Smith - Political Philosophy - Chapter 7
Smith - Political Philosophy - Chapter 7
Smith - Political Philosophy - Chapter 7
Philosophy
steven b. smith
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
109
110 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
the Ought to the Is. Machiavelli’s call is to take one’s bearings from the
“effectual truth of things”: do not look at what people say, look at what they
do. To be sure, Machiavelli focuses on key features of reality: murders, con-
spiracies, coups d’état. He is more interested in the actual evils that men do
than in the goods to which they aspire. You might even say that Machiavelli
takes delight in demonstrating, much to our chagrin, the space between our
loft y intentions and the actual consequences of our deeds.
And yet there is more—far more—to Machiavelli than the term “real-
ism” connotes. The term may be deeply misleading. Machiavelli speaks the
language of political innovation, renewal, and even redemption. The book
draws on the biblical language of prophecy, and Machiavelli presents him-
self as a prophet of liberation. In the passage cited above, he boldly an-
nounces his break with—indeed, his repudiation of—all those who have
come before him. He both replaces and combines elements from both Chris-
tianity and the Roman republic to create a new form of political organiza-
tion distinctly his own: the modern state. He is the architect of the modern
sovereign state that is given theoretical expression in the later writings of
Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau, to say nothing of contemporary writers on
both the left and the right, from Max Weber and Carl Schmitt to Antonio
Gramsci, the author of a book called The Modern Prince.
But look again. Consider the structure of the first three chapters. “All
states, all dominions that have held and do hold empire over men, are either
republics or principalities,” Machiavelli declares in the opening sentence of
chapter one (I/5). He then asserts that in this work he will deal only with prin-
cipalities, leaving the discussion of republics for elsewhere, one assumes his
Discourses. Having distinguished principalities and republics as the only two
kinds of regime worth mentioning, he goes on to distinguish between
two kinds of principality: hereditary princes like Lorenzo, who have ac-
quired their authority through tradition and blood line, and new princes.
But then Machiavelli goes on to tell the reader that the exclusive sub-
ject of the book will be the new prince—not Lorenzo at all, but precisely the
kind of prince who has achieved his authority through his own guile, force,
and cunning. The true addressee of the book must necessarily be the poten-
tial prince, someone with sufficient political audacity to create his own au-
thority. The Prince is addressed to a new kind of leader, one who is prepared
to create his own authority ex nihilo. But there is literally only one creator
who is able to create from scratch. Machiavelli’s prince seems to be an an-
swer to the creator described in the opening chapters of Genesis. The Prince
describes a new kind of political leader emancipated from traditional forms
of authority and virtue and endowed with a species of ambition, love of
glory, and elements of prophetic authority that we today might call “cha-
risma.”
that govern men’s lives. Machiavelli’s armed prophet is more than a gangster;
he is an educator.
Although it is characteristic of Machiavelli to talk tough—armed
prophets always conquer and the unarmed always lose—he clearly recog-
nizes that there are huge exceptions to this rule. The most obvious and im-
portant exception of an unarmed prophet conquering is Jesus Christ. Jesus
conquered by words alone, which helped to establish first a sect, then a reli-
gion, and eventually an empire. Words may well be a weapon as powerful as
a gun. And, then, what is Machiavelli himself but an archetypal unarmed
prophet? He controls no troops or territory. Yet he is clearly attempting to
conquer in large part through the transformation of our understanding of
good and evil, of virtue and vice. In order to make people obey, you must
first make them believe. Machiavelli’s prophetic prince must have many of
the qualities of a philosopher and a religious reformer.
Machiavelli’s point is that if you want liberty, you have to learn how not
to be good, at least as Christianity has defined goodness. The Christian vir-
tues of humility, turning the other cheek, and forgiveness of sins must be re-
jected if you want to do good as opposed to just be good. You have to learn
how to get your hands dirty. Between the innocence of the Christian and the
worldliness of Machiavelli’s new morality, there can be no reconciliation.
These are two incompatible moral positions. But Machiavelli goes further.
The safety and security enjoyed by the innocent, their freedom to live blame-
less lives and untroubled sleep, depends entirely upon the prince’s clear-eyed
and even ruthless use of power. The true statesman must be prepared to mix
a love of the common good, a love of his own people, with a streak of cruelty
that is often deemed essential for a great ruler in general. It is simply another
example of how moral goodness grows out of and requires a context of moral
evil. Machiavelli’s advice is clear: if you cannot accept the responsibilities
of political life, if you cannot accept the harsh necessities that may require
cruelty, deceit, and even murder, then get out of the way. Do not seek to
impose your own high-minded innocence—sometimes called justice—on
the requirements of statecraft, because it will only lead to ruin. In our era,
the presidency of Jimmy Carter is usually taken as Exhibit A of this confu-
sion of Christian humanitarianism with raison d’état.
