Watson 2019 Games
Watson 2019 Games
Watson 2019 Games
Facsimile of 1
the first edition in The Cambridge Encyclopedia of Anthropology. Online: http://doi.org/10.29164/19games
Games
Though there is no universally accepted definition for what constitutes a ‘game’, games are typically defined as goal-oriented,
rules-based activities closely associated with the notion of ‘play’. In anthropology, though seldom the primary focus of a
monograph, games can serve as a window into the broader lives and valuations of their players. More practically, they can also
be excellent vehicles for conducting participant-observation and building rapport with interlocutors. The three sections of this
entry seek to provide a general overview of anthropological insights into the world of games. The first section covers attempts to
define games as a concept. The second section asks what makes games meaningful. The third section examines anthropological
approaches to the most recent major development in the world of games: the rise of digital games.
Games as a concept
The arenas that mark archaeological sites—like The Great Ballcourt of Chichen Itza or the Colosseum of
Rome—and board games whose lineage can be traced back thousands of years—like Senet, Go, Mancala,
and backgammon—are testaments to games’ longstanding place in human history. Games can also have
strong geographic linkages. Global spectacles like the Olympic Games and World Cup draw participants
and billions of spectators from most of the world’s nations. Some games, like cricket throughout much of
the British Commonwealth, can make manifest linkages between distant nations. Other games, like the Sri
Lankan board game Carrom or the Finnish ball game Pesäpallo, are played primarily within the borders of
particular nation-states. Games are played by people of different ages and walks of life: from hopscotch in
the schoolyard to bridge in retirement homes, and from improvised football to exclusive polo.
Although games are widespread and familiar to many of the world’s peoples, providing a compelling,
overarching definition for what constitutes ‘a game’ has proved difficult. Rules are widely seen as an
important component of games (e.g. Huizinga 1949; Caillois 1961; Suits 1967; Avedon & Sutton-Smith
1981; Meier 1995; Suits 1995; Salen & Zimmerman 2003). But of course, rules govern many aspects of
human life and are not restricted to games alone. What ostensibly sets the rules of a game apart from other
rules-based activities is not just the special reasons for which these rules are constructed, but also the
players’ attitude toward those rules. As Bernard Suits, who spent much of his career working on a universal
To play a game is to attempt to achieve a specific state of affairs [prelusory goal], using only means
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 2
permitted by rules [lusory means], where the rules prohibit use of more efficient in favour of less
efficient means [constitutive rules], and where the rules are accepted just because they make
Suits connects his definition of games to a particular way of playing them (i.e. ‘the lusory attitude’). He
does not, for example, consider those who cheat to be adopting a lusory attitude and thus does not consider
them to be playing the game (2005: 25). Yet, as Angela Schneider points out, games seldom play out so
neatly in practice: some players might play by the rules, but others will not; some players will be invested
in the game, but others might not be (2001). Nonetheless, for Schneider, a game like rugby is still a game
even if the motivations for playing and adherence to the rules differ from player to player. When it comes to
adhering to a game’s rules, Schneider contends ‘[e]thically we should of course, but logically we needn’t’
(2001: 158). As we shall see in more detail throughout this entry, the diverse reasons people have for
playing games and the different ways in which they go about negotiating a game’s rules are where games
Anthropologists have offered many insightful analyses of the extent of the relationships between games and
play. For example, David Graeber has theorised that play is unpredictable, whereas games are clearly
defined by rules (Graeber 2015). For Graeber, what is special about a game’s rules vis-à-vis the rules of
propriety in regular life is that the rules of a game are easily discernible at any given moment, and thus
present a ‘utopia of rules’. Thomas Malaby, one of the most prominent anthropologists writing on the
subject of games and play, has posited his own definition of games—‘[a] game is a semibounded and
socially legitimate domain of contrived contingency that generates interpretable outcomes’ (2007: 96)—and
decouple playful experience from a determinate relationship with games, just as scholars of ritual
(many of them anthropologists) have recognized ritual as a cultural form irrespective of whether it
Malaby’s ‘decoupling’ stance is not intended as an outright separation of games and play, but rather, akin
to the point made by Schneider, is meant to point out that the two concepts need not necessarily go hand in
hand. The strength of Malaby’s approach is that it leaves the door open for interchange between
anthropological work on games and anthropological work on play—such as that of Gregory Bateson
Indeed, anthropological work on games and play, respectively, has greatly helped to refine understandings
of games. For example, Roger Caillois, one of the twentieth century’s best-known theorists of games and
play, emphasised the role of games as playful activities largely outside the sphere of economic productivity.
