Woodward, Lyotard On Film
Woodward, Lyotard On Film
Woodward, Lyotard On Film
Abstract:
Jean-François Lyotard’s work remains a largely untapped resource for
film-philosophy. This article surveys four fundamental concepts which indicate
the fecundity of this work for current studies and debates. While Lyotard was
generally associated with the “theory” of the 1980s which privileged language,
signs, and cultural representations, much of his work in fact resonates more
strongly with the new materialisms and realisms currently taking centre stage.
The concepts examined here indicate the relevance of Lyotard’s work in four
related contemporary contexts: the renewed interest in the dispositif, new
materialism, the affective turn, and speculative realism. The concept of the
dispositif (or apparatus) is being rehabilitated in the contemporary context because
it shows a way beyond the limiting notion of mise en scène which has dominated
approaches to film, and Lyotard’s prevalent use of this concept feeds into this
renewal. While matter is not an explicit theme in Lyotard’s writings on film, it is
nevertheless one at the heart of his aesthetics, and it may be extended for
application to film. Affect was an important theme for Lyotard in many contexts,
including his approaches to film, where it appears to subvert film’s “seductive”
(ideological) effects. Finally, the Real emerges as a central concept in Lyotard’s last
essay on cinema, where, perhaps surprisingly, it intimates something close to
a speculative realist aesthetics. Each of the fundamental concepts of Lyotard’s
film-philosophy are introduced in the context of the current fields and debates to
which they are relevant, and are discussed with filmic examples, including Michael
Snow’s La Région centrale (1971), Roberto Rossellini’s Stromboli (Stromboli, terra di
Dio, 1950), Francis Ford Coppola’s Apocalypse Now (1979), and neo-realist cinema.
303
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
304
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
Dispositif
The notion of the dispositif was introduced into film theory in the early
1970s with theorists such as Christian Metz and Jean-Louis Baudry. It is a
concept also prevalent in poststructuralist philosophy, most notably the
thought of Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, and Lyotard. The idea has
already had a significant reception in Anglophone film theory, translated
by the term “apparatus” (see Rosen, 1986), but it is gaining renewed
attention among many film theorists today. (This new reception tends to
be more comfortable with the French term, and leaves it untranslated.)
The rediscovery and current relevance of the notion of dispositif for film
theory has been charted by, among others, Adrian Martin (2011) and
André Parente and Victa de Carvalho (2008).
Both articles seek to give an account of the current relevance of the
notion of the dispositif by contrasting it with a dominant way in which
cinema has been understood in the past. Martin names this the mise en
scène, and, citing the critical work of Raymond Bellour, explains its
limitations as follows:
With the assumption of the centrality of the scene comes a great baggage,
which is precisely the baggage of classicism in the arts: continuity,
verisimilitude, the ensemble effect in acting performance, narrative
articulation, the necessity for smoothness and fluidity, centring, legibility
and formal balance. (2011)
305
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
Parente and de Carvalho point to what they call simply “Cinema Form,”
which is characteristic of narrative cinema with its concern to create a
“reality effect” and its employment of an “aesthetics of transparency.”
Echoing Martin’s analysis, this aesthetic is that of the mise en scène, where
the focus is on the scene itself, the illusion of reality created in the
cinematic frame.
The turn from mise en scène to dispositif is a turn from a focus on the
scene itself to a focus on the mise en, the “putting into” scene, the whole
apparatus of cinema which makes cinematic effects possible (Martin,
2011). Martin defines the dispositif quite generally as “a fixed and
systematic set-up or arrangement of elements,” then hastens to clarify that
306
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
307
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
are “badly formed,” which do not contribute to the unity and sense of the
scenes or of the whole film.
These conventions of representation, generally so familiar that they
remain unconscious and unnoticed, are exploded by the unconventional
cinematic dispositif employed in Snow’s La Région centrale. This film
radically flouts two of the three main elements of the cinematic dispositif
that Parente and de Carvalho identify: the cinematic technology, and the
narrative form. Working with a technician, Snow developed a new
technology for the capture of images, consisting of a mechanised support
able to move the camera in all possible directions. The robotic movements
could be preprogramed, obviating the need for direct human intervention
during the filming. The film itself is the result of setting this mechanism
in motion in a remote, mountainous Canadian landscape. Its 180 minutes
of twisting and turning perspectives on the landscape owes little or
nothing to narrative-representative cinema.
