Wiley Philosophy & Public Affairs: This Content Downloaded From 200.89.140.130 On Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
Wiley Philosophy & Public Affairs: This Content Downloaded From 200.89.140.130 On Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
Wiley Philosophy & Public Affairs: This Content Downloaded From 200.89.140.130 On Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265298?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Wiley is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy &
Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
MICHAEL W. DOYLE Kant, Liberal Legacies,
and Foreign Affairs*
* This is the first half of a two-part article. The article has benefited from the extensive
criticisms of William Ascher, Richard Betts, William Bundy, Joseph Carens, Felix Gilbert,
Amy Gutmann, Don Herzog, Stanley Hoffman, Marion Levy, Judith Shklar, Mark Uhlig,
and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs. I have also tried to take into account
suggestions from Fouad Ajami, Steven David, Tom Farer, Robert Gilpin, Ernest van den
Haag, Germaine Hoston, Robert Jervis, Donald Kagan, Robert Keohane, John Rawls, Nich-
olas Rizopoulos, Robert W. Tucker, Richard Ullman, and the members of a Special Seminar
at the Lehrman Institute, February 22, I983. The essay cannot be interpreted as a consensus
of their views.
i. The liberal-patriotic view was reiterated by President Reagan in a speech before the
British Parliament on 8 June I982. There he proclaimed "a global campaign for democratic
development." This "crusade for freedom" will be the latest campaign in a tradition that,
he claimed, began with the Magna Carta and stretched in this century through two world
wars and a cold war. He added that liberal foreign policies have shown "restraint" and
"peaceful intentions" and that this crusade will strengthen the prospects for a world at
peace (New York Times, 9 June I982). The skeptical scholars and diplomats represent the
predominant Realist interpretation of international relations. See ns. 4 and I 2 for references.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
206 Philosophy & Public Affairs
II
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
207 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
But the dilemma within liberalism is how to reconcile the three sets
of liberal rights. The right to private property, for example, can conflict
with equality of opportunity and both rights can be violated by democratic
legislation. During the i8o years since Kant wrote, the liberal tradition
has evolved two high roads to individual freedom and social order; one
is laissez-faire or "conservative" liberalism and the other is social welfare,
or social democratic, or "liberal" liberalism. Both reconcile these conflict-
ing rights (though in differing ways) by successfully organizing free
individuals into a political order.
The political order of laissez-faire and social welfare liberals is marked
by a shared commitment to four essential institutions. First, citizens
possess juridical equality and other fundamental civic rights such as
freedom of religion and the press. Second, the effective sovereigns of the
state are representative legislatures deriving their authority from the con-
sent of the electorate and exercising their authority free from all restraint
2. Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace" (I795) in The Philosophy of Kant, ed. Carl J.
Friedrich (New York: Modem Library, I949), p. 453.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
208 Philosophy & Public Affairs
apart from the requirement that basic civic rights be preserved.3 Most
pertinently for the impact of liberalism on foreign affairs, the state is
subject to neither the external authority of other states nor to the internal
authority of special prerogatives held, for example, by monarchs or mil-
itary castes over foreign policy. Third, the economy rests on a recognition
of the rights of private property, including the ownership of means of
production. Property is justified by individual acquisition (for example,
by labor) or by social agreement or social utility. This excludes state
socialism or state capitalism, but it need not exclude market socialism or
various forms of the mixed economy. Fourth, economic decisions are
predominantly shaped by the forces of supply and demand, domestically
and internationally, and are free from strict control by bureaucracies.
In order to protect the opportunity of the citizen to exercise freedom,
laissez-faire liberalism has leaned toward a highly constrained role for
the state and a much wider role for private property and the market. In
order to promote the opportunity of the citizen to exercise freedom, wel-
fare liberalism has expanded the role of the state and constricted the role
of the market.4 Both, nevertheless, accept these four institutional re-
3. The actual rights of citizenship have often been limited by slavery or male suffrage,
but liberal regimes harbored no principle of opposition to the extension of juridical equality;
in fact, as pressure was brought to bear they progressively extended the suffrage to the
entire population. By this distinction, nineteenth-century United States was liberal; twen-
tieth-century South Africa is not. See Samuel Huntington, American Politics: the Promise
of Disharmony (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 198I).
