Steve Clarke - Naturalism Science and The Supernatural
Steve Clarke - Naturalism Science and The Supernatural
Steve Clarke - Naturalism Science and The Supernatural
October 2008
Abstract
There is overwhelming agreement amongst naturalists that a naturalistic ontology should not
allow for the possibility of supernatural entities. I argue, against this prevailing consensus,
that naturalists have no proper basis to oppose the existence of supernatural entities.
Naturalism is characterised, following Leiter and Rea, as a position which involves a primary
commitments must be compatible with this primary commitment. It is further argued that
properly applied scientific method has warranted acceptance of the existence of supernatural
entities in the past and that it is plausible to think that it will do so again in the future. So
1. Introduction
theory of a key philosophical concept’ (De Caro and Macarthur, 2004, 2). Naturalism is also a
divisive issues such as whether, for example, there is room or not for mental and moral
properties in a naturalist ontology, properly understood. Perhaps the only ontological issue on
which there is overwhelming agreement amongst naturalists is that there is no room for
says that there is nothing, or that nothing is so, except what holds in nature … naturalism on
any reading is opposed to supernaturalism’ (2004, 23). Philip Pettit tells us that ‘Naturalism
imposes a constraint on what there can be, stipulating that there are no nonnatural or
of all things, of what is that it is and what is not that it is not’ (1963, 173). What is in dispute,
should be guided by the methods and findings of the sciences (Kornblith, 1985, 3-8). All
naturalists seem to concur about the importance of scientific methodology for a genuinely
naturalistic inquiry. Indeed, many see this as the core commitment of naturalism. According
to Brian Leiter, ‘Naturalism in philosophy is always first a methodological view to the effect
that philosophical theorizing should be continuous with empirical enquiry in the sciences’
(1998, 81). Michael Rea, an opponent of naturalism, concurs (Rea, 2000, 50-72). In his view
Now because the naturalist defers to science on methodological matters, it seems that she
must also defer to science on ontological matters. If it is possible that the naturalist’s
substantive ontological claims may conflict with the results of current or future scientific
investigations, then it seems that the naturalist must withdraw those ontological claims.
According to Rea ‘… naturalism, whatever it is, must be compatible with anything science
might tell us about nature or supernature.’(Rea, 2002, 55). He continues, ‘Thus, no version of
naturalism can include any substantive thesis about the nature of nature or supernature.’(Rea,
2002, 55). If Rea (2002) is right, then it seems that even the widely accepted naturalist
While most naturalists will find Rea’s premise uncontentious, they will be unlikely to accept
the conclusion that he draws from it. They will agree that philosophical naturalism must be
compatible with whatever science tells us about nature or supernature, but will also be
inclined to the view that science can only say certain things about nature and supernature. In
particular they will be inclined to the view that science, properly understood, can never
warrant belief in supernatural entities. And if there are good reasons to think that science can
4
never warrant belief in supernatural entities, then naturalists can be justified in making
In this paper I will argue, against the above line of reasoning, that the naturalist cannot rule
out the possibility of warrant for belief in supernatural entities (where ‘supernatural’ is
understood is Rea and Stroud’s broad, colloquial sense to refer to anything other than the
natural) on the basis of any reasonable inferences about future scientific evidence. And
because the naturalist cannot rule out the possibility of such warrant, the naturalist is not
entitled to draw up ontological strictures against the supernatural. Rea’s premise may not be
sufficient to support his conclusion, but his conclusion is warranted nevertheless, or so I aim
viewpoint. The ASN concedes that it is logically possible for there to be warrant for the
conclusion that supernatural entities exist. However, the ASN asserts that we have good
reason to hold that the supernatural is an explanatory category that will not be utilised by
science, and because of this naturalists – whose beliefs are guided by scientific method – are
warranted in dispensing with the possibility of warrant for the existence of supernatural
entities.
2. Preliminaries
Before we go on, it will help to clear up some preliminary issues. First, it may be noted that, if
the problem under discussion for ontological naturalists results from acceptance of
methodological naturalism, then one option that is open to the ontological naturalist is to give
5
ontological naturalism per se. I note, along with Rea (2002) and Leiter (1998), that
ontological strictures against the supernatural. The ontological naturalist is free to respond to
this argument by abandoning methodological naturalism. If she were to do this, then the
ontological naturalist would be casting herself adrift of the naturalistic program in philosophy
entirely, which seems to be a very drastic response to the problem posed, but it is a possible
response.