In the philosophical literature this is known as the problem of dirty
hands, so called after a play, Les Mains sales, written by the French philoso-
pher Jean-Paul Sartre. The problem of dirty hands refers to the confl ict
between the harsh requirements of politics and the equally demanding de-
sire for moral purity, to keep the world at a distance. In Sartre’s play, which
takes place in a fictional eastern European country during World War II, a
communist resistance fighter named Hoederer upbraids an idealistic young
recruit who balks at the order to carry out a political assassination. The
communists are no different from members of any other party, Hoederer
explains. They will do whatever they have to do to achieve victory: “How you
cling to your purity, young man! How afraid you are to soil your hands! All
right, stay pure! What good will it do you? Why did you join us? Purity is an
idea for a yogi or a monk. Well, I have dirty hands. Right up to the elbows.
I’ve plunged them in filth and blood. But what do you hope? Do you think
anyone can govern innocently?”
Or take another example: Carol Reed’s great film The Third Man. There
an American innocent named Holly Martins comes to postwar Vienna to
join his boyhood friend and idol, Harry Lime, who, Martins discovers, is
Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding 117
deep inside a murderous black market racket. From a ferris wheel high
above the bombed-out city, they look down on the people below, and Harry
asks: “Would you really feel any pity if one of those dots stopped moving
forever? If I offered you twenty thousand pounds for every dot that stopped,
would you really, old man, tell me to keep my money, or would you calculate
how many dots you could afford to spare?” As they prepare to part, Harry
provides a speech that would have done Machiavelli proud: “Under the Bor-
gias they had warfare, terror, murder, and bloodshed, but they produced
Michelangelo, Leonardo da Vinci, and the Renaissance. In Switzerland they
had brotherly love—they had 500 years of democracy and peace, and what
did that produce? The cuckoo clock.”
Or take one more example: John Le Carré’s splendid Cold War thriller
The Spy Who Came in from the Cold. Here a British agent, Alec Lemas, car-
ries on an affair with an idealistic young Englishwoman who has joined the
Communist Party out of a belief in nuclear disarmament and world peace.
In the course of the story, the two are used to protect an East German agent
who has been turned by the English intelligence forces. After their unwitting
role in the plot is made clear, Lemas explains what the world of high espio-
nage is all about: “There’s only one law in this game, the expediency of tem-
porary alliances. What do you think spies are? Moral philosophers measuring
everything against the word of God or Karl Marx? They’re not! They’re just a
bunch of seedy squalid bastards like me: little men, drunkards, queers, hen-
pecked husbands, civil servants playing cowboys and Indians to brighten
their rotten little lives. Do you think they sit like monks in London balancing
right against wrong?”
These are all examples of what I would call faux Machiavellianism:
intellectuals engaging in tough talk to show that they really have lost their
idealism, the intellectual’s equivalent of losing one’s virginity. It suggests that
the world is divided between the strong and the weak, between realists who
see things the way they really are and the idealists who require the comfort
of moral illusions.
Machiavelli does not so much reject the idea of the good as redefine it.
He is continually speaking the language of virtue—actually virtù—a word
which retains the Latin root for the word “man” and which translates into
something like our term for manliness. What distinguishes Machiavelli’s
use of this term is that he seeks to locate it in certain extreme situations
such as political foundings, changes of regimes, and wars, both domestic
and foreign. What distinguishes Machiavelli from his predecessors is his
118 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
the other half. And in a famous image he compares fortuna to a raging cur-
rent or a flood, but says that virtù, using foresight, can create artificial bar-
riers like dams to control the uncontrollable and put in order what is by
nature chaotic. It follows that those who rely or depend too much on the
power of luck—like those people who live in perpetual hope that they will
purchase a winning lottery ticket—will come to ruin, while those who adapt
themselves to the times have a greater chance of success. This seems to be a
variation of the adage that fortune favors the prepared.