As he put it, ‘[a]t the end of the game, all can and must start over at the same point. Nothing has been
harvested or manufactured, no masterpiece has been created, no capital has accrued’ (1961: 5). However,
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 3
subsequent anthropological work on play, like that of David Lancy amongst the Kpelle—who, Lancy found,
see work and play not as mutually exclusive but as components of all human endeavours—has compellingly
questioned a hard work/play binary (1980). Meanwhile, ethnographic work on certain games, like T.L.
Taylor’s account of professional digital games players (2012), shows that there are most definitely games in
which capital is accrued and all does not start over at the same point. It is in no small part because of these
anthropological efforts that hard divisions like Caillois’ between games and work have now largely been
abandoned by theorists of games and play. As Jesper Juul, a leading scholar within the relatively new field
of games studies, explains, ‘both are clearly not perfect boundaries, but rather fuzzy areas under constant
Anthropologists have compellingly argued that games and play are distinct, if often related, concepts.
However, many who read about games in the English language will likely find this position discordant with
the existence of games and play as interrelated words. As Johan Huizinga—a scholar to whose seminal
work Homo ludens nearly all subsequent theorists of games and play make reference—noted, this
connection seems inexorable: one plays a game (1949: 37). How might we reconcile these two facts? While
Huizinga claims that ‘you do not “do” a game as you “do” or “go” fishing, or hunting […] you “play” it’
(1949: 37), it might actually be useful to think of the English term ‘to play a game’ in the sense of how one
does a game (just as one sings a song or drives a car) in order to better distinguish between various ways
in which people approach games. Thus one might play a game playfully—or angrily, or reluctantly—just as
Similarly, it can at times be useful to take a step back from efforts to precisely define games, and instead
use a broader conceptualization of what games are. One prominent example of such a move comes from the
…we see a complicated network of similarities overlapping and criss-crossing: sometimes overall
I can think of no better expression to characterize these similarities than “family resemblances”; for
the various resemblances between members of a family: build, features, colour of eyes, gait,
temperament, etc. etc. overlap and criss-cross in the same way—And I shall say: ‘games’ form a
Wittgenstein by no means had the last word on games, a fact to which the subsequent accounts of Caillois,
Suits, and others is testament. However, his description accords well with the implicit approach of most
anthropologists to games, whose preoccupation—like when handling most subjects—is less with providing a
universally tenable definition of games, and more with discerning what is meaningful about the particular
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 4
Indeed, some of the most insightful discussions of games within anthropology emerge when particular
games are described in contradistinction to related themes. For example, Arjun Appadurai has examined
the enduring popularity of cricket in postcolonial India as an example of decolonization being a ‘dialogue
with the colonial past’ rather than a ‘dismantling of colonial habits and modes of life’ (Appadurai 1995).
Roberte Hamayon, Harry Walker, and Ted Leyenaar have all shown how games can both impact and reflect
relations between indigenous peoples and the state (Leyenaar 1992; Walker 2013; Hamayon 2016).
Leyenaar, for example, studied the ancient Mesoamerican ball game Ulama in contemporary Mexico and
found that, like many of the indigenous peoples who created and developed the game, Ulama had been
pushed to the margins of the Mexican state. Victor Turner and others have made productive comparisons
between ritual and games—for Turner, for example, both are notable for how they place their participants
(and potential observers) in a transitional state that falls outside normal life (Turner 1982; Seligman et al.
