0% found this document useful (0 votes)
33 views19 pages

Criticality in Art, Architecture, and Design Chap 3

This document summarizes a passage from The Routledge Companion to Criticality in Art, Architecture, and Design that describes a "crit" or critique session led by artist and teacher Michael Asher at the California Institute of the Arts. The summary describes how Asher conducted unusually long critiques of up to 5 hours, where students would bring pets and engage in activities like napping or knitting as critiques unfolded. It then recounts a specific critique session where Asher listened carefully and asked thoughtful questions to students about their artwork and intentions, steering discussions in productive directions over the multi-hour period.

Uploaded by

zoe Chen
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
33 views19 pages

Criticality in Art, Architecture, and Design Chap 3

This document summarizes a passage from The Routledge Companion to Criticality in Art, Architecture, and Design that describes a "crit" or critique session led by artist and teacher Michael Asher at the California Institute of the Arts. The summary describes how Asher conducted unusually long critiques of up to 5 hours, where students would bring pets and engage in activities like napping or knitting as critiques unfolded. It then recounts a specific critique session where Asher listened carefully and asked thoughtful questions to students about their artwork and intentions, steering discussions in productive directions over the multi-hour period.

Uploaded by

zoe Chen
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 19

This article was downloaded by: 10.3.98.

104
On: 10 Nov 2021
Access details: subscription number
Publisher: Routledge
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: 5 Howick Place, London SW1P 1WG, UK

The Routledge Companion to Criticality in Art, Architecture,


and Design

Chris Brisbin, Myra Thiessen

Crits, consensus, and criticality

Publication details
https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315623412-3
Michael Newall
Published online on: 30 Aug 2018

How to cite :- Michael Newall. 30 Aug 2018, Crits, consensus, and criticality from: The Routledge
Companion to Criticality in Art, Architecture, and Design Routledge
Accessed on: 10 Nov 2021
https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/doi/10.4324/9781315623412-3

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR DOCUMENT

Full terms and conditions of use: https://www.routledgehandbooks.com/legal-notices/terms

This Document PDF may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproductions,
re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.

The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or
accurate or up to date. The publisher shall not be liable for an loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages
whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

3
CRITS, CONSENSUS, AND
CRITICALITY
Making artists in the contemporary art school

Michael Newall

Introduction
In 2004, sociologist Sarah Thornton documented a day of critiques, or crits as they are often
known, run by the artist and teacher Michael Asher, at the California Institute of the Arts for
the Master of Fine Arts program.1 The first student up, Thornton records, “has hung two large,
well-crafted pencil drawings on the wall.”2 In front of the work, the class has assembled.

Asher sits motionless . . . [s]tudents stare impassively into space, swirling their coffee,
their legs hanging over the arms of chairs . . . [e]ach student has set up camp, staked
out some territory, and distinguished him- or herself with a pet, a pose, or a signature
activity.3

Some students draw or knit, one has brought a sleeping bag, another a Tempur-Pedic pillow. A
number come with dogs: “Dogs are allowed . . . so long as they are quiet,” explains a student.4
“At 10:25am everyone is seated,” and Asher, “legs crossed, clipboard in hand,” nods toward
the student.5 The student stresses that he is “just going to workshop some ideas,” and that he
has been distracted by personal matters.6 One wonders if he is disowning the work’s shortcom-
ings in advance. He then speaks articulately and frankly about how his drawings reflect his own
feeling of dislocation around his heritage. But, by the end of his statement, he is, as Thornton
says, “unravelling.”7 He concludes, “[s]orry, I am doing this badly. I don’t really know why I
am here.”8
Asher holds back from speaking, and the students fill the gap. A female student reflects sym-
pathetically on the theme of the work and its relative invisibility in contemporary art. She then
raises a different issue, challenging the student’s apparent appropriation of other cultures in his
drawings—a strategy he has adopted to resolve his own sense of dislocation. Can it be justified?
The student himself seems unsure.9 Thornton goes on: “At 1:15pm we’re in a definite lull,
and Asher speaks his first words . . . he says, ‘[p]ardon me.’ The students raise their heads. I sit
in anticipation, expecting a short lecture . . . But no. . . . he says, ‘[w]hy didn’t you enter the
project through language or music?’”10 That turns the discussion away from the content of the
work and toward the student’s chosen medium. Then, “[a]t 1:30pm . . . Asher vaguely raises a
finger. I expect he is going to adjourn for lunch,” but instead he asks the student, “[w]hat do

14
Crits, consensus, and criticality

you want . . . ? Put the group to work.”11 The student replies, “I guess I’m wondering about
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

the viability of political activism in my work.”12 A conversation sparks around this new topic,
positions are laid out and defended. At 2:00pm, Asher draws the crit to a close. Two further crits
that day will take the class through to 1:00am.
Michael Asher (1943–2012) was perhaps the most renowned teacher of crits. His were unu-
sually long—four to five hours. In this extended timescale, student behaviors developed in
unusual ways, including the napping, knitting, and pets.13 But, aside from those aspects, his crits
are similar to most others in art schools, which, regardless of where they are practiced, tend to
fall into similar structures and dynamics.
However, this form of teaching is a relatively recent development in art schools. Asher ran
crits at the California Institute of the Arts (CalArts for short) from 1974. No history of the crit
exists, but its origins in art schools appear to lie in the 1960s.14 Crits also exist in architecture
and design, although their character and history is somewhat different in these disciplines.15 My
focus is on crits in art schools, but much of what I say can also be applied with some revisions
to crits in architecture and design.
Crits are practiced much the same across departments of painting, sculpture, and other media.
But they fit most naturally into art schools such as CalArts that are not divided into departments,
allowing students to work across media, for as we will see, that is the kind of work they encour-
age. The typical features seen in Asher’s class are as follows.16 The student presents their work to
the group of staff (at CalArts, Asher’s teaching assistant was also present) and students, explaining
their intentions for it. The group then responds with questions and feedback. For Asher, the
only rule in this conversation is that students have to “listen to and respect each other,” but we
will see that there are also other constraints on how students engage in crits. Finally, students are
expected to act on the feedback they have received. This is a crucial feature of crits; they are a
major channel by which art school students receive feedback. Indeed the artist Josh Stone, who
was the subject of the crit Thornton describes, recalls it as a positive experience, despite its dif-
ficulties: “From that critique, I learned how to . . . use a different voice in my art.”17
An important element of crits in many art schools is the role of the student’s peers in giving
feedback. Few teachers are quite so self-abnegating as Asher, but in many crits student opinions
can and often do carry as much weight as those of teachers. This also means that I am less con-
cerned with crits that are in effect ‘open juries’ where the class is present, but usually only listen-
ing, while teachers discuss student work in the process of assessing it. This occurs in some Master
of Fine Arts programs in the United States and is common in architecture and design crits.18
This chapter has three general objectives. First, despite being so widespread, there are no
accounts of just what crits teach, how they teach it, and why they are preferred to more con-
ventional forms of teaching art; the first four sections aim to remedy this oversight. Crits have
only occasionally been the subject of scholarly attention, James Elkins’ work providing the
only extensive treatments of the topic in art schools, and artists and teachers themselves have
given crits little reflection, at least in print.19 The account I give here holds that a successful crit
depends on the audience developing a consensus around the interests the work can support.
Second, the question of understanding what and how crits teach gains urgency from con-
cerns that have been raised about the effectiveness of crits and the harm crits can cause students.
Elkins has significant doubts about their effectiveness as a form of teaching, as do others. Crits
are, Elkins says, “in effect . . . simply too complicated to understand.”20 Crits can also be harm-
ful to students, most notably channeling hostility toward them in ways that those coming from
outside art, architecture, and design schooling can find shocking. Art historian Griselda Pollock
has put this in the strongest terms, claiming that some students “have literally died of the expe-
rience.”21 In the fifth section, ‘Failed crits,’ I examine various kinds of ineffective, hostile, and