But Machiavelli goes further than this. Virtù is not simply a matter of
adaptation and adjustment to the circumstances. It is also a matter of forc-
ing the circumstances to adapt to you. There is a violent and aggressive as-
pect to Machiavelli’s idea of adapting to the occasion. “I judge this indeed,”
he writes, “that it is better to be impetuous than cautious because fortune is
a woman and it is necessary, if one wants to hold her down, to beat her and
strike her down” (XXV/101). In other words, fortune responds more easily
to audacity than to caution, to boldness and resoluteness than to modera-
tion. Machiavelli’s virtue is nothing if not a policy of preemption. Further-
more, Machiavelli tells the reader that such policies are more likely to find
favor among the young, who he says are “less cautious, more ferocious, and
command her [fortuna] with more audacity” (XXV/101).
Two Humors
What kind of government did Machiavelli think best? As he indicates at the
beginning of The Prince, there are two kinds of regimes: principalities and
republics. But each of these regimes is based on certain contrasting disposi-
tions or what he calls “humors.” “For in every city,” Machiavelli writes in
chapter 9, “two diverse humors are found, which arises from this: that the
people desire neither to be commanded nor oppressed by the great and the
great desire to command and oppress the people” (IX/39).
Machiavelli here uses a psychological, even quasi-medical term—
“humors” (umori)—to designate the two great classes of people on which
every state is based. Machiavelli’s theory of the two humors is reminiscent of
Plato’s account of the three classes of the soul, with one vivid exception: each
class in the city is bound to a “humor,” but neither humor is anchored in
reason. Every state is divided into two classes, the grandi, the rich and pow-
erful who wish to dominate, and the popolo, the common people who wish
merely to be left alone, who desire neither to rule nor be ruled. One might
122 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
expect the author of a book entitled The Prince to favor the great. Are not
these aristocratic goals of honor and glory precisely what Machiavelli has
been advocating?
Yet Machiavelli proceeds to deprecate radically the virtues of the no-
bility. “The end of the people,” he says, “is more decent than that of the
great, since the great want to oppress and the people want not to be op-
pressed” (IX/39). His advice seems to be that the prince should seek to build
his power base on the people rather than the nobles. Because of their ambi-
tion for power, the nobles will always be a threat to the prince, while a
prince who has the people for his base can rule with greater ease and confi-
dence. In an interesting reversal of the classical conception of politics, it is
the nobles who are here said to be fickle and unreliable, while the people are
more constant and stable. “The worst that a prince can expect from a hos-
tile people is to be abandoned by it,” Machiavelli writes, “but from the
great, when they are hostile, he must fear not only being abandoned but
also that they may move against him” (IX/39–40).
The main business of government consists, then, in knowing how to
control the great because they are always a potential source of conflict. The
prince must know how to chasten the ambition—to humble the pride, as it
were—of the great and powerful. This, as we will see, will be a major theme
in the political philosophy of Hobbes. The rule of the prince or sovereign
requires the ability to control ambition and to do so through selective poli-
cies of execution, public accusations, and political trials. Remember the
example of Remirro de Orco and how his execution left the people “satis-
fied and stupefied.” Here is a perfect example of how both to control the
ambitions of the nobles and to cater to the desires of the people.
Machiavelli’s prince, while not exactly a democrat, recognizes the es-
sential decency of the people and the need to keep their faith. By decency
Machiavelli seems to mean their absence of ambition, the absence of the de-
sire to dominate and command. But this decency is not the same as good-
ness. For there is a tendency on the part of the people to descend into what
Machiavelli deems “idleness” or license. The desire not to oppress others may
be decent, but at the same time the people must be taught how to defend their
liberty. Fifteen hundred years of Christianity have left men weak, without
the capacities to exercise political responsibility or the resources to defend
themselves from attack. Just as the prince must know how to control the
ambitions of the nobles, he must know how to strengthen the desires of
the common people.
Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding 123
be taught to value their liberty above all else. The most excellent princes of
the past were those, like Moses, who brought tablets of the law and prepared
their people for self-government. It is fitting that Machiavelli concludes The
Prince with a chapter calling upon his countrymen to emancipate them-
selves and to liberate Italy from foreign intruders.
Machiavelli’s Utopianism
Let me conclude this analysis of The Prince by considering what I want to
call Machiavelli’s utopianism. On the face of it, this term seems to be an
oxymoron. Doesn’t Machiavelli exhort us to consider only “the effectual
truth” of things, as opposed to imagined principalities, that is, to look at
what people do, not at what they say, at the Is rather than the Ought? Yet
despite his avowed rejection of ancient utopianism, Machiavelli tells readers
to take as their models the greatest founders of peoples and nations, that
these founders must be endowed with certain charismatic or prophetic prop-
erties, and that such people have come to power not through force alone but
through their own virtù. These views provide evidence for an idealistic, even
utopian, strain in Machiavelli’s thought.