4. The sources of classic, laissez-faire liberalism can be found in Locke, the Federalist
Papers, Kant, and Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books,
I974). Expositions of welfare liberalism are in the work of the Fabians and John Rawls,
A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, I971). Amy Gutmann,
Liberal Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, I980), discusses variants of
liberal thought.
Uncomfortably parallelling each of the high roads are "low roads" that, while achieving
certain liberal values, fail to reconcile freedom and order. An overwhelming terror of anarchy
and a speculation on preserving property can drive laissez-faire liberals to support a law-
and-order authoritarian rule that sacrifices democracy. Authoritarianism to preserve order
is the argument of Hobbes's Leviathan. It also shapes the argument of right wing liberals
who seek to draw a distinction between "authoritarian" and "totalitarian" dictatorships. The
justification sometimes advanced by liberals for the former is that they can be temporary
and educate the population into an acceptance of property, individual rights, and, eventually,
representative government. See Jeane Kirkpatrick, "Dictatorships and Double Standards,"
Commentary 68 (November I979): 34-45. Complementarily, when social inequalities are
judged to be extreme, the welfare liberal can argue that establishing (or reestablishing)
the foundations of liberal society requires a nonliberal method of reform, a second low road
of redistributing authoritarianism. Aristide Zolberg reports a "liberal left" sensibility among
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
209 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
TABLE I
Liberal Regimes
and the Pacific Union Total
Period (By date "liberal")a Number
U.S. scholars of African politics that justified reforming dictatorship. (See One Party Gov-
ernment in the Ivory Coast [Princeton: Princeton University Press, I9691, p. viii.) And the
argument of "reforming autocracy" can be found in J. S. Mill's defense of colonialism in
India.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2IO Philosophy & Public Affairs
TABLE I (cont.)
Liberal Regimes
and the Pacific Union Total
Period (By date "liberal")a Number
I850-I900 Switzerland, I3
the United States,
Belgium, Great Britain,
Netherlands
Piedmont - i86i, Italy i86i -
Denmark -i866
Sweden I864-
Greece I864-
Canada I867-
France I87I-
Argentina i88o-
Chile I89I-
I900-I945 Switzerland, 29
the United States,
Great Britain,
Sweden, Canada
Greece -19II, I928-I936
Italy -I922
Belgium -I940;
Netherlands -I940;
Argentina -I943
France -I940
Chile -I924, I932
Australia I9OI-
Norway I905-I940
New Zealand I907-
Colombia I9I0-I949
Denmark I9I4-I940
Poland I9I7-I935
Latvia I922-I934
Gernany I9I8-I932
Austria I9I8-I934
Estonia I919-I934
Finland I9I9-
Uruguay I9I9-
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2II Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreiqn Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
212 Philosophy & Public Affairs
TABLE I (cont.)
Liberal Regimes
and the Pacific Union Total
Period (By date "liberal")a Number
Sen,egal I963-
Malaysia I963-
South Korea I963-I972
Botswana I 966-
Singapore I965-
Greece I975-
Portugal 1976-
Spain I 978-
Dominican Republic 1978-
a. I have drawn up this approximate list of "Liberal Regimes" according to the four
institutions described as essential: market and private property economies; polities that are
externally sovereign; citizens who possess juridical rights; and "republican" (whether re-
publican or monarchical), representative, government. This latter includes the requirement
that the legislative branch have an effective role in public policy and be formally and
competitively, either potentially or actually, elected. Furthermore, I have taken into account
whether male suffrage is wide (that is, 30 percent) or open to "achievement" by inhabitants
(for example, to poll-tax payers or householders) of the national or metropolitan territory.
Female suffrage is granted within a generation of its being demanded; and representative
government is intemally sovereign (for example, including and especially over military and
foreign affairs) as well as stable (in existence for at least three years).