15
Michael Newall

otherwise failed crits. While it is clear that they do occur, I want to be clear that crits need not
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

be like this.
Third, I examine how crits influence art. Almost all professionally successful contemporary
artists attend art school, increasingly studying to Master of Arts or Master of Fine Arts level and
beyond in the United Kingdom, the United States, and Australasia.22 Since crits are a widespread
teaching method in these places, they are a familiar experience to a great many contemporary
artists. ‘Crits and the art world’ and ‘Crits and pluralism’ show that crits influence and shape art
by promoting a particular kind of pluralism, and they tend to do so regardless of the intentions
of the teachers who run them. Pluralism has been a contentious feature in contemporary art,
and the last section of the chapter examines another distinctive element in the contemporary art
school teaching: critical theory. I show that the two are often complementary, but that there
remains an irreconcilable tension between them.
This chapter draws on a range of empirical resources, including documentation of, and
observations about, crits made by others (which I cite throughout). It is also informed by my
own observations and experiments with crits undertaken as a teacher (which I do not discuss
here). Although I will not dwell on it, my approach has an affinity with progressive theories
of education such as those of Paulo Freire and Lev Vygotsky. Notably, the reliance on a group
of peers for feedback rather than a teacher has strong parallels with Freire’s dictum that “[t]o
teach is not to transfer knowledge but to create the possibilities for the production or construction
of knowledge.”23 Lastly, while my project here is primarily theoretical and descriptive, I also
make some recommendations about how crits could be improved. Understanding what gives
crits their distinctive educational value helps to show how they can more completely fulfill their
potential, and the recommendations I make are in this spirit.24

Understanding crits
I take it that the value of crits is distinct from the transfer of knowledge from teacher to student.
If it were that, it could only be an inefficient and ineffective method of teaching compared to
more conventional methods such as lectures, workshop instruction, and so on. This is because
any such method of teaching can only have its effectiveness compromised when presented in
a crit format, where the other threads of conversation will confuse or obscure it. If a crit were
really no more than an inferior form of some better-understood type of teaching, it would be
impossible to plausibly account for the prevalence of the crit in art schools. So I take it that crits
must instead achieve a distinctive pedagogical aim and must rely on their distinctive feature: the
response of the group. How then does the group’s response provide useful feedback or criticism
for the student: why is it more valuable, or have a value distinct from simply seeking feedback
from a teacher? Answering these questions is the key to understanding crits.
One can think about any kind of teaching as guiding a student toward a state where that
teaching is no longer needed.25 In the case of crits, it will ideally guide the student’s work
toward a state where it would meet (more or less) with the approval of the crit group. What
does it take to get this approval? One requirement is that the student’s own intentions for the
work should roughly speaking be fulfilled. But more than that is needed, for the student’s inten-
tions must also be of the right kind. Broadly speaking, that happens when the group agrees with
the student that their intentions are worthy, which is to say, that in fulfilling them the work has
value as art. What qualities give a work this value? Minimalist artist Donald Judd held that “a
work needs only to be interesting,” and I adopt his term ‘interesting’ to describe those qualities
of the work that the viewer is able to value as artistic—that sustain what I shall call the viewer’s
‘interest.’26 The term as I use it is generic: it does not stipulate any particular properties (e.g., the

16
Crits, consensus, and criticality

aesthetic) that contribute to an artwork having value as art; rather, it leaves open what might be
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

of interest to the viewer.27 I should also distinguish my use of the word ‘interest’ from others. I
do not mean a selfish bias or partiality, nor do I intend to invoke the philosophical distinction
between interested and disinterested pleasure, used by Kant.28
Now, the approval of the group occurs when the group agrees that the student’s intentions
are worthy, and that they are fulfilled in the work. Partly, this involves getting the student’s
interest in their work, and the interest that the group finds itself able to take in the work, to
coincide, or, at least, to substantially overlap. This is typically a complex process. When a stu-
dent gives an account of their work to the group, it usually includes an account of their interest
in it—the kinds of interest they intend it to sustain—the reasons, they believe, that it is of value
as art. The group’s initial response will typically include various accounts of what qualities its
members find of interest, or where such qualities could be developed, in the work. Especially
in the case of early student work, this will often diverge—sometimes dramatically—from the
student’s intentions.
This can happen in two broad ways. First, the group may find that the intentions the student
had for the work are unfulfilled. The work might be executed in such a way that the intended
effects are not, or not fully, realized. Asher called this the “disparity between what a person says
their work is about and what is actually being observed.”29 That happened in the crit Thornton
documents—when the student’s attention was drawn to the troubling quality of their appropria-
tion of other cultures. Intentions can go unfulfilled in another way too: the group’s members
may find themselves unable to take the interest in the work that the student themselves does.
For example, it may be the formal or expressive effects that the student likes do not interest
members of the group enough to sustain a successful artwork in their eyes. Autobiographical
content, fascinating to the student, might not be of interest to others. This too was gently
touched on in the crit, Thornton noted, when it was observed that the student’s chosen theme
was relatively invisible—which is to say, not of broad interest.
Second—and this applies particularly to early student work—the group will likely be inter-
ested in a range of aspects of the work that the student has not considered. Members of the
group might be interested in its formal qualities, its art historical context, its social, political, and
ideological dimensions, to give some examples. Often, a student might not even have thought
about many of these things, but the group’s interest in them shows how such a meaning could
be developed. A painter may not have thought about the support they paint on, the way the
work is hung, nor about the social and political connotations that accompany their chosen
subject matter, but the group can draw attention to all these things and show how they might
come to have some kind of value in the work. Artist and critic Lucy Soutter makes just this
point about crits:

This kind of training forces students to extend their sense of engagement beyond their
own experience and the image or object they have made to consider its edges and
external supports . . . [as well as] the phenomenological, social, historical, political and
institutional implications of their work.30

In this way, the group’s responses will show the student where their intentions are not fulfilled,
and suggest ways in which the work could attain a broader and more complex significance, and
in the process become more interesting to the group.
These are the distinctive pedagogical values of the crit: they are not, at least not effectively
and reliably, achieved by other means. Consider a scenario where a teacher could give a student
precisely the same feedback in the context of an individual tutorial. If that were to occur, the

17
Michael Newall

feedback would have a different significance. From an individual teacher, it is only ever a single
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

point of view, reflecting their individual interests and commitments, which the student may
not, and may not want, to share. Where the group reaches a consensus, it cannot be dismissed
in this way—the agreement of the group carries a special kind of legitimacy—and indicates the
potential for a reliable transpersonal significance. It will also tend to echo the judgments of the
contemporary art world, a point I will return to later.
Following the crit, the student is expected to act on the responses they have received, often
revising and developing both their work (either the work presented to the group, where it is a
work in progress, or new work) as well as their intentions for it. The group will also typically
give advice based on their responses: ideas about how to more successfully fulfill intentions, and
about how those intentions could be revised or broadened to better interest the group. The
student is not necessarily expected to take the advice offered by the group, but is expected to
respond by, one way or another, increasing the interest of their work to the group. In the case
of the crit Thornton describes, the student’s practice changed significantly, putting aside the
subjects and strategies the group found uninteresting and problematic, and developing a new
approach better attuned to the interests of the group (and the art world). This account raises a
range of questions. Let me start from the theoretical side, before turning to the practical.

