Revista Zafea2020
Revista Zafea2020
Revista Zafea2020
https://doi.org/10.14201/azafea2020226783
Paolo Scolari
Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore - Milano
ABSTRACT
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
68 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
RESUMEN
1. The article cites Nietzsche’s works using the following abbreviations: AC = The
Antichrist; BGE = Beyond Good and Evil; BT = The Birth of Tragedy; D = Daybreak;
EH = Ecce Homo; GM = On the Genealogy of Morality; GS = The Gay Science; HH =
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 69
and human suffering
Human, All Too Human; TI = Twilight of the Idols; UF = Unpublished Fragments; and
Z = Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
70 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 71
and human suffering
she came to define his existential parable as a real “story of pain” (Andreas-
Salomé, 1894; cf. Fazio, 2009, pp. 206-207, 209).
Foremost among any interpretation, however, is that of Nietzsche, who
speaks of his pathological experience philosophically and presents it in a
hermeneutical guise. His reflections on his personal valetudinarian condi-
tion transcend the annalistic aspect, thus enabling a broader interpretation
in which pain becomes the key to comprehending human existence. He was
the first to realise that “his story – the story of illness and healing – is not just
his own personal story”, but closely concerns all men (HH, II, Preface, 6).
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
72 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
or worse, “it is not the sickness itself that inspired” human thought. Behind
the incessant search for bright, comfortable places, whether metaphysical or
earthly, there is always the desperate desire to escape from a deep state of
anguish. “Suffering thinkers are led and misled” to “involuntary detours,
alleyways, resting places, and sunny places of thought … the sick body with
its needs unconsciously urge, push and lure the mind – towards sun, still-
ness, mildness, patience, medicine, balm in some sense” (GS, Preface for the
second edition, 1).
In his personal story, Nietzsche retraced the steps of this twofold expe-
rience. First of all, he aimed to “do away with all the deductions that struggle
to grow like poisonous mushrooms from pain, from disappointment, from
tedium, from isolation and other swampy terrains”, which do nothing but
“generate in the long run something worse than that which had to be elimi-
nated along with them” (GS, Preface for the second edition, 1; HH, II, Pre-
face, 5). Once the ground was cleared, he intended to give voice to the pain.
It is precisely from this liberated pain, in fact, that philosophy springs. It is
actually these very “states of suffering themselves that philosophize” – “as is
the case with all sick thinkers” (and perhaps, as Nietzsche believed, it is pre-
cisely these who “prevail in the history of philosophy”), pain is not merely
an end in itself, but for the sole fact of becoming manifest always presents
a request for meaning. It creates the problem and urges the human being to
ask questions continually. “Subjected to the pressure of evil, thought” never
ceases to ask itself why (GS, Preface for the second edition, 2).
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 73
and human suffering
sence of pain and the loss of its specific importance. It is likened to a ‘bump
in the road,’ difficult but surmountable. “Pain is illusion, error, nothing but
the error”, as Socrates would say, quoted by Nietzsche in Die Geburt der
Tragödie (GM, III, 12; BT, 15). In this case, “as soon as the error is recogni-
sed, suffering must disappear” – the intellect identifies the malformation and
removes it surgically. As in a dialectical game, evil is nothing but the negative
pole that is resolved in the “absence of pain”, which becomes “the highest
good … that has to be valued positively and found to be the positive itself”
(GM, III, 17).
In order to mitigate pain and not feel its tragic positivity, it is hidden be-
hind more pleasant, appealing names. Humans are just not able to live with
this conundrum. Since “pain hurts”, it is unbearable and therefore “adorned
with such inoffensive names… means of consolation … “to refresh, soothe
and narcotize”. It is above all in Christianity that Nietzsche sees this logic
in action. In Zur Genealogie der Moral, he describes “the ascetic priest” as
“a doctor who combats suffering, who narcotizes and relieves pain, conso-
ling and refreshing”. Only this priest can “chase away the dark sorrow of
man”, giving “a religious interpretation and ‘justification’” to his ills. “He
exploits suffering and finally comes to sanctify it”, succeeding in giving it
meaning: the suffering man can now “be informed of the ‘cause’ of his su-
ffering”, which becomes the “way to being blessed”. Nietzsche completely
rejects such dynamics, on the strength of having learned under a teacher like
Schopenhauer, who first taught him to take “the sufferings of humanity se-
riously” and to expose “the antidotes against these sufferings” and “pillory
the unheard-of quackery with which men, even up to our own age, and in
the most sublime nomenclature, have been wont to treat the illnesses of their
souls” (GM, III, 17, 20; D, 52; BGE, 61; UF, 10 [21], 14 [89]).