Lyotard (1977/2017c, pp. 52–53) lists some of the ways in which the
conventions of cinema are overturned with this exceptional cinematic
dispositif:
Snow’s work is just one example of how experimental cinema can create
cinematic dispositifs other than the dominant narrative-representational
one (in his various writings, Lyotard also refers to the works of
experimental filmmakers such as Hans Richter, Viking Eggeling,
Francis Thompson, Gianfranco Baruchello, Tony Conrad, and Werner
Nekes).
According to Parente and de Carvalho, while experimental cinema,
the cinema of attraction, and expanded cinema are nothing new, the
displacements of the classical cinematic dispositif they enact are becoming
increasingly centralised because of the many mutations of the cinematic
308
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
Matter
In his already cited article, Martin (2011) links the currency of the
dispositif with the question of matter, writing that “it is precisely
materiality – the ways in which we define it, and deploy it, in relation
to cinema – which is at stake, and in flux, today.” This question of
materiality may be inscribed in a wider network of contemporary
questions and concerns which sometimes goes under the name “new
materialism” (see, for example, Bennet, 2010; Coole & Frost, 2010;
Dolphijn & Van der Tuin, 2012; Hickey-Moody & Page, 2015). Broadly
speaking, new materialism is distinguished by the concern to accord a
degree of agency to matter, objects, or things, an agency which has
traditionally been reserved for human beings. New materialism positions
itself as a corrective to the culturalism or social constructivism which
dominated the humanities in the latter half of the twentieth century; it
seeks to reconsider the importance of the material qualities of the body,
the natural world, and things in general beyond their reduction to human-
imposed systems of signification, narrative, and meaning. It sees human
beings alongside and interacting with things within complex networks.
The notion of “agential matter” reconceives agency as a dynamism
inherent in matter which makes a thing something that other things,
including but not exclusively human beings, must contend with (Poe,
2011, p. 157).
New materialism developed initially as a metaphysical and political
concern, and Andrew Poe could write in 2011 that “it is unclear yet and
how neo-materialists regard the question of whether there remains an
aesthetic dimension to ‘things’” (p. 161). This question has since been
further explored, and has been taken up by some in relation to film
(see, for example, the 2012 collection by Estelle Barrett and Barbara Bolt,
which is explicitly framed as an attempt to meet this challenge in the arts,
and includes a section on film). As the remarks of both Martin and Poe
309
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
quoted here suggest, there is not yet any consensus around how a
rethinking of the materiality of film can and should be thought, and
theorists contributing to this general trajectory are in fact moving in a
number of directions. It is in this context that we may consider the
pertinence of the theme of matter in Lyotard’s film-philosophy as one
such possible direction.
“Matter” is not a term made central in any of Lyotard’s writings on film,
but it is central to much of his wider writings in aesthetics. There are,
I would suggest, a number of ways matter may be seen as thoroughly
implicated in Lyotard’s reflections on film. For a start, his first and so-far
most influential essay on film, “Acinema,” may be understood in the
context of his philosophical approach at the time, sometimes described as
“libidinal materialism.” This is a phrase which names a development in
French philosophy in the early 1970s which also includes Deleuze and
Félix Guattari’s Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (1972/1983),
by which Lyotard’s book Libidinal Economy (1974/1993) was deeply
influenced. (This point of contact is doubly notable, since the influence of
Deleuze’s work has, of course, been instrumental in the development of
both film-philosophy and new materialism.)
