Contract: Daniel Markovits
Contract: Daniel Markovits
Contract: Daniel Markovits
Daniel Markovits
....................................................................................................................
Introduction
1
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 24 (1981).
2
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 50 (1981).
3
Two very different additional sets of doctrines further limit the class of agreements that
might establish contracts.
On the one hand, doctrines concerning fraud, duress, and incapacity insist that the
agreements behind valid contracts must be knowingly and freely made. And on the other
hand, doctrines that deny contractual recognition to illegal agreements or, more broadly, to
agreements that violate public policy, prevent contract law from lending its aid to projects
that the broader legal order considers unacceptably undesirable.
The first set of doctrines might be explained as shoring the central role of agreements in
contract law, by requiring that the agreements at the heart of valid contracts be, in some
general sense, genuine or full-throated. The second set of doctrines, by contrast, subjects
contract law to limits based on values that come from outside the morality of agreements.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
332 Daniel Markovits
4
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 71 (1981).
5
This distinction is famously illustrated by the case of Williston’s tramp, who is told by a
benevolent passer-by that if he walks to a nearby clothier, he may select an overcoat on his
benefactor’s credit. See Williston and Jaeger, A Treatise on the Law of Contracts, 3rd ed.,
Vol. 1 (Baker, Voorhis, 1957), § 112. Whether or not this promise is supported by good
consideration depends on the parties’ intentions with respect to the tramp’s walking to the
store. If the benefactor intends the promise to induce the tramp to walk to collect the coat
(perhaps to assuage her guilt on going to a warm home), and if the tramp intends the walk to
induce the provision of the coat, then there is consideration. If, on the other hand, the
benefactor is merely offering to buy the tramp a coat but not to get it for him, and the tramp
is merely deciding whether or not to collect on the offer, then there is no consideration.
6
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 90 (1981).
7
See, e.g. James Baird Co. v. Gimbel Bros, 64 F.2d 344 (2d. Cir. 1933).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 333
obligation of the contract does not inhere or subsist in the agreement itself proprio
vigore, but in the law applicable to the agreement, that is, in the act of the law in
binding the promisor to perform his promise. When it is said that one who enters
8
See, e.g. Drennan v. Star Paving, Co., 333 P.2d 757 (Cal. 1958).
9
See, e.g. Hoffman v. Red Owl Stores, Inc., 133 N.W.2d 267 (Wisc. 1965).
10
See, e.g. Teachers Ins. & Annuity Assoc. v. Tribune Co., 670 F. Supp. 491, 497
(S.D.N.Y. 1987). For a systematic survey of the US American decisions, see A. Schwartz
and R. Scott, ‘Precontractual liability and preliminary agreements’, Harvard Law Review
120 (2007), 661–707, 672.
11
G. Gilmore, The Death of Contract (Ohio State University Press, 1974), 61.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
334 Daniel Markovits
upon an undertaking assumes the legal duties relating to it, what is really meant is
that the law imposes the duties on him. A contract is not a law, nor does it make
law. It is the agreement plus the law that makes the ordinary contract an enforce-
able obligation.12
12
Groves v. John Wunder, Co., 286 N.W. 235 (Minn. 1939).
13
J. Raz, ‘Promises in morality and law’, Harvard Law Review 95 (1982), 916, 937 (reviewing
P. Atiyah, Promises, Morals, and the Law).
14
Ibid.
15
O.W. Holmes, ‘The path of the law’, Harvard Law Review 10 (1897), 457–78, 459.
16
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 335
duty to keep a contract at common law means a prediction that you must
pay damages if you do not keep it, – and nothing else’17 and, in this
connection, dismissing ‘those who think it advantageous to get as much
ethics into the law as they can’.18 Contract law ought, that is, to hold the
morality of agreements tightly, but at arm’s length.
A theory of contract law cannot, therefore, mechanically adopt or
mindlessly mimic one or another preferred account of the moral obliga-
tions associated with the agreements, or promises, through which contracts
typically arise. Instead, explaining or justifying agreement’s central place
in contract law requires an independent inquiry into the distinctively
political and even legal values that this area of doctrine promotes, includ-
ing through enforcing agreements.