Nowhere is Machiavelli’s idealism more on display than in the final
chapter of The Prince, “Exhortation to Seize Italy and Free Her from the
Barbarians.” This chapter has probably given rise to more discussion than
any other part of the book. Why at the end of what to many readers seems
no more than a technical, how-to manual on politics does Machiavelli con-
clude with a passionate call for liberation? Some readers even believe there
was a gap of several years between the composition of the first twenty-five
chapters of the book, written in 1513, and the final chapter. For such readers
the sections of the final chapter that speak of the liberation from the bar-
barians and the call for the redemption of Italy could only have been written
around the year 1518.
Far from an afterthought, these reflections were an obsession of Ma-
chiavelli’s throughout all of his writings. His answer to the weakness and
disunity of the Italian states was the myth of the prince: the figure personi-
fying virtù, strength, and charisma whose redemptive power could point
the way to a new Rome. In fact the opportunity for such a prince to exhibit
real virtù is dependent on the current degradation of society, just as “it was
necessary for anyone wanting to see the virtue of Moses that the people of
Israel be enslaved in Egypt” (XXVI/102). The prophet and his people are
linked. There is no such thing as a prophet without a people, or redemption
Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding 125
Machiavelli’s Discourses
For serious students of Machiavelli, the Discourses on Livy—the full title of
the book is actually Discourses on the First Ten Books of Titus Livy—has al-
ways been considered his most important work. In part because of its length
and the organization of its subject matter, it is not read nearly so frequently
as The Prince. In fact the relation between the two books has been some-
thing of an enigma for generations of readers.
The Prince was published in 1513, the year after Machiavelli was ex-
pelled from public office. The date of the Discourses is more difficult to
establish. The best guess is that it was written sometime between the years
1513 and 1517, although it was not published until 1531, four years after Ma-
chiavelli’s death. Even so, he seems to have been working on both books
simultaneously. In the second chapter of The Prince, he makes what seems
to be an allusion to the Discourses. He remarks that The Prince will deal
only with principalities and that he has saved his discussion of republics for
elsewhere. That is commonly believed to be a reference to the Discourses.
126 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
trees in these gardens that Machiavelli first read sections of his tribute to
republics to his Medicean audience!
Yet something seems amiss. Machiavelli is writing a book in praise of
republics but dedicates it to two members of the aristocracy, who by their
birth, education, and upbringing were bound to be deeply hostile to the
cause of republican government. To be sure, Machiavelli’s best friends were
members of this class. The two best known were his friend Francesco Vettori,
the Florentine ambassador to Rome with whom he shared a lengthy corre-
spondence, and the historian Francesco Guicciardini. What was he trying to
accomplish? What seems clear is that he intended the Discourses as a kind of
educational treatise for these young aristocrats. He presents himself as a
teacher, an educator. The length and academic form of the work—a commen-
tary on an ancient historian—would presumably have appealed to the two
young Florentine humanists. In any case Machiavelli knows how to flatter his
readers: “I have chosen to dedicate these, my discourses, to you in preference
to all others; both because, in doing so, I seem to be showing some gratitude
for benefits received, and also because I seem in this to be departing from
the usual practice of authors, which has always been to dedicate their works
to some prince and blinded by ambition and avarice, to praise him for all his
virtuous qualities when they ought to have blamed him for all manner of
shameful deeds” (Dedication/201–2).
In his dedication Machiavelli seems to be engaged in an act of self-
criticism, repudiating his dedication of The Prince to Lorenzo. “So to avoid
this mistake,” he continues, “I have chosen not those who are princes, but
those . . . who deserve to be . . . those who know how to govern a kingdom,
not those who, without knowing how, actually govern one” (Dedication/202).
Machiavelli enjoys underscoring the youth of his audience. In fact book 1 of
the Discourses ends with a reference to “very young men” who won triumphs
for Rome. In the dedication and throughout the book, Machiavelli presents
himself as a guide to the young.