2008). Ellen Oxfeld has studied Mahjong amongst Chinese entrepreneurs in Calcutta and found the nature
of the game, with its risks and rewards, similar to the nature of her interlocutors’ business endeavours
(Oxfeld 1993). Loïc Wacquant has discussed boxing and race in Chicago’s Southside neighbourhood, where
for his interlocutors the order of a boxer’s regimen stood as a counterpart to the disorder many
experienced in their lives outside the gym (Wacquant 2004). And Robertson Allen, T.J. Cornell, and T.B.
Allen have examined the relationships between war and games – including those specifically made to
acclimatise citizens to the military (Cornell & Allen 2002; Allen 2017).
This is not to say that in such accounts games are relegated to mere foils for understanding more important
concepts; just as games can help to hone our understandings of other phenomena, these phenomena can
help to hone our understanding of games. Such a fact has been famously displayed by Claude Lévi-Strauss
[a]ll games are defined by a set of rules which in practice allow the playing of any number of
matches. Ritual, which is also ‘played’, is on the other hand, like a favoured instance of a game,
remembered from among the possible ones because it is the only one which results in a particular
type of equilibrium between the two sides. The transposition is readily seen in the case of the
Gahuku-Gama of New Guinea who have learnt football but who will play, several days running, as
many matches as are necessary for both sides to reach the same score (1962: 20).
Both the games an anthropologist chooses to focus on and what she or he reads into them can have
significant implications. It goes without saying that not all games are equally meaningful, and one of the
tasks facing anthropologists and others interested in analyzing games is figuring out how to parse the
myriad varieties of games often on display. For example, Huizinga contended that ‘[s]olitary play is
productive of culture only in a limited degree’ (1949: 47) and that it is the ‘play-community’ formed
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 5
between players that gives games their social importance (1949: 17-8). Though much of Huizinga’s work
has been critiqued by subsequent scholars of games, almost all of them focus on multiplayer games as
sources for meaningful play—a point which takes on new importance with the rise of digital games, as we
shall see in the next section. Monetary stakes are another way in which games can be meaningful to their
players. Indeed, much of the anthropological literature on games focuses on those in which money is at
stake (see, for example, the entry on gambling in this encyclopedia). Nonetheless, anthropologists have
compellingly argued that money alone is seldom what makes games meaningful.
Likely the most famous such example, and perhaps the best-known account of a game within anthropology,
comes from Clifford Geertz’s account of the Balinese cockfight. In Geertz’s analysis, the cockfight is not a
mere spectacle upon which the Balinese wager vast sums of money, but a process through which ‘the
Balinese forms and discovers his temperament and his society’s temper at the same time’ (1973: 451).
Framed as such, the cockfight is meaningful for how it perpetuates the traditions and valuations of the
past. Moreover, Geertz’s presence at one particular unsanctioned cockfight meant that he was also present
for the police action which broke it up: by fleeing with the rest of the participants and hiding out alongside
some of them, he finally established a convivial rapport with his interlocutors (1973: 415-6). While the fame
of Geertz’s rendition of the cockfight might make it seem like it was the only game in town, Geertz’s own
account shows otherwise. As he notes, in his field site there was a ‘sociomoral hierarchy’ of players and
games:
At most cockfights there are, around the very edges of the cockfight area, a large number of
mindless, sheer-chance type gambling games (roulette, dice throw, coin-spin, pea-under-the shell)
operated by concessionaires. Only women, children, adolescents, and various other sorts of people
who do not (or not yet) fight cocks—the extremely poor, the socially despised, the personally
idiosyncratic—play at these games, at, of course, penny ante levels. Cockfighting men would be
Geertz’s decision to focus on the cockfight gave us an arresting view into his field site. But one must
wonder whether these other games were as meaningless as he made them out to be, or whether a closer
look at them might have revealed a different type of ethnography more sensitive to the daily lives and
valuations of Balinese who were not elite men. Indeed, children’s games have featured as a specific point of
focus in other ethnographic accounts, from Stewart Culin’s writings about cat’s cradle amongst North
American indigenous peoples (1907: 761-80), to Mizuko Ito’s work on digital games amongst Japanese and
Newer anthropological accounts of games tend to criticise approaches like Geertz’s. Malaby, for example,
