophy and therewith between the state and reason. There is no place
in his thought for the enlightenment of the people. He has no heart for
the people, no compassion. He cannot admit a Messianic future of man¬
kind when all men will be united in genuine knowledge of God. This is the
reason why he is altogether blind to biblical prophecy and hence to the
core of Judaism.38
On the basis of all these facts Cohen reached the conclusion that so far
from deserving celebration, Spinoza fully deserved the excommunication.
So far from rescinding the excommunication, Cohen confirmed it, acting
as a judge in the highest court of appeal. The grounds of his verdict were
not the same as the grounds of the lower court. He was not concerned with
Spinoza’s transgression of the ceremonial law and his denial of the Mosaic
authorship of the Pentateuch. He condemned Spinoza because of his infi¬
delity in the simple human sense, of his complete lack of loyalty to his own
people, of his acting like an enemy of the Jews and thus giving aid and
comfort to the many enemies of the Jews, of his behaving like a base
traitor. Spinoza remains up to the present day the accuser par excellence of
Judaism before an anti-Jewish world; the disposition of his mind and heart
toward Jews and Judaism was “unnatural,” he committed a “humanly
incomprehensible act of treason,” he was possessed by “an evil demon.” 30
Our case against Spinoza is in some respects even stronger than Cohen
thought. One may doubt whether Spinoza’s action is humanly incompre¬
hensible or demoniac, but one must grant that it is amazingly unscrupu¬
lous. Cohen is justly perplexed by the fact that “the center of the whole
[theologico-political] treatise” is the disparagement of Moses and the ideal¬
ization of Jesus, although the purpose of the work is to secure the freedom
of philosophizing. He explains this anomaly by Spinoza’s belief that the
suppression of philosophy goes back to the Mosaic law. Cohen does not
assert that Moses championed the freedom of philosophy, but he raises the
pertinent question whether Jesus championed it.40 Why then does Spi¬
noza treat Judaism and Christianity differently? Why does he take the side
of Christianity in the conflict between Judaism and Christianity, in a con¬
flict of no concern to him as a philosopher? Cohen believes that Spinoza
had a genuine reverence for Jesus’ teachings. According to Spinoza’s own
statements he preferred spiritual Christianity to carnal Judaism.41 But is
Spinoza a spiritualist? Cohen says that spirit or mind, if applied to God, is
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 245
abrogation of the ceremonial law, however, not only because that abroga¬
tion is in his opinion a necessary condition of civic equality of the Jews but
also as desirable for its own sake: the ceremonial law is infinitely burden¬
some, nay, a curse.45
In providing for the liberal state, Spinoza provides for a Judaism which
is liberal in the extreme. The “assimilationist” “solution to the Jewish
problem” which Spinoza may be said to have suggested was more impor¬
tant from his point of view than the “Zionist” one which he likewise sug¬
gested. The latter as he understood it could seem to require the preserva¬
tion of the ceremonial law although the abandonment of the spirit which
has animated it hitherto.46 The former suggestion and the general purpose
of the Theologico-political Treatise are obviously connected: freedom of
philosophy requires, or seems to require, a liberal state, and a liberal state is
a state which is not as such either Christian or Jewish. Even Cohen sensed
for a moment that Spinoza was not entirely free from sympathy with his
people.47 Spinoza may have hated Judaism; he did not hate the Jewish
people. However bad a Jew he may have been in all other respects, he
thought of the liberation of the Jews in the only way in which he could
think of it, given his philosophy. But precisely if this is so, we must stress
all the more the fact that the manner in which he sets forth his pro¬
posal—to say nothing of the proposal itself—is Machiavellian: the humani¬
tarian end seems to justify every means; he plays a most dangerous
game;48 his procedure is as much beyond good and evil as his God.
All this does not mean, however, that Cohen’s critique of Spinoza’s
Theologico-political Treatise is altogether convincing. His political thought
claims to be inspired by biblical prophecy and hence is Messianic. In oppo¬
sition to Spinoza, it starts from the radical difference between nature and
morality, the Is and the Ought, egoism and pure will. The state is essen¬
tially moral, and morality cannot be actual except in and through the state.
The difficulty presented by the fact that morality is universal and the state
is always particular is overcome by the consideration that the state is part
of a universal moral order, as is shown by the existence of international
law and by the intrinsic possibility, which is at the same time a moral ne¬
cessity, of a universal league of states. The radical difference between
nature and morality does not amount to a contradiction between nature
and morality: nature does not render impossible the fulfillment of the
moral demands. The morally demanded infinite progress of morality, and
in particular the “eternal progress” toward “eternal peace,” nay, every
single step of morality, requires for its “ultimate security” the infinite dura¬
tion a parte post of the human race and hence of nature; this infinite
duration or eternity is secured by the idea of God “who signifies the har¬
mony of the knowledge of nature and of moral knowledge,” who is not a
person, nor living, nor existing, nor a spirit or mind, but an idea, “our”
idea, that is, our hypothesis in what Cohen regards as the Platonic meaning
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 247
Cohen (or his authority) also notes that according to the most authentic
text of the Code, the Gentile who performs the seven Noahidic command¬
ments because of a decision of reason does not indeed belong to the pious
Gentiles, but to the wise ones.56 But he does not show that Spinoza knew
that reading to be the most authentic reading. The reading used by Spi¬
noza is still the common reading, which it would not be if it were in shock¬
ing contrast to the consensus of Judaism as Cohen asserts and hence would
have shocked every Jewish reader.57 In addition, the allegedly best reading
does not necessarily improve the fate of the wise Gentiles unless one proves
first that the fate of the wise Gentiles is as good as that of the pious Gen¬
tiles. Cohen finally asserts that the passage in question contradicts two
other passages of the Code which in his opinion do not demand that the
pious Gentile believe in the revealed character of the Torah. It suffices to
say that the two passages are silent on what precisely constitutes the piety
of the Gentiles and are therefore irrelevant to the issue58 Cohen also
refers to a different treatment of the subject in Maimonides’ commentary
on the Mishna; but this merely leads to the further question whether that
commentary, composed much earlier than the Code, is equal in authority
to the Code.
But, to return to the main issue, that is, to the question whether the
ordinary reading, used by Spinoza, of the passage under consideration
makes sense as a Maimonidean utterance: can Maimonides have taught, as
Spinoza asserts he did, that Gentiles who perform the seven Noahidic
commandments because reason decides so are not wise men? The answer is
simple: Maimonides must have taught it because he denied that there are
any rational commandments. Cohen might have objected to this argument
on the ground that if Maimonides’ denial of the rationality of any com¬
mandments or laws were his last word, he could not well have attempted
to show that all or almost all commandments of the Torah have “rea¬
sons.” 59 The reply is obvious: according to Maimonides all or almost all
commandments of the Torah serve the purpose of eradicating idolatry, an
irrational practice, and are in this sense “rational”; they are rational in the
sense in which, not a healthy body, but a medicine, is “healthy.” 00 One
could say that Maimonides’ denial of the rationality of any law is implied
in the incriminated passage itself regardless of which of the two readings
one prefers; for the term which Cohen renders by “reason” [da1 at) does
not necessarily mean reason in particular, but may mean thought or opin¬
ion in general: 61 it makes sense both to assert and to deny that opinion
justifies the seven Noahidic commandments.
