Introduction To Logic - Muttahhari
Introduction To Logic - Muttahhari
Introduction To Logic - Muttahhari
2
Definition of Logic
Applications of Logic
1
Ālatun qānūniyatun taʻṣimu murāʻātuhā al-dhihna ‘ani ʼl-khaṭāʼi fī ʼl-fikri,
Avicenna [Ibn Sīnā], al-Ishārāt wa ʼl-Tanbīhāt [Hints and Instructions], 1403/1982,
pp. 8-9.
2
Tartību umūrin maʻlūmatin li-taḥṣīli amrin majhūlin; mulāḥaẓatu ʼl-maʻqūli
3
which the mind proceeds toward the unknown to turn it into
known facts.2
2
Tartību umūrin maʻlūmatin li-taḥṣīli amrin majhūlin; mulāḥaẓatu ʼl-maʻqūli
li-taḥṣīli ʼl-majhūli; al-fikru ḥarakatun ilā ʼl-mabādiʼ / wa min mabādiʼ ilā ʼl-
murādi.
4
premises may be inaccurate, i.e. the subject matter of reasoning
may be accurate, but the form of reasoning may be unfounded.
5
2. The Subject of Logic
6
For instance, in discussing the states of ‘man’ we have to deal with
his aspect as an animal and his identification with an animal, and
the fact that animal properties are to be found in him; hence the
usage of the term essential accident, which is determined by some
specific definition to avoid that confusion and it may, in logical
terms, be dissociated from non-essential accidents (‘awāriḍ al-
gharibah). The definition of essential accidents is beyond the
scope of this textbook.
7
treat quantity. Accordingly, the subject of a science, i.e.
what is treated in the problems of that science, intertwine
with the problems of sciences; otherwise, the problems of
sciences would not be closely connected, in which case,
the relation between two arithmetical problems would
have been on a par with that of an arithmetical problem
with a medical or physical one. Therefore, any science
requires some subject and the distinction among sciences
lie in that of the subjects of those sciences.
2. Based on the second theory, the interrelation among
sciences arises from their applications and effects. Given
that a specific subject be not surrounded by a series of
problems and every problem belong to a different subject,
in case those problems share certain applications, subjects,
and goals, they are considered as interconnected and
distinctions may be drawn between them and further
problems treated in further sciences.
Nonetheless, this theory is unfounded. The homogeneity
and identity of a series of problems in terms of effects,
applications, and goals arise from the essential similarity
of those problems which in turn stems from the fact that
all those problems constitute the states and accidents of a
specific subject.
8
Logic demonstrates the accurate method of definition and
argumentation. Definiens and argument, the subject of logic, will
be further treated below.
9
perception are ignorance and denseness respectively. When we see
someone whom we have not seen earlier, or we visit a city which
we have not visited before, we feel that we have something which
we formerly lacked which is a conception of that person or that
city.
4
Al-‘ilmu huwa ʼl-ṣūratu ʼl-ḥāṣilatu min al-shayʼi ‘ind al-‘aqli.
10
However, mind, in its perceptive relation to objects, does not
assume a judgemental state. It happens that it perceives them
without passing any judgement on them. In cases where it assumes
a judgemental state and passes a judgement between two objects,
the opinion formed is termed as judgement and the judged
(maḥkūmunun ‘alayhi) and the object of judgment (maḥkūmunun
bihi) - i.e. the two objects judged by mind, which are formed in
the mind – are different things. Conceptions are the forms between
which the mind judges.
Therefore, when one judges in his mind that the weather is hot,
that feedback is judgement, but the mentally posited forms of
weather and heat are conceptions.
11
For instance, the conceptions of heat and cold require no
reasoning, hence their necessity; however, we need to think to
conceive angels and jinn, hence their theoretical nature.
5
Ambiguity and disambiguity of conceptions were treated in the footnotes of
the second volume of our Uṣūl-i Falsafah (Principles of Philosophy), wherein it is
discussed that they arise from simplicity and composition. Simple mentally posited
elements are clear and necessary, but composite ones are theoretical and in need of
definition. Necessary conceptions are like those of existence, inexistence, necessity,
possibility, and impossibility. Theoretical ones are like those of man, animal, heat,
cold, triangle, square, and the like.
12
4. Universal and Particular
Further conception are formed in the mind for which there exist a
series of names to signify those meanings and conceptions,
instances of which include conceptions of man, fire, city,
mountain, and the like. General (‘āmm) nouns are used to
designate such conceptions which are termed as ‘universal’, since
13
they are applicable to many an member and they are even
potentially applicable to an infinite number of members.
14
Equivalence denotes that each of the two universals applies to all
the members of the other; i.e. these two universals share the same
domain, in which case the relation between the two universals is
equivalent and the two universals are termed as the two
equivalents (mutasāwiyayn).
The first is like man and tree. No man is a tree and no tree is a
man. Man does not include the tree members. Neither man
includes tree members, nor human members are included by tree.
Neither man includes anything from the domain of the tree, nor a
tree includes anything from the human domain.
The second is like man and surprised. Any man is surprised and
any surprised is man. The human domain is the same as the
surprised’s domain and the domain of the surprised is the same as
the human domain
The third is like man an animal. Any man is an animal, but any
animal is not a man. For instance, a horse is an animal, but not a
15
man. Some animals are men, like human members who are both
human and animal.
The fourth is like man and white. Some men are white and some
whites are men (men of the white race), but some men are not
white (like men of the black and yellow races) and some whites
are not men, like snow which is white, but not human).
16
It is stated that when any universal is considered in relation to the
members of that universal and its relation to its members be
considered, it falls into one of the following five categories: 1.
Species (nawʻ); 2. Genus (jins); 3. Differentia (faṣl); 4. General
accident (‘araḍ-i ‘āmm); 5. Particular accident (‘araḍ-i khāṣṣ).
17
included by the essence of its members, e.g. line, surface, and
volume. They are all quantities plus something else; in other
words, quantity is partially, rather than completely, included in
their essence, rather than anything beyond their essence.
6
As mentioned above, if a universal be particular to essence, it is either more
general than essence or it is equal to it; in that if a universal be particular to essence,
it may possess one two relations from among the four relations, i.e. complete
generality and equivalence. A question arises here: What about the other two
relations? Could a universal be particular to essence and be simultaneously exclusive
to essence or more general than partial inclusion to essence? The answer is negative.