Lyotard’s “libidinal materialism” might be seen as a certain take on the
web of agential things, combining human beings and things in a network
of relations vitalised by the dynamic force of libido. Libidinal materialism
is a general ontology, according to which all things are produced and
transformed in what Lyotard calls the “libidinal band.” In an apparent
anticipation of the lists of random, material, nonhuman things fetishised
by new materialists and object-oriented ontologists, Lyotard (1974/1993)
writes that the libidinal band “is made from the most heterogenous
textures, bone, epithelium, sheets to write on, charged atmospheres,
swords, glass cases, peoples, grasses, canvases to paint” (p. 2). The
libidinal band is a system in which dispositifs are arrangements of material
elements invested with libidinal energy (desire) which function according
to their own autonomy, working on bodies to affect the way desire flows in
and through those bodies, changing how the bodies themselves are
organised, and how desire is channelled in them. Humans themselves are
viewed from a nonhuman perspective as “economic” systems of desire, in
such a way that conscious agency can be accounted for (in terms of
Freudian secondary psychical processes), but not given primacy, and
such that they may be seen as profoundly connected with the things in
their environment, open to transformation in relation to the flows and
dispositifs they are “plugged into.” In the libidinal band humans and
nonhuman things are constituted together, in larger economies of
libidinal flow and organisation. It is in this way that Lyotard can point
310
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
311
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
312
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
the effects these can create. Yet ultimately, for Lyotard, matter concerns a
pure sensuous presence which can only be felt, not constructed as a
theory to be used for identification in advance. We can only properly
speak of “this” matter in this film, this scene, this shot. Lyotard’s
emphasis on matter as an aesthetic category leads, as he himself
emphasised, to the abandonment of aesthetics as a theory – that is, as
a stable system of concepts which allows us to recognise things and set
them up in a discourse of knowledge – and a materialist aesthetic of film
would compel us in the same direction. Matter would only ever be a
function of affect, something to be felt.
Affect
Affect is another area around which a recent focus of interest in film
theory (for example, Brinkema, 2014; Rutherford, 2003) can be seen
within the wider context of critical cultural theory, where, since the mid-
1990s, there has been a so-called “affective turn” (for example, Clough &
Halley, 2007; Gregg & Seigworth, 2010). It may be thought of more or less
broadly: very broadly, the turn would include a recent interest in emotion
and feeling generally speaking. Yet more narrowly, affect refers to pre-
personal, pre-subjective, unconscious bodily feelings, in distinction to the
recognisable and representable emotions experienced by a conscious
subject (this distinction was influentially explained in Massumi, 1995).
Two main currents feed into the affective turn – the theory of psychobiol-
ogist Silvan Tompkins, and that of Gilles Deleuze. With the combined
influence of the latter’s Cinema books and wider writings on affect, it is no
surprise that we see Lyotard’s Vincennes colleague once again as a pivotal
figure. A host of questions and ways of answering them are thrown up by
this turn, but again we see a move away from the linguistic, semiotic, and
representational tendencies of earlier theories, which focused on the
rational structures intelligible beneath the aesthetic surface of the film,
towards an interest in how cinematic sounds and images impact on and
affect the bodies of spectators, transforming their somatic states and
feelings.
While Deleuze’s theory of affect has a clearly Spinozan pedigree,
Lyotard’s is primarily Freudian (though there is an admixture of Friedrich
Nietzsche in both). Again affect is an issue which traverses Lyotard’s
various periods and approaches, and it could be taken up in at least two
distinct ways in relation to different concerns with Sigmund Freud. In the
period of Libidinal Economy and “Acinema,” affect appears as a part of the
libidinal economy, and often called by the name “intensity” (inspired by
Georges Bataille and Pierre Klossowski). Affect is the intense, disruptive
effect of libidinal energy when it reaches excessively high or low states in a
313
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
314
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
There is a panic on the scene. All the little stories concerning the principal
and secondary characters sketched previously are wiped out or blurred,
rendered ungraspable in an instant. The scene empties itself of meaning.