Sources: Arthur Banks and W. Overstreet, eds., The Political Handbook of the World,
I980 (New York: McGraw-Hill, I980); Foreign and Commonwealth Office, A Year Book
of the Commonwealth I980 (London: HMSO, I980); Europa Yearbook, I98I (London:
Europa, I98i); W. L. Langer, An Encyclopedia of World History (Boston: Houghton-Mifflin,
I968); Department of State, Country Reports on Human Rights Practices (Washington,
DC: Government Printing Office, ig8i); and Freedom at Issue, no. 54 (Jan.-Feb. I980).
b. There are domestic variations within these liberal regimes. For example, Switzerland
was liberal only in certain cantons; the United States was liberal only north of the Mason-
Dixon line until I865, when it became liberal throughout. These lists also exclude ancient
"republics," since none appear to fit Kant's criteria. See Stephen Holmes, "Aristippus in
and out of Athens," American Political Science Review 73, no. I (March 1979).
c. Selected list, excludes liberal regimes with populations less than one million.
5. Fred Hirsch, The Social Limits to Growth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
'977).
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2I3 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
III
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
214 Philosophy & Public Affairs
TABLE 2
* The table is reprinted by permnission from Melvin Small and J. David Sin
to Arms (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications, I982), pp. 79-80. This is a partial list of
international wars fought between i8i6 and I980. In Appendices A and B of Resort to
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
215 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
Anns, Small and Singer identify a total of 575 wars in this period; but approximately 159
of them appear to be largely domestic, or civil wars.
This definition of war excludes covert interventions, some of which have been directed
by liberal regimes against other liberal regimes. One example is the United States' effort
to destabilize the Chilean election and Allende's government. Nonetheless, it is significant
(as will be apparent below) that such interventions are not pursued publicly as acknowl-
edged policy. The covert destabilization campaign against Chile is recounted in U.S. Con-
gress, Senate, Select Committee to Study Governmental Operations with Respect to In-
telligence Activities, Covert Action in Chile, 1963-73, 94th Congress, Ist Session (Washington,
DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1975).
The argument of this article (and this list) also excludes civil wars. Civil wars differ from
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2I6 Philosophy & Public Affairs
intemational wars not in the ferocity of combat but in the issues that engender them. Two
nations that could abide one another as independent neighbors separated by a border might
well be the fiercest of enemies if forced to live together in one state, jointly deciding how
to raise and spend taxes, choose leaders, and legislate fundamental questions of value.
Notwithstanding these differences, no civil wars that I recall upset the argument of liberal
pacification.
8. Imperial Gennany is a difficult case. The Reichstag was not only elected by universal
male suffrage but, by and large, the state ruled under the law, respecting the civic equality
and rights of its citizens. Moreover, Chancellor Bismarck began the creation of a social
welfare society that served as an inspiration for similar reforms in liberal regimes. However,
the constitutional relations between the imperial executive and the representative legis-
lature were sufficiently complex that various practices, rather than constitutional theory,
determined the actual relation between the government and the citizenry. The emperor
appointed and could dismiss the chancellor. Although the chancellor was responsible to
the Reichstag, a defeat in the Reichstag did not remove him nor did the government
absolutely depend on the Reichstag for budgetary authority. In practice, Germany was a
liberal state under republican law for domestic issues. But the emperor's direct authority
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
217 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
Statistically, war between any two states (in any single year or othe:
short period of time) is a low probability event. War between any tw(
adjacent states, considered over a long period of time, may be somewha
more probable. The apparent absence of war among the more clearlb
liberal states, whether adjacent or not, for almost two hundred year,
thus has some significance. Politically more significant, perhaps, is that
when states are forced to decide, by the pressure of an impinging worlc
war, on which side of a world contest they will fight, liberal states winc
up all on the same side, despite the real complexity of the historical
economic and political factors that affect their foreign policies. An(
historically, we should recall that medieval and early modern Europe
were the warring cockpits of states, wherein France and England anc
the Low Countries engaged in near constant strife. Then in the latc
eighteenth century there began to emerge liberal regimes. At first hesitan
and confused, and later clear and confident as liberal regimes gainec
deeper domestic foundations and longer international experience, a pa
cific union of these liberal states became established.
over the army, the army's effective independence from the minimal authority of the War
Ministry, and the emperor's active role in foreign affairs (including the influential separate
channel to the emperor through the military attaches) together with the tenuous consti-
tutional relationship between the chancellor and the Reichstag made imperial Germany a
state divorced from the control of its citizenry in foreign affairs.