Consensus in crits
My approach requires that the crit group is capable reaching a consensus—a significant overlap
in the individual responses of the group. Why should there be a consensus? Why should a series
of subjective responses converge and overlap in the way I have described? There is no a priori
reason why this should happen. We might well imagine, even expect, that a group of observ-
ers will respond in ways that generate no consensus. Consensus does not always occur in crits,
but I believe that consensus is always possible, and in a well-run crit it will usually come about.
Traditionally in aesthetics, a consensus of taste can be reached because individuals possess
a ‘common,’ that is, shared, sense: a sensus communis. They share potentials of understanding
and imagination that ensure that they have the capacity to respond in the same way to the same
object. I will not commit to that eighteenth-century approach, but I do draw from it the idea
that consensus relies on a common sense. For Immanuel Kant, the sensus communis is “a power
to judge that in reflecting takes account . . . of everyone else’s way of presenting [i.e., appre-
hending something].”31 Kant thinks that we do this in the following way: “we compare our
judgment not so much with the actual as with the merely possible judgments of others, and
[thus] put ourselves in the position of everyone else.”32 Of course, in a crit one does not need
to imagine or infer the possible responses of others; the others are right there, furnishing actual
responses. Group members can gauge their own capacity to respond as others do, and idiosyn-
cratic responses—outliers—can be identified and discounted, so establishing a consensus.
In an important respect, we will need to vary from Kant. What Kant calls the “formal fea-
tures” that serve as the basis for his conception of the aesthetic may be of interest to the group,
but they are only likely to be one among many kinds of interests, and, as I have said, I place no
constraints on what these interests may be.33 Putting aside the much-argued case of the aesthetic,
where a consensus emerges, I take it that it will depend on shared dispositions of perception and
thought.34 Psychology tells us that our perceptual capabilities are largely shared, determined as
they are mostly by a common physiology and physical environment. Beyond this, our responses
are also conditioned to a significant degree by a common social, technological, and cultural
environment. Such facts of common physiology, psychology, environment, society, and cul-
ture allow a group to respond—to see, feel, understand—in ways that overlap and so shape the

18
Crits, consensus, and criticality

interests that the student and group are collectively capable of taking in art. That is to say, they
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

give an assurance that consensus is possible.


This account allows that the common sense, as I shall now call it, need exist only as a poten-
tial in the group’s members at the outset of a crit. Most of the group might not know of, say, a
particular philosophical theory, and thus will not see how it is used in a student artwork; they
might well be ignorant of an art historical style, and how a student’s painting draws on and
references it; or about events in recent politics or popular culture, and so miss an artwork’s com-
mentary on these things. But, as part of the process of the crit, they can come to recognize these
things and evaluate for themselves how interesting the use they are put to is.
I take it that the facts of our physiology, perception, and psychology are fairly unchanging,
but the facts of environment, culture, and technology are subject to change. Sometimes this
change is quick; sometimes it is slow. The common sense, so far as it is based on these things, is
changeable too, and this is reflected in the changing interests that a group will take in a work.
New interests can arise—around changes in culture, ideas, and technology for instance—and art
students, like artists, can discover new ways to exploit these.
In this account, the common sense thus takes the place of older standards of judgment. No
longer is the art student’s work evaluated against some external standard, such as the classical
style as in the case of the academic tradition, or the style of a ‘master’ (as in masterclass or atelier
teaching), or against nature.35 So, what makes the common sense an appropriate standard of judg-
ment for the contemporary art school? With these earlier kinds of teaching, their appropriate-
ness is clear: art of earlier periods valued adherence to those standards of style and likeness to
nature. In one sense, the answer in the case of crits is similar: the standard of judgment applied
in crits significantly overlaps with that used to judge art in what is now the mainstream of the
contemporary art world. That will take a little explanation, and I will return to this idea later.
Another answer can also be given. The crit is historically unusual in the teaching of art in that it
rejects the imitation of models. The standard of judgment the crit imposes does not come from
a tradition, master, or nature. Rather, it comes from a community, of which the student is part,
and the response of that community is, with some qualifications, free. In this way, the use of
consensus as the standard of judgment reflects an aspiration of contemporary art inherited from
Modernism: that traditional forms be overturned, and that direct experience of the contempo-
rary world instead guide the artist.36

Originality and self-expression


I said that there are some qualifications to the freedom of the group’s response. These tend to
be so much a part of our contemporary conception of art, that it may feel strange to call them
constraints; rather, they tend to be so deeply instilled that they are incorporated into our inter-
ests and play a role in shaping the consensus. But it is worthwhile spelling these out clearly, for
they further shape the workings of crits.
The first of these is originality: a student cannot repeat something that has already been done.
One can draw from the work of others—forms, themes, strategies—and one can quote or
respond to the work of others, but one cannot reproduce it. Originality as a value in art has a
history, and, while its value has not gone unquestioned, there is no doubt that it has prevailed
in the contemporary art world, as well as in artist’s education.37 To fulfill the expectation for
originality, students need to know something about contemporary art. In particular, they have
to be up to date with work using similar media and themes to their own. If they are not, they
risk repeating the innovations of others when they should be building on them, reacting against
them, or otherwise finding their own approaches. The need for this has been impressed into

19
Michael Newall

art students since the 1960s. Artist John Baldessari, who also taught at CalArts, tells a story that
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

makes this point. “I had a teaching assistant in ’70 who had a rubber stamp made that said: ‘Nice
idea, but it’s already been done by,’ and there was a line and you filled it in.”38 Rubber stamp
aside, the expectation is standard in art schools. A typical Fine Arts degree specification requires
its students to produce “an original body of work within the field of fine art.”39 History and
theory of art classes play some part in this aspect of artist training. But it is through crits that stu-
dents receive tailored advice on these lines. Teachers (it is the teachers that are usually best able
to give this kind of advice) seeing a student making work similar in some way to artist X, may
say, “Do you know the work of X?” Or (less gently), “How does this differ from X’s work?”
Or (less gently again), “This has already been done by X.” Where this happens in a crit, the
whole group comes to better know where the scope for originality lies, and where it does not.
The second requirement is that students should in fact have the interests that they claim to
have in their work. In this limited sense, their work should be a self-expression. Some able stu-
dents can feign this. Sociologists studying students at Coventry College of Art in the late 1960s
found a student who confessed that “all the things he does at college are ‘cover-stories’—he
does the things he is really interested in at home.”40 The student was the only one in his year to
achieve a first-class diploma. We might wonder why this should worry anyone—if an artist can
produce work that interests us, why should we be concerned whether they are interested in it,
or whether they have merely simulated their interest? But it does; most of us would feel cheated
and manipulated if an artist we admired confessed that the interests and values they claimed to
have were bogus. The expectation is an old one, and, like the expectation for originality, is
linked to a Romantic conception of the artist who was expected to express their feelings, emo-
tion, and temperament through their work. We do not necessarily expect this from art today,
but we still require that an artwork is a self-realization or revelation of an individual.41
This expectation is tied up with perhaps the most awkward feature of crits. If a work genu-
inely presents a student’s interests and it attracts criticism, this can be painful. So far as one’s art
is tied up with one’s identity, it can occasion genuine anguish. Moreover, this process occurs
in what is effectively a public forum, witnessed, and enacted by teachers and peers. Crits can be
emotionally trying in a range of ways, and I will discuss some others shortly. But this one is set
apart from others because it is not wholly avoidable. The discomfort and anxiety that Thornton
documented is a good example of this. That kind of pain may be mitigated to some degree if
students are made aware of this feature of crits in advance, and if the group frames its comments
sympathetically. But, by their nature, effective crits do involve this kind of criticism.