Why? The answer fall in the domain of philosophy and the answer is philosophically
clear, but we do not treat it for the time being.
It is also worthy of note in passing that the relation of complete inclusion
between particular to essence and essence is always such that it is particular to
essence and more general than essence and the more particular to essence than
particular to essence, but it is impossible vice versa, in that it is not possible for
essence to be more general than particular to essence. This is also discussed in the
domain of philosophy.
18
5. Definitions
19
It goes without saying that preliminary discussions of any
discipline treat a series of definitions of the subjects dealt with in
that field; nonetheless, definitions used in any discipline are
different from its problems, in that they are extraneous to that
discipline but they are employed for conceptual clarification.
Logical judgements provide us with an authentic method to define
concepts.
Inquiries
It is not for logic, but for philosophy and sciences, to address such
inquiries which concern extraneous objects. However, logic is
concerned with the answers provided by philosophy and sciences;
i.e. such questions are not addressed by logic, but it provides the
20
manner of producing valid answers. In fact, only one of the
qualities is addressed by logic and that is the quality of valid
reasoning; nonetheless, this quality concerns how it should be,
rather than how it is.7
Considering the fact that all questions, but the first and the last
ones, may be asked by the interrogative particle hal in Arabic or
āyā in Persian, all these questions may be reduced to three main
questions: ‘What is it?’ (Arabic mā, Persian chīst); ‘Is / Does ...?’
(Arabic hal, Persian āyā); ‘Why?’ (Arabic li-ma, Persian chirā).
7
Which science is supposed to provide answers to these questions? It is
proved in theology that theology is supposed to answer the first two questions, i.e.
whatness and existence. Regarding the ninth question, i.e. whyness, if the question
addresses the primary causes, i.e. the causes not caused by causes, the answer is
supposed to be provided by theology, but if the inquiry concerns immediate and
particular causes, the sciences are supposed to answer them. The sciences are
supposed to reply to a large number of questions concerning, the manners, quantities,
places, and times, and the sciences are diversified by the number of the subjects
investigated therein.
8
Ussu ʼl-maṭālibi thalāthatu ‘ilmi / maṭlabu mā, maṭlabu hal, maṭlabu lim.
21
achievable, our definition would be imperfect definition (ḥadd-i
nāqiṣ). Now, when the accidents and judgements, rather than the
constituents of essence and quiddity of an object be achievable, or
if we simply intend to delineate the boundaries of a concept, as to
what is embodied by it, and we have sufficient judgments and
accidents to distinguish between it and other concepts, such
definition would be a perfect definition by accident (rasm-i tāmm),
but if such distinction may not be neatly drawn, it would be
imperfect definition by accident (rasm-i nāqiṣ).
9
For further details, see Ṣadr al-Dīn Shīrāzī’s annotations on the logical
sections of the commentary on Ḥikmat al-Ishrāq.
22
6. Judgments: Propositions
Logic deals with meanings and perceptions, but does not directly
touch upon terms (in contrast to grammar), and any logical
definition, classification, or statement is intertwined with
meanings and perceptions, but it inevitably treats, at times, the
definitions and classifications of terms for their semantic
relevance; in other words, those terms are classified in terms of
their meanings and definitions.
10
Manṭiqī dar band-i baḥth-i lafẓ nīst / līk baḥth-i lafẓ ū rā
‘āriḍī ʼst.
23
animal, but esroh is non-significant or indefinite and it is not a
discourse.
24
indicates some reality, something that happened, is happening, or
is to happen, something that was, is, or will be. For instance, ‘I
went to pilgrimage to Mecca last year’; ‘I will take the MA
entrance exams next year’; ‘I am ill now’; ‘Iron expands as it is
heated’.
What has been mentioned so far concerns discourse and term, but
meanings are mainly intended herein. Any verbal proposition
25
(Arabic qaḍiyyat al-lafẓiyyah, qaḍiyyat al-malfūẓah, Persian
qaḍiyyah-yi lafẓī, qaḍiyyah-yi malfūẓah) is equal to a mentally
posited (dhihniyyah) and intelligible (maʻqūlah) proposition. In
other words, the term proposition is applied to the verbal form of
‘Zayd is standing’ and the meaning that is in our mind is also
referred to as proposition. The verbal form of this sentence is
termed as verbal proposition and the meaning is termed as
intelligible proposition.
26
7. Classification of Propositions
The subject and the predicate are the two terms (ṭaraf, dual
ṭarafayn, pl. aṭrāf) of a categorical proposition. These two terms
27
should always be simple (mufrad) and/or imperfect composite. If
we say, ‘Watermelon is useful’ the subject of the proposition is an
imperfect composite, but a perfect composite may never be one
term or both terms of a categorical proposition.
28
either a relation of compatibility (mutual implication or
equipollence, talāzum) or one of incompatibility (taʻānud).
29
Accordingly, propositions, in the former classification, fall into
categorical (or attributive) and conditional; conditional
propositions, in turn, divide into conjunctive and disjunctive.
30
instance, when we say, ‘Zayd is standing’, it is an affirmative
categorical proposition. When we say, ‘This is not the case that
Zayd is standing’, it is a negative categorical proposition. ‘If it
rains abundantly, crops will be abundant’ and ‘If it does not rain
on the mountains / Tigris will dry out’ are affirmative conjunctive
conditional propositions. ‘It is not true that if it rains abundantly,
crops will be scarce’ is a negative conjunctive conditional
proposition. ‘A number is either even or odd’ is an affirmative
disjunctive conditional proposition. ‘It is not true that a number is
either even or another number’ is a negative disjunctive
conditional proposition.
31
conceived in the mind (mā bi-hi yunẓar), and the universal
conception serves as a means to express some judgment or
statement about the members of a universal. The former may be
likened to a mirror which is seen and the latter resembles a mirror
wherein reflections are seen.
32
either being mentioned or not. If there is no mention of such
quantities, we will have an indefinite proposition (Arabic qaḍiyyat
al-muhmalah, Persian qaḍiyyah-yi muhmalah). Such propositions
lack independent validity in sciences and philosophy and they
should be classified as quantified particular propositions; for
instance, when we say, ‘Man is hasty’, we do not clarify if all or
some of men are hasty.
Particular negative, e.g. ‘Some animals are not men’ (baʻḍu ʼl-
ḥayawāni laysa bi-insānin).
33
- rather than singular, physical and indefinite ones - are used in
sciences.