These and similar considerations do not affect the main issue, namely,
the fact that Cohen may well be right in asserting that Spinoza acted
ignobly in basing his denial of the universalism of traditional, postpro-
phetic Judaism on a single Maimonidean utterance. In the words of
Rosenzweig, beneath the deep injustice of Cohen’s judgment lies its still
250 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
human as regards its end, since it aims only at political felicity, but it is
divine qua divinely revealed. Cohen quotes Spinoza’s explanation: the
Mosaic law “may be called the law of God or divine law since we believe
that it is sanctioned by the prophetic light.” He remarks: “But why do we
believe this? This question is not answered by the anonymous author.” But
does not the community consisting of the anonymous author who speaks as
a Christian and his Christian readers believe it as a matter of course, so
that the question as to why “we believe it” does not have to arise? Spinoza
had originally said that the divine law aims only at the highest good;
immediately before saying that the Mosaic law can be called divine with a
view to its origin as distinguished from its aim, he says according to Cohen
that the divine law “consists chiefly in the highest good”: hence, Cohen
infers, Spinoza admits now a secondary content of the divine law without
stating immediately what that secondary content is, namely, the sensual
means which sensual men need. But Spinoza did not say that the divine
law consists in the highest good; he says that it consists in the prescriptions
regarding the means required for achieving the highest good: the divine
law consists chiefly of the prescriptions regarding the proximate means and
secondarily of the prescriptions regarding the remote means; since “sensual
man” is incapable of intellectual love of God, his needs fall wholly outside
of the divine law as here considered by Spinoza. It must be added that
according to Spinoza even the divine law in the strictest sense is of human
origin; every law is prescribed by human beings to themselves or to other
human beings. Cohen throws some light on Spinoza’s teaching regarding
the divine law by making this remark on Spinoza’s assertion that “the
highest reward of the divine law is the law itself”: “here he has literally
taken over a sentence of the Mishna from the well-known Sayings of the
Fathers, only adding the word ‘highest.’ ” Cohen underestimates the im¬
portance of Spinoza’s addition: Spinoza’s egoistic morality demands for the
fulfillment of the commandments rewards other than the commandments
or perhaps additional commandments; it does not leave room for mar¬
tyrdom.84
Rosenzweig finds Cohen guilty of injustice to Spinoza, not because of
defective objectivity, but rather because of defective “subjectivity,” that is,
of “insufficient reflection about the conditions and foundations of his own
person. He ought to have made his attack with a clearer consciousness of
the fact that, not indeed he himself, but the times which had borne and
raised him, Cohen himself, would not have been possible without Spi¬
noza.” The distinction between Cohen himself and his time, which is due
to idealizing or apologetic interpretation, is immaterial here, for if Cohen’s
thought had nothing to do with the thought of his time, he would not
have met Spinoza by reflecting about the presuppositions of “his own per¬
son.” Cohen accuses Spinoza of blindness to biblical prophetism, but this
phenomenon as Cohen understood it was brought to light by what he calls
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 253
first glance these premises seem to be arbitrary and hence to beg the whole
question. They are not evident in themselves, but they are thought to be¬
come evident through their alleged result: they and only they are held to
make possible the clear and distinct account of everything; in the light of
the clear and distinct account, the biblical account appears to be confused.
The Ethics thus begs the decisive question—the question as to whether
the clear and distinct account is as such true and not merely a plausible
hypothesis. In the Theologico-political Treatise, however, Spinoza starts
from premises which are granted to him by the believers in revelation; he
attempts to refute them on the bases of Scripture, of theologoumena
formulated by traditional authorities, and of what one may call common
sense. For in the Treatise Spinoza addresses men who are still believers and
whom he intends to liberate from their “prejudices” so that they can begin
to philosophize; the Treatise is Spinoza’s introduction to philosophy.
The results of this examination of Spinoza’s critique may be summarized
as follows. If orthodoxy claims to know that the Bible is divinely revealed,
that every word of the Bible is divinely inspired, that Moses was the writer
of the Pentateuch, that the miracles recorded in the Bible have happened
and similar things, Spinoza has refuted orthodoxy. But the case is entirely
different if orthodoxy limits itself to asserting that it believes the aforemen¬
tioned things, that is, that they cannot claim to possess the binding power pe¬
culiar to the known. For all assertions of orthodoxy rest on the irrefutable
premise that the omnipotent God, whose will is unfathomable, whose ways
are not our ways, who has decided to dwell in the thick darkness, may exist.
Given this premise, miracles and revelations in general, and hence all bibli¬
cal miracles and revelations in particular, are possible. Spinoza has not suc¬
ceeded in showing that this premise is contradicted by anything we know.
For what we are said to know, for example, regarding the age of the solar
system, has been established on the basis of the assumption that the solar
system has come into being naturally; miraculously it could have come into
being in the way described by the Bible. It is only naturally or humanly
impossible that the “first” Isaiah should have known the name of the
founder of the Persian empire; it was not impossible for the omnipotent
God to reveal to him that name. The orthodox premise cannot be refuted
by experience nor by recourse to the principle of contradiction. An indirect
proof of this is the fact that Spinoza and his like owed such success as they
had in their fight against orthodoxy to laughter and mockery. By means of
mockery they attempted to laugh orthodoxy out of its position from which
it could not be dislodged by any proofs supplied by Scripture or by reason.
One is tempted to say that mockery does not succeed the refutation of the
orthodox tenets, but is itself the refutation. The genuine refutation of
orthodoxy would require the proof that the world and human life are per¬
fectly intelligible without the assumption of a mysterious God; it would
require at least the success of the philosophic system: man has to show
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 255
himself theoretically and practically as the master of the world and the
master of his life; the merely given world must be replaced by the world
created by man theoretically and practically. Spinoza’s Ethics attempts to
be the system, but it does not succeed; the clear and distinct account of
everything which it presents remains fundamentally hypothetical. As a
consequence, its cognitive status is not different from that of the orthodox
account. Certain it is that Spinoza cannot legitimately deny the possibility
of revelation. But to grant that revelation is possible means to grant that
the philosophic account and the philosophic way of life are not necessarily,
not evidently, the true account and the right way of life: philosophy, the
quest for evident and necessary knowledge, rests itself on an unevident de¬
cision, on an act of the will, just as faith. Hence the antagonism between
Spinoza and Judaism, between unbelief and belief, is ultimately not theo¬
retical, but moral.