Second, it might also be thought that, along with Leiter and Rea, I am being too strict in
considerations. Many actual naturalists probably do not explicitly consider their views to be
ontological naturalisms are a ‘good fit’ and they endorse both, without explicitly considering
the relationship between them. This may be an accurate description of the reasoning of many
actual naturalists, however, it is beside the point, when the point is the understanding of
relationship between ontological and methodological naturalism then it seems that they would
be driven to the view espoused by Rea and Leiter, because it appears to be the only view
which makes sense of the close association between methodological and ontological
naturalism.
6
Third, it is often noted that the distinction between the natural and the supernatural is ill-
defined, and it might be thought that the vagueness of the distinction between the natural and
the supernatural means that discussion of the ontological commitments of naturalism must be
hopelessly speculative. A reasonably sharp distinction between the natural and the
supernatural can usually be inferred from a clear definition of the natural. David Armstrong
defines naturalism in a way that incorporates a clear definition of the natural. According to
him naturalism is ‘… the doctrine that reality consists of nothing but a single all-embracing
spatio-temporal system’ (1981, 149).2 If we understand the natural this way then we can have
a reasonably clear sense of the supernatural; namely, anything that might exist that is outside
the single all-embracing spatio-temporal system. Other definitions of the natural will lead to
Of course not everyone will accept Armstrong’s definition of the natural or any other
particular definition of the natural. In the absence of agreement regarding the definition of the
natural, the charge that the boundary between the natural the supernatural is ill-defined is hard
to argue against. However, for the purposes of my argument it will not be necessary to find an
exact distinction between the natural and the supernatural. We still have a working distinction
between the natural and the supernatural, even if we are unsure whether certain possible
entities belong in the category ‘natural’ or the category ‘supernatural’, provided that there are
also possible entities that clearly belong in the category ‘natural’ and possible entities that
clearly belong in the category ‘supernatural’. We may be unsure whether ghosts and goblins
are best understood as supernatural entities or as unusual natural entities. However, on any
understanding of the natural-supernatural distinction that shows at least some respect for
ordinary usage, God – an all powerful agent whose existence is unconstrained by either space
7
or time – will be understood as a supernatural agent and ordinary worldly entities – tables,
Contemporary scientists hardly ever invoke the supernatural when formulating scientific
explanations of the past. For example, Newton argued that the stability of the planets in the
solar system is best explained by appeal to the law of gravity, together with God’s careful
initial placement of the planets relative to the sun (Meyer, 2000, 133-134).
biology. Vitalists argued that living matter is imbued with a non-material ‘élan vital’ which
causes it to be living matter. The presence of the élan vital is a crucial component of the
vitalist explanation for the distinction between life and non-life. While some vitalists believed
that the élan vital was an emergent natural property, many vitalists, such as Van Helmont and
Stahl appeared to believe that it was a non-natural substance (Macdonald and Tro
forthcoming), a supernatural substance in the colloquial sense of the term ‘supernatural’ that
is in play here.
design hypothesis, as promulgated by Paley and others. Most biologists, prior to Darwin,
believed that the best explanation for the functional organisation of biological organisms was
that this was intended by a supernatural designer (Ruse, 2001, 112-113). Not only was the
8
activity of a supernatural designer the best scientific explanation for the functional
organisation of living organisms, prior to Darwin (Dawkins, 1986, 5), at that stage the design
Ruse, ‘Before Darwin, one had no choice but to accept a designer’ (2001, 113).3
The above examples of appeal to the supernatural in science are very plausibly understood as
instances of the use of inference to the best explanation (IBE) and it is widely agreed that IBE
is a legitimate mode of inference, used extensively in science, which plays a crucial role in
scientific theory choice and in the formulation of particular theories in science (Lipton, 2004,
154-160; Psillos, 1999, 211-212). It is also widely agreed that IBE is ontologically
committing (Psillos, 1999, 211-212). So, it seems that mainstream scientists of the past have
In IBE, as it is standardly understood, we survey available explanations and accept the best of
these. In Lipton’s terminology we infer to the ‘best potential explanation’ (Lipton, 2004, 58).