Necessity falls into different categories, but we may not deal with
them here. Necessity and probability constitute the modality of
propositions (Arabic jahat al-qaḍāyā, Persian jahat-i qaḍāyā) and
a proposition wherein modality is attested is termed as modal
proposition (qaḍiyyat al-muwajjahah, Persian qaḍiyyah-yi
muwajjahah), but when modality is not to be attested therein, it is
34
termed as assertoric proposition (Arabic qaḍiyyat al-muṭlaqah,
Persian qaḍiyyah-yi muṭlaqah).
35
8. Relations between Propositions
11
In comparison, two propositions either share or do not share their subjects
and/or predicates. If they do not share anything, e.g. ‘Man is a surprised animal’ or
‘Iron is a metal and expands as it is heated’, there is no common denominator
between these two propositions and they are mutually exclusive. When they simply
share their subject, e.g. ‘Man is surprised’ and ‘Man is crafting’, they are equivalents
and they may be termed as the mutually corresponding propositions
(mutamāthilayn). When they only share their predicate, e.g. ‘Man is a mammal’ and
‘Horse is a mammal’, they are similar (mutashābihayn).
However, logicians, in discussing the relations between propositions, do not
attend to whether they share a common denominator or not. In their discussions on
the relations between propositions, they simply consider if two propositions both
share the same subject and predicate, and whether they differ in quantity (kamm), i.e.
universality and particularity, or in quality (kayfiyyah), i.e. affirmation (ījāb) and
negation (salb), or both. Such propositions are termed as the two opposites
(mutaqābilayn), which fall, in turn, into contradictories (mutanāqiḍayn); contraries
(mutaḍāddayn); subalterns (mutadākhilayn); subalterns in contrariety (dākhilayn taḥt
al-taḍādd).
36
well as quality, i.e. they differ in terms of universality and
particularity as well as affirmation and negation; instances of
which include: ‘Any man is surprised’ and ‘Some men are not
surprised’.
When they differ in quality, i.e. one is affirmative and the other is
negative, and they also share quantity, i.e. universality and
particularity. They fall into two categories: they are either both
universal or both particular. If they are both universal, they are
termed as contraries (mutaḍāddayn), e.g. ‘Any man is surprised’
and ‘No man is surprised’. But, in case they are both particular,
they are termed as subalterns in contrariety (dākhilayn taḥt al-
taḍādd), e.g. ‘Some men are surprised’ and ‘Some men are not
surprised’.
37
are termed as coexistence of contraries (Arabic ijtimāʻ al-
naqīḍayn, Persian ijtimāʻ-i naqīḍayn) and negation of contraries
(Arabic irtifāʻ al-naqīḍayn, Persian irtifāʻ-i naqīḍayn)
respectively. This is the law of contrariety which is frequently
discussed these days.
38
In the fourth category, both propositions are either affirmative or
both are negative, but one is universal and the other is particular. It
is worthy of note that in propositions, in contrast to simples, the
particular is always more general than the universal. In simples the
universal is always more general than the particular. For instance,
man is more general than Zayd, but in propositions, the
proposition ‘Some A’s are B’ is more general than the proposition
‘Any A is B’, since if any A be B, some A’s are certainly B, but if
some A’s be B, all A’s are not necessarily B. Asserting the more
general proposition does not necessarily require the assertion of
the more particular proposition, but the assertion of the more
particular necessitates the assertion of the more general
proposition, and the denial of the more particular proposition does
not necessitate the denial of the more general proposition;
however, the denial of the more general proposition necessitates
the denial of the more particular proposition.
39
9. Contradiction – Conversion
40
Potentiality and actuality and finally time.12
When we say, ‘Man laughs, horse does not laugh’ there is not an
instance of contradiction (tanāquḍ), since the subjects are not
identical. When we say, ‘Man laughs, Man is not quadruped’ there
is no contrariety, since the predicates are not identical. When we
say, ‘If moon eclipse occurs, it will be obligatory to establish the
prayers for the occurrence of natural phenomena (ṣalāt al-āyāt),
but if it does not occur, it will not be obligatory to establish such
prayers, there is no contrariety, since the conditions are different.
If we say, ‘Man is not scared in the day, man is scared at night,
there is no contradiction, since the times are different. If we say,
‘The weight of a litre of water is one kilogramme on the earth and
it is, for instance, half a kilogramme in the atmosphere [i.e. in the
high altitudes], there is no contradiction, since the places are not
identical. ‘Human knowledge is variable, divine knowledge is
invariable’ is not contradictory, since the relations, ad hoc, the
second or governed nouns of the genitive constructs, muḍāfun
‘alayhi, of the two subjects, are not identical. There is no
contradiction in ‘The total area of Tehran is 1,600 km2 and some
part of the area of Tehran, e.g. east of Tehran, is not 1,600 km2’,
since they are different in terms of particularity and universality.
There is no contradiction in ‘Any human infant is potentially
diligent and some human infants are not diligent in actuality’,
since they are not identical in terms of potentiality and actuality.
12
Dar tanāquḍ hath waḥdat sharṭ dān,
41
The same conditions apply to the contraries (mutaḍāddayn),
subalterns in contrariety (dākhilayn taḥt al-taḍādd), and subalterns
(mutadākhilayn), in that two propositions are contraries or
subalterns in contrariety, or subalterns if they share the above said
unities.
42
Similarly, ‘Nothing of the man is of stone’ (lā shayʼa min ʼl-insāni
bi-ḥajarin), which is the universal negative, is the contradiction of
‘It is not the case that nothing of the man is of stone’ (laysa lā
shayʼa min ʼl-insāni bi-ḥajarin), and when we say, ‘Some
constituents of man are of stone’ is its contradiction, by which we
intend to say that the relation of contradiction applies to it.
43
universe, or vice versa. In this case, the state of preferring
one of the alternatives over the other is termed as opinion
(Arabic and Persian ẓann, Persian gumān).
3. In the third case, one term is totally negated and regarded
as impossible in its entirety, and the mind exclusively and
certainly inclines toward one term, and this state is termed
as certitude (yaqīn).
44
may be assumed that they both apply simultaneously.
Accordingly, both terms of the proposition are equal to our mind;
consequently, our mind may never attain certitude, since attaining
certitude is dependent on the decisive inclination of the mind
toward one of the two terms and the total negation of the other
term.
Conversion
45
propositions used in sciences are quantified ones. Now, we must
take into account the quantified propositions in stating the
conditions of simple converses and contrapositions.