For the understanding of that moral antagonism the Jewish designation
of the unbeliever as Epicurean seemed to be helpful, especially since from
every point of view Epicureanism may be said to be the classic form of the
critique of religion and the basic stratum of the tradition of the critique of
religion. Epicureanism is hedonism, and traditional Judaism always sus¬
pects that all theoretical and practical revolts against the Torah are in¬
spired by the desire to throw off the yoke of the stern and exacting duties
so that one can indulge in a life of pleasure. Epicureanism can lead only to
a mercenary morality, whereas traditional Jewish morality is not merce¬
nary: “the reward for [the fulfillment of] the commandment is the com¬
mandment.” Epicureanism is so radically mercenary that it conceives of
its theoretical doctrines as the means for liberating the mind from the
terrors of religious fear, of the fear of death, and of natural necessity.
Characteristically modern unbelief is indeed no longer Epicurean. It is no
longer cautious or retiring, not to say cowardly, but bold and active.
Whereas Epicureanism fights the religious “delusion” because of its terri¬
ble character, modern unbelief fights it because it is a delusion: regardless
of whether religion is terrible or comforting, qua delusion it makes men
oblivious of the real goods, of the enjoyment of the real goods, and thus
seduces them into being cheated of the real, “this-worldly” goods by their
spiritual or temporal rulers who “live” from that delusion. Liberated from
the religious delusion, awakened to sober awareness of his real situation,
taught by bad experiences that he is threatened by a stingy, hostile nature,
man recognizes as his sole salvation and duty not so much “to cultivate his
garden” as in the first place to plant a garden by making himself the master
and owner of nature. But this whole enterprise requires, above all, political
action, revolution, a life-and-death struggle: the Epicurean who wishes to
live securely and retiredly must transform himself into an “idealist” who
has learned to fight and to die for honor and truth. But in proportion as
the systematic effort to liberate man completely from all nonhuman bonds
256 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
seems to succeed, the doubt increases of whether the goal is not fantas¬
tic—whether man has not become smaller and more miserable in propor¬
tion as the systematic civilization progresses.
Eventually the belief that by pushing ever farther back the “natural
limits” man will advance to ever greater freedom, that he can subjugate
nature and prescribe to it his laws, begins to wither away. In this stage the
religious “delusion” is rejected, not because it is terrible, but because it is
comforting: religion is not a tool which man has forged for dark reasons in
order to torment himself, to make life unnecessarily difficult, but a way out
chosen for obvious reasons in order to escape from the terror, the exposed¬
ness, and the hopelessness of life which cannot be eradicated by any prog¬
ress of civilization. A new kind of fortitude which forbids itself every flight
from the horror of life into comforting delusion, which accepts the elo¬
quent descriptions of “the misery of man without God” as an additional
proof of the goodness of its cause, reveals itself eventually as the ultimate
and purest ground for the rebellion against revelation. This new fortitude,
being the willingness to look man’s forsakenness in its face, being the cour¬
age to welcome the most terrible truth, is “probity,” “intellectual probity.”
This final atheism with a good conscience, or with a bad conscience, is dis¬
tinguished from the atheism at which the past shuddered by its conscien¬
tiousness. Compared not only with Epicureanism but with the unbelief of
the age of Spinoza, it reveals itself as a descendant of biblical morality.
This atheism, the heir and the judge of the belief in revelation, of the secu¬
lar struggle between belief and unbelief, and finally of the short-lived but
by no means therefore inconsequential romantic longing for the lost belief,
confronting orthodoxy in complex sophistication formed out of gratitude,
rebellion, longing, and indifference, and in simple probity, is according to
its claim as capable of an original understanding of the human roots of the
belief in God as no earlier, no less complex-simple philosophy ever was.
The last word and the ultimate justification of Spinoza’s critique is the
atheism from intellectual probity which overcomes orthodoxy radically by
understanding it radically, that is, without the polemical bitterness of the
Enlightenment and the equivocal reverence of romanticism. Yet this
claim, however eloquently raised, cannot deceive one about the fact that its
basis is an act of will, of belief, and that being based on belief is fatal to
any philosophy.
The victory of orthodoxy through the self-destruction of rational philos¬
ophy was not an unmitigated blessing, for it was a victory, not of Jewish
orthodoxy, but of any orthodoxy, and Jewish orthodoxy based its claim to
superiority to other religions from the beginning on its superior rationality
(Deut. 4:6). Apart from this, the hierarchy of moralities and wills to
which the final atheism referred could not but be claimed to be intrin¬
sically true, theoretically true: “the will to power” of the strong or of the
weak may be the ground of every other doctrine; it is not the ground of the
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 257
doctrine of the will to power: the will to power was said to be a fact. Other
observations and experiences confirmed the suspicion that it would be
unwise to say farewell to reason. I began therefore to wonder whether the
self-destruction of reason was not the inevitable outcome of modem ra¬
tionalism as distinguished from premodem rationalism, especially Jewish-
medieval rationalism and its classical (Aristotelian and Platonic) founda¬
tion. The present study was based on the premise, sanctioned by powerful
prejudice, that a return to premodern philosophy is impossible. The
change of orientation which found its first expression, not entirely by acci¬
dent, in the article published at the end of this volume 66 compelled me to
engage in a number of studies in the course of which I became ever more
attentive to the manner in which heterodox thinkers of earlier ages wrote
their books. As a consequence of this, I now read the Theologico-political
Treatise differently than I read it when I was young. I understood Spinoza
too literally because I did not read him literally enough.
NOTES
1. Consider Leon Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution, translated by Max
Eastman (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press), I 329-331, III 154-155.
2. Heinrich Heine, “Die romantische Schule,” in Sdmtliche Werke (Elster), V 217.
Cf. the discussion of romanticism in Hegel’s Aesthetik.
3. Consider Jenseits von Gut und Bose, chap. 8.
4. Wilhelm Meisters Wanderjahre, 3. Buch, 11. Kapitel.
5. Jenseits von Gut und Bose, No. 251; cf. Morgenrote, No. 205.
6. Einfuhrung in die Metaphysik (Tubingen: 1953), p. 152. This book consists of
a course of lectures given in 1935, but as stated in the Preface, "Errors have been
removed.” Cf. also the allusion on p. 36 to a recent “cleansing” of the German
universities.
7. Cf. Gerhard Scholem, “Politik der Mystik. Zu Isaac Breuer’s ‘Neuem Kusari,’ ”
Juedische Rundschau, No. 57 (1934).
8. Cf. Yehezkel Kaufmann, The Religion of Israel, translated and abridged by Moshe
Greenberg (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960), pp. 2, 233-234.