The justificatory ritual seems to be inherent to human existence, divi-
ded between the appearance of evil without reason and an endless search
for meaning. Nietzsche points out that the most distressing thing for man
is “to suffer without knowing why”: he who finds himself in this condition
is “eager to find reasons, remedies, and narcotics that give relief” to his su-
ffering (GM, III, 20). In his reinterpretation of Nietzsche, Gilles Deleuze
argues that human beings are unable to eliminate pain entirely and therefore
internalize and spiritualize it, seeking a new meaning that can be given to it
(Deleuze, 1992, pp. 156-158). As Nietzsche says in the Genealogie, humans
share the anguish of not being able to conceive the idea of meaningless suffe-
ring and “need an explanation” that will allow them to live serenely. In fact,
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
74 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
“what really causes them to rebel against suffering is not suffering itself, but
the absurdity of suffering. The fact that the despairing question “why do we
suffer?” remains unanswered is the curse that up until today has continued
to plague humanity”. Right from the beginning, “suffering has always po-
sed the problem of its cause”, carrying within it a “claim to meaning”. The
human being must at all costs find “a meaning, a ‘reason’ for suffering”,
he longs to be “saved” from the illogicality of suffering, to be “no longer a
leaf in the wind, a plaything of absurdity, of ‘nonsense.’” So he immediately
runs for cover, “interpreting” and “filling” this “enormous emptiness” with
something that might be able to account for “absurd suffering”. After all,
such a man thinks to himself, “any meaning is better than no meaning at all”
(GM, III, 20).
According to Nietzsche, the process of justification is fulfilled both in a
religious and a secularized context. On the one hand, “Christians have trans-
ferred to suffering an entire secret machinery of salvation”, and on the other,
“in past ages, men have been able to explain every kind of suffering based
on the spectators of suffering”. To the former an ethereal, eternal salvation,
to the latter a veritable show, both “cruel” and “edifying”. The historical
and cultural contexts may change, but the justificatory mechanism is the
same. Nothing can remain unexplained and escape human rationality, but
everything must happen for some salvific purpose or be totally revealed and
observed, and therefore rendered intelligible. Men of every era have strived
to “deny and remove from the world suffering that is hidden, undiscove-
red, without witnesses” through “the invention of gods and intermediate
beings of every height and depth, something, that is, that also sees in the dark
and does not easily let an interesting display of suffering escape”. They have
come to the point of eradicating the meaning of existence from existence
itself and placing it elsewhere, thus ultimately losing a real relationship with
life. “Thanks to such inventions and stratagems they have justified life and
its ‘evil,’ depriving it of its ‘enigmatic’ and ‘problematic’ character” (GM, II,
7; III, 28; GS, 13; AC, 23; cf. Aurenque, 2013, pp. 54-55).
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 75
and human suffering
In the city, there seems to be no more room for pain. It is the modern me-
tropolis, inhabited by the “Last man” of Also sprach Zarathustra (Vorrede),
a prototype of the massified human beings who “invented happiness” and
“left the districts where life was hard”, and to whom “becoming ill is always
a fault” (Z, Preface, 5).
The society of the last men sets universal well-being as the highest value
and is therefore no longer able to recognise itself as sensitive to pain. It seeks
instead to minimize it, hide it, even eliminate it in order to pursue comfor-
table and convenient pleasure. In a bourgeois climate of Hegelian-positivist
optimism, confidence in the rationality of history, in the future, and in pro-
gress is pushed to the extreme. Everything goes, without the slightest doubt,
in the only possible direction, towards a tomorrow that will undoubtedly
prove better than today. A naive mentality, according to Nietzsche, where
there is a will to numb existence and “make it painless” (UF, 1971, 3 [151]).
The city “sets itself to carrying out tasks geared to eliminating pain”. Its in-
habitants go so far as to evaporate all the aspects of pain relating to the body,
transforming it into an abstract and harmless thought that does not overly
disturb their lives. “Pain is hated much more than formerly; indeed, one can
hardly endure the presence as a thought and makes it a matter of conscience
and a reproach against the whole of existence” (HH, II, 187; GS, 48; cf. Die
Philosophie im Tragischen Zeitalter der Griechen).
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
76 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 77
and human suffering
7. Convalescent thoughts
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
78 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
Because of his encounter with suffering, Nietzsche was well “aware of the
advantages that my erratic health gives me overall burly minds” and of the
“inexhaustible benefit” that he has been able to draw from his “time of severe
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 79
and human suffering
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
80 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
I know that it delves deep (uns vertieft) within us”. Suffering causes us to
penetrate uns vertieft, in the twofold sense highlighted by Leonardo Casini,
based on the original German, of delving deep down and, at the same time,
making us deeper. It slowly carves deep into the human being, thus allowing
him to explore his most secret and tragic darker areas so that he might rise to
the surface with a new awareness (GS, Preface for the second edition, 3; D,
114; cf. Casini, 1990, 281; cf. Bizzotto, 1981, pp. 48-51, 53-54).
The man who descends into the cavern of his interiority must watch out
for one of the most insidious dangers that can occur when dealing with suffe-
ring, which risks imprisoning him in the subterranean world of the subject.
