Beyond Hermeneutic
Beyond Hermeneutic
Beyond Hermeneutic
Nicholas Davey**
S. Beckett
25
26 Nicholas Davey
The future of hermeneutics must take the form of the transformation of hermeneu-
tics into a practical philosophy or philosophy of praxis [. . . ]
Hermeneutics understood in this wider universal sense moves into the region of
“practical philosophy,” a region which Joachim Ritter and his school, finding them-
selves situated in the midst of the German tradition of transcendental philosophy,
tried to revive. Philosophical hermeneutics is aware of what it could mean to move
in this direction. A theory of the praxis of understanding is obviously theory and
not practice, but a theory of practices is still not some kind of technique, nor is it
an effort to make societal practice more scientific. Rather, hermeneutics offers a
philosophical reflection on the limits of all scientific and technical control of nature
and of society. These limits are truths that need to be defended against the modern
concept of science, and defending these truths is one of the most important tasks
of philosophical hermeneutics. (Gadamer, 2007, p. 71)
This essay will explore how the questions asked in the 1997 essay about
“the beyond of interpretation” culminate in the principal claim of the 2014
essay that the future of hermeneutics resides in its transformation into a
philosophy of praxis. For reasons that become increasingly clear, this paper
is positively disposed to the practice–turn in hermeneutics. However, the
conclusion of the 2014 essay that hermeneutics re–thought as a philosophy
of practice that “will draw the world ever closer to being what for Hegel
(and afterwards for Marx) is the place of the spirit, where the spirit feels
itself finally (but never thoroughly) at home” (Vattimo, 2015, p. 727)1 is, we
shall argue, open to serious challenge. I do not intend to debate whether this
remnant of Hegelian thought plays the role of a necessary organising fiction
in Vattimo’s hermeneutics (much in the same way that Gadamer’s “antic-
ipation of completeness” does in his). However, I will question whether
the centrality of praxis in hermeneutics will ever succeed in allowing the
hermeneutic agent to feel at home in the world. There is, perhaps, an anal-
ogy here between Schubert’s Winterreise and Vattimo”s argumentation: the
consequence of dissolving hermeneutics as method is that the hermeneuti-
cal agent (the journeying spirit) can never return to itself. If the aim of praxis
is to facilitate that return, then the question is simply whether hermeneutics
construed as a de–alienating praxis is doomed to fail?
What renders Vattimo’s concluding appeal to praxis problematic is that
(1) there is (literally) a world of difference between turning hermeneutics
towards an explicit “philosophy” of practice and recognising the operation of
praxis within hermeneutics. If the operation of praxis is recognised as driving
hermeneutics towards the question of future orientated meaning, the future
of hermeneutics can never, arguably, conclude. (2) If hermeneutics is turned
towards an explicit philosophy of praxis, then, will it not have to confront
what Gadamer calls “the indissoluble problem of its rational application”?
(Gadamer, 2007, p.234). In other words, hermeneutic praxis always faces
the possibility of its failure. (3) If hermeneutics is to be developed into a
“philosophy of praxis” how does Vattimo avoid realising precisely the fear
articulated in Beyond Interpretation, namely, that hermeneutics becomes just
one philosophy amongst others? Let us turn directly to some of the key
arguments in that text.
1. The conclusion is anticipated in Farewell to Truth where Vattimo writes at its close, “The
absolute character of the spirit consists, for us, not in the fact (as the still somewhat Cartesian
Hegel perhaps thinks) of being near to itself in the most total certainty and self–transparency but
in constituting the only end which all objective attainments, the pragmatic truths, may aim as the
authentic, never totally given, overcoming of every form of alienation.” (A Farewell to Truth, Columbia
University Press, 2011, p. 140).
Praxis and the Impossibility of Hermeneutics? 29
2. Beyond Interpretation
What I relate is the history of the next centuries: I describe what is coming, what
can no longer come differently: the advent of nihilism [. . . ]
What does nihilism mean? That the highest devaluate themselves. The aim is
lacking; “why?” finds no answer. (Nietzsche, 1968, p. 4 and 9).
30 Nicholas Davey
It (praxis) essentially takes the form of a tendential transition between the passivity
that class dominate imposes on “subaltern” social groups (what Gramsci calls “the
economico–corporative stage’) and the “intellectual and moral reform” that is
supposed to allow them to become actors in their own history (and in this sense
seems to return strictly to the Aristotelian definition of motion: “The fulfilment of
what is potential as potential. . . ”). (Cassin, 2013, pp. 827–28).
4. Failures of Practice
Of Aesthetic and Hermeneutic rationality: It’s a difference that picks up the question
of the linkage in Kant between The Critique of Pure Reason and The Critique of
Judgement. Although orthodox Kantians may find the proposition audacious, to
me it seems clear that the Kantian intellect can function as an organ of objective
knowledge of the world, that is, be universally valid, on the basis of the community
that is established, in a manner ever historical and eventual, among subjects who
share the aesthetic experience. Not just in their appreciation of the same works of
art or natural beauty but in the acknowledgment of the same civil, religious and
mythical models [. . . ] (Vattimo, 2008, p. 136).
practical philosophy is not the application of theory to praxis [. . . ] but arises itself
from the experience of praxis due to the reason and reasonableness inherent in it
(Gadamer, 1992, p. 217).
have to be thought in different and far more positive terms than those which
characterise Gadamer’s position in Truth and Method. (Vattimo, 1997, p. 109).
Bibliographic references
Benso S. & Schroeder B., Between Nihilism and Politics; The Hermeneutics of Gianni
Vattimo, 2010, Albany, State University of New York 2011.
Böhm S., Repositioning Organisation Theory, Palgrave Macmillan, London 2006.
Cassin B., “Praxis” in the Dictionary of Untranslatables, A Philosophical Lexicon,
Princeton University Press, 2013, p. 825.
Davey N., Unfinished Worlds, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh 2014.
Gadamer H.G., Philosophical Hermeneutics, trans. D. Linge, University of Califor-
nia Press, Berkley 1977.
–––––, Truth and Method, Sheed and Ward, 1989.
–––––, “Citizens of Two Worlds”, in On Education, Poetry, and History, Applied
Hermeneutics, Albany, State University of New York Press 1992.
–––––, The Enigma of Health, Polity, London 1996.
–––––, “Hermeneutics as Practical Philosophy”, The Gadamer Reader, trans. R.
Palmer, Evanston, North Western University Press, 1996.
–––––, “Classical and Philosophical Hermeneutics”, The Gadamer Reader, ed. R.
Palmer, Evanston, 2007.
Leszek Kolakowski, Positivist Philosophy, From Hume to the Vienna Circle, Penguin,
London 1972.
Rowland C. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Liberation Theology, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge 1999.
Vattimo G., Beyond Interpretation, trans. David Webb, Polity, London 1997.
–––––, A Farewell to Truth, Columbia University, New York 2008, p. 136.
–––––, “The Future of Hermeneutics”, in The Routledge Companion to Hermeneu-
tics, ed. Jeff Malpas and Hans–Helmuth Gander, Routledge, London 2015, p.
721–728.