9. Maimonides, Mishneh Torah, H. teshubah VI 3.
10. Achad ha-Am in his essay “External Freedom and Internal Servitude.”
11. Cf. Spinoza, Theologicopolitical Treatise, praef. (sect. 7 Bruder).
12. Thtodicee, Discours de la Conformity de la foi avec la raison, sect. 3, and Vergil,
Georgica, IV 86-87. The poet speaks of the battle between two rival queens for
the rule of a single beehive. The philosopher seems to think of the question
whether philosophy or revelation ought to be the queen.
13. Cf. Franz Rosenzweig, Kleinere Schriften (Berlin: Schocken, 1937), pp. 354-398.
14. On the relation between Rosenzweig’s and Heidegger’s thought, see Karl Lowith,
Gesammelte Abhandlungen (Stuttgart: 1960), pp. 68-92.
15. Rosenzweig, op. cit., pp. 380, 387.
16. Eclipse of God (New York: 1952), p. 97; cf. the German original, Gottesfinstemis
258 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
(Ziirich: 1953), pp. 87-88. I did not attempt to bring the translation somewhat
closer to Heidegger’s German statement which, incidentally, is not quite literally
quoted by Buber. Cf. Heidegger, Nietzsche, II 320.
17. Hermann Cohen, Ethik des reinen ’Widens, 4th ed., p. 422: “Der Prophet hat
gut reden: Himmel und Erde mogen vergehen; er denkt sie in seinem Felsen,
den ihm Gott bildet, wohlgegriindet.”
18. Eclipse of God, p. 81; Gottesfinstemis, p. 71. I believe that the translator made
a mistake in rendering “Fiihrung einer Welt” by “Conduct of the world,” and
I changed his translation accordingly, but I do not know whether I am right;
it does not appear from the Preface that Buber has approved the translation.
19. Cf. the reasoning with which Wellhausen justifies his athetesis of Amos 9:13-15:
“Roses and lavender instead of blood and iron.” Skizzen und Vorarbeiten (Berlin:
1893), V 94.
20. Der Satz vom Grund, p. 142; Was heisst Denken? pp. 32 ff.
21. Gottesfinstemis, pp. 143, 159-161; Eclipse of God, pp. 154, 173-175. Cf. Rosen-
zweig, op. cit., pp. 192, 530. Cf. above all the thorough discussion of this theme by
Gershom Scholem, Zur Kabbala und ihrer Symbolik (Zurich: 1960), chaps. 1, 2.
22. Cf. Gottesfinstemis, p. 34 with pp. 96-97 and 117 or Eclipse of God, pp. 39—40
with pp. 106 and 127.
23. Heidegger, Sein und Zeit, sect. 57. Consider C. F. Meyer’s Die Versuchung des
Pescara.
24. Cf. Frohliche Wissenschaft, No. 343.
25. Jenseits, Nos. 45, 224; Gotzen-Dammemng, "Die ‘Vemunft’ in der Philosophic,”
Nos. 1-2.
26. Letter to Overbeck of February 23, 1887. Cf. Jenseits, No. 60; Genealogie der
Moral, I No. 7, III Nos. 23, 28 beginning; Nietzsche, Werke (Schlechta), III 422.
27. Frohliche Wissenschaft, No. 344; Jenseits, No. 227; Genealogie der Moral III
No. 27.
28. Jenseits I; Frohliche Wissenschaft, Nos. 347, 377. Thomas Aquinas S.th. 1 q. 1.
a. 4. and 2 2 q. I. a. 1.
29. Sein und Zeit, pp. 48-49, 190 n. 1, 229-230, 249 n. 1.
30. Kleinere Schriften, pp. 31-32, 111, 281-282, 374, 379, 382, 391, 392.
31. Op. cit., pp. 108-109, 114, 116-117, 119, 155-156.
32. Nietzsche, Also Sprach Zarathustra, “Of Thousand Goals and One.”
33. Cf. also Kant, Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen (Kehrbach), p. 43.
34. Kleinere Schriften, p. 154; Briefe (Berlin: Schocken, 1935), p. 520.
35. Ethics, V prop. 25 and prop. 36 schol.; cf. Tr. theol.-pol. VI sect. 23. Cf. Goethe’s
letter to F. H. Jacobi of May 5, 1786.
36. “Spinoza iiber Staat und Religion, Judentum und Christentum,” in Hermann
Cohens Jiidische Schriften (Bruno Strauss), III 290-372; “Ein ungedruckter
Vortrag Hermann Cohens iiber Spinozas Verhaltnis zum Judentum,” eingeleitet
von Franz Rosenzweig, Festgabe zum zehnjdhrigen Bestehen der Akademie fur die
Wissenschaft des Judentums, 1919-1929, pp. 42-68. Cf. Ernst Simon, “Zu Her¬
mann Cohens Spinoza-Auffassung,” Monatsschrift fur Geschichte und Wissen¬
schaft des Judentums (1935), pp. 181-194.
37. Jiidische Schriften, pp. 293, 320, 325-326, 329-331, 343, 358, 360; Festgabe,
pp. 47-50, 57, 61-64.
38. Jiidische Schriften, pp. 299, 306-309, 329, 360-362.
39. Ibid., pp. 333, 361, 363-364, 368, 371; Festgabe, p. 59.
40. Ibid., pp. 46, 47, 49-50; Jiidische Schriften, p. 344.
41. I bid., pp. 317-321, 323, 337-338.
42. Ibid., p. 367; Festgabe, p. 56. Cf. Tr. theol.-pol. I sect. 35 and 37 with the titles
of Ethics I and II (cf. Cogitata Metaphysica II 12) and V 36 cor.
Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion / 259
43. Tr. XII 19, 24, 37; XIII 23; XIV 6, 22-29, 34-36; XX 22, 40; Tr. pol. VIII
46. Cf. especially Tr. XII 3 where Spinoza takes the side of the Pharisees against
the Sadducees. The contrast of Tr. XFV with Hobbes’s Leviathan, chap. 43, is
most revealing.
44. Tr. V 7-9.
45. Ibid., V 13, 15, 30-31; XVII 95-102; XIX 13-17.
46. Cohen, Jiidische Schriften, III 333.
47. Ibid.
48. Cohen, Kants Begriindung der Ethik, 2d ed., p. 490, speaks of the “gewagte Spiel”
of Kant in his Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der blossen Vemunft, a work
according to Cohen rich in “ambiguities and inner contradictions.”
49. Ethik, pp. 61, 64, 94, 439-458, 468-470, 606. Cf. Kants Begrilndung der Ethik,
2d ed, pp. 356-357.
50. Spinoza, Tr. pol. I 2. Cohen, Ethik, pp. 64, 269, 272, 285-286, 378, 384-386;
Kants Begrilndung der Ethik, pp. 394-406, 454. Cf, however, Hegel, Rechts-
philosophie, sect. 94 ff.