It might be supposed that we should refrain from inferring to the truth or truth-aptness of an
explanation until we have identified the ‘best actual explanation’. But this sets the bar too
high to account for our actual inferential practices, because it seems always possible that we
have failed to consider some or other explanation that is actually better than any available
explanation. Most, if not all, of our currently accepted scientific explanations are the result of
inference to the best potential explanation. It is possible that these will be shown to not be the
best actual explanation of the phenomena that they are intended to explain in the future, but
this does not stop scientists from inferring to their truth-aptness and inferring that the entities
None of the exemplar supernatural explanations remain the best explanation of the
phenomena that they were intended to explain. Indeed, there are no clear contemporary
examples of an explanation that appeals to the supernatural constituting the best scientific
explanation of any natural phenomenon. These days, supernatural scientific explanations are
associated with minority movements at the fringe of science, such as the Intelligent Design
movement.4 However, we should not let the current fringe nature of supernatural explanation
in science prevent us from acknowledging the role that the supernatural has played in
Because the supernatural has been repeatedly invoked in scientific explanations in the past,
instances where explanations that invoked the supernatural were considered the best
reasonable to expect that explanations that invoke the supernatural will be considered to be
the best explanations of at least some natural phenomena in science in the future.
My argument for the conclusion that naturalists cannot dispense with the supernatural can
now be spelled out. [1] Philosophical naturalists are committed to accepting scientific
methodology crucially involves the use of IBE, which is ontologically committing. [3] IBE in
science has led us to the conclusion that supernatural entities exist and it is reasonable to
believe that it may do so again. Therefore, [4] Philosophical naturalists must allow for the
This is a striking conclusion and given the determined opposition to the supernatural
expressed by leading naturalists such as Pettit and Stroud, I expect it to be a conclusion that
will be contested by many. In what follows I attempt to head off a number of possible
objections. The objections can be divided into three categories, which will be addressed in the
next three sections of the paper, one category per section. First, it many be argued that my
examples are not genuine instances of IBE. Second, it may be conceded that they are genuine
instances of IBE, but argued that, despite appearances, the supernatural does not and will not
figure in genuine scientific explanations. Third, it may be disputed that IBE really is an
acceptable form of scientific inference. Having seen off the above lines of objection, I will
Although it may be conceded that Newton, Paley and some of the vitalists considered the
explanations for a variety of natural phenomena, it might be argued that these explanations
were not, in fact, accepted because of the correct application of IBE. All I have shown, it may
phenomena that invoked the supernatural to be the best available explanations of these
phenomena. But these authorities may have been mistaken. Are there good reasons to think
that our exemplar scientific explanations that invoked the supernatural were not in fact the
best explanations that were available in their respective times? The following have been
suggested to me:
11
First, it may be suspected that the assessments of scientists of the past regarding the quality of
available explanations that invoked the supernatural was distorted by the longstanding
influence of Christian thinking upon Western science. Christianity systematically distorted the
judgments of Western scientists so that explanations that invoked the supernatural appeared to
be better explanations than their purely naturalistic rivals, when in fact they were not better
I concede that the longstanding influence of Christian thought may have caused Western
science to favour some supernatural explanations over purely natural ones in the past.5
1
Rea (2002) does not develop these comments. They function as stage-setting for an
ambitious argument against naturalism that turns on the alleged inability of naturalists to
discover the modal properties of the world using the methods of natural science. Assessment
2
Also Armstrong (1989, 3) describes naturalism as ‘… the doctrine that nothing at all exists
3
See also Sober (1993, Ch. 3). In a recent paper McLaughlin (2007) takes issue with Sober’s
(1993) view that Paley’s argument from design, which was most forcefully advocated in
1802, was representative of then prevailing scientific opinion. McLaughlin’s views need not
detain us, however, as he concedes that “… the argument from design was a part of science up
to about 1730” (McLaughlin, 2007, 27). This dispute is about when the argument from design
4
For extensive discussion of the Intelligent Design movement see Pennock (2001).