Contradiction in crits
Responses given during crits are often contradictory. This is not something that students study-
ing outside art, architecture, and design usually have to contend with. On the whole, feedback
in other disciplines is unequivocal and consistent; students are expected to take the advice
they receive. But what is a student expected to do when given contradictory responses? David
Vaughan and Mantz Yorke call contradictory feedback “an example of the pedagogy of art and
design,” and acknowledge that it can result in “confusion” for students.42 The issue divides into
a few separate problems, as there are different kinds of contradictory responses.
First are situations where an idiosyncratic response contradicts those that make up the consensus.
This occurs when one or more members of the group perceive or understand the work in a
way that most other members of the group find they cannot share. Someone may find a work
interesting, where most others cannot find an interest in it. Or someone may be unable to see the
interest in a work, where others do. We are all apt to make idiosyncratic responses on occasion.

20
Crits, consensus, and criticality

By their nature, they spring from something particular to the individual: a perception, attitude, or
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

association that is a matter of personal experience, and that others do not share. In crits, idiosyn-
cratic responses are typically discounted—and they need to be if a consensus is to be identified.
Anyone who has taken part in crits will be familiar with this.43 However, idiosyncratic opinions
should be distinguished from cases where an individual notices an aspect of the work that the rest
of the group has not noticed and, in pointing it out, gets the others to share that response to it.
Such cases are instances not of idiosyncrasy, but of convergence toward a consensus.
Second is contradictory advice. Members of the group whose responses lie within the consensus
can still give contradictory advice. Say there is a consensus about a flaw or problem in the work;
members of the group may give contradictory suggestions about how to fix this. Vaughan and
Yorke describe what a student is supposed to do when they receive such feedback: “the expec-
tation [is] that the student will consider the advice and make their own decision about it as part
of the learning process.”44 That is, indeed, all they can do. The student has to choose which—if
any—of the advice to take. However, contradictory advice does not threaten the consensus,
which relates only to the group’s perception, understanding, and evaluation of the work.
Third is a situation I call divided consensus. In some cases, it is wrong to dismiss outlying
responses—those that differ from and even contradict a consensus—as idiosyncratic. I have in
mind responses that represent the views that come from a member of a minority underrep-
resented in the group—whether in terms of gender, class, ethnicity, sexuality, or disability.45
These different responses have a basis in the social and cultural context of the relevant minority,
and often include a different experience of social power relations. Here it is right to speak of a
divided consensus, for if that minority were better represented in the group (or if already well-
represented in terms of numbers, better able to find its voice), it would give rise to a consensus
of its own, perhaps overlapping with, but distinct from, the dominant consensus. How does
the crit function in such circumstances? The situation is complex and can sometimes be far
from ideal, as the discussion of women’s experiences in crits below shows. There are happier
approaches: in crits, as in the wider art world, there is often a desire to expand the range of the
majority’s interests to include at least some of the interests of minorities. Partly this arises out of
a concern with justice. There is a widespread concern to understand and counter unequal power
relations. Partly this comes from an interest in exploring the scope of human experience. Thus,
there is an interest in understanding the different kinds of experience that different perspectives
outside the mainstream offer. In this way, crit groups can (i) be capable of finding interest in
art made from a minority perspective, and (ii) be able to take into account and come to share
minority responses to art made from a majority perspective.

Failed crits
I have already mentioned Elkins’ position on crits, that they are “in effect . . . simply too com-
plicated to understand.”46 His book Why Art Cannot Be Taught gets its title from this concern.
He argues that a variety of features of crits make it very hard for students to learn from them.
These include contradictory feedback and the potential for what I call hostile crits.47 I have said
enough now for it to be clear that I disagree with Elkins: if the kinds of practical difficulties he
describes can be overcome, crits offer a valuable and distinctive kind of learning. I have already
dealt with contradictory feedback above, so this section examines hostile crits and other practical
issues that can cause a crit to fail—that is to say, can prevent a student from learning from them.
They can all be overcome, mostly in straightforward ways, provided teachers have an aware-
ness of them. I should add that crits can flounder in many different ways, and this catalog is not
intended to be comprehensive.48

21
Michael Newall

Hostile crits
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

As I have said, what students need to be told in crits is often difficult to take, but, equally, teach-
ers can make this process harder than is necessary. A series of YouTube videos records crits at
SUNY’s Albany campus. Comparing a student’s work to that of a professional artist, one of
the teachers says: “I guess I’m saying she’s good and you’re bad.”49 Another student, who has
made a drawing from a photographic source is told, “that photograph, forgive me, is a lot more
interesting than this drawing; the drawing is really boring.”50 And another student is told, “I
think it [your work]’s really, really stupid.”51 The students respond to these remarks in different
ways: with denial, measured capitulation, or anxious laughter. But however apt the teachers’
points, they are not tactfully communicated. The emotionally freighted character of crits, and
the hostile interactions that can cause them, are widely commented on. Art historian Howard
Singerman remarks on crits’ “everyday cruelty.”52 Elkins writes of having seen crits “held in
front of all the students and faculty” where “it was not uncommon to see the student cry in
front of everyone.”53 Art historian Elena Crippa records an observer of crits at Saint Martin’s
School of Art (London) finding them “devastating.”54 Architectural historian Kathryn Anthony
has shown that crits in architecture and design are no better in this respect.55
The crit has posed special difficulties for female students. At Coventry College of Art in
the late 1960s, “many students, especially the girls, found this unnerving and depressing in the
extreme.”56 Charles Madge and Barbara Weinberger’s study of students at Coventry vividly
documents the depression and anxiety this kind of teaching could cause.57 In this context,
Pollock’s claim that students “have literally died of the experience” is plausible.58 There is anec-
dotal evidence that outright hostility, toward both women and men, occurs less frequently than
it has in the past.59 In the 1960s and 1970s, teachers were almost uniformly male, and cultural
norms of the time made it more difficult than it is now for women to engage vigorously in such
an environment. All the disparaging comments that I discuss in this section are made by men.
Still, as the comments from Albany show, such hostile crits have not disappeared, and such
teaching cultures continue. Rachel Garfield, currently an Associate Professor at the University
of Reading (Berkshire, United Kingdom), observes,

[i]n one of the institutions I taught, the crit, rather than being a safe place where
learning can happen, was often a bullying environment of survival of the fittest, where
students did run out of the room crying . . . [t]hat kind of crit is a bear pit of posturing,
not a learning tool.60

Clearly, hostile crits should be avoided wherever possible. First, they can do psychological harm
to students. Second, an emotionally fraught state can only make learning more difficult. Staff
need to take these matters seriously, and not diminish the impact of hostile behavior towards
students and their learning. But it is worth observing that the structure of crits allows and even
encourages harsh criticism. Speaking individually to a student, a teacher is likely to be measured
and sympathetic. But if a group is commenting on a student’s work, there is a tendency for one
critical remark to be expanded on and amplified by others in the group.61 Many accounts of
teaching at Coventry illustrate this well. Here is one example: the student is working in textiles
and given the pseudonym ‘Andrea’ by the sociologists.

The tutors disliked her passivity, her lack of ideas and opinions. They said she had
not been able to explain herself or why she was doing weaving. She had no enthu-
siasm, excitement, or sense of involvement. One tutor said she closed her mind and

22
Crits, consensus, and criticality

contributed nothing. If she couldn’t make the tutors interested in her at the next tuto-
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

rial, she ought to be thrown out—she was just wasting the tutors’ time. In the face of
these criticisms, Andrea was defensive and angry.62

This kind of amplification of criticism—which, as I say, can occur in comments from both staff
and students—also needs to be monitored and resisted.