13
In other words, when the simple converse of a proposition be affirmative,
the contraposition of it would also be affirmative, and when the simple converse of a
proposition be universal, its contraposition would be affirmative and vice versa.
46
According to the second definition, [simple conversion and
contraposition] differ in terms of affirmation and negation, i.e. the
converse of a universal affirmative is a universal negative, and the
converse of a universal negative is a particular affirmative, and the
converse of a particular negative is a particular affirmative, and
there is no converse for a particular affirmative. Examples are
mentioned here for the sake of brevity.14
14
What has been mentioned so far regarding the classifications and relations
of propositions are applicable to categorical/attributive as well as conditional
propositions. However, the fact that we have so far provided examples from
categorical/attributive propositions should not lead to the passivity of the mind. It is
to be noted in passing that conditional propositions, whether conjunctive or
disjunctive, are governed by a series of particular relations, termed as requirements
of conjunctions and disjunctions (Arabic lawāzim al-muttaṣilāt wa ʼl-munfaṣilāt,
Persian lawāzim-i muttaṣilāt wa munfaṣilāt), but they are not touched upon herein
for brevity’s sake.
47
10. Syllogism
What is a syllogism?
48
a mental operation whereby prior facts and knowledge are used to
obtain a conclusion and convert something unknown into
something known. Our definition of syllogism indicates that it is a
kind of reasoning.
Categories of Arguments
Arguments (ḥujaj, sg. Arabic ḥujjah, Persian ḥujjat) fall into three
categories, in that our mind may take three courses in proceeding
from a known proposition or some known propositions toward an
unknown proposition:
49
Proceeding from particular to particular and from mutually
exclusive to mutually exclusive is termed as tamthīl by logicians
and qiyās by jurisprudents and uṣūlīs.16 Proceeding from particular
to universal is termed by logicians as induction (istiqrāʼ) and
proceeding from universal to particular is termed by logicians and
philosophers as deduction (qiyās).17
16
Logicians use the term tamthīl and jurisprudents and uṣūlīs,
i.e. experts in the principles of jurisprudence, use the term
deduction (qiyās). It is reported that Abū Ḥanīfah made use of
analogy in jurisprudence, i.e. he used logical analogy or tamthīl.
17
A question arises here concerning an assumed fourth
category: proceeding from universal to universal. How should it be
termed? What would be its validity? The answer is that two
universals are either mutually exclusive or equivalent or complete
inclusion or partial inclusion. The first of these four categories falls
into analogy, since, as mentioned earlier, analogy is not specific to
particular; proceeding from particular to particular is termed as
analogy since whereby the mind proceeds from mutual exclusion to
mutual exclusion. Nonetheless, if two universals are instances of
complete inclusion and partial inclusion and the mind proceeds
from specific to general, it falls into the category of induction, but if
it proceeds from general to specific, it is a category of deduction. If
two universals be equivalent, they are instances of deduction, and if
they be instances of partial inclusion, they fall into the category of
analogy.
50
2. The mind is able to reason validly or invalidly when it has
access to some known facts, in that it is unable to reason,
even to reason invalidly, with access to one known fact. In
deduction, it even deals with more than one known fact.
3. Prior knowledge paves the path for the operations of the
mind and reasoning, even invalid reasoning, when the
acquired knowledge is not purely inconsistent. A new
thought may not emerge from a multitude of knowledge
lacking middle terms.
18
A question arises here: Based on the aforesaid points,
knowledge is acquired through either direct observation or
reasoning, and reasoning falls into analogy, deduction, induction.
What is the role of experiment and into which category does it fall?
The answer is that experiment (tajribah) falls into the category of
deductive reasoning aided by observation, but the deduction formed
therein, as maintained by prominent logicians, is enthymeme
(qiyās-i khafiyy), which is formed by the mind per se, and it will be
treated elsewhere in our discussions. Some later authors have
invalidly classified experiment as a type of induction.
51
11. Syllogistic Categories
52
(aṣghar) and major (akbar) respectively, and each of the two is
attested in one of the two premises.
Hypothetical Syllogism
19
Now let us consider this question: Does a hypothetical
syllogism in any of its forms - i.e. whether with a conjunctive or
disjunctive premise, and whether with a hypothetical antecedent or
a hypothetical consequent, whether asserting or denying the
antecedent or the consequent – leads to a conclusion or it is
concluding (muntij) in some of these forms? The answer is that it is
53
Conjunctive Proposition
‘Iron is a metal.’
Metal plays the role of the middle term. The middle term should
be attested in both the minor and the major. Accordingly, the
terms of syllogism are the following: 1. Minor term; 2. Major
term; 3. Middle term.
The middle term, serving as a nexus between the minor and the
major, is attested in both premises and renders them consistent.
First Figure
54
In the first figure, the middle term occurs as the predicate in the
minor and as the subject in the major. ‘Any Muslim believes in the
Qur’an. Any believer in the Qur’an acknowledges the equality of
races, asserted by the Qur’an. Therefore, any Muslim
acknowledges the equality of races’ is an instance of the first
figure, since the middle term (believer) is the predicate in the
minor and the subject in the major. This is the most natural of
conjunctive syllogisms. The conclusion of the first figure is self-
evident; i.e. when the two premises are true and they occur in the
first figure, their conclusion will be evidently true. In other words,
when we assert the two premises and they occur in the first figure,
they will evidently and decisively be concluding. Accordingly,
there would be no need to produce demonstrations for the
conclusiveness of the first figure; in contrast, the conclusiveness
of the other three figures requires demonstration.
Second Figure
55
In the second figure, the middle term is the predicate of both
premises, an instance of which is: ‘Any Muslim believes in the
Qur’an. No fire worshipper believes in the Qur’an. Therefore, no
Muslim worships fire.
In the third figure the middle term serves as the subject of both
premises; an instance of which is ‘Any man seeks knowledge by
his innate disposition. Any man seeks justice by his innate
disposition. Therefore, some of those who seek knowledge seek
justice as well.’
56
the two premises. Nonetheless, this is a non-concluding syllogism:
‘No man is ruminant; any man is a writer’, since the minor term is
negative. ‘Some men are knowledgeable; some men are just’ is
non-concluding, since both premises are particular, but one of the
two premises should be universal.
In the fourth figure, the middle term is in the subject of the minor
premise and in the predicate of the major premise. This is the most
far-fetched of the figures. This is perhaps for this very low
frequency that this figure is not attested in Aristotle’s Organon,
but it was added later by logicians. The conditions of this figure
are not uniform, i.e. it may occur in any of these two forms: 1.