[t]his treatment of a game…trades one kind of reductionism for another. In his zeal to trump
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 6
whatever material stakes were in play with the different stakes of meaning-making, Geertz
eliminated from consideration any consequence beyond the affirmation of meaning. On his view,
games become static appraisals of an unchanging social order; and thereby one element that is vital
for any understanding of the experience of play is lost. That element is the indeterminacy of games,
and the way in which, by being indeterminate in their outcomes, they encapsulate (albeit in a
The structure of Malaby’s argument is reminiscent of Lévi-Strauss’ distinction between ritual and games. In
this case, Geertz appears to have inverted game and ritual by interpreting the cockfight ‘like a favoured
instance of a game’ (i.e. Lévi-Strauss’ ritual) rather than as an actual game which might have different
outcomes from one instance to the next. This, however, begs the question of whether the Balinese cockfight
It is worth noting the work of Anthony Pickles for how it manages to highlight both the perpetuation of
tradition found in accounts like Geertz’s, and the potential for changes to social order found in accounts
like Malaby’s. Pickles offers a fascinating account of two card-based gambling games in Goroka, Papua
New Guinea. One game, called kwin (queen), is strategic and slow-paced, slow to adopt changes in rules,
and popular amongst older players, while the other game, called bom (bomb), is faster-paced, part of a
quickly changing genre of games, and popular amongst younger players (Pickles 2014). Pickles’ dual focus
allows us to see in kwin one game that is akin to Geertz’s interpretation of the cockfight, and in bom
another which has more in common with newer anthropological interest in the negotiability of games.
Crucially, meaning here is found not just in these respective games and what they stand for, but in the
tension between them and their respective players—a point worth bearing in mind for anthropologists who
Pickles’ account of bom shows us how new rules and new games can be created in a relatively short period
of time. But it is also worth remembering Schneider’s aforementioned point that, while games may have a
set of rules, these are not always universally and perfectly adhered to. Rather, rules are constantly
susceptible to being undermined or renegotiated by their players, either inadvertently, as in a new player
making an error out of ignorance, or purposefully, as in cases of cheating (Consalvo 2005, 2007, 2009).
This process is not the corruption of games so much as it is an essential and important part of them. In
other words, games are not just meaningful for the potential actions that their rules dictate, but for how
players choose to go about adjudicating disputes about those rules. For example, Linda Hughes, studying
American schoolgirls who play the ball game foursquare, finds that the game serves not simply as a playful
pastime for the children, but also helps them to learn lifelong skills like problem solving and teamwork
(1991, 1999). Indeed, in many games, adjudication of the rules is handled by the players themselves; think,
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 7
When the financial or physical stakes of a game rise (and especially when both happen at once), very often
adjudication shifts from the players themselves to a third party responsible for ensuring both safety and
fairness. Think of the referees in many games typically referred to as ‘sports’, such as football or boxing, or
the presence of dealers in casinos. As Geertz notes, the cockfight too has its ‘umpire (saja komong; djuru
kembar)…[whose] authority is absolute’ (1973: 423, 424). The presence of a third-party adjudicator does
not necessarily mean that a game is more meaningful than a game adjudicated by its players, but it can
have important implications. For example, compare two different instances of the game football: one is a
professional match with a referee, the other is a pickup match played in a public park. In professional
football, the practice of ‘simulation’ or ‘diving’ is commonplace. It involves players exaggerating or outright
feigning the effects of physical contact from opposing players in the hopes that the referee will be fooled
and call a foul against the opposing team. In pickup football, where players determine fouls communally,
this practice is far less prevalent. Both instances are technically the same game, sharing football’s rules
As we can see from the works discussed in this section, determining what makes games meaningful is a
tricky endeavour contingent upon many factors. One must consider what constitutes the particular game
being discussed, how that game relates (or does not relate) to other games played within a particular field
site, and the different ways in which players go about negotiating particular instances of gameplay.