The masterclass by stealth


A single teacher who leads a crit can manipulate it so that it serves a quite different function to
what I have described. In particular, they may use it to instill in students their own ideas of what
is valuable in art, thereby encouraging their own favored approach or style in art. Such teachers
will usually dominate discussion, picking out for praise work in line with their approach, and
denigrating, overtly or subtly, work that does not align with it. Sometimes teachers are aware
of doing this; they see it as their proper role. Other times a teacher may do this inadvertently
through the expression of their convictions, enthusiasm, and charisma.63 In either case, the crit,
as I have described it, is effectively hijacked and turned into a continuation of an older tradition
of teaching—a version of the masterclass or atelier. This is a form of teaching where the students
work alongside a ‘master’ in their studio, absorbing, carrying on, and perhaps developing the
master’s approach. In contemporary art, this may involve transmission of conceptual strategies as
much as, or instead of, visual style. There are things to be said in favor of contemporary versions
of kind of this kind of teaching. It has a long and successful history in German art schools.64 But
the form I have described is a masterclass by stealth. It misleads the students, who typically do
not expect this kind of teaching. They find themselves having to go through the sham of being
‘consulted’ for their responses, which can only win approval when they accord with the teach-
er’s position. It can be particularly unhelpful for those students who, unaware of the situation
before joining the class, first must understand what is going on (for the univocal character of the
masterclass can only be obscured by the multivocal crit), and then may find themselves resistant
to the standards to which they find themselves unexpectedly required to meet. Masterclass train-
ing should be advertised as such, and not be hidden in the form of a crit.

Crits that produce the ‘wrong’ consensus


Sometimes crits produce a consensus that seems ‘wrong’—I will say exactly what I mean by
‘wrong’ shortly. I have found this occasionally happens when students in the early years of their
program take the lead in a crit. There are two general situations in which this can occur. The
first happens when a group does not fully explore its capacity for certain kinds of responses. For
example, a group might judge an image of a nude without exploring questions of whose ‘gaze’ it
is presented for, or judge an abstract ‘action painting,’ without exploring how it functions as an
expression of stereotypical machismo. Considering those questions could well upend the group’s
original response. The second occurs when a group is unaware of a work’s lack of originality due
to its lack of awareness of relevant examples of contemporary art. For example, the group may
approve of work when, if its members had a better knowledge of contemporary art, they would
find it derivative and inadequate compared with the work of other artists working in the area.
What is ‘wrong’ about these kinds of ‘wrong’ consensus? Consensus in a crit depends on two
things that are lacking here. First, the group must fully explore its capacity to find interest in an
artwork. Without that, it can overlook features of value, as well as defects, as in the example of
the nude. Second, the group must be apprised of existing art that affects the interest the group

23
Michael Newall

will take in the work or affects how the group will judge the work’s originality. A ‘wrong’
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

consensus fails to satisfy at least one of these conditions.


Reaching a consensus is a process, and it is helpful to think of a ‘wrong’ consensus as a stage
in this longer process. To help the group overcome a ‘wrong’ consensus, students may need a
teacher (i) to point out the possibility of certain kinds of responses (the group can then judge
their own capacity for these responses and their own interest in them), or (ii) to draw the group’s
attention to other artworks relevant to gauging the interest in the work under consideration.

Crits in which the student rejects the group’s judgment


Sometimes students dismiss or ignore the judgment of the group. The following exchange,
from the class at Albany, shows how things can go when this is not understood. It is also, self-
evidently, an example of a hostile crit where the conversational form encourages the teachers to
reinforce and amplify criticism. The student, a middle-aged man, begins by explicitly rejecting
the group’s judgment.

Student: I t’s not up to anybody in this room. There are symbols in art and symbols mean
something, and, . . . and symbols have meant what they mean for more than 200
years now and I just don’t see why I should, . . . why what you’re saying should
make me want . . . should mean anything to me.
Teacher 1: Who is it intended for?
Student: It’s intended, it’s intended basically for anybody who sees it . . .
Teacher 2: (interrupting): It doesn’t work like that.
Student: . . . people might take it the wrong way, but I can’t help that.
Teacher 2: No, it doesn’t work like that.
Teacher 3: . . . This is a rather naïve discussion we’re having; I feel as if I could be having the
same talk with a high school junior . . .
Teacher 1: Yeah, a child.65

Such exchanges can happen very easily in crits. A common strategy is that a student will observe
that the group’s opinions are ‘subjective’, and that they are, therefore, justified in ignoring them.
Even sympathetic teachers can be affronted once it becomes apparent that a student is intending
to discount all their responses and advice. The student, already resolved to be unreceptive, is
unlikely to be any more receptive to an impromptu discussion of the purpose of the crits, even if
it is better presented than the above example. These exchanges can be avoided by ensuring that
students are aware in advance that the consensus of the group provides the standard of judgment.

Crits and the art world


These final sections explore how crits shape the art and artists that come out of them. In
approaching this, it will help to first address a question I have delayed examining. Why are the
judgments of crits of value to students who will shortly find themselves working in another
environment—the contemporary art world?
I have touched upon an answer already: work that meets with the approval of a crit group will
also be more likely to meet the approval of the larger audience of the art world. That is to say, the
criteria for approval used in crits in some sense overlap with those used by the art world. By ‘art
world,’ I mean to include those with influence in the exhibition, funding, support, and discourse
around contemporary art—it is an important audience for those graduating from art schools.

24
Crits, consensus, and criticality

This raises a worry and prompts a further question. The worry, which I will quickly dismiss,
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

is this: perhaps the agreement of the crit group with the art world is explained by members of
the group absorbing the values of the art world. That would explain the apparent coincidence
of opinion, but it would do significant damage to my claim that responses by members of the
crit group are substantially free, for these would instead be dictated by the art world. It is pos-
sible that crits can work like this, but this would turn them into an analog of what I called the
masterclass by stealth, where it is Artforum, Frieze, e-flux, or some other source whose unspoken
authority is covertly transmitted to students. As with the masterclass by stealth, this would be a
needlessly inefficient and ineffective way of teaching. If this is what teaching by crit amounts to,
it would, of course, be better conveyed by other kinds of teaching, such as lectures, seminars,
or workshops.
The further question is this: how then is it that the criteria for approval in crits overlap with
those applied in the contemporary art world? To answer this it will help, first, to introduce the
idea of a concept of art—by this I mean an idea of what art should be or do, which an artist uses to
guide their art-making.66 A concept of art thus implies criteria for judgment of art, and criteria
for judgment will often imply a concept of art.
Historically, concepts of art have stipulated that art should aspire to some particular quality
that optimizes its artistic value. To take two simple examples: we can speak of a mimetic con-
cept of art, which holds that art should involve lifelike representation; or a formalist concept of
art, which sees artistic value residing in the aesthetic experiences occasioned by formal features
of an artwork. Is there a contemporary concept of art? One contender is what philosopher
Arthur Danto called pluralism. As he put it, “[i]t does not matter any longer what you do,
which is what pluralism means” or, in even pithier form, “with qualification, anything goes.”67
Pluralism, on this description, is characterized precisely by not stipulating what art should be
or do. It removes the constraints of earlier concepts of art, and it guides art-making by saying,
roughly speaking, do as you like, anything goes. There will indeed need to be qualification. For
instance, we can add the expectations for originality and self-expression that I described earlier
and to which work in crits were also subjected. Crits have a similar character, in that they too
give freedom for the student to present work without any constraints of older concepts of art
and, in a similar way, to largely pursue their own interests.
There is more to say, for crits also require that students heed the consensus of the group. Is
there a similar expectation in the art world? It is beyond the scope of this chapter to answer this
question properly. But it is obvious that judgment in the art world works in a range of ways—it
is sometimes made by individuals and sometimes by groups. Where judgment relies on a group’s
decision—on museum acquisition committees, prize-giving juries, and foundations deciding on
grants, for example—that will in effect often mean a consensus decision, made on a similar basis
to what occurs in crits.
So, the standards of judgment used in crits and in the contemporary art world thus reflect one
another to a significant degree, and the former might even be considered a more public, more
legible version of the latter in some cases. As I have said, that should hardly be surprising, since
crits could otherwise have little value.