51. Pirke Abot, III 2.
52. Kants Begrilndung der Ethik, pp. 309, 430, 431, 439, 446, 452, 511, 544-545,
554.
53. Festgabe, p. 44 (Kleinere Schriften, p. 355).
54. Jiidische Schriften, II 265-267. Cf. Tr. Ill 25, 33, 34, for example, with Rashi
on Isaiah 19:25, Jeremiah 1:5, and Malachi 1:10-11 and Kimhi on Isaiah 48:17.
55. Festgabe, pp. 64-67; Jiidische Schriften, III 345-351. Cf. Tr. V 47-48.
56. Misreading his authority or Caro, Cohen erroneously asserts that Caro declares
the reading “but to the wise ones” to be the correct reading.
57. Cf. also Manasse ben Israel, Conciliator (Frankfort: 1633), ad Deut. q. 2. (p.
221).
58. In one of the passages (Edut XI 10) Maimonides says that the pious idolators
have a share in the world to come; but how do we know that he does not mean
by a pious idolator an idolator who has forsworn idolatry (cf. Issure Biah XIV 7)
on the ground that idolatry is forbidden to all men by divine revelation? In the
other passage (Teshubah III 5) he merely says that the pious Gentiles have a
share in the world to come; the sequel (III 6 ff, see especially 14) could seem
to show that the pious Gentile is supposed to believe in the revealed character
of the Torah.
59. Jiidische Schriften, III 240.
60. Guide, III 29 end; Aristotle, Metaphysics, I003a33 ff.
61. Cf. M. T. H. Yesodei ha-Torah I 1.
62. Cohen, Die Religion der Vemunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, p. 205.
63. Festgabe, p. 53; Jiidische Schriften, III 365; cf. II 257.
64. Ibid., pp. 335-336; Tr. IV 17 (cf. 9-16) and 21.
65. Jiidische Schriften, III 351; Festgabe 50-54.
66. Comments on Der Begriff des Politischen by Carl Schmitt.
/ Perspectives on
the Good Society
260
Perspectives on the Good Society / 261
the American novel of the time following World War II since the novel
enjoys a particularly high prestige in present-day America. Above all, the
contemporary American novel—especially if contrasted with the contem¬
porary British novel—shows how much Judaism and Christianity are
embattled in present-day America. According to Mr. Scott, this kind of
literature preaches up the radical divorce of the self from contemporary
society or the existence without roots. By confining itself “to the narrow
enclave of the self,” recent American fiction has compelled itself to
produce—apart from very few exceptions—nothing but “pale and blood¬
less ghosts.” Since it does not see human beings in the light of the biblical
faith in creation, it does not see them with humility and charity: the
individual without history and hence authenticity creates beings with¬
out history and hence authenticity. Of this literature it has been claimed
that it corresponds to the “post-Christian” character of our world. Mr.
Scott rejected this claim with contempt. If I understood him correctly, in
his view it is not the non-Christian character of our world, but the non-
Christian or non-Jewish character of the writers concerned, which is re¬
sponsible for their sterility. I cannot comment on the literature in question
since I do not know it. Yet living in this country at this time in constant
contact with young Americans who are compelled to face and to resist that
literature, I cannot help having some familiarity with the moral phenome¬
non of which the contemporary American novel as characterized by Mr.
Scott seems to be an expression if not a cause.
Not a few people who have come to despair of the possibility of a decent
secularist society, without having been induced by their despair to question
secularism as such, escape into the self and into art. The “self” is obviously
a descendant of the soul; that is, it is not the soul. The soul may be respon¬
sible for its being good or bad, but it is not responsible for its being a soul;
of the self, on the other hand, it is not certain whether it is not a self by
virtue of its own effort. The soul is a part of an order which does not origi¬
nate in the soul; of the self it is not certain whether it is a part of an order
which does not originate in the self. Surely the self as understood by the
people in question is sovereign or does not defer to anything higher than
itself; yet it is no longer exhilarated by the sense of its sovereignty, but
rather oppressed by it, not to say in a state of despair. One may say that the
self putting its trust in itself and therefore in man is cursed (Jer. 17:5-8).
It is an unwilling witness to the biblical faith. Mr. Scott was right in reject¬
ing the view that our world is “irredeemably post-Christian” on the ground
that “the Holy Spirit bloweth where it listeth,” but I believe that one
should admit the fact that the unbelief in question is in no sense pagan,
but shows at every point that it is the unbelief of men who or whose par¬
ents were Christians or Jews. They are haunted men. Deferring to nothing
higher than their selves, they lack guidance. They lack thought and disci¬
pline. Instead they have what they call sincerity. Whether sincerity as they
262 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
understand it is necessary must be left open until one knows whether sin¬
cerity is inseparable from shamelessness; sincerity is surely not sufficient; it
fulfills itself completely in shrill and ugly screams, and such screams are not
works of art. “Life is a tale told by an idiot” is a part of a work of art, for
life is such a tale only for him who has violated the law of life, the law to
which life is subject. It is true that the message of the writers in question is
not that of Macbeth. They scream that life is gutter. But one cannot sense
that life is gutter if one has not sensed purity in the first place, and of this
which is by nature sensed first, they say nothing, they convey nothing. The
self which is not deferential is an absurdity. Their screams are accusations
hurled against “society”; they are not appeals to human beings uttered in a
spirit of fraternal correction; these accusers believe themselves to be be¬
yond the reach of accusation; their selves constitute themselves by the
accusation; the self as they understand it is nothing but the accusation or
the scream. Every accusation presupposes a law; accusations of the kind
voiced by them would require a holy law; but of this they appear to be
wholly unconscious. Their screams remind one of the utterances of the
damned in hell; they themselves belong to hell. But hell is for them not
society as such, but “life in the United States in 1963.” Their despair is due
to their having believed in the first place that life in the United States in
1963 is heaven or could be heaven or ought to be heaven. They condemn
contemporary American society; their selves constitute themselves by this
condemnation; they are nothing but this condemnation or rejection—a
condemnation not based on any law; they belong to this society as com¬
pletely as their twin, the organization man; their only difference from the
latter is, or seems to be, that they are miserable and obsessed.
