Experience of The Alien in Husserl's Phenomenology
Experience of The Alien in Husserl's Phenomenology
Experience of The Alien in Husserl's Phenomenology
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Brill is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Research in
Phenomenology
Ruhr-Universtàt Bochum
19
II
The question concerning the form in which the alien appears for the first
time, i.e., whether it appears as the neutral or the masculine/feminine alien,
is a question we have already implicitly answered. Husserl's response is
clear: the intrinsically first I-alien is the non-I in the form of an other I; it is the
gendered other, the gendered alien (I 137/CM 107; XVII 248). The reason for this
is obvious. The neutral alien, which attaches to things from their side, is not
alien in the radical sense, that is, in the sense of "originally inaccessible." For
there are no things and no aspects of things to which I would be denied
access. They all lie within the scope of my experience, if not in fact then
certainly in principle, and thus belong to what Husserl described as the
"sphere of owness." For example, in order to perceive the backside of the
thing which is always co-present and given only as such, I need simply alter
my position. The impossible gaze behind the mirror begins there, where the
distance is insurmountable, there with the other who does not belong to my
field of possibilities. Thus, if the world of things assumes traits of alienness, it
does so only insofar as they refer to alien experiences, which in spite of all
communalization, never fully coincide with those of mine. This secondary,
borrowed alienness consists in the fact that the accessibility to the world of the
other is "not unconditional" (I 160/CM 132). In light of alien experience,
this secondary alienness encroaches even on me insofar as I take on charac
teristics which do not stem from me.
This distinction of primary alienness of the other and secondary alienness
of the world and myself—albeit a distinction which is in no way self
evident—leads us to the fundamental presuppositions of the Husserlian theory
of constitution. Why constitution of the other? We cannot and need not go into
all the nuances and transformations of the concept.9 But this much is clear:
Ill
Finally, let us thus pose the question whether Husserl was actually successful
in showing that alienness is that which is "originally inaccessible," without it
changing behind our backs again into what is accessible or belonging. The
question is neither easy to answer nor does it entail a simplistic response. On
first glance it seems Husserl crossed the threshold to the alien accompanied
by two escorts. The own I and everything belonging to it serves as model, as
original for the alien. Own and alien meet one another for their part on the
ground of a general reason presumed by every experience. Basically it is the
same that becomes modified and unfolds in and through the medium of my
Self. The shock of the alien and of the heterogeneous is cushioned by starting
with the own and moving over on to what is common. Own experience and general
reason still guarantee an accessibility even of what is inaccessible. Michael
Theunissen explains empathy by means of self-alienation as virtually a
double process by which I simultaneously alienate myself and remove the
alienness of the other.11 What seems to me decisive is precisely the radicality
of the perspective which keeps our reflections in suspense, namely, the insistence
on the alien as alien as its "being-sense" (I 135/CM 105). The self-crossing
over, considered as "intentional reaching-over" or as "intentional modifica
NOTES
1. For the larger context of these reflections, see my Ordmng im Zwielicht (Frankfurt: Suh
kamp, 1987), esp. 122-25.
2. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vemunft (Hamburg: Meiner, 1956), Β 864; trans. Norma
Kemp Smith, Critique of Pure Reason (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965).
6. Edmund Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, trans. Dorion Cairns (The Hague: Martinu
1977). Henceforth CM.
7. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Le visible et l'invisible (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), 308;
phonso Lingis, The Visible and the Invisible (Evanston: Northwestern University Pr
254. Henceforth Le Visible and The Visible.
8. Emmanuel Levinas, Le temps et l'autre (Montpellier, 1979), 196; trans. Richard
Time and the Other (Duquesne, 1987). The nodal-point of this essay—appearing for
time in 1947—is the relation of temporal otherness and otherness of the other.
9. Cf. the well-known study from R. Sokolowski, The Formation of Husserl's Concept of C
(The Hague: Martinus Nijhoif, 1964); and more recently to this point, cf. Ε. S
"Intention und Konstitution," in Phdnomenologische Studien (Frankfurt, 1987).
10. Edmund Husserl, Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological
First Book, trans. F. Kersten (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoif, 1983).
11. Michael Theunissen, Der Andere (Berlin: Gruyter, 1977), 141; trans. Christoph
The Other (Cambridge: MIT, 1984), 150. In another place (85, 90), he speak
"alienness that comes over me in alien-ation"—and which is naturally not "sus
Does not that have to mean: which I let come over me?
12. Cf. the excellent study on Derrida, text, and related themes in R. Bernet's "Die unge
genwârtige Gegenwart. Anwesenheit und Abwesenheit in Husserls Analyse des Zeitbe
wuBtseins," in Zeit und Zeitlichkeit bei Husserl und Heidegger, ed. E. W. Orth,
Phànomenologische Forschungen 14 (Freiburg/Miinchen, 1983). Concerning the general
problematic of the Husserlian theory of sensation which seeks a middle course between
fundamentalism and constitutionalism, cf. M. Sommer, Husserl und der Friihe Positivismus
(Frankfurt, 1985). This, incidentally, is a real find for the research of scientifically induced
metaphor of concepts with which Husserl's texts abound.
13. Cf. Merleau-Ponty's richly scored essay on Husserl, "Le philosophe et son ombre," in Signes
(Paris: Gallimard, 1960), 215: "L'ouverture perceptive au monde, dépossession plutôt que
possession, ne prétend pas au monopole de l'être"; trans. Richard C. McCleary, "The
Philosopher and His Shadow," in Signs (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1964),
170. Concerning sensation as an "I-alien," cf. Husserliana IV: 334f. Merleau-Ponty refers
especially to this work in his essay on Husserl.
14. This is Thesis V from the list of theses of disputation which Husserl advances in his
dissertation (Halle, 1887). See Edmund Husserl und die phdnomenologische Bewegung. Zeugnisse in
Text und Bild, ed. R. Sepp (Freiburg/Miinchen, 1988), 169.
15. The insight into the "essential asymmetery" that I sought to develop from the interplay of
question and answer earlier in Das Zwischenreich des Dialogs (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff,
1971), e.g., 150f, 306f, I would today advance more strongly against the demand for
symmetry which is also tied to a communicative reason.