Both premises are affirmative and the minor term is universal; 2.
Both premises differ in terms of affirmation and negation; one of
the two premises is universal. Since we deal with the principles
and generalities of logic rather than elaborating on logical
syllogisms, we will not touch upon examples which are
concluding and non-concluding syllogisms.20
20
This mnemonic poem is mentioned in some books on logic
to help students memorize the four figures:
When the middle term is the predicate of the minor
And the subject of the major we have the first figure.
When the middle term serves as the predicate of both
[premises], it is the second [figure]; when the middle term serves as
the subject of both premises, it is the third [figure].
The fourth figure is the converse of the first [figure].
awsaṭ agar ḥaml yāft dar bar-i ṣughrā u bāz,
waḍʻ bih kubrā girift shekl-i nakhustīn shumār.
ḥaml bih har du duwwum, waḍʻ bih har du siwwum
rābiʻ-i ashkāl rā ‘aks-i nakhustīn shumār.
57
12. Validity of Syllogism (1)
21
Syllogisms are used in many a discipline. Experimental
sciences are not deprived of syllogism, but according to precise
studies of logicians like Avicenna and Naṣīr al-Dīn Ṭūsī, a
syllogism is to be found in any experiment (we have dealt with it in
the footnotes of the second volume to Principles of Philosophy,
Uṣūl-i Falsafah). If it is asserted that syllogism is invalid, all
sciences, rather than only those evidently employing it in their
reasoning and argumentation, will lose their validity. It is worthy of
note that in such case, philosophy is the first discipline to lose its
validity, since it is more syllogistic than any other discipline. Logic
will be invalid as well, since: 1. Syllogisms are employed in logical
reasoning and argumentation; 2. The majority of logical laws,
directly or indirectly, concern the quality of syllogism and when
syllogism be invalid, most of logical laws would be stripped of
subject.
58
is an operation of the mind. However, it is discussed as a subject
of logic, since it is a type of argument which constitutes one of the
two subjects of logic. What is a part of logic and is termed as the
gate to syllogism consists of the laws governing syllogism, stating
that a syllogism is supposed to have such and such conditions and
requirements; similar to the human body which is no part of any
discipline, but the scientific problems are related to the human
body which is a part of physiology or medicine.
59
Tawḥīdī reports a scholarly debate on the validity of logic between
Sīrāfī and Mattā ibn Yūnus, the Christian philosopher, in the
presence of Ibn al-Furāt. This report is recounted in Muḥammad
Abū Zahrah’s monograph, Ibn Taymiyyah. Ibn Taymiyyah, a
prominent Sunni jurisprudent and traditionist and the main
progenitor of Wahhābism wrote a refutation on logic entitled al-
Radd ‘alā ʼl-Manṭiq.
60
Before we embark upon suggesting the critiques and the responses
to them, we need to define thinking, whose definition we
deliberately postponed. We need to define them since syllogism is
a type of reasoning and we also mentioned above that the debates
between the proponents and opponents of Aristotelian logic
concern the validity of syllogism and in fact concern the validity
of this type of reasoning. The opponents maintain that this
accurate type of reasoning is invalid and the proponents hold that
syllogistic reasoning is not only valid, but any other type of
reasoning is consciously or unconsciously based on syllogistic
reasoning.
Definition of Thinking
61
recollection. It is quite ordered. It is as if the
reminiscences of our mind are intertwined like the links of
a chain. The links emerge sequentially and in
psychological terms, there is some association (tadāʻī).
Such association is reflected in the proverb, one word
leads to another (al-kalāmu yajurru ʼl-kalām). It is the
same as association of ideas and sequence of thoughts.
Accordingly, besides its simply passive impressionability
and collection and preservation, the mind is also engaged
in operations, in that it retrieves or reminisces the
collected forms based on a series of specific laws, as
discussed in psychology. It operates on the collected
forms through association of ideas without significant
changes made to them.
3. Analysis is the third operation of the mind, in that in
addition to the two above said operations, it analyses a
specific form impressed on it from the external world. The
mind decomposes and analyses it, whereas such
decomposition and analysis do not occur in the external
world. There are different forms of analysis. A form may
be at times decomposed into several forms or it may be
decomposed into several meanings. In the former, the
mind decomposes a form into several forms like the
mental decomposition of an organ which is a combination
of constituents and such function is based on the capacity
of the mind and whereby it is connected to other things. In
the latter, the mind decomposes one form into several
meanings; for instance the mind defines ‘line’ as a one-
dimensional continuous quantity, i.e. it decomposes the
quiddity of the line into three constituents: quantity,
continuity, single dimension; nonetheless, these three
constituents do not exist in the external world. The mind
62
at times composes and there are different types of
composition. One type is to intertwine several forms, like
depicting a horse with a human face. Philosophers deal
with the decomposition, analysis, and composition of
meanings. In contrast, a poet and an artist deal with the
decomposition and composition of forms.
4. Specification (tajrīd) and generalization (taʻmīm).
Another operation of the mind is to specify the particular
and conceived forms received through sense perception,
i.e. it separates or parcels up several things which always
collocate and the mind has received them as a whole. For
instance, it receives a number through some noun
determined by the number (maʻdūd) and along with a
material object, but it later decomposes and parcels up the
number from its determined noun.
Generalization is a more advanced process whereby the
mind converts the particular and receives forms into
universal concepts. For instance, it receives the forms of
specific individuals, like Zayd, ‘Amr, Aḥmad, Ḥasan, and
Maḥmūd, through sense perception, but converts all of
them into man, a general and universal concept.
It goes without saying that the mind never perceives the
universal concept of man through the senses, but having
perceived particular human beings, like Ḥasan, Maḥmūd,
and Aḥmad, it converts all of them into a general and
universal form. Accordingly, in decomposition and
composition as well as in specification and generalization,
the mind makes alterations in sense perceptions, at times
through decomposition and composition, and at times
through specification and generalization.
5. Our main goal lies in the fifth operation of the mind –
thinking and reasoning whereby a series of known things
63
are intertwined in order to discover an unknown thing.