Crits and pluralism


Crits, we have seen, are strongly allied with pluralism. This section argues that crits also tend to
instill pluralism in students. I do not say that crits teach this, for it typically occurs without any
corresponding intention on the part of a teacher. Nor are students typically able to articulate the
concept of pluralism. Nevertheless, it makes sense to say that the crit tends to instill this concept,

25
Michael Newall

for crits shape what students believe is appropriate or permissible in art, and help to guide their
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

future art-making in distinctively pluralistic ways.


Consider a student who approaches a crit holding a non-pluralist concept of art—that is,
believing that they should pursue some particular quality in art—whether it be mimetic, formal,
expressive, political, or something else. The crit group will put this concept under pressure, as
its members explore the scope for the work to hold different kinds of interest. Recall Soutter’s
remarks: “[t]his kind of training forces students to extend their sense of engagement . . . to
consider . . . edges and external supports . . . phenomenological, social, historical, political, and
institutional implications.”68 A student holding a non-pluralist concept will find themselves
under pressure to consider and acknowledge values that their concept overlooks, ignores, or
rejects. Political artists must consider the media and forms they use to convey their message (as
the student in Asher’s crit was asked to do); formalists must consider phenomenology beyond
the optical; expressionists, the semiotic reading of their gestures—and so on. In this way crits
press students to open their work up to a broader range of meaning and media. At this point,
one might ask: does consensus not repress many viewpoints, and so resist pluralism? In fact, the
reverse is true. Consensus mostly acts to discount the opinions of those who hold non-pluralistic
concepts of art, which stipulate that certain qualities in art should be pursued in preference to
others. Most of a crit audience—most of the time—will deny the restrictive concepts of art
of others. It is not just pluralists who will do this, but anyone who does not hold that same
concept of art. Those who hold restrictive concepts of art will reject other restrictive concepts
that do not agree with theirs. Once the group settles into the process of evaluating work, they
will be driven towards the position that art can have a plurality of values, even if that is not the
art that they, individually, make. Any other position, aside from pluralism, is unworkable in
this context. In this way, crits work against non-pluralist concepts of art, and, in the process,
promote pluralism.69

Are crits critical?


Pluralism is controversial. As Hal Foster put it in the early years of postmodernism, pluralism
makes art “another consumer good,” part of “a steady line of obsolescent products.”70 In the
context of this account of crits, the worry is as follows: it could be that our shared interests—our
shared sense of what is valuable in art—and the pluralism that develops out of this, tends only
toward interests favored and encouraged by entrenched social, political, and commercial pow-
ers in society. This could hold both in artistic terms, where commercially-oriented aesthetics
or other forms that do not threaten the status quo are favored, and in political terms, where the
consumerism, capitalism, sexism, and so on of much contemporary Western culture is unwit-
tingly repeated and propagated.
This argument suggests that crits are not critical, in the sense that critical theory is critical. By
‘critical theory,’ I mean both the work of the Frankfurt School and the broader tradition that
has been influenced by it, which conceives of theory as playing a politically progressive role,
through a process beginning in the criticism of dominant ideologies: attitudes and values that
permeate culture and serve the ends of the dominant social, political, and commercial powers.71
The idea that art should also be critical in this sense—criticizing dominant ideologies to politi-
cally progressive ends—has also become an important element in art and art schools. Thierry de
Duve has outlined how, since the 1980s, critical theory came to have this place in artist training
and how the various disciplines that came to be aligned with critical theory often came to be
drawn into art school teaching:

26
Crits, consensus, and criticality

Linguistics, semiotics, anthropology, psychoanalysis, Marxism, feminism, structuralism,


Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

and post-structuralism . . . entered art schools and succeeded in displacing—sometimes


replacing—studio practice while renewing the critical vocabulary and intellectual tools
with which to approach the making and the appreciating of art.72

Critical theory has also come to have a vital place in crits. We have seen this already in the crit
Thornton documents—the student is criticized for appropriation of other cultures, the kind of
act that capitalism and consumerism happily condone in other contexts.73 Many of the examples
I have given of typical moves in crits incorporate this critical attitude. Broadly speaking, critical
theory gives tools for group members in crits to interrogate and develop their responses in two
general ways. The first involves developing an awareness of how the dominant culture shapes the
interests of audiences. Feminism, for example, allows criticism of the way women are represented
in mainstream visual culture and allows students to object when such imagery is reproduced
unreflectively in the visual arts. Second, critical theory allows students to build on this, by devel-
oping interests beyond those sanctioned by dominant ideologies. So, students may seek out or
develop images and modes of production that are not endorsed by the dominant culture. A crit
group may need these approaches modeled for them before they begin to explore these issues,
but once they have these tools of thinking, there are unlikely to simply discard them. The criti-
cally naïve pluralism that Foster attacks is therefore not the pluralism that crits currently instill.
However, the tension between the crit and critical theory is real and should not be hid-
den. There is no guarantee that a work with critical content, however well it accords with and
accomplishes the aims of critical theory, will meet with the interest of the group.74 We may
expect that it often will—and the politically engaged character of student work often supports
this. But the possibility is always there that the group’s interest in critical approaches will flag,
perhaps because they have seen these themes treated before more compellingly elsewhere, per-
haps because other kinds of meaning seem to them more compelling, or for other reasons that
we may judge good or ill. In this respect, critical content is like any other quality an artwork
may have. The door is always open to it in crits, but there is no guarantee that it will meet with
approval. In other words, the crit allows students the freedom to pursue a critical art, but it also
allows the freedom not to do so.75

Notes
1 Sarah Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World (London: Granta, 2008): ch. 2.Thornton’s book has attracted
some controversy, so it is worth saying that a number of the students in the crits that Thornton writes
about later discussed their experiences in a podcast. None complained about being misrepresented,
although they did not all appreciate the attention the book drew to them. One, Fiona Jack, says “she
absolutely caught the vibe and dynamics of the room.” “The Crit—The Legacy of Michael Asher’s
Post-Studio Class at CalArts,” The Conversation: An Artist Podcast, May 16, 2015, theconversationar
tpodcast.libsyn.com/episode-106-the-crit-the-legacy-of-michael-ashers-post-studio-class-at-calarts,
11:20–25.
2 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 47. The student is Josh Stone. Stone also discusses the experience
in the podcast “The Crit—The Legacy of Michael Asher’s Post-Studio Class at CalArts.”
3 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 48.
4 Ibid.
5 Ibid.
6 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 48.
7 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 49.
8 Ibid.
9 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 49–50.

27
Michael Newall

10 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 52.


Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

11 Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 53.


