On Derridean Différance - Usief
On Derridean Différance - Usief
On Derridean Différance - Usief
On Derridean Différance
Introduction
The French philosopher Jacques Derrida who gained prominence outside France with his
lecture “Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of Human Sciences” delivered at Johns
Hopkins University in 1966 problematises the Western philosophical as well as scientific notion
of the centre. He attributes this to “logocentrism,” a term which was first coined by the
philosopher Ludwig Klages in the 1900s. “Logocentrism,” according to Derrida, refers to the role
of the metaphysical notion of the irreducible “logos” in producing speech. This proximity of
and a reassuring certitude, which itself is beyond the reach of play. (Writing and
Difference 352)
demonstrates this notion at play by showing different names that have assumed the role of a
It could be shown that all the names related to fundamentals, to principles, or to the center
It may be shown how this notion of “logocentrism,” however, does not accord with the
theological “Logocentrism,” which is accepting the Logos as central to Christian belief. For, if
For we have not a high priest who is unable to sympathise with our weaknesses, but
one who in every respect has been tempted as we are, yet without sinning. (Hebrews
4.15)
The word “logos” finds its origin in the Proto-Indo-European root word leg- “meaning ‘to
collect, gather,’ with derivatives meaning ‘to speak’ on the notion of ‘to gather words, to pick out
words.’” According to the same notion, the Greek word logos also meant “‘computation,
account,’ also ‘reason.’” In fact, the sense of presence that Derrida attributes to language, albeit
critically, finds a splendid illustration in the meaning acquired by a close Latin word of logos,
namely lignum, which “practically” refers to “‘wood, firewood,’” although it literally means
Grammatology
upon his reading of logocentrism. In fact, the eleventh edition of A Glossary of Literary Terms,
published decades after deconstruction was popularised by Derrida fails to arrange for an entry to
the term except under a discussion of deconstruction. This is not in accord, for whatever reason,
with the claim that writers from Plato to Saussure or texts from “from the Phaedrus to the Course
3
in General Linguistics” (103) are given over to its tendencies. Moreover, it unqualifiedly
assumes the critic’s assumption of the term with the same sweeping generalisation of it:
Derrida’s reiterated claim is that not only all Western philosophies and theories of
language but all Western uses of language, hence all Western culture, are logocentric; that
is, they are centred or grounded on a “logos” (which in Greek signified both “word” and
“rationality”) or, in a phrase he adopts from Heidegger, they rely on “the metaphysics of
presence.” (80)
A possible “natural” reason for this occultation is explained by Michael Harrison of The
Chicago School of Media Theory when he discusses the origin of the word in question,
. . . it first appeared in academic writing around 1929 as the German Logozentrisch in the
work of philosopher and psychologist Ludwig Klages. The Oxford English Dictionary,
which defines “logocentric” as, simply, “centered on reason,” claims the word was first
used in English by theologian V. A. Demant in 1942 and Dictionnaire Le Robert cites its
first use in French in 1942 (BDLT 5). In their use, it was generally employed to describe
difficult to talk about its origin, despite this information, is that we cannot possibly
Spivak says in her Translator’s Preface to Of Grammatology how the notion of the
mere technique, and yet a menace built into speech – in effect, a scapegoat – is a symptom
of a much broader tendency. He relates this phonocentrism to logocentrism – the belief that
the first and last things are the Logos, the Word, the Divine Mind, the infinite
understanding of God, an infinitely creative subjectivity, and, closer to our time, the
Deconstruction
Derrida’s aim through deconstruction may be summarised in the order prescribed by him
which he intends to critique is narratively obtained through attempting to expose the “bad
abstraction” made, not exclusively but most importantly, by Saussure when he understands
language as “phonologic” and rejects writing as having any role in the science of language. Here,
what is worth noting is the retro-spective critique of logocentrism applied by Derrida who assumes
the metaphysical language of those he reviews to be indicative of the logocentrism of the West, “in
general.”
5
This logocentrism, this epoch of the full speech, has always placed in parenthesis,
suspended, and suppressed for essential reasons, all free reflection on the origin and status
of writing, all science of writing which was not technology and the history of a technique,
itself leaning upon a mythology and a metaphor of a natural writing. It is this logocentrism
which, limiting the internal system of language in general by a bad abstraction, prevents
Saussure and the majority of his successors from determining fully and explicitly that
Derrida says about the process of différance that “one begins by determining it as the
ontico-ontological difference before erasing that determination” (24) and about trace that it “is not
more natural than cultural, not more physical than psychic, biological than spiritual” (47, 48).