12
However this line of reasoning cannot account for all of the instances where the supernatural
has been invoked in scientific explanation. When Ruse tells us that ‘Before Darwin, one had
no choice but to accept a designer’ (2001, 113), I take it that he is arguing that an unbiased
scientist would have found supernatural design to be the best explanation of the functional
organisation of living organisms, before Darwin, because this was by far and away the best
hypothesis was the best explanation of the functional organisation of living organisms
available before Darwin, not just the best explanation available from a Christian point of
view.
Second, it may be doubted that the individual scientists who provided our exemplar scientific
explanations that invoke the supernatural canvassed all available explanations, before
deciding which of these was the best. If they did not canvas all available explanations, then
they cannot be said to have conducted IBE in a proper manner.6 One way of responding to this
line of objection would be to examine the historical record in detail and see if there were
significant available explanations of the relevant phenomena that were not considered by
Newton, Van Helmont, Stahl and Paley. However, such historical examination is probably
explanations were left unconsidered then these omissions would be noted by other scientists
working in their areas of enquiry. Furthermore, it is reasonable to assume that the exemplar
5
On the influence of Christianity on the development of Western science see Brooke (1991)
6
Thanks to Peter Forrest for suggesting this line of objection.
13
explanations attained the prominence that they did precisely because they were considered
A third possible reason for suspecting that our exemplar explanations were not, in fact, the
best explanations of the phenomena that they were intended to explain, available in their
respective times, can be developed by considering the process of selecting between competing
consider how well these competing explanations exemplify a range of explanatory virtues.
and it seems that any explanation of a natural phenomenon that invokes the supernatural
commits us to a natural-supernatural distinction, making that explanation less simple than its
purely natural rivals. Perhaps scientists of the past lost sight of the importance of simplicity in
explanations.
even if an explanation that invokes the supernatural is not the simplest available explanation
of a natural phenomenon, it may be the best explanation all things considered, because it may
have other compensating explanatory virtues. So it seems that this line of objection will not be
14
sufficient to sustain the conclusion that all of our exemplar supernatural explanations were not
Our second form of objection involves accepting that at least some of the exemplar
supernatural explanations are indeed genuine instances of IBE, advocated by real scientists of
the past, but arguing that it does not follow that future scientific explanations could invoke the
supernatural. One way to develop this second form of objection is to argue that, although the
examples of scientific explanations that invoke the supernatural are genuine instances of IBE
formulated by real scientists, they are nevertheless not genuine scientific explanations.
Instead, they are explanations that go beyond the domain of science, properly understood. For
example, it may be admitted that the design hypothesis was a genuine scientific hypothesis,
and conceded that a supernatural designer is more likely than a natural designer, but it could
nevertheless be argued that the inference that the designer of nature is a supernatural agent is
not, properly speaking, a scientific inference and so explanations that appeal to a supernatural
This line of objection will probably not attract much support these days, as the project of
trying to demarcate the proper domain of scientific explanation from the domain of non-
scientific explanation has been out of favour for some time (Laudan, 1983). But even if we
could successfully argue that instances of IBE, which build on scientific results and which
invoke the supernatural, are not, properly speaking, ‘scientific inferences’, this would not be
sufficient for the purposes of the ASN. The problem is that this line of reasoning does nothing
15
to undermine the legitimacy of instances of IBE that are based on scientific evidence, which
invoke the supernatural. All that has been achieved is a hollow rhetorical victory. If we
endorse IBE at all it is because we endorse IBE as a general form of inference. So it seems
that if we endorse IBE, we must be willing to endorse all explanations that are the result of
well-formed instances of IBE based on established scientific evidence, even if we decide that
some of these explanations are not worthy of the epithet ‘scientific’. But this may include
endorsing explanations that invoke the existence of supernatural entities, and this is not a
A second way of arguing for the conclusion that future scientific explanations will not involve
the supernatural, is to argue that inferences to the existence of the supernatural are not a part
of ‘mature science’. Immature sciences may involve all manner of explanations, but the
mature sciences only involve a restricted range of explanations, and this does not include
appeals to the supernatural, or so this line of argument has it. A huge problem for a proponent
of this line of argument is that she owes us an account of the history of science that explains
the transition of science from its immature state to maturity. In order to satisfy the needs of
the ASN, it seems that any such account must meet two criteria. First, it must explain why
mature science no longer allows inferences to the existence of the supernatural. Second, it
must show that the transition of science to maturity occurs at roughly the same time as the
time that supernatural explanations fell out of favour in the sciences, during the Nineteenth
Century. But standard accounts of the history of science do not seem to meet either of these
Century and it does not involve any obvious stipulation against the invocation of the
supernatural (Koyré, 1957; Dijksterhuis, 1961). But unless these criteria are met we, are left
with absolutely no reason to think that supernatural explanations will not reappear in a future
16
science, so the appeal to ‘maturity’ as a means to exclude the supernatural from current and
Another possible line of argument, for the conclusion that current and future science has
matured to the state where it can reasonably be expected that scientists will no longer make
appeals to the supernatural, begins with the observation that, although genuine scientific
explanations of the past have involved appeals to the supernatural, these have become
increasingly rare over the course of time. A corollary of the development of science, has been
the successive replacement of explanations that invoke the supernatural with purely
naturalistic explanations. It may be argued that, because we have seen the successive rejection
we can induce that future mainstream scientists will not invoke supernatural explanations.
This argument might be termed the ‘naturalistic induction’ and it may seem that the ASN can
appeal to the naturalistic induction to try to convince us that the supernatural has no place in
future science. If science has matured gradually, then there need be no distinct transition-
phase in which the passage of science from immaturity to maturity takes place.
‘supernatural induction’, introduced earlier. These two inductive arguments lead to opposing
conclusions, but both appear to be well-formed inductive arguments. Second, the naturalistic
induction is only an inductive argument, and while it may provide us with some reason to be
guarantee that future scientists will not find themselves faced with evidence for which a
supernatural explanation is the best available explanation, all things considered. And because
it gives us no such guarantee, it cannot be a sufficient basis for the ASN to reject the
17
supernatural in science. Third, it appears that we can conceive of clear examples of possible
circumstances for which, if the right sort of evidence were to come along, then the best
explanation of that evidence would involve appeal to the supernatural. To see this, consider
the following example, due to Bill Dembski. Suppose that we find the words ‘Made By
Yahweh’ inscribed in tiny letters on each and every living cell that we examine (Dembski,
2000, 256). If we did discover reliable evidence of this highly unlikely state of affairs, then it
seems clear enough that the best explanation for the presence of the inscription on cells is that
a supernatural being, ‘Yahweh’ wishes it to be known that He is the creator of all living
organisms.7
In arguing that explanations that invoke the supernatural can be scientific explanations I have
However, IBE is not without its critics. Some criticisms of IBE are best understood as
components of larger, more general criticisms of science. For example, Richard Rorty argues
that the choice of an explanation as ‘the best’ only indicates that it is in the interests of
From a Wittgensteinian or Davidsonian or Deweyan angle, there is no such thing as ‘the best explanation’; of
anything; there is just the explanation which best suits the purpose of some given explainer. (Rorty, 1988, 69)
7
A second example of a possible scenario that would be best explained by appeal to the
Rorty’s overall attitude to science is that it has no privileged access to the way the world is.
This is because be holds that the project of trying to represent the way the world is, is deeply
completely out of step with mainstream contemporary naturalists who hold that science does
have privileged access to the way the world is. Rorty’s criticisms of IBE are of no assistance
to the ASN because, if they were successful, they would accomplish too much. They might
undermine warrant for believing in the supernatural that may be derived by use of IBE, but if
they do so then they do so by undermining the case for the privileging of scientific method,
If there are lines of criticism of IBE that are of use to the ASN then these must be ones that
undermine warrant for belief in the supernatural, but do not also undermine the naturalist case
for privileging scientific method. We will examine two lines of criticism of IBE that appear to
fill this role. These are due to Nancy Cartwright (1999) and Bas van Fraassen (1980). Both
are critics of IBE, but they are not critics of all ampliative inferences in science and they are
show that the case for there being warrant for belief in the supernatural can survive the
criticisms of IBE due to Cartwright and van Fraassen, even if these are accepted. This is
because, I will argue, we can be warranted in believing in supernatural entities even if we are
only allowed to employ the restricted ranges of ampliative inferences that are endorsed by
Most of the philosophers who oppose IBE, including Cartwright and van Fraassen, do so for
the purposes of opposing scientific realism. This is because IBE plays a crucial role in
19
contemporary arguments for scientific realism. Indeed, acceptance of the legitimacy of IBE is
sometimes considered to be the defining feature of scientific realists, separating them from
their opponents, who only consider more restrictive forms of inference to be legitimate
(McMullin, 1994). In recent times debates about the acceptability or otherwise of scientific
realism have focussed increasingly on the status of IBE, mostly because of the influential ‘no-
miracles argument’, which was first articulated by Hilary Putnam (1975, 73).