This authoritarian element not only influenced German foreign policymaking, but also
shaped the international political environment (a lack of trust) the Reich faced and the
domestic political environment that defined the government's options and capabilities (the
weakness of liberal opinion as against the exceptional influence of junker militaristic na-
tionalism). Thus direct influence on policy was but one result of the authoritarian element.
Nonetheless, significant and strife-generating episodes can be directly attributed to this
element. They include Tirpitz's approach to Wilhelm II to obtain the latter's sanction for
a veto of Chancellor Bethmann-Hollweg's proposals for a naval agreement with Britain
(I909). Added to this was Wilhelm's personal assurances of full support to the Austrians
early in the Sarajevo Crisis and his, together with Moltke's, erratic pressure on the Chan-
cellor throughout July and August of I9I4, which helped destroy whatever coherence
German diplomacy might otherwise have had, and which led one Austrian official to ask,
"Who rules in Berlin? Moltke or Bethmann?" (Gordon Craig, The Politics of the Prussian
Army [New York: Oxford University Press, I9641, pp. xxviii and chap. 6). For an excellent
account of Bethmann's aims and the constraints he encountered, see Konrad H. Jarausch,
"The Illusion of Limited War: Chancellor Bethmann-Hollweg's Calculated Risk, July I9I4,"
Central European History 2 (I969).
The liberal sources of Italy's decision are pointed out in R. Vivarelli's review of Hugo
Butler's Gaetano Salvemini und die Italienische Politik vor dem Ersten Weltkrieg in the
Journal of Modern History 52, no. 3 (September I980): 54I.
The quotation from President Wilson is from Woodrow Wilson, The Messages and Papers
of Woodrow Wilson, ed. Albert Shaw (New York: The Review of Reviews, I924), p. 378.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2I8 Philosophy & Public Affairs
9. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: Penguin, I980), I, chap. I3, 62; p. i86.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
219 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
is not rational (first best) for either individually if there is some chance
that the other will back down first (the game of "chicken").Io
Specific wars therefore arise from fear as a state seeking to avoid a
surprise attack decides to attack first; from competitive emulation as
states lacking an imposed international hierarchy of prestige struggle to
establish their place; and from straightforward conflicts of interest that
escalate into war because there is no global sovereign to prevent states
from adopting that ultimate form of conflict resolution. Herein lie Thu-
cydides's trinity of "security, honor, and self-interest" and Hobbes's "dif-
fidence," "glory," and "competition" that drive states to conflict in the
international state of war.II
Finding that all states, including liberal states, do engage in war, the
Realist concludes that the effects of differing domestic regimes (whether
liberal or not) are overridden by the international anarchy under which
all states live.I2 Thus Hobbes does not bother to distinguish between
"some council or one man" when he discusses the sovereign. Differing
domestic regimes do affect the quantity of resources available to the state
as Rousseau (an eighteenth-century Realist) shows in his discussion of
Poland, and Morgenthau (a twentieth-century Realist) demonstrates in
his discussion of morale. 13 But the ends that shape the international state
of war are decreed for the Realist by the anarchy of the international
order and the fundamental quest for power that directs the policy of all
States, irrespective of differences in their domestic regimes. As Rousseau
argued, international peace therefore depends on the abolition of inter-
national relations either by the achievement of a world state or by a radical
isolationism (Corsica). Realists judge neither to be possible.
io. Robert Jervis, "Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma," World Politics 30, no. I
(January I978).
i I. Thucydides, The Peloponnesian Wars, trans. Rex Warner (Baltimore, MD: Penguin
Books, I954) 1:76; and Hobbes, Leviathan, I, chap. I3, 6i, p. I85. The coincidence of
views is not accidental; Hobbes translated Thucydides. And Hobbes's portrait of the state
of nature appears to be drawn from Thucydides's account of the revolution in Corcyra.