The eloquence, and the implicit prescriptions which are associated with it,
sink in the overflow of information. […] There is nothing to do, nor to plan,
nor to remember, nor to sense, there is nothing on the horizon. One is
stupid. The panic is that no narrative can take charge of the chaos of the
given and propose an obligation for the addressee. This addressee is not
seduced. (p. 59)
315
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
The Real
“The real” has been placed firmly on the agenda for film theory with the
emergence of second wave Lacanianism in the late 1980s. A pivotal figure
here is of course Slavoj Žižek, and other notables include Joan Copjec
and Todd McGowan. In contrast to the first wave (represented by
influential figures such as Christian Metz and Laura Mulvey), which
viewed film on the model of the mirror phase and gave priority
to the imaginary register, second-wave Lacanianism pointed to the
misunderstanding of the gaze by these earlier theorists and sought to
rehabilitate Jacques Lacan’s relevance to film through a refocusing of
316
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
attention on the register of the real (see McGowan, 2008; McGowan &
Kunkle, 2004). For Lacan, the real does not designate empirical reality as
constructed and perceived by an adult mind, but rather the residues of
our first, infant perceptions of the world which persist in the unconscious
and at times insist in our psychic life, disrupting the sense we make of the
world. For Lacanian theorists, films are interpreted as analogues for the
drama of psychic economy, in which elements of the real intrude into and
disrupt the fantasy which structures the narrative.
The real is a concept which appears in its own way in Lyotard’s
film-philosophy, emerging in his last essay on the topic, “The Idea of
a Sovereign Film” (2000/2017b). Here he is concerned to locate the
artistic event inside, or immanent to, representational narrative through a
discussion of “realist” film. He defines this as follows:
I will call realist any art (literary, pictorial or filmic) which represents
perceptual reality (visual, sonorous, etc.) and the human voices which
belong to this reality. And also which narrates the movement of reality,
which renders its succession in a narrative: a beginning, an event that is a
kind of conflict, a crisis, and the outcome that constitutes the conclusion of
the narrative. (p. 63)
317
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
The breath deregulates itself, the breath which regularly animates the
narrative. A tracking shot forwards or backwards, very slow or very quick, a
zoom, a panorama, a freeze frame, a fade, a defocusing, an ellipsis in the
linking of shots, and many other procedures can also produce this
breathlessness. (p. 65)
318
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
reality allows “a real” to surface in its familiar components, one that seems
to emerge from reality itself, and not from a reality which is only psychical.
It is not “my” unconscious (the filmmaker’s or the viewer’s) that manifests
itself then, but the unconscious of reality. (p. 68)
319
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
the paradox of art […] is that it turns towards a thing which does not turn
towards the mind, that it wants a thing, or has it in for a thing which wants
nothing of it. (p. 142)
The problem that poses itself then for aesthetics is, “how can the mind
situate itself, get in touch with something that withdraws from every
relationship?” (Lyotard, 1988/1991, p. 142). These formulations, while
brief and suggestive, seem to anticipate the attempts to think the real
beyond the conditioning imposed by the mind with which speculative
realism is concerned. Some of Durafour’s interpretations of Lyotard’s
aesthetics head strongly in this direction. For example, he writes, “the
question of painting: how does colour ‘see itself’? The question of music:
how does sound ‘hear itself’?” (Durafour, 2012, p. 263). That is, the
questions of art and aesthetics for Lyotard are questions of how to access
sensation as it is “in itself,” prior or other to the ways that we throw
networks of sense over objects in order to tame and domesticate them for
our needs. It is not a question, Durafour (2017) notes, of believing that
cinema can give us the “things-in-themselves” (for “how would we know
what they are?”), but of letting things come “half-way to meet us” (p. 27).
If film is movement, then the real, the matter, of film would be the
320
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
Conclusion
I have proposed Lyotard’s work as a still very under-exploited resource for
film-philosophy. It might be objected that Lyotard’s interventions are too
disparate, and do not form a cohesive whole: the essays are written from
quite different theoretical perspectives, address different issues, and do
not give us a clear picture of what a Lyotardian film-philosophy would
look like. There are two responses to be made here. First, despite their
surface heterogeneity, at a sufficient level of generality we can see that
Lyotard presents a body of work which offers alternatives to the still-
common tendency to “read” films, to interpret their meaning according to
signs and significations. Instead, he focuses on the non-signifying
dimensions of the body, affect, pragmatic relations between film,
spectator, and society, and the “real” which resists interpretation, all in
ways which challenge and complicate similar moves in phenomenology
and psychoanlayis. This is why I have suggested that Lyotard’s work is
ripe for rediscovery in the contemporary context, with its move from
cultural constructivism to realism and materialism. Second, the dispersed
and fragmentary nature of Lyotard’s ideas was very deliberately
cultivated, and can be viewed as a strength. Lyotard was a thinker who
doubted the ability of any one perspective to capture what is at stake in
philosophical reflections, and approached philosophy experimentally,
working as many artists do: trying something out, abandoning it, and
trying something else. This method prevents us from treating Lyotard as
another master-thinker to be slavishly repeated or applied: it requires us
to select from his works, and develop them ourselves in creative ways.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Askin, R., Hägler, A., & Schweighauser, P. (2014). Introduction: Aesthetics after the
Speculative Turn. Speculations, V: 6–38.