As it happens, the most prominent theories of contract law all
proceed in just this fashion – they set out from distinct (sometimes
overlapping, sometimes competing) accounts of the point of contract
and indeed of the point of contract’s emphasis on enforcing agreements.
The theories may be loosely classified by reference to these accounts of
contract’s purpose. The classification is necessarily imperfect, as the
theories must be interpreted before they may be assigned to categories
and are in any event not so monolithic as the categories suppose.
Nevertheless, even an imperfect organising frame helps for understand-
ing contract law and theory, most notably because it reveals that the
several most prominent approaches to contract differ not just at their
margins but, instead, understand this body of law in fundamentally
different ways.
One class of theories, which includes both economic accounts of con-
tract and philosophical theories that seek to connect contract to the
morality of harm, understands contract law in allocative terms – that is,
as a technology for distributing benefits and burdens across persons.
A second class of theories understands contract in integrative terms – that
is, in virtue of the relations among persons that contracts engender.
Intramural differences also exist within each class, of course, and
attending to these reveals both the internal flexibility of the allocative
and integrative approaches to contract and the deep structural differences
that nevertheless separate them.
17
Ibid.
18
Ibid.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
336 Daniel Markovits
The two most prominent allocative theories of contract law are the effi-
ciency-based account that has come to dominate the academic study of
contract in the United States and the harm-based theory that seeks to
assimilate contract to the broader morality of injury and, most narrowly
within the law, to tort.
19
D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, at bk. III, pt. II, sec. V, 522, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.),
(1978) (emphasis removed).
20
R. Craswell, ‘Contract law, default rules, and the philosophy of promising’, Michigan Law
Review 88 (1989), 489, 496.
21
See, e.g. A. Schwartz and R. Scott, ‘Contract theory and the limits of contract law’, Yale Law
Journal 113 (2003), 541, 556. Some theorists have developed analogous accounts according
to which contract law maximises not efficiency but party choice or autonomy (the fact that
the Kaldor–Hicks conception of efficiency at the root of the economic theory constructs
efficiency out of party choice accounts for the closeness of the analogy). One example of such
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 337
a theory is J. Kraus, ‘The correspondence of contract and promise’, Columbia Law Review 109
(2009), 1603. Some have suggested that Charles Fried’s view of contract law, elaborated in his
book Contract as Promise, possesses this structure: C. Fried, Contract as Promise: A Theory of
Contractual Obligation (Oxford University Press, 1981). See, e.g. E. Weinrib, The Idea of
Private Law, revised ed. (Oxford University Press, 2012), 50–1. Another interpretation,
pursued below, treats Fried’s view as an integrative rather than an allocative theory.
22
Schwartz and Scott, ‘Contract theory and the limits of contract law’ at 556.
23
For an early statement of this theory aimed at academic lawyers, see R.L. Birmingham,
‘Breach of contract, damage measures, and economic efficiency’, Rutgers Law Review
24 (1970), 273.
24
R. Craswell, ‘Against Fuller and Perdue’, University of Chicago Law Review 67 (2000), 99,
107.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
338 Daniel Markovits
25
J. Gordley, The Philosophical Origins of Modern Contract Doctrine (Oxford University
Press, 1991), 235. A similar point is made in P. Atiyah, Promises, Morals, and the Law
(Clarendon Press, 1981), 50–1.
26
See R. Coase, ‘The nature of the firm’, The Firm, The Market, and the Law 33 (1988), 43–4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 339
27
See C. Goetz and R. Scott, ‘The mitigation principle: toward a general theory of contractual
obligation’, Virginia Law Review 69 (1983), 967.
28
For a judicial application of this approach, per Judge Richard Posner, see Evra Corp.
v. Swiss Bank Corp., 672 F.2d 951 (7th Cir. 1982).
29
See J. Kraus, ‘Philosophy of contract law’ in J. Coleman and S. Shapiro (eds.), The Oxford
Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford University Press, 2002), 687.
Kraus argues that the economic analysis of law ‘rejects the significance of traditional
distinctions between apparently different bodies of law’ (699), such as contract and tort,
and, moreover, ‘does not take the doctrinal invocations and restatements as legal data to be
explained’ (692), but instead focuses its attention on explaining case outcomes. Earnest
Weinrib has made a similar point. See E. Weinrib, The Idea of Private Law, revised ed.