I2. Kenneth N. Waltz, Man, the State, and War (New York: Columbia University Press,
I954, I959), pp. I20-23; and see his Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley, I979). The classic sources of this form of Realism are Hobbes and, more
particularly, Rousseau's "Essay on St. Pierre's Peace Project" and his "State of War" in A
Lasting Peace (London: Constable, I9I7), E. H. Carr's The Twenty Year's Crisis: 1919-
1939 (London: Macmillan & Co., I951), and the works of Hans Morgenthau.
I3. Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Government of Poland, trans. Willmoore Kendall (New
York: Bobbs-Merrill, I972); and Hans Morgenthan, Politics Among Nations (New York:
Alfred A. Knopf, I967), pp. I32-35.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
220 Philosophy & Public Affairs
I4. Hobbes, "De Cive," The English Works of Thomas Hobbes (London: J. Bohn, I84I),
2: I 66-67.
I5. Ibid., p. I7I.
I6. Jervis, "Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma," pp. I72-86.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
221 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
I7. Robert H. Jackson and Carl G. Rosberg, "Why West Africa's Weak States Persist,"
World Politics 35, no. I (October I982).
i8. Interpreted from Michael Haas, International Conflict (New York: Bobbs-Merrill,
1974), pp. 8o-8I, 457-58.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
222 Philosophy & Public Affairs
ig. Jervis, "Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma," pp. i86-2IO, 2I2. Jervis examines
incentives for cooperation, not the existence or sources of peace.
20. There is a rich contemporary literature devoted to explaining international cooperation
and integration. Karl Deutsch's Political Community and the North Atlantic Area (Prince-
ton: Princeton University Press, I957) develops the idea of a "pluralistic security com-
munity" that bears a resemblance to the "pacific union," but Deutsch limits it geographically
and finds compatibility of values, mutual responsiveness, and predictability of behavior
among decision-makers as its essential foundations. These are important but their particular
content, liberalism, appears to be more telling. Joseph Nye in Peace in Parts (Boston: Little,
Brown & Co., I97I) steps away from the geographic limits Deutsch sets and focuses on
levels of development; but his analysis is directed toward explaining integration-a more
intensive form of cooperation than the pacific union.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
223 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
attributes nor historic alliances or friendships can account for the wide
reach of the liberal peace. The peace extends as far as, and no further
than, the relations among liberal states, not including nonliberal states
in an otherwise liberal region (such as the north Atlantic in the I930s)
nor excluding liberal states in a nonliberal region (such as Central Amer-
ica or Africa).
At this level, Raymond Aron has identified three types of interstate
peace: empire, hegemony, and equilibrium.21 An empire generally suc-
ceeds in creating an internal peace, but this is not an explanation of peace
among independent liberal states. Hegemony can create peace by over-
awing potential rivals. Although far from perfect and certainly precarious,
United States hegemony, as Aron notes, might account for the interstate
peace in South America in the postwar period during the height of the
cold war conflict. However, the liberal peace cannot be attributed merely
to effective international policing by a predominant hegemon-Britain in
the nineteenth century, the United States in the postwar period. Even
though a hegemon might well have an interest in enforcing a peace for
the sake of commerce or investments or as a means of enhancing its
prestige or security; hegemons such as seventeenth-century France were
not peace-enforcing police, and the liberal peace persisted in the interwar
period when international society lacked a predominant hegemonic power.
Moreover, this explanation overestimates hegemonic control in both pe-
riods. Neither England nor the United States was able to prevent direct
challenges to its interests (colonial competition in the nineteenth century,
Middle East diplomacy and conflicts over trading with the enemy in the
postwar period). Where then was the capacity to prevent all armed con-
flicts between liberal regimes, many of which were remote and others
strategically or economically insignificant? Liberal hegemony and lead-
ership are important (see Section V below), but they are not sufficient
to explain a liberal peace.
