Carroll (2002) - Instantaneous Motion.
Carroll (2002) - Instantaneous Motion.
CARROLL
INSTANTANEOUS MOTION
Our everyday thought and talk are strewed with mentions of objects’
having properties at an instant. For example, a few minutes ago, I
told a student that I would be in my office at 1:30 P.M. today. My
statement was consistent with my not being there at 1:29:59 P.M.
and consistent with my not being there at 1:30:01 P.M. In fact, my
statement was consistent with my not being there 0.0 . . . 01 seconds
before or after 1:30, no matter how many zeros are filled in.1
There is some resistance among philosophers to taking, at face-
value, apparent thought and talk of an object’s having a property at
an instant. Thanks to Zeno, this is especially true when the property
in question is motion. Sometimes, seeming allusions to motion at an
instant are taken to be descriptions of motion over a small temporal
interval (cf., “For at a moment it is not possible for anything to be
either in motion or at rest”, Aristotle, Physics 239b.) More often,
motion at an instant is taken somewhat more seriously; it is thought
to be definable in terms of motion over intervals. On this view,
instantaneous velocity is defined in terms of the object’s interval
velocities (cf., Anton, 1992, p. 311):
If s(t) is the position function of an object along a coordinate line, then the object’s
ds
velocity at time t0 is defined by: v(t0 ) = dt 0
= limt →t0 s(t t)−s(t
−t0 .
0)
(‘ds/dt’ is the symbolic name for the derivative of the function s(t),
which is defined by the given limit expression.) What this definition
Tooley and by Bigelow and Pargetter. They all involve an object that
exists for a nonzero temporal interval. Then I will ask the reader to
make a judgment of whether there was a change in the motion of the
object during that interval or ask the reader to make a counterfactual
judgment of whether there would have been a change in the motion
during that interval if certain events had not occurred. We are often
prepared to make these judgments without making any prior judg-
ments about the motion of the object at the particular instant in
question. These change-of-motion intuitions will reinforce the prob-
lems for the Russellian view revealed by Tooley and by Bigelow and
Pargetter.
This is a project that is squarely within contemporary meta-
physics. My project is analogous to metaphysicians’ attempts to
criticize some extant account of, say, lawhood or causation. I will
show that the Russellian view does not state necessary and suffi-
cient conditions for instantaneous motion by presenting possible
situations where it is plausible to think that this view is false. As is
the norm with critical metaphysics, the issue is whether the view in
question is necessarily true. My arguments do not clearly undermine
the truth of the Russellian view and hence do not clearly undermine
the uses physics makes of the standard definition of velocity. Indeed,
as I speculate in the final section of my paper, I believe that this
is one reason why the Russellian view remains the received view.
This does nothing to diminish the importance of my thesis. Aside
from my thesis’s straightforward importance to better understanding
the nature of motion, it bears on how exactly physical theory might
explain the motion of objects.
1. NO CHANGE, NO DIFFERENCE
wise lets the velocity be the value of the standard two-sided limit.
Unfortunately, this revised analysis will at least have some strange
consequences in cases where the limit is one thing coming in from
the left and something different coming in from the right. Consider
an object, c, whose position function is k(t) = 0 if t ≤ 1 and k(t) = 2t
− 2 if t > 1.
c starts out at rest. It remains at rest for a bit, from t = 0 until about t
= 1. After t = 1, c is moving. What is tricky about the function k is its
behavior at t = 1 (see Tooley, 1988, p. 245; Jackson and Pargetter,
1988, p. 141; Mortensen, 1985, p. 2). Like the original definition,
the revised definition leads to the conclusion that, on the Russellian
view, c is neither at rest nor in motion. The relevant limit does not
exist; it goes to two from one side, zero from the other. This is a
strange consequence for the revised analysis, because, if the object
had not existed before t = 1 but otherwise had this same position
function, then it would have been in motion at t = 1. But, since it did
exist before t = 1, it does not. Existing at earlier times undermines
being in motion at a later time. How strange. Strangeness aside,
additional problems for this revised Russellian view will be raised
in Sections 3 and 4.
Bigelow and Pargetter have not quite correctly described the motion
of e at t0 . They think that the example is sufficiently specified to
determine the motion facts about e. As they see it, as the example
is specified, it is true that e is not in motion and not at rest. But,
in fact, the example is not sufficiently specified to determine the
motion facts. It is left open by the specification that the object could
either be at rest or in motion.