12 Ibid.
13 According to Jack, this also extended to Asher: “Michael used to nod off all the time.” “The Crit—The
Legacy of Michael Asher’s Post-Studio Class at CalArts,” 11:50–12:00.
14 Crits are documented at St Martin’s School of Art at this time (where they were known as group criti-
cisms), although they did not become almost ubiquitous in UK art teaching until after the 1970s. For
crits at St Martin’s, see Elena Crippa, “From ‘Crit’ to ‘Lecture-Performance,’” in The London Art Schools:
Reforming the Art World, 1960 to Now, ed. Nigel Llewellyn (London:Tate Publishing, 2015): 137–138. For
crits at Coventry, see Charles Madge and Barbara Weinberger, Art Students Observed (London: Faber &
Faber, 1973). Coventry is discussed under the name Midville College of Art.
15 Kathryn H. Anthony, Design Juries on Trial:The Renaissance of the Design Studio (New York:Van Nostrand
Reinhold, 1991): 11.
16 A variant is the ‘silent’ crit, in which the student does not speak, at least until the end of the crit, so that
the group responds to the work unmediated by the student’s own account of it. Artist and teacher Mary
Kelly gives an account of this in Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 54–55.
17 “The Crit—The Legacy of Michael Asher’s Post-Studio Class at CalArts,” 44:00–44:10.
18 For MFA assessment crits, see Jori Finkel, “Tales From the Crit: For Art Students, May Is the Cruelest
Month,” New York Times, April 30, 2006, www.nytimes.com/2006/04/30/arts/design/tales-from-the-
crit-for-art-students-may-is-the-cruelest-month.html. For architecture and design crits, see Anthony,
Design Juries on Trial.
19 Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught (Urbana and Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 2001): esp. 111–166;
James Elkins, Art Critiques: A Guide (Washington, DC: New Academia Publishing, 2011). Thierry de
Duve provides another theoretically astute account of art schools, but does not discuss crits; Thierry
de Duve, “When Form has Become Attitude—And Beyond,” in Nicholas de Ville and Stephen Foster
(eds.), The Artist and the Academy: Issues in Fine Art Education and the Wider Cultural Context (Southampton:
John Hansard Gallery, 1994).
20 Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught: 112. Since crits are central to studio teaching, he concludes from this
that art, in the context of the contemporary art school, cannot be taught.
21 Griselda Pollock, “Art, Art School, Culture: Individualism after the Death of the Artist,” in The Block
Reader in Visual Culture, ed. Jon Bird et al. (London and New York: Routledge, 1996): 59.
22 According to Harold Rosenberg, “only one of ten of the leading artists of the generation of Pollock
and de Kooning had a degree (and not in art), while of ‘thirty artists under thirty-five’ shown in
Young America 1965 . . . the majority had BAs or MFAs.” Harold Rosenberg, “Educating Artists,”
in Harold Rosenberg, The De-definition of Art: Action Art to Pop to Earthworks (London: Secker &
Warburg, 1972): 39. Now, in the US, most professionally successful contemporary artists hold an MFA.
Howard Singerman wrote in 1999 of the “unchallenged administrative success” of the degree. Howard
Singerman, Art Subjects: Making Artists in the American University (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University
of California Press, 1999): 6. In the UK and Australasia, the situation is much the same, with Master of
Arts degrees being widely sought after. As I write, out of over 100 nominees for the Turner Prize since
1984 all but two appear to have a Bachelor of Arts qualification from an art school, and about half have
a postgraduate qualification (such as a Master of Arts or Master of Fine Arts). I owe these statistics to
Martin Lang.
23 Paulo Freire, Pedagogy of Freedom: Ethics, Democracy and Civic Courage, trans. Patrick Clarke (Lanham,
MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1998): 30. See also Lev Vygotsky, Mind in Society:The Development of Higher
Psychological Processes (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978). I should add that I have seen
no evidence that educational theory has played a role in the development or practice of crits.
24 However, I have tried to avoid repeating existing advice to teachers and students. A small literature gives
guidance about how best to administer crits (as a teacher) and negotiate them (as a student). See Elkins,
Why Art Cannot Be Taught and Art Critiques: A Guide; Kendall Buster and Paula Crawford, The Critique
Handbook: A Sourcebook and Survival Guide (Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 2006);
Margo Blythman, Susan Orr, and Bernadette Blair, Critiquing the Crit (Higher Education Academy,
2007), www.adm.heacademy.ac.uk/projects/adm-hea-projects/learning-and-teaching-projects/criti
quing-the-crit/; and Sarah Rowles, ed., Art Crits: 20 Questions: A Pocket Guide (London: Q-Art, 2013).
25 Of course, teaching involves more than this—this is a necessary rather than sufficient condition for
teaching something.

28
Crits, consensus, and criticality

26 Donald Judd, “Specific Objects,” in Donald Judd, Complete Writings, 1959–1975: Gallery Reviews, Book
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

Reviews, Articles, Letters to the Editor, Reports, Statements, Complaints (Halifax: The Press of the Nova Scotia
College of Art and Design, 1975).
27 Judd himself favoured what is often now called the phenomenological. My understanding of inter-
est does not imply a preference for this quality over others—I mean it in the more open sense I
describe.
28 Immanuel Kant, Critique of Judgment, trans. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987): sections 2–4.
29 Michael Baers, “Michael Asher (1943–2012): Parting Words and Unfinished Work,” e-flux 39 (2012),
www.e-flux.com/journal/michael-asher-1943-2012-parting-words-and-unfinished-work/
30 Lucy Soutter, “What Lies Beneath,” Frieze 101 (2006): 179. Soutter draws here on her experience as a
student at CalArts.
31 Kant, Critique of Judgment: §40. I draw here on Jennifer McMahon’s analysis of Kant. (Jennifer A.
McMahon, Aesthetics and Material Beauty: Aesthetics Naturalized (New York and London: Routledge,
2007): 6.
32 Kant, Critique of Judgment: §40.
33 Ibid.
34 The commonsense bears comparison to Pierre Bourdieu’s habitus: the relatively durable collection of
dispositions for perception, thought, and behavior that are often held at an unconscious level. Pierre
Bourdieu, Outline of A Theory of Practice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977). However, I
would not want to commit to the idea that these dispositions—especially perceptual dispositions—are
always simply a matter of acculturation.
35 For the academy, see Nikolaus Pevsner, Academies of Art: Past and Present (New York: Da Capo Press,
1940). For masterclass and atelier training, see Albert Boime, The Academy and French Painting in the
Nineteenth Century (London: Phaidon, 1971). For one approach that sees nature as the proper model for
art students and artists, see John Ruskin, The Elements of Drawing (London: Smith, Elder & Co., 1857).
36 As Charles Harrison described it, Modernism involves “a commitment to skepticism in the face of
received ideas and beliefs . . . combined with an inclination to regard direct experience as the true source
of knowledge.” Charles Harrison, Modernism (London: Tate, 1997): 18.
37 The postmodernist attacks made on originality from the 1970s are properly understood as targeting a
different notion of originality from the one I use here. That notion holds that canonical works of art
are properly understood as wholly original—entirely a creation of the artist, and unrelated to the culture
from which they emerged. Roland Barthes argued that something much closer to the reverse is true:
that what an artist makes is rightly understood as an amalgam of sources. Roland Barthes, “The Death
of the Author,” in Roland Barthes, Image Music, Text, trans. Stephen Heath (New York: Farrar, Straus &
Giroux, 1978). Rosalind Krauss gives a comparable account focusing on the visual arts, describing “the
copy as the underlying condition of the original.” Rosalind E. Krauss, “The Originality of the Avant-
Garde,” in Rosalind E. Krauss, The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1986): 162.
38 John Baldessari in “Conversation: John Baldessari and Michael Craig-Martin,” in Art School: Propositions
for the 21st Century, ed. Steven Henry Madoff (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009): 52.
39 Programme specification for MA Fine Art, University for the Creative Arts, UK, 2010, revised 2012,
http://webdocs.ucreative.ac.uk/MA%20Fine%20Art%20Programme%20Spec-1329306960214.pdf.
Sometimes it is said that art student work is not original. For an example, see Grayson Perry’s and
Gillian Wearing’s remarks in Hannah Ellis-Petersen and Nancy Groves, “Back to Art School: Grayson
Perry and Gillian Wearing Meet Tomorrow’s Stars,” Guardian, August 8, 2016, www.theguardian.com/
artanddesign/2016/aug/08/back-to-art-school-grayson-perry-and-gillian-wearing-visit-degree-
shows. Here, a more demanding idea of originality is being used. The originality of art students can be
modest—a small or less significant innovation. Perry and Wearing use the term to describe work that
shows a greater degree of innovation, or significance. As Wearing says, “Originality comes later, but you
do want to be unique” (ibid.).
40 Madge and Weinberger, Art Students Observed: 185.
41 Also, as I have discussed, a crit group will often find potential meanings that the student has not yet
considered for their work, and it is expected that students may adopt and develop these meanings them-
selves in their subsequent work. So, while dissimulation about intentions may not be the best point for
a student to come from, it is still possible that sooner or later the process of the crit will result in the
student discovering their own interests.