Peace through equilibrium (the multipolar classical balance of power
or the bipolar "cold war") also draws upon prudential sources of peace.
2i. Raymond Aron, Peace and War (New York: Praeger, I968) pp. I5I-54. Progress and
peace through the rise and decline of empires and hegemonies has been a classic theme.
Lucretius suggested that they may be part of a more general law of nature: "Augescunt
aliae gentes, aliae miniuntur/Inque brevis spatio mutantur saecula animantum,/Et quasi
cursores vitai lampada tradunt." [Some peoples wax and others wane/And in a short space
the order of living things is changed/And like runners hand on the torch of life.] De Rer.
Nat. ii, 77-79.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
224 Philosophy & Public Affairs
22. Kenneth Waltz, Theory of International Politics, chap. 8; and Edward Gulick, Eu-
rope's Classical Balance of Power (New York: Norton, I967), chap. 3.
One of the most thorough collective investigations of the personal, societal, and inter-
national systemic sources of war has been the Correlates of War Project. See especially
Melvin Small and J. David Singer, Resort to Arms (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, I982) for a more
comprehensive list and statistical analysis of wars. J. David Singer ("Accounting for Inter-
national War: The State of the Discipline," Journal of Peace Research i8, no. I [i98i])
drew the following conclusions: "The exigencies of survival in an international system of
such inadequate organization and with so pervasively dysfunctional a culture require rel-
atively uniform response (p. ii). . . . domestic factors are negligible;" war "cannot be
explained on the basis of relatively invariant phenomena" (p. i).
Michael Haas, International Conflict, discovers that, at the systemic level, "collective
security, stratification, and hegemonization systems are likely to avoid a high frequency in
violent outputs" (p. 453); but "no single [causal] model was entirely or even largely sat-
isfactory" (p. 452). At the social level, war correlates with variables such as: "bloc promi-
nence, military mobilizations, public perceptions of hostility toward peoples of other coun-
tries, a high proportion of gross national product devoted to military expenditures . . ." (p.
46I). These variables appear to describe rather than explain war. A cluster analysis he
performs associates democracy, development, and sustained modernization with the ex-
istence of peaceful countries (pp. 464-65). But these factors do not correlate with pacifi-
cation duing the period i8i6-i965 according to M. Small and J. D. Singer, "The War
Proneness of Democatic Regimes," Jerusalem Journal of International Relations 5o, no.
4 (Summer I976).
Their conclusions follow, I think, from their homogenization of war and from their attempt
to explain all wars, in which a myriad of states have engaged. I attempt to explain an
interstate peace, which only liberal regimes, a particular type of state and society, have
succeeded in establishing.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
225 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
IV
23. The incompatibility of democracy and war is forcefully asserted by Paine in The
Rights of Man. The connection between liberal capitalism, democracy, and peace is argued
by, among others, Joseph Schumpeter in Imperialism and Social Classes (New York: Me-
ridian, I955); and Montesquieu, Spirit of the Laws I, bk. 2o, chap. i. This literature is
surveyed and analyzed by Albert Hirschman, "Rival Interpretations of Market Society:
Civilizing, Destructive, or Feeble?" Journal of Economic Literature 2o (December i 982).
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
226 Philosophy & Public Affairs
24. Two classic sources that examine Kant's international theory from a Realist per-
spective are Stanley Hoffmann, "Rousseau on War and Peace" in the State of War (New
York: Praeger, I965) and Kenneth Waltz, "Kant, Liberalism, and War," American Political
Science Review 56, no. 2 (June i962). I have benefited from their analysis and from those
of Karl Friedrich, Inevitable Peace (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, I948);
F. H. Hinsley, Power and the Pursuit of Peace (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
I967), chap. 4; W. B. Gallie, Philosophers of Peace and War (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, I978), chap. i; and particularly Patrick Riley, Kant's Political Philosophy
(Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield, I983). But some of the conclusions of this article
differ markedly from theirs.