Therefore, when he says “The ‘theological’ is a determined moment in the total movement of the
trace,” this does not suggest anything about “theology” but leaves the readers trying to figure out
what a “determined moment” means in “the total movement of the trace,” with the first statement
quoted in this paragraph already suggesting the need for “an erasing (of) determination.” It is as
rhetorical, in the non-colloquial sense as to say, “From the moment that there is meaning there are
nothing but signs” (50). This movement of différance is explained by Derrida thus,
This différance is therefore not more sensible than intelligible and it permits the
articulation of signs among themselves within the same abstract order - a phonic or graphic
text for example - or between two orders of expression. It permits the articulation of
speech and writing - in the colloquial sense - as it founds the metaphysical opposition
6
between the sensible and the intelligible, then between signifier and signified, expression
the arguments made by the writer himself. He says “Without a retention in the minimal unit of
temporal experience, without a trace retaining the other as other in the same, no difference would
do its work and no meaning would appear,” whereas about experience itself he says, “‘Experience’
has always designated the relationship with a presence, whether that relationship had the form of
consciousness or not” (62, 60). In other words, he is calling forth the idea of différance which
always already calls for the “matter” of both time and presence. It becomes concludable then that
this phenomenon which “founds the metaphysical opposition” is already circumscribed in the
“sensible things” of time and presence which precede it. Thus, he becomes guilty of an “originary”
demarcation between “sensible and intelligible,” and subsequently of whatever charge he brings
well as what it entails, Spivak’s notes from her Preface are helpful.
In the last two chapters of the Interpretation, meditating in great detail upon "The
risk of some self-bafflement, to explode the idea of any unified agency for the psyche. By
the time Freud comes to write the "Note," he has clearly established that the workings of
the psychic apparatus are themselves not accessible to the psyche. It is this apparatus that
"receives" the stimuli from the outside world. The psyche is "protected" from these stimuli.
7
permanent "memory-traces" -marks which are not a part of conscious memory, and which
will constitute the play of the psyche far removed from the time of the reception of the
arises [periodically and irregularly] in the perceptual system instead of the permanent
traces." (GW XIV. 4-5, SE XIX. 228) There are periods, then, when the perceptual system
is not activated and that is precisely when the lasting constitution of the psyche is being
determined. It is only the periods of its actual activation that gives us the sense of time.
(xxxix, xl)
piece of deconstruction, such as when he speaks about how an act of metaphorisation always
This experience of the effacement of the signifier in the voice is not merely one illusion
among many-since it is the condition of the very idea of truth but I shall elsewhere show in
When he does take this up elsewhere, however, he stops short of making the same
conclusion in what may be called as a Derridean or Nietzschean precaution, the amiable criticism
Ideality and substantiality relate to themselves, in the element of the res cogitans, by a
It calls itself infallible and if the axioms of natural reason give it this certitude, overcome
the provocation of the Evil Spirit, and prove the existence of God, it is because they
constitute the very element of thought and of self-presence. Self-presence is not disturbed
by the divine origin of these axioms. The infinite alterity of the divine substance does not
self-relationship and the purity of auto-affection. God is the name and the element of that
which makes possible an absolutely pure and absolutely self-present self-knowledge. From
Descartes to Hegel and in spite of all the differences that separate the different places and
moments in the structure of that epoch, God's infinite understanding is the other name for
the logos as self-presence. The logos can be infinite and self-present, it can be produced as
auto-affection, only through the voice: an order of the signifier by which the subject takes
from itself into itself, does not borrow outside of itself the signifier that it emits and that
affects it at the same time. Such is at least the experience-or consciousness-of the voice: of
proclaims itself as the exclusion of writing, that is to say of the invoking of an "exterior,"
with the deconstructible premises of “[logos] produced as auto-affection” and “voice” which are
themselves follows an “ironical” path with the critic posing the argument to the reader rhetorically
9
with a surety that they would themselves draw the conclusion. The evidence for precisely the
opposite of what is conveyed by these lines is what is being referred to here as his rhetorical
strategy: “the subject takes from itself into itself, does not borrow outside of itself the signifier that
it emits and that affects it at the same time.” If one poses to think why it is that the critic does not
immediately hold this narrative up to suggest that this is “the condition of the very idea of truth”
which is the consideration that has led us on here, the reason becomes clear: if he were to suggest
this, he would be as much guilty of calling in categorical “truth” claims that he himself is so
desperately trying to wash his hands off. Instead, this rhetorical strategy would persuade the
unsuspecting reader to make the conclusion that he wants to make without suspecting the writer
himself of falling short of deconstructive grace. The categorical conclusion which can be drawn
from this is the fact that deconstruction is a metaphysics that seeks to ambush the metaphysics of
dependent on the “lie” of logocentrism making Derrida “the critic-philosopher” described by Paul
de Man in “Semiology and Rhetoric,” to say as yet nothing of the logocentric incompatibility of
deconstruction. “. . . if truth is the recognition of the systematic character of a certain kind of error,
then it would be fully dependent on the prior existence of this error” (32).
born of a deep trust in the technique of deconstruction which is why it still does not resonate in
content with what has been done here. In an attempt to bring to light a sense of presence that
Derrida had overlooked in a certain comment made by him at an interview, she says that “When
Derrida claims for himself that he is within yet without the clôture of metaphysics, is the
10
difference not precisely that he knows it at least?” (Translator’s Preface xxxviii) It must be also
pointed out that the “metaphysics” alluded to by Spivak need not be the “metaphysics” alluded to
here to the extent that it is not the intention to pass judgement on whether deconstructionists up to
now have with or without intention held to the “metaphysics” in their writings being exposed.