29
Michael Newall

42 David Vaughan and Mantz Yorke, I Can’t Believe It’s Not Better:The Paradox of NSS Scores for Art & Design
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

(Group for Learning in Art and Design, Higher Education Academy, 2009): 15, www.heacademy.ac.uk/
system/files/nss-report.pdf
43 Elkins gives an account of idiosyncratic responses among teachers. Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught:
128–132.
44 Vaughan and Yorke, I Can’t Believe It’s Not Better:The Paradox of NSS Scores for Art & Design.
45 I include women here as a minority in respect of having a minority position in terms of power in
society.
46 Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught, 112.
47 Elkins’ more recent book, Art Critiques: A Guide, does not change this view, but advises students on how
to best negotiate the challenges crits pose them.
48 Elkins describes a number of other ways crits can fail. Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught: 112–165.
49 www.youtube.com/watch?v=GKab0_8Bp2Y
50 www.youtube.com/watch?v=CqnzJ4omxoA
51 Ibid.
52 Singerman, Art Subjects: 211.
53 Elkins, Why Art Cannot Be Taught: 3.
54 Crippa, “From ‘Crit’ to ‘Lecture-Performance’”: 138.
55 Anthony, Design Juries on Trial.
56 Madge and Weinberger, Art Students Observed: 276.
57 See esp. Madge and Weinberger, Art Students Observed: 83–85, as well as the observations of students,
such as ‘Pam’ (124–127) and ‘Diana’ (151–154). There are many other suggestive passages. For example,
a tutor writes of another student, “Jean has not got very much talent or depth of character. Her work is
shallow and her attitude self-indulgent. One more mediocre art student” (128). Later, she is recorded as
thinking of making a life-size “double coffin,” with “herself in one side” (132).
58 Pollock, “Art, Art School, Culture: Individualism after the Death of the Artist.” For more on art school
education at this time and women, see Lisa Tickner, Hornsey 1968: The Art School Revolution (London:
Frances Lincoln, 2008): 96–99. The casual sexism of the teachers at Coventry is a related topic, and viv-
idly documented by Madge and Weinberger—although it is perhaps no worse than that seen in much of
the culture of the time. One female student is described by a staff member as “stolid, puddingy . . . [m]
ediocre certainly” (144). Another is “a nice girl, a serious girl even”: however, “[h]er work is diabolical”
(154). On the Pre-Diploma course (the precursor to present-day Foundation courses) at Coventry, male
students gained approval more often, and were more successful at gaining admission to diploma courses
(the precursor to present-day BA Fine Art courses) (36–38).
59 Rowles, Art Crits: 91–93.
60 Rachel Garfield, email message to the author, April 29, 2012.
61 This is so, even putting aside any adverse personal dynamics between individuals.Where those exist, the
situation can be further exacerbated.
62 Madge and Weinberger, Art Students Observed: 37–38.
63 O. C. Garza gives a vivid account of photographer Garry Winogrand’s teaching, which seems an exam-
ple of this; www.ocgarzaphotography.com
64 John Reardon has interviewed a range of artists working in German art schools about their teach-
ing practices in this tradition. John Reardon, Ch-ch-ch-changes: Artists Talk About Teaching (London:
Ridinghouse, 2009).
65 www.youtube.com/watch?v=cGBKcEhcraI
66 Concepts of art are not definitions of art. Definitions of art aim to provide necessary and sufficient con-
ditions for something to be a work of art. That is not something that concepts of art do, although they
are sometimes adapted to this purpose. For a survey of definitions of art, see Stephen Davies, Definitions
of Art (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991).
67 Arthur C. Danto, “The End of Art,” in Arthur C. Danto, The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1986): 115; Arthur C. Danto, After the End of Art (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1997): 47.The observation, at last taken roughly, is not original to Danto. Peter Bürger,
for instance, had earlier written of the “simultaneity of the radically disparate” in art. Peter Bürger,
Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans. Michael Shaw (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984): 63.
68 Soutter, “What Lies Beneath,” 179.

30
Crits, consensus, and criticality

69 It is worth adding that even the mere format of the crit goes some way to promoting pluralism. The
Downloaded By: 10.3.98.104 At: 11:00 10 Nov 2021; For: 9781315623412, chapter3, 10.4324/9781315623412-3

format provides a kind of stage or frame for the presentation of a plurality of views, giving each view
a kind of equality. The student’s awareness of the mere possibility of this—that a plurality of views may
exist, even if they are not in fact heard by the student—tends to reinforce the kind of pluralism I have
described.That is to say, even when crits fail to work as I have described, or they fail in the various ways
I have outlined, the crit’s format can still suggest and promote pluralism.
70 Hal Foster, “Against Pluralism,” in Hal Foster, Recodings: Art, Spectacle, Cultural Politics (Seattle, WA: Bay
Press, 1985): 24.
71 James Bohman, “Critical Theory,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta (Fall 2016
edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/critical-theory/
72 De Duve, “When Form Has Become Attitude—And Beyond”: 27. De Duve, writing in the mid-1990s,
was jaded about how this had developed in some prominent art schools: “‘critical attitude’ became just
that, an attitude, a stance, a pose, a contrivance” (ibid.). Nevertheless, critical theory has remained an
important feature of art school education since then.
73 CalArts is widely regarded for its incorporation of critical theory in its visual arts programs. See, for
example, Thornton, Seven Days in the Art World: 62–63.
74 Critical theorists may say that rational, well-informed interests will give priority to critical concerns.
But, even if this was so, interests need not be rationally determined, although I think that group mem-
bers should be able to give reasons (rational or otherwise) for their interests.
75 I think this also means that crits are not the best way to teach a thoroughgoing or programmatic critical
art practice. Critical practices are better taught in a masterclass environment where the focus needed
can be guaranteed. Staff and students can agree at the outset their focus on critical aims. Then texts can
be read, and student work considered, without the risk that the class’s attention will move off in other
directions. For an example on such lines, see Claire Bishop’s description of artist Tania Bruguera’s teach-
ing. Claire Bishop, Artificial Hells: Participatory Art and the Politics of Spectatorship (London: Verso, 2012):
ch. 9.

31

You might also like

pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy