Aesthetics and Philosophy in American Colleges
Aesthetics and Philosophy in American Colleges
Aesthetics and Philosophy in American Colleges
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The American Society for Aesthetics and Wiley are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism
theoretical ballast to keep her in the air. But in 1917, Igor Stravinsky, in exile,
with instinctive social insight, wrote, in spite of his disclaimer that nothing
matters save 'la mttiere sonore," a "Triumphal March of the Devil," in his
Story of a Soldier. The balloon of progress lay on the fields of Flanders, com-
pletely deflated.
With the demise of the idea of progress as a belief in automatic, universal
betterment, millions of people have come to regard progress as impossible and
unattainable in this age of insane destruction. The belief in the possibility of
progress must not be allowed to disappear. If it does, the history of music
and of everything worth while is finished.
THOMAS MUNRO
Like all other sciences, aesthetics was hatched in the parent nest of philosop
It has hesitated long on the edge of the nest, before flying out to set up one
own. Its elder brother, psychology (formerly known as "mental philoso
went through the same pangs of separation a few decades ago. Psycholo
grown mightily since, and has brought back many a choice morsel of kno
to its elderly parents. Aesthetics as a formal, academic subject still feels
at home under the sheltering wing of philosophy.
Since the eighteenth century, it has held a somewhat uncertain place
member of the philosophical family. Its position is not unlike that of a la
unexpected arrival, a rather unsought and accidental infant, come to bles
old age of a couple whose other children have long since grown up. The in
awkward attempts to walk and do things for itself are entertaining but
embarrassing, among its well-poised older brothers. It often talks too m
and uses big words which it does not understand. When the family
noses, in planning a picnic or assigning tasks to be done, its existence is
times forgotten.
Aesthetics is sometimes listed among the recognized branches of philos
sometimes not. The student can read a long list of recent histories of phil
and surveys of contemporary problems, without discovering that aesth
exists, or that any great philosophers have been concerned about ar
troductions to philosophy" are worth noticing these days, as the nearest appr
to comprehensive philosophical systems. Our philosophers have appa
given up writing new systems of their own, but they do occasionally p
these brief epitomes for the young. Friedrich Paulsen's Introduction to
losophy,' still used since William James endorsed it in 1895, does not m
aesthetics among the branches of philosophy-logic, ethics, epistemology
metaphysics. Neither art nor aesthetics is mentioned in its Index.
I Tr. by F. Thilly. Holt, N. Y., 1895. First ed., Berlin, 1892.
textbooks containing no aesthetics (or less than one tenth of one percent) are
Bertrand Russell's The Problems of Philosophy,2 R. B. Perry's Present Philosophi-
cal Tendencies,3 Vergilius Ferm's First Adventures in Philosophy,4 Howard Sel-
sam's What is Philosophy (A Marxist Introduction) ,' and W. A. Sinclair's Introduc-
tion to Philosophy.6
On the other hand, several older introductions to philosophy had chapters on
aesthetics, or aesthetic value, or "the beautiful"-for example, those by G. T
Ladd (1890) and W. T. Marvin (1912). R. W. Sellars7 includes aesthetics
("a reflection upon the nature of beauty whether in art or in nature") along with
ethics in axiology (theory of values) as one of the main divisions of philosophy.
G. T. W. Patrick's Introduction to Philosophy8 has an unusually long chapter
on "Aesthetic Values," with sections on objects of beauty, the science
of aesthetics, art periods in history, the art impulse, the fine arts, art and m
art and social morale, the play motive, the imagination, theories of the beautiful,
empathy, the psychology of aesthetic experience, music, and beauty as ideal
value. Recent introductions by D. R. Major,9 Durant Drake,'0 G. W. Cunning-
ham,"1 and C. B. Garnett"2 have sections on aesthetics or on beauty.
Philosophy in American Education, the vigorous new book by a commission of
the American Philosophical Association,"3 omits aesthetics from its list of "the
basic courses in philosophy" (history of philosophy, ethics, logic, and meta-
physics). But it does emphasize art as one of the "specific extraphilosophical
subject matters" which should be analyzed by philosophy. "Philosophy,"
it says, "can fit into such programs of mutual aid between related humanities
in three principal ways: (a) through the analytical disciplines of aesthetics
and philosophical linguistics; (b) by contributions to the history of ideas; (c)
in its interpretation and criticism of the moral and speculative ideals expressed
in literature and the arts."'14
Histories of philosophy in English often pay little attention to aesthetics or
the philosophy of art, passing quickly over important works on the subject by
leading philosophers. In Bertrand Russell's new History of Western Philosophy,'5
"aesthetics" receives three brief index references; "art" none. Hegel's monu-
2Holt, N. Y., n. d.
3 Longmans Green, N. Y., 1919.
4 Scribner's, N. Y., 1936.
6 International Publishers, N. Y., 1939.
6 Oxford, London, 1944.
7The Principles and Problems of Philosophy. Macmillan, N. Y., 1926.
8Houghton Mifflin, Boston, 1924, 1935.
9 Doubleday Doran, N. Y., 1933.
10 Invitation to Philosophy. Houghton Mifflin, 1933.
"1 Problems of Philosophy. Holt, 1935.
12 Quest for Wisdom. Crofts, N. Y., 1942. (Thanks for several of these titles to Jared
S. Moore, professor of philosophy at Western Reserve, who has taught aesthetics there for
many years.)
13 B. Blanshard, C. J. Ducasse, and others. Harper, N. Y., 1945.
14 P. 236.
15 Simon and Schuster, N. Y., 1945. Cf. histories of philosophy by Thilly, Rogers, W. T.
Marvin, and others.
it would seem that they bring in a generous amount of content from the arts
and psychology, with comparative analysis of forms in different media. This is
far ahead of the general level of development at the present time.
Persistent disagreement on the status of aesthetics in philosophy has not pre-
vented numerous American philosophers from writing books about it. William
Knight's Philosophy of the Beautifut has a chapter on "The Philosophy of Amer-
ica," which reviews a surprising list of aestheticians from 1815 on-now mostly
forgotten, alas! -down to Gayley and a youthful John Dewey in 1887. Since
then, substantial writings on aesthetics have appeared under the names of
Santayana, Whitehead, Dewey, Parker, Prall, Ducasse, Chandler, Pepper,
Gilbert, Flaccus, George Boas, Parkhurst, Edman, Kallen, T. M. Greene, Morris,
Nahm, and others, in the philosophy departments of Harvard, Columbia, Prince-
ton, Brown, Pennsylvania, Michigan, Ohio, California, Duke, Johns Hopkins,
Bryn Mawr, Northwestern, and the New School for Social Research. This list is
far from complete; it omits several able writers, especially some who have recently
begun their work in this country. But it is long and honorable enough to make
one wonder why the subject of aesthetics itself is still so often treated as an orphan
stepchild in American philosophy departments. If someone happens to be
around who wants to teach it, well and good; if not, the lack is apparently not
considered very serious. Few philosophy departments are inclined to develop
aesthetics, as at Barnard, into a diversified program of detailed courses. One or
two half-year courses of a highly abstract nature, on beauty and aesthetic value,
are usually considered ample. Few departments assign more than one instructor
to the field.
For this slow development, many reasons can be given, including a lack of
demand on the part of students. But would there not be more demand if aes-
thetics were differently taught? One stumbling-block has been the traditionally
narrow conception of aesthetics as restricted to the abstract study of beauty and
aesthetic value. When this is all aesthetics deals with, it can never attract
many students to pursue it very far.
Some philosophers in this country and in Germany have gone to great pains
to exclude from aesthetics a number of subjects which, everyone concedes, are
closely related to it. Unfortunately, these hair-splitting distinctions are still
being made, to the continued bewilderment of students and the public. Thus
Helmut Kuhn, writing on "Philosophy of Art" in the new Encyclopedia of the
Arts,20 begins, "In order to determine the purpose of a philosophy of art, we
must distinguish it from aesthetics. . . Aesthetics, the philosophical analysis of
beauty, may be distinguished from the study, philosophical or otherwise, of art
as a form of human productivity ... This dualistic notion sprang from a desire to
emancipate the luxuriant growth of the modern study of art in its various aspects
(sociological, anthropological, psychological, and so forth) from the tutelage of a
conservative and classicistic aesthetics. It is reflected by the double-barrelled
title of the most important periodical in the field, the Zeitschrift fur Asthetik und
Aligemeine Kunstwissenschaft, founded by Max Dessoir in 1906." A little
21 "Education as Philosophy." Swarthmore College Bulletin, vol. XLII, no. 4,7th month
1945. Dr. Blanshard has recently been appointed Professor of Philosophy at Yale.
agree to call the field "philosophy of art," or "science of art," or "art theory,"
or Kunstwissenschaft, one name will do as well as another. It would not be
hard to coin a better name than "aesthetics," if one could start from scratch.
But "aesthetics" has achieved more general use than any other term, and it is
commonly defined so as to include these closely related fields. So why confuse
the issue by needless distinctions, and a needless multiplicity of labels? The
important thing is to get the job done somehow: to start, in a concerted and
vigorous way, systematic investigation of the arts and related types of human
experience; to develop instruction in American colleges for the sake of all inter-
ested students, and to provide adequate facilities for advanced research.
This is not to say that the distinctions quoted above are false or entirely use-
less. It is important to distinguish between factual and evaluative studies;
between observing works of art and defining general aesthetic categories, etc.
These are different tasks, emphases, and approaches within the subject of
aesthetics, which should be distinguished as well as interrelated. But it is
harmful to erect them at the start into restrictive boundaries for the whole sub-
ject; to fence off a little realm of abstract value-theory, and obstruct free traffic
between it and its neighbors. A precise definition of the limits of aesthetics is
not urgently needed at the present stage. If made at all, it should be made in
terms of more and less. When art criticism becomes sufficiently general and
fundamental, covering a wide range of art and scrutinizing value-standards, it
becomes aesthetics. When art history becomes sufficiently general and funda-
mental, revealing major culture-epochs, styles, trends, and causal relations, it
becomes aesthetics. When psychology discloses main recurrent factors in per-
sonality and social behavior which affect the creation and use of art, it becomes
aesthetics. When semantics deals constructively with aesthetic terms and
meanings, it becomes aesthetics.
There is no distinct subject of aesthetics in the nature of things. There is a
set of diverse phenomena, called "aesthetic" and "artistic," which can as yet be
only roughly marked off. There is a varied group of intellectual approaches to
them, for the purpose of raising and answering as well as possible a numberof
different problems, which seem important to different generations. Aesthetics
as a subject will thrive best by freely admitting many scientific, critical, artistic,
historical, and educational approaches to its counsels; by admitting many dif-
ferent types of data and hypotheses, whether or not they conform to some pre-
established definition of what aesthetics ought to include. In educational
administration, as in organizing college departments, some marking off of fields
is necessary for practical purposes. But it should never be too exact or obstruc-
tive to new approaches, which may seek to cut across the old boundaries.
At the present time aesthetics, or the group of subjects loosely designated by
that name, is growing too large to be adequately taught within the limits of the
ordinary philosophy department, however well-disposed some individual philoso-
phers may be. The philosophical nest is elastic enough to accommodate a sizable
fledgling. But there are limits to the growth of any one branch of philosophy,
especially when a small department is expected to cover the whole traditional
field.
l Part I is by Katharine Gilbert; Parts II and III are by Helmut Kuhn. The article by
Ames was published in this JOURNAL, Sept. 1945, vol. IV, no. 1.