Kant's republican constitution is described in Kant, "Perpetual Peace," The Philosophy
of Kant, p. 437 and analyzed by Riley, Kant's Political Philosophy, chap. 5.
25. Kant, "Universal History," The Philosophy of Kant, p. I 23. The pacific union follows
a process of "federalization" such that it "can be realized by a gradual extension to all
states, leading to eternal peace." This interpretation contrasts with those cited in n. 24. I
think Kant meant that the peace would be established among liberal regimes and would
expand as new liberal regimes appeared. By a process of gradual extension the peace would
become global and then perpetual; the occasion for wars with nonliberals would disappear
as nonliberal regimes disappeared.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
227 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
or state of nations. The first is insufficient; the second and third are
impossible or potentially tyrannical. Kant develops no organizational em-
bodiment of this treaty, and presumably he does not find institutionali-
zation necessary. He appears to have in mind a mutual nonaggression
pact, perhaps a collective security agreement, and the cosmopolitan law
set forth in the Third Definitive Article.26
The Third Definitive Article of the Eternal Peace establishes a cos-
mopolitan law to operate in conjunction with the pacific union. The
cosmopolitan law "shall be limited to conditions of universal hospitality."
In this he calls for the recognition of the "right of a foreigner not to be
treated with hostility when he arrives upon the soil of another [country],"
which "does not extend further than to the conditions which enable them
[the foreigners] to attempt the developing of intercourse [commerce] with
the old inhabitants." Hospitality does not require extending either the
right to citizenship to foreigners or the right to settlement, unless the
foreign visitors would perish if they were expelled. Foreign conquest and
plunder also find no justification under this right. Hospitality does appear
to include the right of access and the obligation of maintaining the op-
portunity for citizens to exchange goods and ideas, without imposing the
obligation to trade (a voluntary act in all cases under liberal constitu-
tions).27
Kant then explains each of the three definitive articles for a liberal
peace. In doing so he develops both an account of why liberal states do
maintain peace among themselves and of how it will (by implication, has)
come about that the pacific union will expand. His central claim is that
a natural evolution will produce "a harmony from the very disharmony
of men against their will. "28
26. Kant's "Pacific Union," the foedus pacificum, is thus neither a pactum pacis (a single
peace treaty) nor a civitas gentium (a world state). He appears to have anticipated something
like a less formally institutionalized League of Nations or United Nations. One could argue
that these two institutions in practice worked for liberal states and only for liberal states.
But no specifically liberal "pacific union" was institutionalized. Instead liberal states have
behaved for the past i8o years as if such a Kantian pacific union and treaty of Perpetual
Peace had been signed. This follows Riley's views of the legal, not the organizational,
character of the foedus pacificum.
27. Kant, "Perpetual Peace," pp. 444-47.
28. Kant, the fourth principle of "The Idea for a Universal History" in The Philosophy of
Kant, p. I20. Interestingly, Kant's three sources of peace (republicanism, respect, and
commerce) parallel quite closely Aristotle's three sources of friendship (goodness, pleasure
or appreciation, and utility). See Nicomachean Ethics, bk. 8, chap. 3, trans. J.A. K. Thomson
(Baltimore, MD: Penguin, I955).
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
228 Philosophy & Public Affairs
29. The "Prussian Model" suggests the connection between insecurity, war, and au-
thoritarianism. See The Anglo-American Tradition in Foreign Affairs, ed. Arnold Wolfers
and Laurence Martin (New Haven: Yale University Press, I956), "Introduction," for an
argument linking security and liberalism.
30. Small and Singer, Resort to Arms, pp. I76-79.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
229 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
230 Philosophy & Public Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
23I Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
Dilemma" game. There a failure of mutual trust and the incentives to enhance one's own
position produce a noncooperative solution that makes both parties worse off. Contrarily,
cooperation, a commitment to avoid exploiting the other party, produces joint gains. The
significance of the game in this context is the character of its participants. The "prisoners"
are presumed to be felonious, unrelated apart from their partnership in crime, and lacking
in mutual trust-competitive nation states in an anarchic world. A similar game between
fraternal or sororal twins-Kant's republics-would be likely to lead to different results. See
Robert Jervis, "Hypotheses on Misperception," World Politics 2o, no. 3 (April I968), for
an exposition of the role of presumptions; and "Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma,"
World Politics 30, no. 2 (January I 978), for the factors Realists see as mitigating the security
dilemma caused by anarchy.