Thinking is actually a type of coupling and procreation of
ideas; in other words, thinking is a type of thought
investment aiming to gain benefits and to increment the
capital. The operation of thinking is a type of composition,
but a generative and concluding one, in contrast to
poetical and wishful compositions which are sterile and
non-concluding
In discussing the validity of syllogism, one should
consider this problem: Is the mind actually able to achieve
a new known thing through the composition of facts and
thereby convert something unknown into something
known, or the only approach to gain knowledge and
convert the unknown into known is to add to its
knowledge through direct relation with the external
world? Is it possible to gain knowledge through
intertwining the knowledge inside the mind?
The different views of experimentalists and sensationalists
on the one hand and those of rationalists and analogists on
the other lie in this point. Experimentalists hold that the
only approach to gaining new knowledge is to connect to
external objects through the senses and the valid method
of investigating the objects is to make use of experiment.
However, rationalists and analogists maintain that
experiment is one of the possible approaches, but new
knowledge may be gained through intertwining the known
facts and also previous knowledge and establishing such
knowledge aiming to gain further knowledge is termed as
definition by essence (ḥadd), deduction (qiyās), and
demonstration (burhān).
Acknowledging the validity of experiment and
recognizing it as one of the six principles of deduction,
64
Aristotelian logic further presents the laws governing
syllogisms which include the employment of the known
for discovering the unknown and converting the unknown
into known. It goes without saying that Aristotelian logic
would be meaningless and fruitless if the approach to the
acquisition of knowledge were restricted to direct contact
with the unknown, and the known may not be employed to
discover the unknown.
We herein decompose and analyse a simple example
which is usually presented as a puzzle to the students so
that it may be clarified that the method through which the
mind at times makes use of the known to unravel some
unknown. Put the case that there are five hats, three of
which are white and two of them are red. Three
individuals are sitting on different steps of a ladder and
the one who is on the third step sees the other two, the one
sitting on the second step only sees the one sitting on the
first step, and the one sitting on the first step does not see
the other two. The first and the second individuals are not
allowed to look behind them. They are blindfolded when
one of the hats is put on the head of each of them and the
other two hats are concealed. Then, the blindfolds are
removed and each of them is inquired about the colour of
the hat that he is wearing. The one on the third step,
having looked at the hats of the other two, thinks for a
while and says, ‘I don’t know.’ The one sitting on the
second step, having looked at the hat of the one sitting on
the first step discovers the colour of his own hat and says
that he is wearing a white hat. The one sitting on the first
step immediately says, ‘My hat is red.’
Now, we may inquire about the methods of the first two
individuals who discovered the colours of their hats
65
without seeing them. Did they use any type of reasoning
other than deduction? Why was the third individual unable
to discover the colour of his hat?
The answer to the last question is that the colours of the
hats of the first and the second individuals did not provide
him with any evidence, since one was white and other was
red. Besides those two hats there were three other hats one
of which was red and two were white and his hat could be
either white or red. Therefore, he said that he did not
know. He could discover the colour of his hat only if the
hats of the other two were both red. In that case, he could
say that his hat was white, since he saw that the other two
individuals were wearing red hats, and since he knew that
there were only two red hats, he could discover that his
hat was white. However, since the other two wore red and
white hats, he was unable to discover the colour of his
own hat. The second individual, having heard that the
third one said that he did not know, discovered that the
first one and himself were not wearing red hats, unless the
third one would not have said that he did not know, but
could discover the colour of his hat. Accordingly, his own
hat and that of the first one should be white or one of them
should wear white and the other red. Since he saw that the
first individual’s hat was red, he discovered that his hat
was white; i.e. he discovered, from the fact that none of
the hats were red (based on what the third one had said)
and that the first one was wearing a red hat discovered that
his own hat was white.
The first one succeeded in discovering that he was
wearing a red hat, since he learned from the third one that
his hat and that of the second one were not both red, and
he learned from what the second individual had said that
66
he was wearing a white hat that his hat could not be white,
since if it were white, the second individual could not
have succeeded in discovering the colour of his own hat,
and it was by knowing those two facts that he discovered
the colour of his hat which was red.
This is a student game, but it is a good example for the
operations of the mind whereby without the aid of
observation, it discovers something unknown simply
through deduction and analysis. The mind, in such
instances, forms a syllogism and attains to a conclusion. If
one reflects on the point, he will perceive that the mind, in
such instances, does not only deduce, but it forms various
syllogism; nonetheless, the mind forms them and comes to
a conclusion so instantaneously that one does not notice
the numerous mental operations. It is useful to know the
logical laws governing syllogisms in that man knows the
valid methods of employing analogies and averts
numerous pitfalls.
The analogies formed by the second individual in
discovering the colour of his hat are the following: If the
colour of my hat and that of the first person were both red,
the third person would not have said that he did not know.
Nonetheless, he said that he did not know, so my hat and
that of the first person are not red (it is a hypothetical
syllogism and its conclusion so far is that the hats of the
first and the second persons are not red).
Now that my hat and that of the first one is not red, they
are either white or one is white and the other is red, but
they are not both white, since we notice that the first
person’s hat is red, so one is white and the other is red.
My hat is either white and that of the first person is red, or
the first person’s hat is white and mine is red.
67
Nonetheless, the first person’s hat is red; therefore, my hat
is white.
The abstract deduction of the first person are the
following: If my hat as well as the second person’s hat
were both red, the third person would not have said that he
did not know. Therefore, my hat and that of the second
person are not both red (hypothetical syllogism).
Now that they are not red, they are either white or one is
white and the other red. However, they are not both white,
since if both were white, the second person would have
been unable to discover that his hat was white. Therefore,
one hat is red and the other is white (another hypothetical
syllogism).
Now that one is white and the other red, either my hat is
white and that of the second person is red, or the second
person’s hat is white and mine is red. However, if my hat
were white, the second person would not have been able
to discover that his hat was red. Therefore, my hat is not
white, but red.
Observation lies in one of the premises of one of the three
syllogisms used by the second person, but it is not
employed in any of the syllogisms formed by the first
person.
68
13. Validity of Syllogism (2)
69
and/or perceptions might be faulty and unreliable and their
unreliability may be asserted. Aristotelian logic which is
termed as formal logic on this account is not responsible
for such unreliability, but it is responsible for presenting a
valid form of such propositions that disarrangement and
confusion may not lead to error.
70
chopper who collects materials; whereas logic is simply
an instrument of assessment in that it draws a distinction
between valid and invalid forms and figures of reasoning
rather than as material used in reasoning, hence its
likening to a plumb-line and a level wherewith a mason
measures the verticality and depth of a wall. These
instruments are neither used as those of collecting
construction materials, e.g. bricks, soil, lime, and cement,
nor as a means of assessing the quality of such materials.
