Chapter 2
Chapter 2
Chapter 2
Chapter 2
UTILITARIANISM
Chapter 2
Utilitarianism
Introduction
On January 25, 2015, the 8th Special Action Force (SAF) conducted a police operation
at Tukanalipao, Mamasapao in Maguindanao. Also known as Oplan Exodus, it was
intended to serve an arrest warrant for Zulkifli Bin Hir or Marwan, a Malaysian terrorist
and bomb maker who had a 5-million-dollar bounty on his head. This mission
eventually led to a clash between the Philippine National Police’s (PNP) SAF, on one
hand, and the Bangsamoro Islamic Freedom Fighters (BIFF) and the Moro Islamic
Liberation Front (MILF) on the other. Although the police operation was successful
because of the death of Marwan, the firefight that ensued claimed sixty-seven lives
including forty-four SAF troopers, eighteen MILF Fighters and five civilians. However,
the relatively high number of SAF members killed in this operation caught attention of
many including Philippine media and the legislature.
In one of the Congress investigations that followed this tragic mission, then Senate
President Franklin Drilon and Senator Francis Escudero debated the public hearing of
an audio recording of an alleged conversation that attempted to cover up the massacre
of the PNP-SAF commandos. Drilon questioned the admissibility of these recordings
as evidence under the Anti-Wire Tapping Law whereas Escudero cited Section 4 of the
Anti-Wire Tapping Act (RA 4200) and explained that any communication or spoken
word or the existence, contents, substance, purport, or meaning of the same or any part
thereof or any information therein contained, obtained and secured by any person in
any violation of the preceding sections of this Act shall not be admissible in evidence
in any judicial, quasi-judicial, legislative or administrative hearing or investigation.
“Seator Grace Poe, previous chairperson of the senate committee on public order and
dangerous drugs argued otherwise, “Sinabi na ni Senaator Drilon na ito daw ay illegal,
na hindi daw pwede, na ako daw ay pwedeng maging liable kung ito daw ay ipapakinig
sa senado, ako naman, ano ba naman itong mga batas na ito?... Ang mga batas na to ay
para malaman natin ang katotohanan at magkaroon tayo ng hustisya. Itong anti-
wiretapping or mga recording na ganito, kung hindi pwedeng lalabs sa publiko, pwede
naming gawing basehan sa executive session.”
Senator Poe response leads us to ask: Can the government infringe individual rights If
it is morally permissible for the government to infringe individual rights, when can the
government do so? Does it become legitimate to sacrifice individual rights when
considering the greatest benefit for the greatest number of people?
The case exposes the aftermath of the Mamasapano incident and the Senate
investigations. The senate inquiry proceedings raised questions on the possibility of
wiretapping and the intrusion of one’s right to privacy. While the 1987 Philippine
Constitution does protect one’s right to private communication, it did provide some
exemptions to its inviolability. These exemptions included a lawful order of the court
and/or issues concerning public safety and order. RA 4200 (Anti-Wire Tapping Law
and RA 9372 (or the Human Security Act of 2007) both provided exemptions on the
inviolability of the right to privacy in instances of treason, espionage, rebellion and
sedition. While this is a certainty a legal issue, can it also contribute a moral concern?
By raising the distinction between moral and legal issues and concerns, do you think
that these two are different? To simplify things, let us put aside the question of law and
let us assume that you were ask to decide whether wiretapping is morally permissible
or not? On what instances is wiretapping morally permissible and on what instance it
is not morally permissible.
Specific Objectives
Lesson
THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY
1
Utilitarianism
- It is an ethical theory that argues for the goodness of pleasure and the determination of
right behavior based on the usefulness of the action’s consequences.
- It claims that one’s actions and behavior are good inasmuch as they are directed toward
the experience of the greatest pleasure over pain for the greatest number of person.
- Its root word is “utility” which refers to the usefulness of the consequences of one’s
actions.
- It is consequentialist – meaning the moral value of actions and decisions is based solely
or greatly on the usefulness of their consequences; it is the usefulness of results that
determines whether the action or behavior is good or bad.
- According to Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873), utility
refers to understanding the results of people’s actions. Specifically, they are interested
on whether this actions contribute or not to the world. The utilitarian value pleasure
and happiness; this means that the usefulness of actions is based on its promotion of
happiness.
o The pursuit for pleasure and pain are in fact the only principle in assessing
action’s morality
- Refers to the motivation of our actions as guided by our avoidance of pain and our
desire for pleasure.