(Oxford University Press, 2012).
30
For genealogical arguments, see, e.g. P. Atiyah, The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract
(1979) and M.J. Radin, ‘Market inalienability’, Harvard Law Review 100 (1987), 1849. For
philosophical arguments, see, e.g. T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard
University Press, 1998), 295–327 and ‘Promises and contracts’ in P. Benson (ed.), The
Theory of Contract Law: New Essays (Cambridge University Press, 2001), 86, 93–4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
340 Daniel Markovits
31
See, e.g. Restatement (Second) of Torts § 552, Information Negligently Supplied for the
Guidance of Others (‘One who, in the course of his business, profession or employment, or
in any other transaction in which he has a pecuniary interest, supplies false information for
the guidance of others in their business transactions, is subject to liability for pecuniary
loss caused to them by their justifiable reliance upon the information, if he fails to exercise
reasonable care or competence in obtaining or communicating the information.’).
32
See Restatement (Second) of Torts § 548 (1977).
33
Restatement (Second) of Contracts §344 (1981).
34
Restatement (Second) of Contracts §344 (1981).
35
See Restatement (Second) of Torts § 552B (1977). An exception to this principle exists for
certain frauds, established (in part) to prevent promisors from being able reduce the extent
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 341
of their liability by arguing that their breaches are not innocent but fraudulent. Compare
Reno v. Bull, 124 N.E. 144 (N.Y. 1919) with Morse v. Hutchins, 102 Mass. 439 (1869) and
see, e.g. Restatement (Second) of Torts § 549(2).
36
For a recent general argument assimilating contract and tort, see M. Gergen, ‘Negligent
misrepresentation as contract’, California Law Review 101 (2013), 953.
37
Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 24 (1981) (emphasis added). Note that although this
definition of offer invokes intentions to assume obligations, the contemplated obligations
need not, under US American law, be specifically legal. Thus the Restatement adds that
‘Neither real not apparent intention that a promise be legally binding is essential to the
formation of a contract, but a manifestation of intention that a promise shall not affect
legal relations may prevent the formation of a contract.’ Restatement (Second) of Contracts
§ 21 (1981). English contract law takes a different view and includes intent to create legal
relations among the elements required for establishing an enforceable contract. See
e.g. Balfour v. Balfour [1919] 2 K.B. 571, 579. English law also acknowledges a strong
presumption that, in contexts involving commercial agreements, the required intent exists.
As Patrick Atiyah has observed, this presumption entails that in practice, in most commer-
cial cases, ‘no positive intention to enter into legal relations needs to be shown’. P.S.
Atiyah, An Introduction to the Law of Contract, 5th ed. (Clarendon Press, 1995), 153.
38
See Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 154 (1981).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
342 Daniel Markovits
39
See, e.g. Hadley v. Baxendale, 156 Eng. Rep. 145 (Court of Exchequer, 1854).
40
See, e.g. Rombola v. Cosindas, 220 N.E.2d 919 (Mass. 1966). Some cases even make reliance
an express element of a claim for breach of contract and refuse to award damages for lost
expectations that cannot be recast as reliance. See, e.g. Overstreet v. Norden Laboratories,
Inc. 229 F. 2d 1286 (6th Cir. 1982). But these cases are probably outliers, and other opinions
take the opposite view. See, e.g. Texaco, Inc. v. Pennzoil, Co., 729 S.W. 2d 768 (Tex. App.
Hous. (1 Dist.) 1987).
41
These points have been familiar for some time. See L.L. Fuller and W.R. Perdue Jr, ‘The
reliance interest in contract damages: 1’, Yale Law Journal 46 (1936), 52.
42
Once again, the doctrinal path by which this result was approached proceeded in stages.
First, older holdings insisting that promissory estoppel might properly be applied only in
the shadow of completed promises (involving both offer and acceptance and lacking only
consideration), see, e.g. James Baird Co. v. Gimbel Bros., 64 F.2d 344 (2nd Cir. 1933), were
replaced with holdings that applied promissory estoppel in the absence of any express
accepted promise, that is, to mere offers, see, e.g. Drennan v. Star Paving Co., 333 P.2d 757
(Cal. 1958). And second, a few opinions went so far as to apply promissory estoppel even
where there existed neither a promise nor even a completed offer, and based instead on
manipulative (but not fraudulent or otherwise conventionally tortious) representations
made during pre-contractual negotiations. See Hoffman v. Red Owl Stores, Inc., 133
N.W.2d 267 (Wis. 1965).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 343
43
Atiyah, Promises, Morals, and the Law, 121.