The late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries have witnessed one of the most significant changes in
the history of games: the rise of digital games, colloquially referred to as ‘video games’. Unlike their
analogue counterparts, digital games are written in code, played on computers or consoles, and viewed on
monitors or television screens. Their rise to prominence—concomitant with the profusion of ever more
affordable, portable, and powerful home electronics—has brought with it numerous different types of
digital games. These run the gamut from digital forms of games like chess and billiards, to ‘Massively
multiplayer online roleplaying games’ (MMORPGs), which consist of vast spaces in which thousands of
players simultaneously navigate their respective avatars. This profusion of new games has rejuvenated an
interest in efforts to define ‘games’ (Juul 2003), and has given rise to the new discipline of games studies
(Aarseth 2001; Jenkins 2004; Boellstorff 2006). Perhaps predictably, many analyses of digital games
bemoan the potential influence of their violent or sexual content (Grossman & DeGaetano 1999; Anderson
& Dill 2000; Breyer 2011)—in so doing repeating the same concern that faces nearly all new and popular
That being said, the rise of digital technology represents a potentially fundamental shift in the world of
games. Namely, one of the most important characteristics of digital games vis-à-vis their analogue
counterparts is how they change spatial relations. While some analogue games are carried out by
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 8
distance—such as correspondence chess—the vast majority are conducted with the participants in close
proximity. Conversely, while some digital games are played with one’s teammates and/or opponents
nearby—such as playing ‘splitscreen’ (multiple people playing a digital game on the same television or
computer monitor) at home or in a group at an internet café—most multiplayer digital games involve
people playing alone from their homes while sharing digital space with their peers.
This fact problematises distinctions like Huizinga’s between solitary and communal games, for players
might be in one sense solitary—playing a game alone in their rooms—but at the same time be connected to
other players through the Internet and in the game itself. This fact can perhaps help to explain some
anthropologists’ findings on digital games. For example, Nicholas Long notes that the players and
producers of the digital game Ultima Online often make note of amazing ‘community’ within the game, but
that Long himself found the relations between players to be far more ephemeral and individualistic (Long
2012). Conversely, Celia Pearce notes how players of one particular game stuck together as a social group
even after the game itself had been discontinued (Pearce 2006, 2007, 2010).
Another key facet of digital games is their role as goods. They are a multibillion dollar industry, and
anthropologists have turned their attention to not just their players but their producers (Malaby 2009b).
The role of gender can loom particularly large, as some digital games are primarily marketed to and played
by men, whereas others are primarily marketed to and played by women (Mason 2013). Real-world gender
inequities can manifest in digital games. For example, Julian Dibbell found that players whose avatars were
women were often subjected to sexual harassment, whereas the same was not true for players whose
avatars were men (Dibbell 1993). Race can play a similar role to gender in terms of both marketability and
gameplay, as some have shown in games where racial stereotypes are part of a game’s content (Leonard
2003), and others have highlighted in games where players themselves use real-world racial slurs
(Shanahan 2004).
The structure of digital games also raises questions about how best to approach them methodologically.
There have been two primary ways in which anthropologists have gone about doing so. The first method
conceptualises these games as ‘virtual worlds’ (Pearce 2006; Nardi & Harris 2006; Taylor 2006; Pearce
2007; Boellstorff 2008; Pearce 2010; Nardi 2010; Long 2012). Treating the space within these games in a
similar way to a physical field site, these scholars conduct long-term participant-observation within them by
registering accounts, creating avatars, and interacting with other players in the virtual world. In this vein,
the title of Boellstorff’s book Coming of age in Second Life—Second Life being the virtual world in which he
conducted his fieldwork—is purposefully designed to emphasise a similarity with Margaret Meade’s classic
Coming of age in Samoa (1928). This approach gives us an in-depth view of what playing these games looks
like in action and the type of interrelationships that it involves—though it is worth noting that, perhaps
because of this approach’s emphasis on virtual worlds as a ‘space’, some who adopt it question these
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 9
The second approach more pointedly engages with digital games from the vantage of the physical world, in
so doing taking a page from the book of anthropologists who emphasise the local importance of various
forms of media, such as television (Abu-Lughod 2005), radio (Englund 2011), and blogs (Doostdar 2004).