The speaker at the dinner session, Mr. Dore Schary (Anti-Defamation
League of B’nai B’rith), agreed with Mr. Scott in implicitly suggesting that
contemporary America is fundamentally healthy, that is, possesses within
itself the remedies for the ills from which it suffers, and that this funda¬
mental health is connected with its being not purely secularist and its not
meaning to be it. The society attacked by the literary avant-gardists is held
together, or is what it is, by the dedication to freedom in the sense that the
freedom and dignity of anyone is supposed to require the freedom and
dignity of everyone. According to Mr. Schary, democracy is not primarily
the rule of the majority, but recognition of the dignity of the individual,
that is, of every individual in his individuality. Only a society in which
everyone can be what he is or can develop his unique potentialities is truly
free and truly great or excellent. What is true of the individual is true also
of the groups of which society consists and in particular of the religious
groups; the freedom and excellence of this country require, above all, that
its citizenry belong to a variety of faiths. Why this is so appears from a
consideration of the ills from which American society suffers. Those ills can
be reduced to one head: the tendency toward homogeneity or conformism,
Perspectives on the Good Society / 263
from prejudice which it achieves; but, as was indicated, the same power
also endangers diversity or fosters homogeneity. As for good will, democ¬
racy was originally said to be the form of government the principle of
which is virtue. But it is obviously impossible to restrict the suffrage to
virtuous men, men of good will, conscientious men, responsible men, or
whichever expression one prefers. While in a democracy the government is
made responsible to the governed in the highest degree possible—ideally
the government will not have any secrets from the governed—the governed
cannot be held responsible in a comparable manner: the place par excel¬
lence of sacred secrecy or privacy is not the home, which may be entered
with a search warrant, but the voting booth. In the voting booth the prej¬
udices can assert themselves without any hindrance whatever. Voting is
meant to determine the character of the legal majority. The legal majority
is not simply the majority, but it is not irrelevant to the legal majority how
the simple majority feels. There may be a stable or permanent majority; in
the United States the stable majority is “white Protestant.” As a conse¬
quence there is a social hierarchy at the bottom of which are the Negroes
(or colored people in general), and barely above them are the Jews. There
is then a prejudice which is both constitutional and unconstitutional
against Negroes and Jews. If I understood Mr. Schary correctly, the con¬
formism against which he directed his attack has the unavowed intention
either to transform all Americans into white Protestants or else to deny
those Americans who are not white Protestants full equality of opportu¬
nity. Yet would not one have to say that this pressure toward conformism
is not the same as that which is exerted by the communications and cos¬
metics industries?
Recognition of religious diversity, as Mr. Schary understood it, is not
merely toleration of religions other than one’s own but respect for them.
The question arises as to how far that respect can be extended. “We who
are religiously oriented state that there is God; clearer identification than
that is denied us.” Who are the “we”? If the “we” are Jews or Christians,
Mr. Schary admits too little; if they are religious human beings as such, he
admits too much. The singular “God” would seem to exclude the possibil¬
ity of respect for Greek polytheism and still more of the polytheism of the
Egyptians who had “a bizarre pantheon of their own . . . they invented
monsters to worship.” Can one respect a religion which worships monsters
or, to use the biblical expression, abominations? Mr. Schary concluded the
paragraph from which these quotations are taken with the remark that “all
men of decency, self-respect and good will are joined in a common
brotherhood.” I take it that he does not deny that men who are not “reli¬
giously oriented” may be “men of decency, self-respect and good will” and
that men who lack decency, self-respect, and good will and therefore refuse
to join the common brotherhood do not for this reason cease to be our
Perspectives on the Good Society / 265
Christians can make a friendly collatio to the secular state cannot be the
belief in the God of the philosophers, but only the belief in the God of
Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob—the God who revealed the Ten Command¬
ments or at any rate such commandments as are valid under all circum¬
stances regardless of the circumstances. That common ground was indeed
not articulated in the meeting devoted to the common ground. The reason
was not that that ground is trivial—in an age in which both Judaism and
Christianity have been affected by existentialist ethics, it is surely not
trivial—but because, as is shown by the whole history of Christian-Jewish
relations, recognition of that common ground is not in any way sufficient
for mutual recognition of the two faiths.
What can such recognition mean? This much: that Church and Syna¬
gogue recognize each the noble features of its antagonist. Such recognition
was possible even during the Christian Middle Ages: while the Synagogue
was presented as lowering its head in shame, its features were presented as
noble. However far the mutual recognition may go in our age, it cannot
but be accompanied by the certainty on the part of each of the two antag¬
onists that in the end the other will lower its head. Recognition of the
other must remain subordinate to recognition of the truth. Even the pagan
philosophers Plato and Aristotle remained friends, although each held the
truth to be his greatest friend, or rather because each held the truth to be
his greatest friend. The Jew may recognize that the Christian error is a
blessing, a divine blessing, and the Christian may recognize that the Jewish
error is a blessing, a divine blessing. Beyond this they cannot go without
ceasing to be Jew or Christian.
To say the least, it was always easier for Christians to recognize the di¬
vine origin of Judaism than for Jews to recognize the divine origin of
Christianity. On the other hand, it was easier for Jews to recognize that
Christians may have a “share in the world to come” than it was for Chris¬
tians to recognize that Jews may be “saved.” This is due to the Jewish
union of the “carnal” and the “spiritual,” of the “secular” and the
“eternal,” of the “tribal” and the “universal”: the Torah which contains
the promise of the eventual redemption of all children of Adam (cf.
Maimonides, Mishneh Torah H. Melakhim XI-XII) was given to, or
accepted by, Israel alone. As a consequence, it was easier for Jews to admit
the divine mission of Christianity (cf. Yehuda Halevi, Cuzari IV 23) than
it was for Christians to admit the abiding divine mission of Judaism. It is
therefore not surprising that, as Mr. Rylaarsdam pointed out, the first
genuine meeting of Jews and Christians should have been initiated by a
Jew, Franz Rosenzweig, and that a comparable Christian response to this
Jewish call should not yet have been forthcoming. Such a response, includ¬
ing above all the recognition of the abiding mission of Judaism, is urgently
demanded in the opinion of Mr. Rylaarsdam because of what happened to
the Jewish people in our lifetime: the butchery of six million Jews by
Perspectives on the Good Society / 267
learn from Christianity? Are Jews still in greater danger to abandon Juda¬
ism in favor of Christianity than Christians are to abandon Christianity in
favor of Judaism? Is there still a greater worldly premium on being a Chris¬
tian than on being a Jew? Or is it obvious to everyone what the Jews have
learned from Christianity since it is obvious what the Jews have learned
from modernity and it is obvious that modernity is secularized Christian¬
ity? But is modernity in fact secularized Christianity? Mr. Cohen seemed
to doubt this. However this may be, he surely referred to the Jew’s “pain of
his historical encounter with Christendom.”