71
is indubitably the instrument of the acquisition of
knowledge.
22
See the section on demonstration (burhān) of Manṭiq al-
Shifāʼ, Egypt, p. 223.
23
See the section on demonstration in Manṭiq al-Shifāʼ, pp.
95-97, 223, 331.
72
experimental method, which is a composition of pure
deduction, induction, and sensationalism, in discovering
nature. Former scholars’ discovery of nature, similar to
their treatment of metaphysical problems, was impeded by
their method of pure deduction. Neither former scholars
rejected induction and experiment in their adherence to
Aristotelian logic, nor later scholars refuted Aristotelian
logic, since it does not recognize deduction as the only
valid method to be applied to all the sciences so that
turning to induction and experiment be considered as
rejecting Aristotelian logic.24
3. Aristotelian logic accords particular significance to
syllogism which consists of two premises; for instance,
conjunctive syllogism, consisting of a minor and a major
syllogism, is not fruitful per se, since when the premises
of syllogism are known, the conclusion is self-evident, but
when the premises are unknown, the conclusion is
24
It is to be noted in passing that turning toward experiment
and turning away from the fetters of deduction began centuries ago
by Muslims, and European scholars continued this approach. Roger
Bacon, one of the forerunners of experimentalism who adopted that
approach three or four centuries before Francis Bacon, had
acknowledged his debt to his Muslim Andalusian teachers. The
other point is that when modern scholars turned toward the
experimental method for the first time went from one extreme to the
other, assuming that induction and experiment were the only means
of acquiring knowledge and thereby totally rejected the deductive
method. However, it became obvious after the passage of two to
three centuries that deduction, induction, and experiment (which
were in the Avicennan terms a composition of those two) were each
fruitful and necessary in their own right, and the significance should
be accorded to knowing their applications. Accordingly,
methodology, a quite fruitful discipline, came into being which
clarifies the applications of each of those methods, though this
discipline is still in its initial stages of development.
73
unknown as well. Thus, what is the application of
syllogism?
The response to this question is that the mere evidence of
the premises is not adequate to know the conclusion. The
conclusion becomes known when the premises are
conjunctive. Conjunction leads to conclusion, like
procreation without which no child may be born. The
point is that validly applied, a conjunction will lead to a
valid conclusion, and it is the function of logic to draw a
distinction between valid and invalid conjunctions.
4. Valid premises may only lead to valid conclusions, and
logic may not affect the rectification of errors, since the
validity of conclusions only lies in the application of valid
premises.
The response is that premises may be purely valid, but the
conclusions may be invalid owing to the application of
invalid figures and conjunctions. These errors may be
rectified by logic. This counterargument, like the previous
one, arises from not considering the role of proper forms,
figures, and structures in drawing valid conclusions. The
third and fourth counterarguments were suggested by
Descartes.25
5. Logic may at best impede the errors of the mind affecting
the form of syllogism, but it lacks any laws to impede the
penetration of error in the material of syllogism.
Accordingly, logic may assure us of the validity of the
form of syllogism, but it is unable to make us certain as to
the material of syllogism. Thus, error may find its way
into syllogism, hence the impracticality of logic. It would
be like closing, in winter, only one door of a house with
25
Furūghī, Muḥammad ‘Alī, Siyr-i Ḥikmat dar Urūpā
(History of Western Philosophy), vol. 1, pp. 138, 163.
74
two doors. It is evident that cold comes in from the open
door and closing one door is insufficient to keep the cold
out of the house. This counterargument was suggested by
Sīrāfī, the grammarian and theologian, in his debate with
Matā ibn Yūnus, and a good exposition of it is to be found
in Amīn Astarābādī’s Fawāʼid al-Madaniyyah.
The response is that impeding the penetration of error in
the form of syllogism is a relative use. The occurrence of
error in the material of syllogism, which may not be
safeguarded through logical laws, may be impeded by
sufficient precaution and consideration supported by the
application of logical laws in the form of syllogisms.
Likening the penetration of error through material and
form to that of cold from two doors is a fallacious
statement per se, since cold may find its way into the
house from each of the doors and make the house nearly
as cold as outdoors and closing one of the doors would be
in vain; nonetheless, it is impossible for the errors of the
form to penetrate through material or vice versa.
Accordingly, granted that we are not able to safeguard
syllogism from material errors, we will be able to
safeguard them from formal errors and thus gain some
relative advantage.
75
14. Validity of Syllogism (3)
76
knowledge of the proposition, ‘Any animal is corporeal’
depends on knowledge of animal species, including man,
wherewith we may know that they are animals. Thus,
knowing the major, i.e. any animal is corporeal, depends
on knowing a conclusion whose knowledge is dependent
on the knowledge of the major, knowing which is
dependent on knowing the conclusion. This is a vicious
circle.
77
Second, we should analyse the argument that knowledge
of the major is dependent on that of its particulars. If it is
intended that knowledge of the major depends on detailed
knowledge of its particulars, i.e. one has to first apply
induction to individual particulars to gain knowledge of a
universal, such argument is unfounded, since gaining
knowledge of a universal is not restricted to the
application of induction to particulars; since we have
knowledge of some universals without prior experiment
and induction, instances of which include our knowledge
of the impossibility of a vicious circle. Further, we gain
knowledge of universals through the experiments of few
individuals as to particulars and there is no need to
experiment further instances, instance of which include a
physician’s knowledge of the properties of medicine and
his patients’ complications. When some universal is
known through experimentation of few instances, it may
be generalized to further instances through a syllogism.
78
the conclusion as embedded in the major is non-detailed
and partial.
26
Al-Nashshār, ‘Alī Sāmī, al-Manṭiq al-Ṣūrī, pp. 21-22;
Furūghī, Muḥammad ‘Alī, Siyr-i Ḥikmat dar Urūpā, vol. 3, the
biography and philosophy of Stuart Mill; Khwānārī, Muḥammad,
Manṭiq-i Ṣūrī, vol. 2, p. 183.
79
therefore, there would be a reiteration of the known, nor
petitio principii.
3. Aristotelian logic is deductive and in deduction the mind
descends at all times, in that the mind proceeds from the
universal to the particular. It was formerly believed that
the mind initially understands the universals and it is
through the universals that it understands the particulars;
however, recent studies demonstrate that it is vice versa,
i.e. the mind ascends from the particular to the universal.
