This Content Downloaded From 188.251.147.90 On Sun, 03 Oct 2021 00:25:31 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 188.251.147.90 On Sun, 03 Oct 2021 00:25:31 UTC
This Content Downloaded From 188.251.147.90 On Sun, 03 Oct 2021 00:25:31 UTC
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/43154319?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophical Topics
Joseph Rouse
Wesleyan University
149
150
Note well that, although the source of Haugeland's concern is that biologi-
cal functions cannot account for truth-telling, the result is to show that they
cannot be genuinely intentionally contentful. They can be dysfunctional in
individual cases, but not wrong in their normal functioning, because such
functionality cannot express anything other than what it effectively differen-
tiates. No matter how subtle and complex the discriminations that functional
norms accomplish, their competence cannot exceed the range of their actual
performance.
Haugeland had once thought that socially instituted norms could do bet-
ter: he used to locate his own approach to intentionality (and Heidegger's) as
defending "third base" among the various "intentionality all-stars," by argu-
ing that the normativity of social practices best accounts for how intentional
holism is compatible with some version of materialism. Haugeland has now
recanted, because he thinks socially instituted norms have limitations com-
parable to those of biological functions (and he now thinks that Heidegger
was responsive to the same concern in Sein und Zeit). Individual agents can
fail to conform to norms, just as particular biological systems can malfunc-
tion, but the "general telling" of the community that institutes those norms
can no more be mistaken in its discriminations than can the functional adap-
tations of a species.
To understand how the constitution of objective accountability exceeds
mere social institution, Haugeland begins by disambiguating and further
articulating the notion of a "constitutive rule," through which games have
become an influential model for understanding the normativity of language
and social practices more generally. He draws illuminating distinctions
between four kinds of constitutive "rule": regulations that govern what
"players" do, standards that govern all phenomena within a game or prac-
tice, skills that discern whether phenomena accord with these standards, and
commitment to abide by skillfully applied standards. The constitutive skills
that determine accord with constitutive standards are in turn distinguished
from "mundane" skills for recognizing and coping with the relevant phe-
nomena in the first place. In chess, which provides a sustained example for
Haugeland's discussion, the constitutive skills amount to the ability to tell a
legal from an illegal move; their mundane counterparts enable recognition
of and appropriate responsiveness to the objects and phenomena (pieces,
moves, and situations on the board) to which these standards apply.
Haugeland claims that, unlike merely instituted norms, such skills and
standards (together, as we shall see, with a commitment to abide by them)
constitute a domain of
151
152
153
II
We are now prepared to consider my critical response to this project and its
execution. I shall focus upon four points. In this section, I take up
Haugeland's distinction between the constitution of "objective phenomena"
and the social institution of norms that cannot hold the "general telling" of
a community to account. Subsequent sections will consider his conception
of objects as what truthful comportments are beholden to, his aspiration to
discover ontological differences among distinct ways of being, and his
account of existential commitment as the source or "ground" of our respon-
sibility to comport ourselves truthfully.
Haugeland's concept of constitution emerges from his attempt to dis-
ambiguate and further articulate the notion of a "constitutive rule," through
which games have been an influential model for understanding the norma-
tivity of language and social practices more generally. The central concerns
here are to understand both the normative authority of constitutive rules and
their normative force or efficacy. My concern is not with the concept of con-
stitution (or disclosure) itself, but with Haugeland's distinction of constitu-
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
IV
162
163
164
165
The concept of epistemic things expresses how the material systems that
focus scientific research always outrun our projections and conceptualiza-
tions of them, precisely the point that Haugeland hoped to characterize in
terms of objective correctness. Without some technical control of their com-
ponents and conceptual grasp of their configuration, experimental systems
cannot even pose explorable questions; yet, to the extent that these systems
are interesting or important, genuinely disclosive of the world, they undo
their own conceptualization. As Rheinberger notes,
Experimental systems grow slowly into a kind of scientific
hardware within which the more fragile software of epistemic
things - this amalgam of halfway-concepts, no-longer-tech-
niques, and not-yet-values-and-standards - is articulated, con-
nected, disconnected, placed, and displaced. Certainly they
delineate the realm of the possible. But as a rule they do not cre-
166
His homage to Popper is his insistence that the constitutive standards of sci-
entific practice be unequivocally vulnerable to the prior determinacy of
things, so that the enterprise itself can be in question.
This demand overlooks the inherent and productive ambiguities
between accountability to procedural norms and to what is disclosed
through their performance. In discussing what Haugeland would call the
normative accountability of research skills, Rheinberger insists upon the
openness of such skills to something unprecedented and unexpected, and the
consequent need not to allow such skills to become rigidly determinate and
hence confrontational.
Haugeland also wants to allow for openness to the unexpected, but in his
remarkable amalgamation of Popper, Heidegger, and Kuhn, he sees it as
authentically resolute openness to giving up one's whole way of proceeding,
a kind of existential falsification, rather than as the normal position of
research within the penumbra of the known.
In these different conceptions of the normativity of experimental sci-
ence, Haugeland and Rheinberger agree in taking scientific practices to be
fundamentally accountable to material phenomena. Where they disagree
concerns what is at stake in such accountability. For Haugeland, the
167
168
169
170
NOTES
An earlier version of this paper was presented to the Central Division of the American
Philosophical Association, for an author meets critics session devoted to John Haugeland's
Having Thought: Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1998). I am grateful to my fellow symposiasts, Daniel Dennett, Brian Cantwell Smith, and
especially John Haugeland for their contributions and responses. Rebecca Kukla also provided
very helpful comments on the penultimate version.
171
111
173
45. Haugeland coined the expression "vapid materialism" in Having Thought, chap. 7, to
express a commitment (along with a comparably vapid holism) that should be attributed
to all of the infielders among his "intentionality all-stars."
174
59. The double sense of nature as "mattering" is fully intended; see Barad, "Meeting the
Universe Halfway," for further explication.
60. The argument in the preceding section also requires, of course, that we reinterpret the
supposed ontological significance of this claim. The question is not which beings can
have intentionality as part of their way of being, but rather what is necessary for the "co-
constitution" of a locus of agency and responsibility, and of something at stake in the dis-
closure of being to which it is responsible.
61. Haugeland emphasizes a different way of distinguishing human intentionality from the
functional normativity of animals. What supposedly marks the distinctive intentionality
of human beings is understanding, whose norms extend beyond mere correct (or func-
tional) performance to objective truth. That is, what human beings supposedly have that
animals do not is a recognition of and responsiveness to a difference between being func-
tionally right and factually wrong ( Having Thought, 310). But as I noted earlier, that dif-
ference integrally concerns semantic contentfulness together with truth-beholdenness. In
the end, I think, Haugeland does not pay enough attention to the intradependence
between truth and meaning, and in his zeal to get beyond a merely socially instituted nor-
mativity, has not done sufficient justice to the mutuality of understanding and intentional-
attributive recognition.
175
176