Which Jew can indeed forget that pain? But confronted by the fact that
the most noble Christians of our age have shown sincere repentance and
sincerely offer us peace, we Jews must not regard Christendom as if it were
Amalek; we must even cease to regard it as Edom. Above all, noblesse
oblige. Mr. Cohen rightly rejected the common Christian notion of Jewish
“pharisaism”: no Jew who ever took the Torah seriously could be self-
righteous, or believe that he could redeem himself from sin by the fulfill¬
ment of the Law, or underestimate the power of sin over him. The true
“Pharisee” in the Christian sense is not the Pharisee proper, but Aristotle’s
perfect gentleman who is not ashamed of anything or does not regret or
repent anything he has done because he always does what is right or
proper. Mr. Cohen went beyond this. He demanded that the Christian
view of the power and the depth of sin be mitigated in the light of “a real¬
istic humanism,” and he asserted that that humanism is found in the Jew¬
ish Bible. Isaiah’s words in 6:5-7 and David’s prayer in Psalm 51:12 sound
“realistic” enough; they are, however, hardly “humanistic.” Similar consid¬
erations apply to Mr. Cohen’s remark about Pauline theology as “a
theology for disappointment.” I had thought that the days of historicist
“debunking” had gone. Yet I cannot but agree with his concluding sen¬
tence: “What more has Israel to offer the world than eternal patience?”
This sentence calls indeed for a long commentary. One sentence must here
suffice: what is called here “eternal patience” is that fortitude in suffering,
now despised as “ghetto mentality” by shallow people who have surren¬
dered wholeheartedly to the modern world or who lack the intelligence to
consider that a secession from this world might again become necessary for
Jews and even for Christians.
If I understood him correctly, Mr. John Wild (Professor of Phi¬
losophy, Northwestern University) introduced the meeting devoted to
“Faith and Action” with the observation that while Judaism and Christian¬
ity agree in believing that faith must issue in action, Christianity has some¬
times succumbed to the Greek, intellectualist understanding of faith and
accordingly severed or almost severed the connection between faith and
action. M. Paul Ricoeur (Professor of Philosophy, Sorbonne), presenting “a
Christian view” of faith and action, started from the facts that the opposi¬
tion between the contemplative life and the active life stems from Greek
Perspectives on the Good Society / 269
philosophy and is wholly alien to Judaism and that in this respect Chris¬
tianity is simply the heir to Judaism. One may agree with M. Ricoeur while
admitting that there is some evidence supporting the view that Greek
philosophy did not as such assert that opposition. It suffices to mention the
name of the citizen-philosopher Socrates. But perhaps one will be com¬
pelled eventually to say that his being a citizen culminated in his tran¬
scending the city, not only the city of Athens but even the best city, in
speech, as well as that the only comprehensive and effective reply to the
claim of contemplation to supremacy is supplied by the Bible. Be this as it
may, M. Ricoeur was chiefly concerned with the question as to whether the
doctrines distinguishing Christianity from Judaism do not lead again to the
depreciation of action. His answer was in the negative. He conveyed to me
the impression that the doctrine of original sin, for instance, is “the specu¬
lative expression” alien to Judaism of an experience which is not alien to
Judaism. Differently stated, the Christian doctrine of justification by faith
was perhaps “present from the beginning in the Bible”; the Jewish saying
that everything is in the hands of God except fear of God would contradict
the doctrine of justification by faith only if it were meant, as it surely is not
meant, to arouse or confirm “any desire to draw glory” over against God
from one’s fearing God. M. Ricoeur asserted that Christianity sometimes
succumbed to “Hellenistic” ways of understanding the relation of faith and
action by divorcing faith from action, especially from social action, or by
denying that there is any connection between the salvation of the individ¬
ual and “historical redemption,” or by being unconcerned with the evil
embodied in “impersonal institutions” (the state, property, and culture) as
distinguished from sin proper; yet in his view this is simply a “reactionary
conception,” incompatible with original Christianity. At any rate, there is
no serious difference in this respect between Christianity and Judaism: “it
is always its Jewish memory that guards (Christianity) against its own
deviations.”
Mr. Nahum N. Glatzer (Professor of Jewish History, Brandeis Univer¬
sity) presented “a Jewish view of faith and action.” He gave a comprehen¬
sive survey of Jewish thought on this subject from the days of the Bible
down to the present. According to what one may call the classic Jewish
view, “knowledge of God,” study, faith, learning, or wisdom both presup¬
poses and issues in righteous action or active piety or “fear of heaven,” but
in such a way that what counts is action. The basis of this view appeared to
be the talmudic theologoumenon that by his right or pious action man
becomes “a participant with God in the work of creation”: whereas regard¬
ing revelation and redemption, man is merely a recipient; regarding cre¬
ation, or rather regarding the continuity of creation, “man is an active
partner” of God. The Jewish view of faith and action was obscured in
different ways and for different reasons in the Middle Ages on the one
hand and in modern times on the other. Owing to their subjugation many
270 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
medieval Jews came to believe that “the world matters little; the rectifica¬
tion of its ills and, finally, its redemption, would come in God’s good
time.” As a consequence of the emancipation of the Jews in the nineteenth
century, an important part of Jewish opinion came to identify social and
other progress with the process of redemption; that which transcends prog¬
ress and action, that with which faith is concerned, tended to be forgotten.
Modern secularism believed that it would put an end to the Jewish-
Christian antagonism by depriving Judaism and Christianity of their
raisons d’etre; its manifest failure which affects equally Jews, Christians,
and nonbelievers calls for a community of seeking and acting of both Jews
and Christians—a community which has originally been rendered possible
by secularism. The failure of secularism shows itself, for instance, in the
ever increasing cleavage between science and humanism. In Mr. Glatzer’s
view that gulf cannot be bridged by a “synthesis” of science and hu¬
manism because science is “neutralist” and humanism is “traditionalist”:
the required “redefinition of the image of man” is beyond the com¬
petence of either or both, not in spite but because of the fact that it
must be a redefinition of man as created in the image of God. “The
hybris of scientism” cannot be overcome with the help of a humanism
which is inspired by the belief in man as a creator. Over against sci¬
entism and humanism Judaism and Christianity are at one.
The greatest divisive power in the past was revealed religion. Even today,
as we have been led to see by reflecting on one of the papers read at the
Colloquium, religious diversity is the obstacle par excellence to conformism
in this country. The differences at any rate between Judaism and Christian¬
ity do not preclude the availability of a common ground. What divides the
human race today in the most effective manner is, however, the antago¬
nism between the liberal West and the Communist East. Even in this case
there exists, as Mr. Gibson Winter (Divinity School, University of Chi-
cago) pointed out in his paper on “National Identity and National Pur¬
pose,” a “common ground”: “their common ground is the limit set upon
their opposition by [their] nuclear power.” Thermonuclear war being
manifestly an act of madness, the common ground must become the basis
of a dialogue—a dialogue to be conducted, not in ideological terms, but
with a view to the duties of this country faced by the world-wide “struggle
against hunger and the aspiration for human dignity”; this country must
cease to “endorse a status quo position in a hungry world.” The dialogue
required is then in the first place a dialogue, not with Soviet Russia, but
with the “have-nots” within the U.S.A. and without. As for the dialogue
with the U.S.S.R., it requires that the “purpose and interest” of “our ene¬
mies” be respected and, above all, that the “apocalyptic framework” for
the dialogue be recognized: in the spirit of Deuteronomy 30:19, we must
choose life—“a future in justice and community”—in the certainty that
the alternative choice leads to thermonuclear annihilation as God’s judg-
Perspectives on the Good Society / 271
ment. What will enable us to continue the dialogue with the U.S.S.R. in
spite of all its hazards is faith, not, of course, in the good will of the Soviet
rulers, but in God. It goes without saying that no such faith can be ex¬
pected from the Soviet rulers: unilateral disarmament is out of the ques¬
tion. Faith equally forbids preventive war. On the other hand one cannot
simply assert that this country must not under any circumstances initiate
the use of nuclear weapons. “The most difficult problem in the use of
nuclear power,” however, concerns retaliation. “Retaliation after a destruc¬
tive attack becomes simply vengeance” and seems therefore to be incom¬
patible with Christian ethics: “to choose the life of others over our own—
this is the message of the Cross.” Yet “the possibility of retaliation is the
power which restrains aggression.”