Nonetheless, the deductive method is rejected in recent
psychological studies on the mind and its operations. In
other words, deductive reasoning is unfounded and
induction is the only valid method of reasoning.
This critique is the scientific exposition of the criticisms
mentioned above. The response is that it is by no means
accurate to restrict the procession of the mind to its
descending course, since, first, as frequently mentioned
above, experiment and scientific conclusion derived from
experimental material demonstrates that the mind
proceeds in ascending as well as descending courses, since
it is through conducting several experiments of a general
law that the mind makes inferences and thereby proceeds
in an ascending course and deductively generalizes that
universal law in further instances in its proceeding in its
descending and deductive course.
Further, all the decisive laws of human mind are not based
on experiment and sense perception. Mental judgements
as to ‘A vicious circle is false’ or ‘One body may not be
present simultaneously in two different places’ and tens of
other similar judgements as to necessity or negation may
not be based on sense perception, induction, or
experiment.
80
How amazing! The argument ‘Deduction is proceeding
from the universal to the particular and the procession
from the universal to the particular is false and
impossible’ is a deductive argument per se and it moves in
a descending course. How may one employ deduction,
which is assumed by him to be false, to reject deduction?!
If deduction is false, this deduction is also false.
Accordingly, there is no argument to substantiate the
falsity of deduction.
4. It is assumed in Aristotelian logic that the relation
between two things in a proposition is in the form of
subsumption (indirāj). Therefore, deduction is restricted
to hypothetical and conjunctive and the latter is restricted
to the four figures, whereas there exist other relations
other than subsumption – equality, majority, and minority
which are applied in mathematics. For instance, it is said,
‘Angle A is equal to angle B; angle B is equal to angle C;
therefore, angle A is equal to angle C.’ This syllogism
does not fall into any of the four figures, since the middle
term is not repeated. In the second proposition, the
predicate is the concept of equality and in the second
proposition, the subject is the angle, rather than equality,
and this proposition is concluding. This criticism is
suggested by mathematical logicians in modern times like
Russell.
The response is that this syllogism is known by logicians,
at least by Muslim logicians, who term it as syllogism of
equipollence (Arabic qiyās al-musāwāh, Persian qiyās-i
musāwāt). They maintain that it consists of several
conjunctive syllogisms whose relations are subsumptive
(indirājī). For further details, books on logic, e.g.
Avicenna’s Ishārāt, may be consulted.
81
5. This logic is formally inadequate, since no distinction is
drawn therein between affirmative [and negative]
categorical propositions [e.g.] ‘Any man has a heart’
whose deep structure is: ‘If something comes into
existence and happens to be human, it should necessarily
possess a heart.’ Such failure to distinguish between the
two has led to colossal metaphysical errors.
The response is that Muslim logicians focus on this issue,
make such distinctions, and accordingly specify the
requirements of syllogism. These discussions fall beyond
the scope of our book.
6. Aristotelian logic is based on concepts and universals of
the mind, whereas universal concepts are not real and
concepts of the mind are particular, and universal is but a
meaningless term. This criticism is suggested by Stuart
Mill and this theory is known as nominalism. The
response is convincingly provided by philosophy.
7. Based on ipseity (Arabic huwiyyah, Persian huwiyyat),
Aristotelian logic considers that anything is itself at all
times, hence the fixity and invariability of concepts in this
logical system. Nonetheless, motion, the law governing
realities and concepts, is the alteration of something into
something else and this logical system is not in accord
with reality. The only valid logic is the one that inspires
motion into concepts and averts the principle of ipseity
and that is dialectic logic. This criticism is suggested by
the proponents of Hegelian logic, particularly those of
dialectic materialism. Discussions on these logical schools
are to be found in both volumes of our Uṣūl-i Falsafah
(Principles of Philosophy). Discussing this criticism is
also beyond the scope of our book.
82
8. Aristotelian logic is based on the law of non-contradiction,
whereas the law of contradiction is the most significant
law governing the mind and reality. This argument is
countered in both volumes of our Uṣūl-i Falsafah
(Principles of Philosophy). The law of non-contradiction
was also discussed above in section 8. Relation between
Propositions. It will be discussed below in Generalities of
Philosophy.
83
15. The Five Arts
84
Syllogisms at times aim to persuade the addressee to do or not to
do something; in which case it would be sufficient to make use of
opinions and non-decisive material. When we intend to prevent
somebody from committing some vice, we express the risks
involved in committing them.
85
2. A subjugating syllogism should consist of materials
asserted by the addressee, whether of certitude or not, be
acceptable or not. This type of syllogism is called dialectic
(jadal); for instance, somebody asserts the words of a
philosopher or jurisprudent and by making references to
that authority’ words, somebody is overcome in debate,
even if we do not acknowledge those words. Dialectic
syllogism may be illustrated by numerous examples, but
we suffice to relate an anecdote.
86
some opinion; for instance, ‘A liar is publicly disgraced’;
‘A coward is deprived and unsuccessful.’
4. Poetry implies a syllogism aiming at simply adorning [the
object] with beautiful and imaginary adornments. Similes
and metaphors embody all the poetical devices. Poetry is
directly related to imagination and since conceptions and
sentiments are intertwined, i.e. any conception awakens
the sentiments and whereby poetry controls sentiments
and may thus lead one to perform amazing things or it
may prevent one from doing them.
The best example would be Rūdakī’s (d. 329/940) poem
addressed to the Sāmānid ruler encouraging him to return
to Bukhārā:
O Bukhārā! Be happy and live happily!
The king is coming toward you as a guest.
The king is a cypress and Bukhārā is a garden,
The cypress is going toward the garden.
The king is the moon and Bukhārā is the sky,
The moon is going toward the sky.
87
Fallacies are either verbal (lafẓī) or material (maʻnawī).
The former arises from the form of syllogism, in that a
homonym (mushtarak-i lafẓī) with two different senses
serve as the middle term, bearing a sense in the minor and
bearing another in the major; accordingly, the form, rather
than the meaning, is reiterated and the conclusion arrived
at will be necessarily invalid.
88
should be governed by logical laws. Accordingly, this
type of fallacy emerges from the substitution of some
valid material with invalid material in a syllogism. It is
important to know different types of fallacies. It may be
stated that philosophers’ statements abound in fallacious
syllogisms, hence the significance to distinguish different
types of fallacies and their application to instances of
fallacious syllogisms.
89