44
See Gilmore, The Death of Contract.
45
See Fried, Contract as Promise.
46
Gilmore, The Death of Contract, 61.
47
See T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, 295–327 and T.M. Scanlon, ‘Promises and
contracts’ in The Theory of Contract Law: New Essays, 93–4.
48
See T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other, 298–300.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
344 Daniel Markovits
49
This is Scanlon’s principle F, which states:
If (1) A voluntarily and intentionally leads B to expect that A will do X (unless B consents
to A’s not doing so); (2) A knows that B wants to be assured of this; (3) A acts with the aim
of providing this assurance, and has good reason to believe that he or she has done so; (4)
B knows that A has the beliefs and intentions just described; (5) A intends for B to know
this, and knows that B does know it; and (6) B knows that A has this knowledge and intent;
then, in the absence of special justification, A must do X unless B consents to X’s not
being done.
Ibid. at 304.
50
See ibid. at 308–9.
51
Scanlon says:
[I]t is reasonable to want a principle of fidelity that requires performance rather than
compensation and that, once an expectation has been created, does not always recognize
a warning that it will not be fulfilled as adequate protection against loss, even if the
warning is given before any further decision has been made on the basis of the
expectation.
Scanlon, ibid. at 304. Furthermore, Scanlon defends a principle for contract law, which he
calls EF (for enforcing fidelity) which holds:
It is permissible legally to enforce remedies for breach of contract that go beyond
compensation for reliance losses, provided that these remedies are not excessive and
that they apply only in cases in which the following conditions hold: (1) A, the party
against whom the remedy is enforced, has, in the absence of objectionable constraint and
with adequate understanding (or the ability to acquire such understanding) of his or her
situation, intentionally led B to expect that A would do X unless B consented to A’s not
doing so; (2) A had reason to believe that B wanted to be assured of this; (3) A acted with
the aim of providing this assurance, by indicating to B that he or she was undertaking a
legal obligation to do X; (4) B indicated that he or she understood A to have undertaken
such an obligation; (5) A and B knew, or could easily determine, what kind of remedy
B would be legally entitled to if A breached this obligation; and (6) A failed to do
X without being released from this obligation by B, and without special justification
for doing so.
Scanlon, ‘Promises and contracts’, at 105. Scanlon believes that his argument shows only
that such legal enforcement of contracts is permitted, not that it is required. See Scanlon,
ibid. at 106.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 345
52
According to contractualism, ‘[a]n act is wrong if its performance under the circumstances
would be disallowed by any system of rules for the general regulation of behaviour which
no one could reasonably reject as a basis for informed, unforced general agreement’. T.M.
Scanlon, ‘Contractualism and utilitarianism’ in A. Sen and B. Williams (eds.), Utilitarian-
ism and Beyond (Cambridge University Press, 1982) 103, 110.
53
These include the psychological benefit of the confidence such protection promotes as well
as the more direct benefit of increasing the likelihood that promisors will perform as
promised. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other at 302–3. Here Scanlon might have added
the benefits associated with encouraging reliance that figure so prominently in utilitarian
and economic accounts of promise and contract.
Scanlon believes the burdens slight because a person can always avoid the obligation to
satisfy expectations simply by warning that she is not making any promises.
54
These benefits accrue, moreover, not just to the promisees who receive them directly but
also to promisors who desire to be able to give firm assurances in order to increase the
value of their promises and hence of what they can demand in exchange for them. See
Scanlon, ‘Promises and contracts’, at 108.
55
The error costs that accrue when legal enforcement is ordered against a person who has not
in fact made an enforceable contract are kept small, Scanlon asserts, by the strict and fairly
formal requirements for entering into a contract. See ibid. And the compliance costs that
accrue when a promisor must make good the expectations created by a promise she has
come to regret command little respect in the contractualist calculus, because they can be
avoided ex ante at a low cost by refraining from making contractual promises and can be
avoided ex post only by neglecting a moral obligation imposed by the moral principle of
promise-keeping, and this is not a cost that promisors can reasonably cite as a ground for
rejecting the legal enforcement of contractual expectations. Ibid.