Of course, Machiavelli exaggerates. If the young readers to whom the
work is dedicated already knew how to govern a kingdom, then his act of
writing the Discourses would appear superfluous. You don’t write a book of
this length to tell people what they already know. Machiavelli insinuates
himself into his readers’ good graces in order to gain their confidence. His
purpose, I want to suggest, is to win over this class to the cause of republi-
canism, to show them the well-ordered republic so that they might create
the republic that might yet be. The Discourses brings out Machiavelli’s ambi-
tion and idealism. His desire is nothing less than to create a new Rome.
128 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
dents that are contained in it, but never think of imitating them, since they
hold them to be not merely difficult but impossible of imitation, as if the
heavens, the sun, the elements of man had in their motion, their order, and
their potency, become different from what they used to be” (Preface/206).
Machiavelli wants to encourage his readers not just to idly and eclec-
tically reflect on what they read but to actively imitate the great deeds of
their ancient ancestors. It is this, he says, that has led him to write a com-
mentary on Livy. Indeed, to do full justice to the Discourses one would need
to read with constant reference to Livy and to Machiavelli’s many other
sources. To be sure, the Discourses is no ordinary commentary. Machiavelli
uses Livy promiscuously, and for long stretches of time he disappears alto-
gether from Machiavelli’s text. He hopes to improve upon Livy and therefore
to improve upon Rome. Machiavelli will not confine himself to the study of
his ancient sources alone but will constantly be “comparing ancient with
modern events” in order to draw “practical lessons” from them. Let us con-
sider some of these lessons.
than any other institution, that has kept Italy weak and divided. “The rea-
son why Italy is not in the same position,” he continues, “why there is not
one republic or one prince ruling there is due entirely to the Church”
(I.12/245). So far Machiavelli sounds like a critic of papal abuses of power,
a complaint quite common and even conventional in his day.
It is not until considerably later that Machiavelli lets the cat out of the
bag. In book 2, chapter 2, he asks the question, why it is that the ancients
seemed more fond of liberty than the moderns? The difference, he answers,
is due to the difference between our religion and theirs. It is not the corrup-
tion of Christianity that is responsible for the loss of liberty and the dis-
unity of Italy; the problem goes back to the founding principles themselves.
Machiavelli then goes on to provide a sharp and devastating series of con-
trasts: “Our religion has glorified humble and contemplative men, rather
than men of action. It has assigned as man’s highest good humility, abne-
gation, and contempt for mundane things, whereas the other identified it
with magnanimity, bodily strength, and everything else that conduces to
make men very bold. And if our religion demands that in you there be
strength, what it asks for is strength to suffer rather than strength to do bold
things” (II.2/364). Here is where Machiavelli drops his bombshell:
What is Machiavelli saying here, and why does he wait until almost
the midpoint in the book to announce it? What does he want us to do?
Rather than simply advocating the reform of Christianity, he seems to be
advocating the creation of a wholly new religion to replace it, in the way
that Christianity once replaced the pagan Roman religion. The founder of a
136 Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding
new republic needs to be the founder of a new religion; he should follow the
example of Numa and create new rites and ceremonies from scratch. He will
be a transformative, even a redemptive, leader such as Machiavelli speaks
about in the final chapter of The Prince. But what would such a Machiavel-
lian civil religion look like? Here Machiavelli is tantalizingly and, I suspect,
deliberately obscure. One cannot legislate these matters in advance. This is
why the founder needs constantly to read history: to see what others have
done in the past so as to discover what to do and what to avoid and how to
make not only a new Rome but a new Jerusalem.
Let every American, every lover of liberty, every well wisher to his
posterity, swear by the blood of the Revolution, never to violate in
the least particular, the laws of the country; and never to tolerate
their violation by others. As the patriots of seventy-six did to the
support of the Declaration of Independence, so to the support of
the Constitution and Laws, let every American pledge his life, his
property and his sacred honor;—let every man remember that to
violate the law, is to trample on the blood of his father, and to tear
the character of his own, and his children’s liberty. Let reverence
for the laws, be breathed by every American mother, to the lisping
babe, that prattles on her lap—let it be taught in schools, in semi-
naries, and in colleges;—let it be written in Primmers, spelling
books, and in Almanacs;—let it be preached from the pulpit, pro-
claimed in legislative halls, and enforced in courts of justice. And,
in short, let it become the political religion of the nation; and let
the old and the young, the rich and the poor, the grave and the
gay, of all sexes and tongues, and colors and conditions, sacrifice
unceasingly upon its altars.
Machiavelli and the Art of Political Founding 139