The no-miracles argument has it that scientific realism is the metaphysical stance that best
explains the success of science, because it is the only metaphysical stance that explains the
success of science without making that success appear to be miraculous. The no-miracles
argument appeals to IBE and appears itself to be an instance of IBE. Because most
contemporary naturalists accept the authority of science and because scientific realism is the
metaphysical stance that makes most immediate sense of the authority of science, most
naturalists are, implicitly or explicitly, committed to scientific realism (Koons, 2000, 49). For
the purposes of this paper I will avoid the temptation to enter debates about scientific realism
and will focus on criticisms of IBE, due to opponents of scientific realism, which might
Cartwright (1983) is an opponent of scientific realism and an opponent of IBE, but not an
opponent of all forms of ampliative inference. She argues that our assessment of which of a
class of competing explanations is the best often involves appeal to ‘pragmatic virtues’, such
as simplicity and elegance in explanation and she argues that these are reflections of our
explanatory preferences, having no obvious relationship to the truth (Clarke, 2001, 705-710).
Because appeals to pragmatic virtues have no obvious connection to the truth, we are not
entitled to infer that, if an explanation is judged by us to be the best available, then it is likely
20
inferences on the grounds that these feature in causal explanations, which we identify as the
explanation is the best causal explanation just because the cause it identifies is the most likely
inference, ‘inference to the most probable cause’ (IPC) is a legitimate form of inference,
according to her.
It might be thought that ASNs could find reasons to rule explanations that invoke the
illegitimate. However, it seems that we can justify belief in supernatural entities using IPC,
which Cartwright does accept. If the most probable cause of the parting of the Red Sea is the
activity of a supernatural agent, then IPC allows us to infer to the existence of that
supernatural agent. Because Cartwright’s criticisms do not extend to causal explanations and
because some explanations that invoke the supernatural are causal explanations, arrived at by
utilising IPC, Cartwright’s criticisms of IBE are insufficient to satisfy the purposes of the
ASN.
Our second opponent of scientific realism, Bas van Fraassen, is perhaps best known for his
advocacy of ‘constructive empiricism’. According to van Fraassen (1980), the use of IBE to
infer to the existence of unobservables involves taking an epistemic risk that we can and
should avoid. Constructive empiricists adopt an agnostic stance regarding the existence of
unobservables. We can allow that the existence of theoretical entities such as electrons and
positrons may best explain a variety of phenomena that require explaining, without also
21
committing ourselves to the existence (or non-existence) of actual electrons and positrons. It
may seem that we could argue similarly, in the case of supernatural entities, allowing that the
existence of the élan vital, for example, would best explain this or that phenomenon, but
resisting the inference that we are, therefore, warranted in inferring that instantiations of the
élan vital actually exist. Adopting constructive empiricism would allow the ASN to find
reasons to render some explanations that invoke the supernatural to be illegitimate. However,
it would not do enough to render all explanations that invoke the supernatural illegitimate,
because supernatural entities need not be unobservable entities. For example, the Old
Testament God, was regularly observed, if we are to believe what we are told in the Bible,
Because the focus of his constructive empiricist objections to IBE were restricted to the realm
of unobservables and because van Fraassen (1980) appeared to endorse instances of IBE in
the case of some observables, van Fraassen’s scientific realist opponents have often taken him
to accept the legitimacy of IBE, in the case of observables.8 More recently, however, van
Fraassen (and coauthors) has insisted that he does not accept IBE in any context (Ladyman et.
al, 1997). Rather, he accepts what Psillos refers to as ‘as-if IBE’ (Psillos, 1997, 371), a form
of ampliative reasoning that is empirically indistinguishable from IBE, but only licences
conclusions about the empirical adequacy of claims about unobservables and unobserved
observables, rather than conclusions of truth-aptness. Nevertheless, it seems that van Fraassen
does at least accept the legitimacy of claims about the truth-aptness of well-formed ampliative
inferences about observed observables, and it seems that this is enough to licence inferences
8
Psillos (1999, 212-213) explains why Van Fraassen has often been read this way.