This is a challenging obstacle to overcome. Nietzsche adverts us against it
because almost spontaneously, “all suffering tends to cause him to turn in
on himself” and transform his condition into a withstanding first-hand ex-
perience. Indeed, “what we suffer most deeply and personally is incompre-
hensible and inaccessible to almost everyone else”. This “omnipotent pride
which allows suffering to be endured” cocoons man egocentrically within
himself: “with too much violence and for too long it makes it personal”.
Jaspers also, analyzing in detail Nietzsche’s illness and its influence on his
philosophical work, points out that, as one of the various existential dangers,
suffering drives forceful thought towards interiority. “The pride of the sick
man”, reviles Nietzsche “rears up like never before” (GS, 338; UF, 1974-
1877, 44 [9]; D, 114; cf. Jaspers, 1996, 115-116).
The only “antidote” to this centralized drifting, according to Nietzsche,
is “alienation and depersonalization”. Through the experience of “pain”, the
“tormented” human being who “suffers acutely” must come out of himself
and learns to “see, with terrible coldness, the things that are outside”. “Suffe-
ring”, which leads “to the supreme disenchantment” of the world in which
man dwells, is “the only way he can be wrested from the deceptive illusions
and dangerous fantasies in which he has lived up to that time. Only this su-
ffering is the extreme liberator of the spirit, the master of the great suspicion”
(GS, Preface for the second edition, 3; D, 114).
Suffering takes us by the hand and brings us to the school of suspicion,
which teaches us not so much how to strengthen our identity as how to
unhinge it by demolishing all our idols and certainties. “The plow of evil”
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 81
and human suffering
breaks and overturns, creating the disillusionment that forces man to make
a clean sweep of all his comfortable compromises and masks, knocking him
off-center and forcing him to accept conversion. This “long, slow pain that
takes its time and in which we are burned, as it were, over green wood, for-
ces us to descend into our ultimate depths and put aside all trust, everything
good-natured, veiling, mild, average..”.. In Nietzsche’s eyes, it is “the stron-
gest and most evil spirits” which have “done the most to advance humanity:
time and again they rekindled the dozing passions, (...) reawakened the sense
of comparison, of contradiction, of delight in what is new, daring, unattemp-
ted; (...) by toppling boundary stones”, all landmarks “on which man’s hu-
manity once perhaps rested” and which today suffering is forcing him to put
behind him once and for all (GS, Preface for the second edition, 3; GS, 4).
While overthrowing all mythology of omnipotence and immortality, su-
ffering pulls the human being forcefully out of his centralized state; it makes
him think about his finitude and look beyond his ego. Vozza tells us that in
Nietzsche, the experience of suffering reveals the inadequacy of one’s own
person and disrupts the monolithic compactness of the ego. It becomes the
stimulating condition of critical and genealogical thinking that undermines
every position gained and every established totality. In Ecce homo, Nietzs-
che confesses autobiographically that “my sickness gave me the right to a
complete reversal of all my habits” and “slowly freed me”. It allowed him to
“return to myself, “aware that “never as in the most painful periods of my
life, at the height of my illness, have I felt so much happiness”. From this
slow and exhausting struggle, man “comes back reborn and transmuted, with
a different skin”, “as if he had lived through something extraordinary and
come to know something new and different compared to before”. This is an
auroral, almost initiatory knowledge; now, in fact, “everything to which the
gaze is directed shines with a new light” (EH, ‘Menschliches, Allzumenschli-
ches,’ 4; D, 114; GS, Preface for the second edition, 4; cf. Vozza, 2003, pp.
236-237; cf. Vozza, 2001, pp. 222-223).
Nietzsche seeks to teach us that once the journey of pain is undertaken,
there is no turning back. This journey always ends by “making one a diffe-
rent man, with a few more uncertainties and, above all, with the will to ask,
from then on, more questions, deeper, more rigorous, tougher, badder and
more silent, than one has ever asked before” (GS, Preface for the second
edition, 3).
In Nietzsche’s philosophy, hermeneutic suffering causes “man to roll from
the center towards an x”, transforming all his certainties into uncertainties.
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
82 thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche
and human suffering
It does not give answers to the meaning of “life”, but from it constantly
regenerates questions. Scored by suffering, human existence ceases to be
something objective, of itself, pure and becomes uncertain, doubtful, pro-
blematic. It is no longer a guarantee, but “itself becomes a problem” (GS,
Preface for the second edition, 3; UF, 1970-1974, 2 [127]; cf. Casini, 1990, pp.
280-281; cf. Senigaglia, 2011, p. 90; cf. Manzi, 2005, pp. 572-577).
References
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83
pablo scolari
thougts of pain. friedrich nietzsche 83
and human suffering
Ediciones Universidad de Salamanca / CC BY-NC-ND Azafea. Rev. filos. 22, 2020, pp. 67-83