Philosophy behind
Poetic Influence - when it involves two strong, authentic poets, - always proceeds by a
misreading of the prior poet, an act of creative correction that is actually and necessarily a
misinterpretation. The history of fruitful poetic influence, which is to say the main
tradition of Western poetry since the Renaissance, is a history of anxiety and self-saving
différance. In the interview with Julia Kristeva titled “Semiology and Grammatology,” found in a
It confirms that the subject, and first of all the conscious and speaking subject, depends
upon the system of differences and the movement of différance, that the subject is not
present, nor above all present to itself before différance, that the subject is constituted only
In other words, according to Derrida, it is in realising the moment of différance that ‘the
subject is constituted.’ Compare this with the narrative of the Tower of Babel in the Bible:
Then they said, “Come, let us build ourselves a city, and a tower with its top in the
heavens, and let us make a name for ourselves, lest we be scattered abroad upon the face
What is underway here is a people of “one language and few words” attempting to “make a
name” for themselves (11.1). Shortly after this, the account describes what God does to them:
“. . . Come, let us go down, and there, confuse their language, that they may not
understand one another’s speech.” So the Lord scattered them abroad from there over the
face of all the earth, and they left off building the city. (11.7-8)
subjectivity is what the “one people” were attempting to build through the construction of the
tower of Babel by making a name for themselves. What God does in Genesis is what Derrida
suggesting the implausibility of building a subjectivity except through différance (20). For those
who believe in him, this results, analogical to the Biblical narrative, in the inability of establishing
If, however, in the description of the moment of différance which gives rise to
one’s subjectivity – which includes his own – Derrida fails to make the intertextual connection
with the biblical narrative of the Tower of Babel, it is predictably the case that every thought
which arose out of derridean subjectivity has the very text for a “trace,” a trace which is
12
simultaneously also a presence even according to the deconstructive standpoint and inasmuch as
References
Abrams, M. H. and Geoffrey Galt Harpham. Glossary of Literary Terms. 11th ed., Cengage
Learning, 2015.
holybooks.com/completes-aristotle-pdf.
Expanded Edition. Translated by Willard R. Trask, revised ed., Princeton UP, 2003.
———. Scenes from the Drama of European Literature. Theory and History of Literature, vol.
Jun. 2021.
Bishop, Paul. “Ludwig Klages and His Philosophy of Language.” Journal of European Studies,
doi.org/10.1177/0047244119892870.
Blanchard, Marc. “Mimesis, Not Mimicry.” Comparative Literature, vol. 49, no. 2, 1997, pp.
176–190. JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/1771344. Accessed 28 June 2021.
Bloom, Harold. Anxiety of Influence: A Theory of Poetry. Second ed., Oxford UP, 1997.
14
Cohen, Tom, editor. Jacques Derrida and the Humanities: A Critical Reader. Cambridge UP,
ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/christuniversity-ebooks/detail.action?docID=217674.
Costa-Lima, Luiz. “Erich Auerbach: History and Metahistory.” New Literary History, vol. 19,
no. 3, 1988, pp. 467–499. JSTOR, www.jstor.org/stable/469085. Accessed 28 June 2021.
Culler, Jonathan. The Pursuit of Signs. Routledge Classics ed., Routledge, 2001. Originally
published in 1981.
———. Structuralist Poetics. Routledge Classics ed., Routledge, 2002. Originally published in
de Man, Paul. “Epistemology of Metaphor.” Critical Inquiry, vol. 5, no. 1, 1978, pp. 13–30.
———. “Semiology and Rhetoric.” Diacritics, The Johns Hopkins UP, vol. 3, no. 3, Autumn,
Geaney, Jane. “Grounding ‘Language’ in the Senses: What the Eyes and Ears Reveal About Ming
15
名 [Names] in Early Chinese Texts. Philosophy East and West, vol. 60, no. 2, U of Hawai'i
Green, Geoffrey. “Erich Auerbach.” The Encyclopedia of Literary and Cultural Theory, vol. I
(Literary Theory from 1900 to 1966). First published on 24 Dec. 2010. Wiley Online
Library, doi.org/10.1002/9781444337839.wbelctv1a012.
Harris, Matthew Edward. “Vattimo and Caritas: A Postmodern Categorical Imperative?” Kritike,
19 May 2021.
John Paul II. Man and Woman He Created Them: A Theology of the Body. Translated by Michael
vatican.va/content/john-paul-ii/en/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_04031979_redemp
tor-hominis.html
Konuk, Kader. East West Mimesis: Auerbach in Turkey. Stanford UP, 21 Sep. 2010. ProQuest
Ebook Central,
ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/christuniversity-ebooks/detail.action?docID=618843.
Bernard, revised 2nd ed., Macmillan and Co., London, 1914. Originally published in
“The One Who Is; The One Who Gives: Aquinas, Derrida and the Dilemma of the Divine
www.youtube.com/watch?v=FU83IZk4n8M.
Redfield, Marc. “Aesthetic Ideology and Literary Theory.” The Centennial Review, vol.
2020.
The Holy Bible: Revised Standard Version. Edited by Bernard Orchard and R. C. Fuller,