Tooley (1988, pp. 243–244) describes a similar example about
which it is at least more plausible to think that the object in question
lacks a true velocity. He asks us to suppose that, at every moment of
an object’s existence, its continued existence and its future spatial
locations (if it does continue to exist) are extremely chancy. No
matter what has transpired up to time t, this object is just as likely
to occupy many different spots in the universe in the moments
following t. According to Tooley:
In such a world, the locations occupied by an object might very well form a radi-
cally discontinuous “curve”. But, at the same time, it might occasionally be the
case that an object, during some interval, occupied positions all of which fell on
some continuous curve that was differentiable at every point. If this did happen,
Russell’s account would imply that the object possessed a velocity at every time
during that interval.
But is it true that an object, in such a probabilistic world, which just happened
to occupy positions on such a curve, would have a velocity? It seems to me that
one is very hesitant to attribute a velocity in such a case, and I would suggest that
the reluctance to do so derives from the feeling that the velocity of an object at a
time should be causally relevant to its positions at later times. (p. 244)
4. NONSUPERVENIENCE
following the interaction though not at the instant of the interaction. So, for
example, and very roughly, if a heated body comes in contact with a cooler body,
and if the first moment they are in contact is t0 , there is no transfer of heat at t0 .
At all times following t0 , however, a transfer has transpired. With that in mind, let
us again suppose that c is a perfectly rigid sphere that is at rest and that the other
perfectly rigid sphere is rolling toward c at a rate of two meters per second. The
two spheres collide at t = 1.
4392 meters high and not even a slight bit higher, 4392 meters high
and not even a slight bit less high?11
These cases are interesting because the counterexamples to the
Russellian view all involve some object’s having certain properties
at exactly one time but not at times arbitrarily close to that time.
So, even if there are objects like this in the actual world, we cannot
know any such information about them. For example, we could not
know that object b existed at t = 2 and did not exist at all times after t
= 2. There is no way we could distinguish that situation from a situ-
ation in which b exists until t = 2 + δ seconds for some positive and
sufficiently small δ. Or, let us think about object c. We are told that
it occupies a different position at each time after t = 1, but occupies
the same position at the times leading up to and including t = 1. It
is these propositions that help comprise the hypothetical example.
This conjunction of propositions is an unknowable proposition.
Thus, in addition to conforming to a sensible epistemology and to
admitting of a revision that may be true (without being necessarily
true), the Russellian view has a shield generated by our epistem-
ological limitations. The counterexamples would be in blindspots
if they were actual. We can know that the Russellian view fails
as a definition, because we can specify hypothetical situations that
encourage judgments about motion at odds with that account. We
make these judgments based on propositions that are part of the
specification of the example, and that is enough to judge that the
Russellian view is not a necessary truth. We cannot, however,
actually know these specified propositions to be true (true in the
actual world) because that would require powers of discrimination
well beyond us. So, at least as far as the Tooley and Bigelow-
and-Pargetter examples are concerned, the Russellian view can be
employed as a contingent truth without fear that someone will
actually stumble upon a situation that could be known to threaten
it.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
NOTES
1 Conversation being what it is, there are some implications of my saying what
I did, implicatures to the effect that I will remain in my office long enough to
accomplish whatever needs to be done. These implicatures, however, are not part
of the content of my statement.
2 It is a presupposition of the Russellian view that space and time are continuous
in the mathematical sense; I will not question that presupposition here. In fact, all
the examples to be discussed involve objects that exist in an absolute Newtonian
spacetime (except where otherwise indicated). All my discussion of motion will
be restricted to linear motion.
3 Denis Robinson, 1989; Dean Zimmerman, 1998, 1999; Katherine Hawley,
the one-sided limits discussed here can be found in (Anton, 1992, pp. 132, A28).
66 JOHN W. CARROLL
7 The 18th century mathematician Colin Maclaurin did define velocity subjunct-
ively by defining uniform motion in terms of covering equal distance in equal
amounts of time and then defining instantaneous velocity in terms of the distance
the object would travel if it moved uniformly from the time in question (see
Jesseph, 1993, pp. 281–282). But, Maclaurin’s approach gives an incorrect judg-
ment about the supernatural positioning case to be discussed in Section 3.
According to MacClaurin’s definition of uniform motion, the object is moving
uniformly from the time in question. So his approach gives the same incorrect
result as the Russellian view; it says that e is in motion. Maclaurin’s approach
also gives a mistaken judgment about the World 2 example to be presented in
Section 4, judging that c has a velocity of two meters per second at t = 1 in World
2.
8 Bigelow and Pargetter initially talk about the velocity of an image on a movie
ence.
10 As described, World 1 and World 2 depend on there being some sort of
REFERENCES