Two comments on this proposal seem to be appropriate. The possibility
of retaliation would lose much of its restraining power if the enemy knew
that a second strike force which survived his successful attack would never
be used against him; hence a decision allegedly demanded by faith must
remain the most closely guarded secret; in other words, the tongue must
pronounce the opposite of what the heart thinks. Second, by saving the
lives of the Soviet people in the contingency under consideration, one
would surrender all the have-not nations to Soviet rule and thus deprive
them for all the foreseeable future of the possibility to be nonatheistic na¬
tions or, more generally stated, to have a future of their own, neither Rus¬
sian nor American; in other words, Mr. Winter’s proposal is based on a
tacit claim to know what God alone can know. Considerations like these
may explain the fact deplored by him that “the institutional weight of our
religious traditions [viz. Christian and Jewish] falls ... on the conserva¬
tive side in the struggle which separates the world.” At any rate there seems
to be a tension between his plea for universal prosperity and freedom and
his remark that “the grave danger for Judaism at this moment is the pros¬
perity which distracts her from [her] vocation. . . . External oppression
can fortify the [chosen] people.”
The Jewish partner of Mr. Winter, Mr. Nathan Glazer (Housing and
Financing Agency, Washington, D.C.), spoke on “The Shape of the Good
Society.” He did not speak from a distinctly Jewish point of view. He dealt
with the most successful revolution of our age, “the organizational revolu¬
tion, or the scientific revolution,” and its implications. Through this revo¬
lution the gap between “the intellectuals,” “the radical and liberal critics,”
on the one hand and the organizations “representing the status quo” has
been closed or at least very much narrowed. The reason was that the intel¬
lectuals proved to possess “new techniques for making organizations more
efficient.” One might say that in proportion as the scientists drew all con¬
clusions from their basic premise, which is the assertion that science is lim¬
ited to “factual” assertions as distinguished from “value” assertions, they
lost the right to be radical critics of institutions and became willing serv-
272 / LIBERALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN
"What Is Liberal Education?” was an address delivered at the tenth annual graduation
exercises of the Basic Program of Liberal Education for Adults, University College,
the University of Chicago, on June 6, 1959; it was printed by the University of Chicago
Press and reprinted in C. Scott Fletcher, ed., Education for Social Responsibility (New
York: Norton, 1961), pp. 43-51.
“Liberal Education and Responsibility” is reprinted from C. Scott Fletcher, ed., Edu¬
cation: The Challenge Ahead (New York: Norton, 1962), pp. 49-70. Copyright 1962
by the American Foundation for Continuing Education.
"The Liberalism of Classical Political Philosophy” is reprinted from Review of Meta¬
physics, XII, No. 3 (March 1959), 390-439.
“How To Begin To Study The Guide of the Perplexed” is reprinted from the intro¬
ductory essay to Moses Maimonides, The Guide of the Perplexed (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1963), pp. xi-lvr.
“Marsilius of Padua” is reprinted from Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, eds., History
of Political Philosophy (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1963), pp. 227-246.
“An Epilogue” is reprinted from Herbert J. Storing, ed., Essays on the Scientific Study
of Politics (New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1962), pp. 305-327. Copyright
© 1962 by Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc. Reprinted by permission of Holt, Rine¬
hart and Winston, Inc.
“Preface to Spinoza’s Critique of Religion” is reprinted from Leo Strauss, Spinoza's
Critique of Religion (New York: Schocken Books, 1965). Copyright 1965 by Schocken
Books, Inc.
“Perspectives on the Good Society” is reprinted from Criterion: A Publication of the
Divinity School of the University of Chicago, II, No. 3 (Summer 1963), 2-9.
273
Index of Names
275
276 / INDEX OF NAMES
Machiavelli, 44, 201, 208, 217, 223, 239, Scholem, Gerhard, 257, 258, 272
242, 246-247 Simon, Ernst, 258
Maimonides, 140-184, 201, 238-239, Sophocles, 43
248-250, 257, 259, 266 Spinoza, 137, 224-259
Manasse ben Israel, 259
Marsilius of Padua, 185-202 Tacitus, 241
Marx, Karl, 24, 48, 219, 225 Thomas Aquinas, 185, 199, 213, 258
Mendelssohn, Moses, 237 Trotsky, Leon, 257
Meyer, C.F., 258 Thucydides, 33, 81-82, 85, 136, 217
Mill, J. St., 17-18, 20
Montesquieu, Charles de Secondat, Baron Virgil, 257
de, 208
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 24, 226-227, 234, Wellhausen, Julius, 231, 235, 258
236-237, 251, 258
Xenophanes, 50, 138
Onqelos the Stranger, 149-150, 157, 169 Xenophon, 71, 138
PHILOSOPHY/POLITICAL SCIENCE
evered and reviled, Leo Strauss has left a rich legacy of work that
continues to spark discussion and controversy. This volume of essays
ranges over critical themes that define Strauss’s thought: the tension between
reason and revelation in the Western tradition, the philosophical roots of
liberal democracy, and especially the conflicting yet complementary relation¬
ship between ancient and modern liberalism. For those seeking to become
acquainted with this provocative thinker, one need look no further.
“Takes its place beside What Is Political Philosophy? as the most appropriate intro¬
duction to Strauss’s thought.” —Hiram Caton, National Review
Strauss s discussion of liberal education in the first two chapters speaks powerfully
to our renewed debate.... And the last chapter, like the rest of the book, is studded
with such gems as his lucid and unforgettable analysis of the distinction between
‘the self’ and the soul.” —Allan Bloom
“In a time when the very meaning of ‘liberal education’ has become a matter of
doubt and controversy, Strauss’s theoretical regrounding of liberalism in classical
political philosophy should be of the greatest significance for thoughtful liberals
everywhere.” —Thomas L. Pangle, University of Toronto