Daniel Miller has studied Facebook use amongst Trinidadians, and he includes in his book a chapter on the
Facebook game FarmVille. Articulating his methodological approach toward one interlocutor, Miller notes
that he would spend ‘hours looking over his shoulder as he does Facebook’ for a view into this person’s
online life (Miller 2011: 78). Similarly, Florence Chee has examined Korean gamer culture from within
internet cafes (2005), and Mizuko Ito has studied the use of educational games by Japanese and American
children in classroom and home settings (2009). Alex Golub has used his own experience with the
MMORPG World of Warcraft to explicitly critique virtual worlds scholars for underemphasising important
extra-game spaces, such as online message boards and real-world gatherings (Golub 2010).
While proponents of each respective approach can sometimes clash, both methods have their strengths
when applied to specific genres of digital games. For example, it is unsurprising that the majority of virtual
worlds work is conducted within MMORPGs like World of Warcraft. These games most closely resemble the
physical world in the sense that players control an avatar within a broader game world, and often contain
robust economies where significant amounts of real money changes hands (Castronova 2001). Meanwhile,
many other digital games, such as those that require no Internet connection, single-player games, those in
which players are disembodied manipulators of many variables (such as Real-time Strategy Games), or
those where players are under the finite time constraints of individual matches, are often only practically
observable from a physically in-situ vantage. Nor are the approaches inherently mutually exclusive. For
example, virtual worlds scholars have more recently and explicitly acknowledged the need to at least be
open to physical aspects of games when they arise (Boellstorff et al. 2012: 33, 34).
A final point to make about digital games has to do with adjudication and negotiability. The previous
section noted the distinction between games that are adjudicated by their players and those games which
are adjudicated by a third party referee. Many digital games present a third form of adjudication: the code
itself. For example, the previous section took the example of football, and noted the difference between
‘diving’ in a match adjudicated by players and a match adjudicated by a referee. In a digital game where
football is depicted, such as Electronic Arts’ popular FIFA series, diving is simply not an option coded into
the game. Even if it were, unless the game also added human referees, it would involve trying to press the
‘dive’ button at the right time and hoping that the computer code would confirm it, rather than the process
of tricking a human referee or negotiating with human teammates and opponents. When the ball goes out
of bounds in FIFA, there is no arguing with the linesman or quibbling with teammates: the code simply
confirms it. The implications of this third type of adjudication found within digital games are still not fully
understood, but it may help to explain the ephemerality of social relations some anthropologists have found
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 10
Conclusion
This entry has provided an overview of anthropological work on games. It has underscored key themes and
developments in the world of games, from varying conceptualizations of what a game is, to how games are
Games will continue to be important sources of anthropological theorization not just because new games
are being crafted every day, as the advent of digital games makes clear, nor just because instances of
games have unpredictable outcomes, as Malaby’s work reminds us, but also because new connections
between games and other important phenomena can always be uncovered. As is often the case with
ethnographic work, people engaging in a seemingly innocuous activity like a casual game can offer
unexpected vantages onto significant issues. Like with most interesting themes, this means that a
discussion about games will never be complete. Readers are therefore encouraged to take a closer look at
games in both their own field sites and daily lives. Who knows just what you might find…
References
Aarseth, E. 2001. Computer game studies, year one. Game Studies 1(1) (available on-line:
http://gamestudies.org/0101/editorial.html).
Abu-Lughod, L. 2005. Dramas of nationhood: the politics of television in Egypt. Chicago: University Press.
Allen, R. 2017. America’s digital army: games at work and war. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Anderson, C. & K. Dill 2000. Video games and aggressive thoughts, feelings, & behavior in the laboratory
Appadurai, A. 1995. Playing with modernity: the decolonization of Indian cricket. In Consuming modernity:
public culture in a South Asian world (ed.) C.A. Breckenridge, 23-48. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.
Avedon, E. & B. Sutton-Smith 1981. The study of games. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Bateson, G. 1987. A theory of play and fantasy. In Steps to an ecology of mind, 183–98. Northvale: Jason
Aronson Inc.
Boellstorff, T. 2006. A ludicrous discipline? Ethnography and game studies. Games and Culture 1(1): 29-35.
——— 2008. Coming of age in Second Life: an anthropologist explores the virtually human. Princeton:
University Press.
Boellstorff, T., B. Nardi, C. Pearce, & T.L. Taylor 2012. Ethnography and virtual worlds: a handbook of
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 11
Breyer, S. 2011. Dissent, Brown v. Entertainment Merchants Association, 564 U.S. 786. Supreme Court of
Caillois, R. 1961. Man, play and games (trans. M. Barash). Champaign: University of Illinois Press.
Castronova, E. 2001. Virtual worlds: a first-hand account of market and society on the Cyberian frontier.
Chee, F. 2005. Understanding Korean experiences of online game hype, identity, and the menace of the
‘Wang-Tta’. Proceedings of DiGRA 2005 Conference: Changing Views - Worlds in Play. Vancouver, British
https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/Delivery.cfm/SSRN_ID294828_code020114590.pdf?abstractid=294828&mirid
=1).
Consalvo, M. 2005. Rule sets, cheating, and magic circles: studying games and ethics. International Review
——— 2007. Cheating: gaining and advantage in videogames. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
——— 2009. There is no magic circle. Games and Culture 4(4), 408-17.
Cornell, T.J. & T.B. Allen (eds) 2002. War and games. Woodbridge: The Boydell Press.
Culin, S. 2012 [1907]. Games of the North American Indians. New York: Dover Publications.
Dibbell, J. 1993. A rape in cyberspace. The Village Voice. 23 December 1993 (available on-line:
https://www.villagevoice.com/2005/10/18/a-rape-in-cyberspace/).
Doostdar, A. 2004. ‘The vulgar spirit of blogging’: on language, culture, and power in Persian Weblogestan.
Englund, H. 2011. Human rights and African airwaves: mediating equality on the Chichewa Radio.
Galloway, A. 2006. Gaming: essays on algorithmic culture. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Golub, A. 2010. Being in the world (of Warcraft): raiding, realism, and knowledge production in a massively
Graeber, D. 2015. The utopia of rules: on technology, stupidity, and the secret joys of bureaucracy. London:
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 12
Melville House.
Grossman, D. & G. DeGaetano 1999. Stop teaching our kids to kill: a call to action against TV, movie &
Hughes, L. 1991. A conceptual framework for the study of children’s gaming. Play and Culture 4, 284-301.
——— 1999. Children’s games and gaming. In Children’s folklore, B. Sutton-Smith, J. Mechling, T. Johnson,
& F. McMahon (eds), 93-119. Salt Lake City: Utah University Press.
Huizinga, J. 1949. Homo ludens: a study of the play element in culture. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Ito, M. 2009. Engineering play: a cultural history of children’s software. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Jenkins, H. 2004. Game design as narrative architecture. In First person: new media as story, performance,
and game, N. Wardrip-Fruin & P. Harrigan (eds), 118-30. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Juul, J. 2003. The game, the player, the world: looking for a heart of gameness. In Level Up: Digital Games
Research Conference Proceedings (ed.) M. Copier & J. Raessens, 30-45. Utrecht: University Press.
Lancy, D. 1980. Work and play: the Kpelle case. In Play and culture, H. Schwartzman (ed.), 324-28. West
Leonard, D. 2003. Live in your world, play in ours: race, video games, and consuming the other. Studies in
Leyenaar, T. 1992. ‘Ulama’, the survival of the Mesoamerican ballgame Ullamaliztli. Kiva 58(2), 115-53.
Long, N. 2012. Utopian sociality. Cambridge Anthropology 30(1), 80-94 (available on-line:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/43610891).
Malaby, T. 2007. Beyond play: a new approach to games. Games and Culture 2(2), 95-113.
——— 2009a. Anthropology and play: the contours of playful experience. New Literary History 40(1),
205-18.
——— 2009b. Making virtual worlds: Linden Lab and Second Life. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Mason, M. 2013. Demographic breakdown of casual, mid-core and hard-core mobile gamers. Mobile Games
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 13
http://developers.magmic.com/demographic-breakdown-casual-mid-core-hard-core-mobile-gamers/).
McLuhan, M. 1964. Understanding media: the extensions of man. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Meade, M. 1928. Coming of age in Samoa: a psychological study of primitive youth for western civilisation.
Meier, K.V. 1995. Triad trickery: playing with sport and games. In Philosophic inquiry in sport. 2nd ed. (eds)
Nardi, B. 2010. My life as a Night Elf Priest: an anthropological account of World of Warcraft. Ann Arbor:
——— & J. Harris 2006. Strangers and friends: collaborative play in World of Warcraft. Proceedings of the
20th Anniversary Conference on Computer-Supported Cooperative Work, Banff, Alberta, Canada, 149–58
Oxfeld, E. 1993. Blood, sweat, and mahjong: family and enterprise in an overseas Chinese community.
Pearce, C. 2006. Productive play: game culture from the bottom up. Games and Culture 1(1), 17-24.
——— 2007. Communities of play: the social construction of identity in persistent online game worlds. In
Second person: role-playing and story in games and playable media (eds) P. Harrigan & N. Wardrip-Fruin,
——— 2010. Discovering Uru: hard fun and the sublime pleasures of impossible gameplay. In Well played
2.0: video games, value and meaning (ed.) D. Davidson, 159-87. Pittsburgh: ETC Press.
Pickles, A. 2014. Bom bombed kwin: how two card games model kula, moka, and Goroka.” Oceania 84(3),
272-88.
Salen, K. & E. Zimmerman 2003. Rules of play. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Schneider, A. 2001. Fruits, apples, and category mistakes: on sport, games, and play. Journal of the
Seligman, A., R. Weller, M. Puett, & B. Simon 2008. Ritual and its consequences: an essay on the limits of
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X
Max Watson. Games. OEA 14
https://web.archive.org/web/20081106223155/http://www.alwaysblack.com/blackbox/bownigger.html).
——— 1995. Tricky triad: games, play, and sport. In Philosophic inquiry in sport (eds) K.V. Meier & W.J.
——— 2005. The grasshopper: games, life and utopia. 2nd ed. Peterborough: Broadview Press.
Taylor, T.L. 2006. Play between worlds: exploring online game culture. Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.
——— 2012. Raising the stakes: e-sports and the professsionalization of computer gaming. Cambridge,
Turner, V. 1982. From ritual to theatre: the human seriousness of play. New York: PAJ Publications.
Wacquant, L. 2004. Body and soul: notebooks of an apprentice boxer. New York: Oxford University Press.
Walker, H. 2013. State of play: the political ontology of sport in Amazonian Peru. American Ethnologist
40(2), 1-49.
Watson, M. 2015. A medley of meanings: insights from an instance of gameplay in League of Legends.
Wittgenstein, L. 1986 [1953]. Philosophical investigations (trans. G.E.M. Anscombe). 3rd ed. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell.
Note on contributor
Max Watson holds Ph.D. and M.Phil. degrees in Social Anthropology from the University of Cambridge and
a B.A. in Middle East Studies with a minor in Economics from McGill University. He currently works in the
This text is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 4.0 International License.
For image use please see separate credit(s). ISSN 2398-516X