22
Before concluding, I will consider two more potential lines of defence of naturalistic
opposition to the supernatural. The first of these is the ‘but science studies the natural’
A possible way to try to evade the conclusion that naturalists should abandon opposition to
the supernatural is to insist that ‘the natural’ just is whatever it is that science studies. If future
science invokes God or some other apparently supernatural entity in a well-formed scientific
explanation, then this acceptance just shows that God must actually be a natural, rather than a
supernatural entity, or so the line of objection has it. If a narrow sense of the term ‘study’ is
intended then this line of objection seems misconceived, because scientists who have invoked
God in scientific explanations did not experiment on or take measurements of God, instead
they sought to explain observed effects by inferring to the existence of God. But presumably
most of those who push this line of objection have in mind a broad sense of the term ‘study’,
which encompasses entities that we come to believe to exist, as a result of inferences from
empirical evidence.
One way of heading off this line of objection would be to accuse its proponents of rendering
the term ‘natural’ completely vacuous. If, as seems reasonable to believe, science can study
anything and everything, then the ‘natural’, on this understanding of the term, encompasses
23
anything and everything, and there is no possibility of the supernatural existing, because there
is no conceptual space left for the supernatural. However, it may be possible to pursue a form
of the line of objection under discussion, while still allowing for the bare possibility of the
supernatural and without concomitantly rendering the term ‘natural’ vacuous. To do this we
might stipulate that the natural is to be equated with everything that has causal efficacy in the
world. If God has had an effect on any part of the world, then God is causally connected to
the world and is therefore natural, or so this line of reasoning goes.9 This way of
understanding the natural allows for the bare possibility of the supernatural existing, but
disallows the possibility of the supernatural causally interacting with the natural. If we accept
the not obviously unreasonable hypothesis that only factors that have some causal connection
to a subject can have explanatory relevance for that subject, then we will have ruled the
supernatural out of the proper domain of scientific explanation without ruling out the bare
possibility of the supernatural and without the rendering the term ‘natural’ entirely vacuous.
My response to this now considerably nuanced line of objection is that it offends against the
Because naturalists are philosophically guided by scientific method, it seems that they must
substantial degree. Scientists might have considered everything that is causally efficacious in
the world to be natural, in which case the line of objection suggested would be of use to the
naturalist. But as it happens scientists have not considered everything that is causally
efficacious in the world to be natural. Overwhelmingly, they have followed ordinary usage
and considered God to be a supernatural entity, on occasions when God has been invoked in
scientific explanations. So it seems that naturalists, by their own lights, should follow actual
I’ve argued that naturalists lack a firm basis for opposition to the supernatural. But it might be
considered that I have misconstrued the nature of naturalists’ opposition to the supernatural.
Naturalists who are opposed to the supernatural are not seeking to make grand claims about
naturalistic ontology, they are simply betting that science will not invoke the supernatural in
the future, or so a line of objection goes. They are entitled to do because current science does
not invoke the supernatural. Future science might revive the supernatural, of course, but all
this shows is that naturalistic opposition to the supernatural is fallible, or so it may be argued.