- Refers to pleasure is only good if and only if, they produce more happiness than
unhappiness. This means that it is not enough to experience pleasure, but to also inquire
whether the things we do make us happier.
- He provided a framework for evaluating pleasure and pain commonly called Felicific
Calculus.
o This means that actions are evaluated on this single scale regardless of
preferences and values. In this sense pleasure and pain can only quantitatively
differ but not qualitatively differ from other experiences of pleasure and pain.
- He clarifies that what makes people happy is intended pleasure and what makes us
unhappy is the privation of pleasure.
- He argues that we act and do things because we find them pleasurable and we avoid
doing things because they are painful.
- He dissents from Bentham’s single scale of pleasure. He thinks that the principle of
utility must distinguish pleasure qualitatively and not merely quantitatively.
- Utilitarianism cannot promote the kind of pleasures appropriate for pigs or to any other
animals. He thinks that there are higher intellectual and lower base pleasure.
- We are capable of searching and desiring higher intellectual pleasures more than pigs
are capable of.
- Contrary to Bentham, Mill argues that quality is more preferable than quantity. An
excessive quantity of what otherwise pleasurable might result in pain.
- Actual choices of knowledgeable persons’ points that higher intellectual pleasures are
preferable than purely sensual appetites.
Lesson
THE PRINCIPLE OF THE
2 GREATEST NUMBER
Principle of the Greatest Number
According to John Stuart Mill, equating happiness with pleasure does not
aim to describe the utilitarian moral agent and independently from others.
This not only about our individual pleasures, regardless of how high,
intellectual, or in other ways noble it is, but it is also about the pleasure of
the greatest number affected by the consequence of our actions.
Utilitarianism
It is not at all separate from liberal social practices that aim to improve the
quality of life for all persons.
Maximizes the total amount of pleasure over displeasure for the greatest
number.
J.S. Mill pushes for the moral irrelevance of motive in evaluating actions.
Interested with the best consequence for the highest number of people. It is
not interested in the motive of agent.
Utilitarian argue that issues of justice carry a very strong emotional import
because the category of rights is directly associated with the individual’s most
vital interests
Mill associates utilitarianism with the possession of moral and legal rights. He
understands that legal rights are neither inviolable nor natural, but rights are
subject to some exceptions.
He points out that when legal rights are not normally justified in accordance to
the greatest happiness principle, then these rights neither be observed, nor be
respected. This is like saying that there are instances when the law is not morally
justified, and in this case, even objectionable.
Mill points out that moral rights take precedence over legal rights
For Mill, justice can be interpreted in terms of moral rights because justice
promotes the greater social good.
Mill explains that the idea of justice supposed two things: a rule of conduct and a
sentiment which sanctions the rule. The first must be supposed common to all mankind,
and intended for their good. The other (sentiment) is a desire that punishment may be
suffered by those who infringe the rule. There is involved, in addition, the conception
of some definite person who suffers by the infringement; whose rights (to use the
appropriated to the case) are violated by it. And the sentiment of justice appears to me
to be, the animal desire to repel or retaliate a hurt or damage to oneself, or to those
whom one sympathizes, widened so as to include all persons, by the human capacity of
enlarged sympathy, and the human conception of intelligent self-interest. From the
latter elements, the feeling derives its morality; from the former, its peculiar
impressiveness, ad energy of self-assertion.
SUMMARY
Bentham and Mill see moral good as pleasure, not merely self-gratification, but
also the greatest happiness principle or the greatest happiness for the greatest number
of people. We are compelled to do whatever increases pleasure and decreases pain to
the most number of persons, counting each as one and none as more than one. In
determining the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people, there is no
distinction between Bentham and Mill. Bentham suggests his felicific calculus, a
framework for quantifying moral valuation. Mill provides criterion for comparative
pleasures. He thinks that persons who experience two different types of pleasures
generally prefer higher intellectual pleasures to base sensual ones.
References/Additional Resources/Readings
Alican, Necip Fikri. Mill’s Principle of Utility: A Defense of John Stuart Mill’s
Notorious Proof. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 1994
Berger, Fred R. Happiness, Justice, and Freedom: The Moral and Political
Philosophy of John Stuart Mill. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.
Crisp, Roger. Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Mill on Utilitarianism.
London: Routledge, 2009.
Lyon’s David. Rights, Welfare and Mill’s Moral Theory. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1994.
Mill, John Stuart. Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. 33 Volumes, London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1994.
Ryan Alan. The Philosophy of John Stuart Mil. London: Macmillan, 1987.
Semmel, Bernard. John Stuart Mill and the Pursuit of Virtue. New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1984.