Barrett, E., & Bolt, B. (Eds.). (2012). Carnal Knowledge: Towards a “New Materialism”
through the Arts. London; New York: I.B. Tauris.
Bennet, J. (2010). Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Durham; London: Duke
University Press.
Brinkema, E. (2014). The Forms of the Affects. Durham; London: Duke University Press.
Bryant, L., Srnicek, N., & Harman, G. (Eds.). (2011). The Speculative Turn: Continental
Materialism and Realism. Melbourne: re.press.
Clough, P. T., & Halley, J. (Eds.). (2007). The Affective Turn: Theorizing the Social. Durham;
London: Duke University Press.
Coole, D., & Frost, S. (Eds.). (2010). New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics.
Durham; London: Duke University Press.
321
Film-Philosophy 23 (2019)
322
Four Fundamental Concepts of Lyotard’s Film-Philosophy
Martin, A. (2011). Turn the Page: From Mise en scène to Dispositif. Screening the Past, 31.
Retrieved from http://www.screeningthepast.com/2011/07/turn-the-page-from-mise-en-
scene-to-dispositif/.
Massumi, B. (1995). The Autonomy of Affect. Cultural Critique, 31: 83–109.
McGowan, T. (2008). The Real Gaze: Film Theory after Lacan. New York: SUNY.
McGowan, T., & Kunkle, S. (Eds.). (2004). Lacan and Contemporary Film. New York: Other
Press.
Mee, S. J. A. (2016). Terrifying Spectatorship: Jean-François Lyotard’s Dispositif and the
Expenditure of Intensities in Steven Kastrissios’s The Horseman. Philament, 21: 19–44.
Mulvey, L. (1975). Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema. Screen, 16(3): 6–18.
Parente, A., & de Carvahlo, V. (2008). Cinema as Dispositif: Between Cinema and
Contemporary Art. Cinémas: revue d’études cinématographiques / Cinémas: Journal of Film
Studies, 19(1): 37–55.
Poe, A. (2011), Things-Beyond-Objects [Book Review of D. Coole & S. Frost (Eds.),
New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics]. Journal of French and Francophone
Philosophy – Revue de la philosophie française et de langue française, XIX(1): 153–164.
Rosen, P. (Ed.). (1986). Narrative, Apparatus, Ideology: A Film Theory Reader. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Rutherford, A. (2003). Cinema and Embodied Affect. Senses of Cinema, 25. Retrieved from
http://sensesofcinema.com/2003/feature-articles/embodied_affect/.
Schrader, P. (1972/2018). Transcendental Style in Film: Ozu, Bresson, Dreyer. Oakland, CA:
University of California Press.
Shaviro, S. (2012). Without Criteria: Kant, Whitehead, Deleuze, and Aesthetics. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Shaviro, S. (2014). The Universe of Things: On Speculative Realism. Minneapolis, MN;
London: University of Minnesota Press.
Trahair, L. (2009). Jean-François Lyotard. In F. Colman (Ed.), Film, Theory and Philosophy:
The Key Thinkers (pp. 222–232). London; New York: Routledge.
Woodward, A. (2014). A Sacrificial Economy of the Image: Lyotard on Cinema. Angelaki:
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 19(4): 141–54.
Žižek, S. (1999). The Undergrowth of Enjoyment: How Popular Culture can Serve as
an Introduction to Lacan. In E. Wright and E. Wright (Eds.), The Žižek Reader
(pp. 11–36). Oxford; Malden, MA: Blackwell.
323