The first response to this objection is that it doesn’t seem to explain why naturalists
persistently single out the supernatural as an object of opposition. If naturalists are entitled to
bet against any and every concept and category that current science does not endorse then
they are entitled to bet against phlogiston, cold fusion, the ether, and a vast array of other
concepts that are not accepted in contemporary science, so it is mysterious that naturalists
single out the supernatural for special attention. Given that naturalists do single out the
supernatural for special attention, it seems more plausible to interpret naturalists as doing
more than merely betting against the supernatural. It seems more plausible to suppose that
The second response to the ‘bet objection’, is that, as bets go it seems to be a riskier one to
make than many other bets that might be made on the basis of current science. Current science
gives us very strong reason to believe that particular entities exist, namely those which we can
25
experiment on and which figure in our best explanatory theories. It also gives us strong reason
to believe that particular theories approximate to the truth. If naturalists were to seek to
identify their position with the bet that hydrogen exists or the bet that the theory of evolution
is approximately true, then they would be making a bet that is strongly grounded in the
findings of current science. By comparison, a bet against the supernatural is much less
strongly grounded in the findings of current science. It is true that current science does not
invoke the supernatural, but currently acceptable scientific theories are not incompatible with
the existence of the supernatural. If the naturalist’s opposition to the supernatural is only a
bet, then it is particularly mysterious why naturalists such as Pettit and Stroud single out the
supernatural to bet against, when there are many safer bets that they might seek to be
identified with.
My third response to this line of objection is to point out that the naturalist’s commitment is
not to current science as such but to scientific method. The naturalist is only indirectly
committed to the findings of current science, in that she (presumably) takes these to be based
on the proper application of scientific method. It is true that current science does not invoke
the supernatural, but more important for the naturalist is the question of whether or not
scientific method issues forth any substantial reason to warrant opposition to the supernatural,
and this is the nub of the disagreement between me and the ASN. The ASN supposes that
scientific method does provides substantial reasons for the naturalist to oppose the
supernatural, but I argue that scientific method does not provide substantial reasons to oppose
the supernatural. How could it? Scientific method has often provided substantial reasons to
endorse the existence of specific types of supernatural entity. Because scientific method does
not provide substantial reason to oppose the supernatural, the naturalist should not be opposed
to the supernatural.
26
8. Concluding remarks
We have seen that there is a strong argument for the conclusion that the supernatural cannot
be excluded from science. Because the supernatural cannot be excluded from science, and
because the naturalist must defer to science about ontological as well as methodological
matters, the naturalist has no grounds for stipulating against the supernatural in her ontology.
Ten different possible lines of objection to this conclusion have been considered and all have
been shown to fall short of their mark. Naturalists should respond to this state of affairs by
References
University Press).
Cartwright, N. (1983). How the Laws of Physics Lie. (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
27
Clarke, S. (1997). When to Believe in Miracles. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 95-
102.
Clarke, S. (2001). Defensible Territory for Entity Realism. British Journal for the Philosophy of
Caro and D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in Question (pp. 1-17). (Cambridge MA: Harvard
University Press).
Press).
Grant, E. (1996). Foundations of Modern Science in the Middle Ages: Their Religious,
Craig and J. P. Moreland (Eds.) Naturalism: a Critical Analysis (pp. 49-63). (London:
Routledge).
Koyré, A. (1957). From the Closed World to the Infinite Universe. (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
University Press).
Ladyman, J., Douven, I., Horsten, I. and van Fraassen, B. C. (1997). A Defence of van
47, 305-321.
Laudan, L. (1983). The Demise of the Demarcation Problem. In R. S. Cohen and L. Laudan
Leiter, B. (1998). Naturalism and Naturalized Jurisprudence. In B. Bix (Ed.) Analysing Law:
New Essays in Legal Theory (pp. 79-104). (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Meyer, S. (2000). Qualified Agreement: Modern Science & the Return of the “God
Hypothesis”. In R. F. Carlson (Ed.) Science and Christianity: Four Views (pp. 127-174)
Mumford, S, (2001). Miracles: Metaphysics and Modality. Religious Studies, 37, 191-202.
Pennock, R. T. (Ed) (2001). Intelligent Design Creationism and its Critics. (Cambridge MA:
Pettit, P. (1992). The Nature of Naturalism II. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Suppl.
Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. (London: Routledge).
Rorty, R. (1988). Is Natural Science a Natural Kind? In E. McMullin (Ed.) Construction and
Rorty, R. (2000). Response to Robert Brandom. In R. R. Brandom (Ed.) Rorty and his Critics
Press).
Sellars, W. (1963). Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. (In W. Sellars, Science,
Perception, and Reality (pp. 127-196) (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul).
Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The Scientific Image. (Oxford: The Clarendon Press).
31
Notes