56
Scanlon, ibid., at 304–5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
346 Daniel Markovits
57
R.R.W. Brooks, ‘The efficient performance hypothesis’, Yale Law Journal 116 (2006), 568, 573.
58
See, e.g. S.V. Shiffrin, ‘Promising, intimate relationships, and conventionalism’, Philo-
sophical Review 117 (2008), 481.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 347
59
S.V. Shiffrin, ‘The divergence of contract and promise’, Harvard Law Review 120 (2007), 708.
60
See, e.g. Restatement (Second) of Contracts § 344 (1981).
61
Various of these claims appear in, for example, D. Friedman, ‘The efficient breach fallacy’,
The Journal of Legal Studies 18 (1989), 1; S.V. Shiffrin, ‘Could breach of contract be
immoral?’, Michigan Law Review 107 (2009), 1551; S.V. Shiffrin, ‘The divergence of
contract and promise’, 708; R.R.W. Brooks, ‘The efficient performance hypothesis’, 568.
62
S.V. Shiffrin, ‘Must I mean what you think I should have said?’, Virginia Law Review
98 (2012), 159.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
348 Daniel Markovits
63
Cf. D. Markovits and A. Schwartz, ‘The myth of efficient breach: new defenses of the
expectation interest’, Virginia Law Review 97 (2011), 1939.
64
Cf. D. Markovits, ‘Sharing ex ante and sharing ex post’ in A.S. Gold and P. Miller (eds.), The
Philosophical Foundations of Fiduciary Law (Oxford University Press, 2014), 209–24.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 349
trust does not establish intimacy but rather serves ‘humdrum ends: We
make appointments, buy and sell.’65
Some thin integrative theories of contract law associate themselves with
moral views that understand even personal promises as establishing thin
relations among parties who remain, within and indeed through their
promises, at arm’s length.66 Other thin integrative theories propose that
contract law, by replacing the trust that lies at the heart of personal
promises with external enforcement, sustains constructive relationships
among parties who remain impersonally detached.67 Regardless of their
internal differences, all thin integrative theories share that contractual
sharing is cabined, ex ante, by the agreement of the parties and thus
differs – structurally and qualitatively – from the open-ended sharing ex
post contemplated by fiduciary obligations.
Thin integrative theories set their trajectory by the observation that
‘[o]ne of the hallmarks of [the] common law is that it does not have a
doctrine of abuse of rights: if one has a right to do an act then, one can, in
general, do it for whatever reason one wishes’.68 This entails that ‘[e]xcept
where the contracting parties are also in a fiduciary relationship, self-
interest is permissible, and indeed is the norm in the exercise of contractual
rights’.69 Thin integrative theories thus embrace the contract doctrines –
the expectation remedy, for example, and the mitigation requirement –
that thick integrative theories condemn. With respect to remedies, for
example, thin integrative theories celebrate the ways in which expectation
damages encourage promisors to avoid the trades that their contracts
describe when the gains from doing so exceed the costs. The thin theories
applaud this practice of ‘efficient breach’ not only, and indeed not princi-
pally, because it increases the contractual surplus available for the parties
to share. More fundamentally, a legal regime that permits efficient breach
of contract permits promisors (and promisees) to fix the limits of their
contractual relations at contract formation and thus to coordinate their
65
Cf. Fried, Contract as Promise, 8.
66
See, e.g. D. Markovits, ‘Promise as an arm’s length relation’ in H. Sheinman (ed.), Promises
and Agreements: Philosophical Essays (Oxford University Press, 2010) and D. Markovits,
‘Contract and collaboration’, Yale Law Journal 113 (2004), 1417.
67
See, e.g. D. Kimel, From Promise to Contract: Towards a Liberal Theory of Contract (Hart,
2003).
68
J. Beatson, ‘Public law influences in contract law’ in J. Beatson and D. Friedmann (eds.)
Good Faith and Fault in Contract Law (Clarendon Press, 1995), 263–88, 266–7.