Also, expectations (including theory and history) can influence behavior, making liberal
states expect (and fulfill) pacific policies toward each other. These effects are explored at
a theoretical level in R. Dacey, "Some Implications of 'Theory Absorption' for Economic
Theory and the Economics of Information" in Philosophical Dimensions of Economics, ed.
J. Pitt (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, I980).
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
232 Philosophy & Public Affairs
35. Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (Boston: Beacon Press, I944), chaps. I-2,
and Samuel Huntington and Z. Brzezinski, Political Power: USA/USSR (New York: Viking
Press, I963, I964), chap. 9. And see Richard Neustadt, Alliance Politics (New York: Co-
lumbia University Press, 1970) for a detailed case study of interliberal politics.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
233 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
zation of Germany and Japan helped construct buttresses for the inter-
national liberal order.36
Thus, the decline of U.S. hegemonic leadership may pose dangers for
the liberal world. This danger is not that today's liberal states will pernit
their economic competition to spiral into war, but that the societies of
the liberal world will no longer be able to provide the mutual assistance
they might require to sustain liberal domestic orders in the face of mount-
ing economic crises.
These dangers come from two directions: military and economic. Their
combination is particularly threatening. One is the continuing asymmetry
of defense, with the United States (in relation to its GNP) bearing an
undue portion of the common burden. Yet independent and more sub-
stantial European and Japanese defense establishments pose problems
for liberal cooperation. Military dependence on the United States has
been one of the additional bonds helpful in transforming a liberal peace
into a liberal alliance. Removing it, without creating a multilaterally di-
rected and funded organization among the liberal industrial democracies,
threatens to loosen an important bond. Economic instabilities could make
this absence of a multilateral security bond particularly dangerous by
escalating differences into hostility. If domestic economic collapses on
the pattern of the global propagation of depressions in the I930S were to
reoccur, the domestic political foundations of liberalism could fall. Or, if
international economic rivalry were to continue to increase, then con-
sequent attempts to weaken economic interdependence (establishing closed
trade and currency blocs) would break an important source of liberal
accommodation.37 These dangers would become more significant if in-
dependent and substantial military forces were established. If liberal as-
sumptions of the need to cooperate and to accommodate disappear, coun-
tries might fall prey to a corrosive rivalry that destroys the pacific union.
Yet liberals may have escaped from the single, greatest, traditional
danger of international change-the transition between hegemonic lead-
ers. When one great power begins to lose its preeminence and to slip into
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
234 Philosophy & Public Affairs
38. George Liska identifies this peaceful, hegemonic transition as exceptional in Quest
for Equilibrium: America and the Balance of Power on Land and Sea (Baltimore, MD: The
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977), chap. 4, p. 75. Wilson's speeches, including his
"War Message," suggest the importance of ideological factors in explaining this transition:
"Neutrality is no longer feasible or desirable where the peace of the world is involved and
the freedom of its peoples, and the menace to that peace and freedom lies in the existence
[emphasis supplied] of autocratic governments backed by organized force which is con-
trolled wholly by their will, not by the wifl of their people." This quotation is from Woodrow
Wilson, The Messages and Papers of Woodrow Wilson, ed. Albert Shaw (New York: The
Review of Reviews, 1924), p. 378. Ross Gregory in The Origins of American Intervention
in the First World War (New York: Norton, 1971) offers an interpretation along these lines,
combining commercial, financial, strategic, and ideological factors in his account of the
policy which brought the United States onto a collision course with Germany.
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
235 Kant, Liberal Legacies
and Foreign Affairs
This content downloaded from 200.89.140.130 on Wed, 21 Mar 2018 19:59:11 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms