McMullin On Science & Values
McMullin On Science & Values
Values in Science
Science is value-laden: certain epistemic values are integral to the entire process of
assessment in science.
Facts: Saying “it is a fact that p” is the same as saying “it is true that p”.
“Objective” values are those that can be grounded not just in preferences but in
some standpoint accessible to reason and knowledge. Example:… ?
Objectivist views of science are now more nuanced and realistic than it was when
Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions was first published (early 1960s).
Core current position about science and scientific knowledge shared by most
defenders of scientific objectivity:
Theories by their very nature are hypothetical and tentative; they remain open to
revision and even rejection.
P2: Underdetermination:
Q The theories of science are not fully determined by the empirical evidence.
The logical link between evidence and theory is neither direct nor fully rule-
governed (“algorithmic”).
Science is value-laden to the extent that there are certain characteristic epistemic
values which are integral to the entire process of assessment in science.
(a) One can judge the extent to which a particular entity realizes the value.
(b) One may be interested in judging the extent to which (if any) this
characteristic really is a value for this kind of entity.
Here one deals with the abstract relation of characteristic and entity under a
particular description. Why is speed rather than strength valuable to an antelope?
Other Valuations
If a theory is being applied to practical ends (as in, say, medicine), and the theoretical
alternatives carry with them outcomes of different value to the agents concerned, we have
the typical decision-theoretic grid involving not only epistemic estimates but also
“utilities” of some sort.
McMullin’s focus on the presence of “values in science” does not refer primarily
to the ethical values required for the success of science as a communal activity (honesty,
intellectual integrity, etc.), or to the values implicit in decision-making in applied science.
Epistemic Values
We cannot definitively establish the values appropriate to the assessment of theory.
But we can provide a tentative list of criteria that have gradually been shaped over
the experience of many centuries, the values that are implicit in contemporary scientific
practice.
Such characteristic values McMullin calls epistemic, because they are presumed
to promote the truth-like character of science, its character as the most secure knowledge
available to us of the world we seek to understand.
An epistemic value is one we have reason to believe will, if pursued, help toward
the attainment of such knowledge.
Current criteria for theory choice in science express the values that one expects a
good theory to embody.
McMullin’s list of criteria for theory choice is in broad agreement with Kuhn’s,
but oriented toward objectivism.
(a) Predictive accuracy is something a theory must have if it is in the long run to
be acceptable.
(d) Unifying Power: The theory should have the capability to bring together
previously disparate areas of inquiry.
(e) Fertility: It should generate both novel predictions and fruitful additions to and
modifications of received knowledge.
There are other epistemic values, like that of reproducibility in an experiment or accuracy
in a measurement.
However, scientists may not attach the same relative weights to different
characteristic values of theory.
There is no alternative mode of access that would allow the degree of “fit”
between theory and world to be independently assessed, and the values appropriate to a
good theory to be definitively established.
McMullin: Value-judgment permeates the work of science as a whole, from the
decision to allow a particular experimental result to count as “accepted” to the decision
not to seek an alternative to a theory which so far has proved satisfactory.
They may derive from the finiteness of time or resources available to the
experimenter, for example.
And sometimes the borderline between the epistemic and the pragmatic may be
hard to draw.
But it is not expediency values that pose the main challenge to the epistemic
integrity of the appraisal process.
If values are needed in order to close the gap between underdetermined theory
and the evidence brought in its support, presumably all values can slip in: political,
moral, social, and religious.
Reports of amazing (and seemingly impossible) successes, each one replaced with
new success claims as earlier ones failed.
Nevertheless, with the media's help, Lysenko enjoyed the popular image of the
"barefoot scientist"—the embodiment of the mythic Soviet peasant genius.
By the late 1920s, the Soviet political bosses had given their support to Lysenko.
When no compelling case can be made for saying that the imposition of a
particular value on the process of theory choice is likely to improve the epistemic status
of the theory, this value should be held to be non-epistemic in the context in question.
Is there any reasoned way to stop short of a relativism that would see in science
no more than the product of a contingent social consensus, bearing testimony to the
historical particularity of culture and personality much more than to an objective truth
about the world?
The characteristic values guiding theory-choice are firmly rooted in the complex
learning experience which is the history of science; this is their primary justification.
We have gradually learnt from experience that humans have the ability to
construct “theories” which can provide a high degree of accuracy in predicting what will
happen, as well as accounting for what has happened, in the world around.
It has been discovered, further, that these theories can embody other values too—
such values as coherence and fertility—and that an insistence on these other values is
likely to enhance the chances over the long run of the attainment of the first goal, that of
empirical accuracy.
It was not always clear that these basic values could be pursued simultaneously.
(B) Realism
In its cautious form, the thesis of realism about science affirms that there are compelling
reasons to accept that in many scientific disciplines, like geology and cell-biology, the
models postulated by our current theories give us reliable, though still incomplete, insight
into the structures of the physical world.
For example by providing a theory in terms of which such values would be shown
to be appropriate demands to lay on scientific theory.
McMullin’s conclusion: To the extent that the above validation moves succeed,
there is reason to trust the values used commonly in current science for theory appraisal
as something much more than the contingent consensus of a peculiar social group.
But a further step is needed, because these values do not of themselves determine
theory-choice.
Other values can and do enter in, the sorts of values that sociologists of science
draw attention to (such as the personal ambition of individual scientists, the welfare of
his/her wider social group, etc.).
Lombroso's research methods were clinical and descriptive, with precise details of
skull dimension and other measurements.
But he did not enjoy the benefits of rigorous statistical comparisons of criminals
and non-criminals.
Adequate control groups, which he lacked, might have altered his general
conclusions.
In the more credible scientific disciplines, the process of learning is one long
series of test and tentative imaginative extensions.
To the extent that non-epistemic values and other non-epistemic factors have been
instrumental in a given original theory-decision, they are gradually sifted by the
continued application of the sort of epistemic value-judgment described above.
The non-epistemic, by definition, will not in the long run survive this process.
The process is designed to limit the effects not only of fraud and carelessness, but
also of ideology, understood in the pejorative sense as distortive intrusion into the process
of shaping our thought to the world.