69
Ibid. at 267.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
350 Daniel Markovits
conduct, ex ante, free from any concern that they will be required to make
additional adjustments, or show additional concern, toward each other ex
post. The thin conception of contract thus supports coordination among
parties who take each other’s contractual intentions at face value and
neither ask nor worry about the interests and motives that lie behind them.
This renders contract especially well suited to sustaining private orderings
in open, cosmopolitan societies, in which traders share little outside a joint
commitment to honour the agreed terms of their trades.
Thin integrative theories thus propose that contract’s foundational value
is not trust, fidelity, loyalty or some other fiduciary ideal but rather good
faith. A fiduciary is ‘required to treat his principal as if the principal were
he’.70 But good faith, by contrast, ‘does not mean that a party vested with a
clear right is obligated to exercise that right to its own detriment for the
purpose of benefiting another party to the contract’.71 Rather, in place of
‘loyalty to the contractual counterparty’, good faith requires ‘faithfulness
to the scope, purpose, and terms of the parties’ contract’,72 which is to say
‘honesty in fact and the observance of reasonable commercial standards of
fair dealing’.73 Thus, as one prominent judge has more colourfully
explained, ‘even after you have signed a contract, you are not obliged to
become an altruist toward the other party’.74 Nor does good faith require
contracting parties to adopt even an attitude of substantive impartiality
between their contractual interests and the interests of their contracting
partners. The law does not seek, ‘in the name of good faith, to make every
contract signatory his brother’s keeper’.75
Indeed, the duty of good faith in performance ‘does not create a separate
duty of fairness and reasonableness which can be independently breached’.76
Instead, good faith characterises contract obligations’ (thin) form and
70
Mkt. St. Assocs. Ltd. P’ship v. Frey, 941 F.2d 588, 593 (7th Cir. 1991).
71
Rio Algom Corp. v. Jimco Ltd., 618 P.2d 497, 505 (Utah 1980).
72
ASB Allegiance Real Estate Fund v. Scion Breckenridge Managing Member, L.L.C., 50 A.3d
434, 440–1 (Del. Ch. 2012) aff’d in part, rev’d in part on other grounds, 68 A.3d 665
(Del. 2013). I owe this reference to Andrew Gold.
73
Uniform Commercial Code §§ 1–201, 2–103.
74
Mkt. St. Assocs. Ltd. P’ship v. Frey, at 594 (7th Cir. 1991) (Posner, J.). Not every court has
always adopted this approach. See, e.g. Parev Prods. Co. v. I. Rokeach & Sons, Inc., 124
F.2d 147 (2d Cir. 1941), which comes close to taking a fiduciary duty view of contractual
obligations, seeking ‘the really equitable solution’ as opposed to ‘a limited rule of good
faith’ (at 150).
75
Mkt. St. Assocs. Ltd. P’ship v. Frey, at 593.
76
Uniform Commercial Code § 1–304 [cmt. 1] (2003).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018
Contract 351
Conclusion
The recognition that contract law is the law of agreements thus frames
understandings of contract law; but it does not fill the frame with specific
content. Instead, the law’s enforcement of agreements might serve very
different kinds of purposes; and it might serve very different particular
purposes within each kind.
Contract law has thus been thought, variously, to promote the efficient
allocation of economic resources or to protect against harms incurred
when promisees rely on promises. And contract law has been thought to
establish intimate and loyal relations between the contracting parties or to
establish respectful coordination among parties who hold one another at
arm’s length.
Contract theory has thus developed a flexibility that mimics the variety
of contractual practice.
77
S.J. Burton, ‘Breach of contract and the common law duty to perform in good faith’,
Harvard Law Review 94 (1980), 369, 371. For cases see, e.g. Sessions, Inc. v. Morton, 491
F.2d 854, 857 (9th Cir. 1974); Ryder Truck Rental, Inc. v. Cent. Packing Co., 341 F.2d 321,
323–4 (10th Cir. 1965); Perkins v. Standard Oil Co., 383 P.2d 107, 111–12 (Or. 1963) (en
banc).
78
Burton, ‘Breach of contract and the common law duty to perform in good faith’, 373.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Exeter, on 15 Jun 2020 at 22:03:52, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781316104439.018