Fused Modality
Fused Modality
Fused Modality
Abstract. According to Svein Eng there are propositions concerning the law which
are descriptive as well as normative, but cannot be separated into one descriptive
and one normative proposition. Eng calls these propositions “fused” (“sammens-
meltede”). In Eng’s theory a proposition with “fused modality” is partly descriptive
and partly normative, but cannot be classified as a separable combination of a claim
about what the law “is” and a claim about what the law “ought to be.” In a “fused”
proposition modality is a question of “degree.” The purpose of this article is to show
why Eng’s theory should be rejected. The introduction of “fused modality” adds
nothing of value to legal theory. Eng claims to have discovered a class of proposi-
tions not previously accounted for, but this is not the case. The lawyer Eng talks
about as making a “fused” proposition is simply a lawyer logically confused.
well as normative, but cannot be separated into one descriptive and one nor-
mative proposition (Eng 2000, 237). Eng calls these propositions “fused”
(“sammensmeltede”). In Eng’s theory a proposition with “fused modality” is
partly descriptive and partly normative, but cannot be classified as a sepa-
rable combination of a claim about what the law “is” and a claim about what
the law “ought to be” (ibid., 252). In a “fused” proposition, modality is a
question of “degree” (Eng 1998, 327).
Eng does not claim that all legal propositions have a “fused modality.” He
says that some legal propositions are purely descriptive and some are purely
normative. And he does not claim that a legal proposition, which is neither
purely descriptive nor purely normative, must necessarily be “fused.”
According to Eng a proposition that contains an “is” as well as an “ought”
can either be a separable combination of a descriptive and a prescriptive
proposition, or an inseparable “fusion” of these two elements (Eng 2000,
237). Eng does not claim that the logical distinction between “is” and
“ought” cannot be upheld (ibid., 258). He maintains that descriptions and
prescriptions are separable in principle, but his point is that they are not
always separable in practice (ibid., 259). Some legal propositions entail a
separable combination of a descriptive and a normative proposition, but
most legal propositions do not (Eng 1998, 321). According to Eng legal argu-
mentation in practice is dominated by propositions with a “fused modality”
(Eng 2000, 246).
It should also be pointed out that Eng’s theory is about the “subjective
meaning” of legal propositions (Eng 2000, 237). It only concerns what the
speaker means to say (Eng 1998, 313). When Eng says that the “meaning”
of a legal proposition has a “fused modality” he is talking about the inten-
tions of the speaker. He is not referring to the “meaning” of the proposition
according to linguistic conventions (Eng 2000, 238).
Eng’s theory has been well received and is admired by legal scholars in
the Scandinavian countries (Peczenik 1998, 88; Dalberg-Larsen 1999, 478;
Bindreiter 2001, 85–92). The purpose of this article is to show why Eng’s
theory should be rejected. The introduction of “fused modality” adds
nothing of value to legal theory. Eng claims to have discovered a class of
propositions not previously accounted for, but this is not the case. The
lawyer that Eng talks about as making a “fused” proposition is simply a
lawyer logically confused.
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004.
82 Christian Dahlman
Eng challenges a theory that claims that the subjective meaning of “Jones
has the right to be compensated by Smith” must be either (1) or (2), by
introducing a third possibility: a “fusion” of propositions with different
modalities.
The question is: What theory is being challenged here? Who is the philoso-
pher of law, who claims that the possible subjective meaning of the phrase
in question is exhausted by (1) and (2)? Unfortunately Eng does not answer
this question. Eng’s entire analysis does not contain a single reference to
someone taking the position he challenges. As far as I can see, this is due to
the fact that no one would present such a theory. It is rather obvious that
the subjective meaning of “Jones has the right to be compensated by Smith”
could also contain
If one asks the lawyer whether he can sort the descriptive from the normative in his
proposition de lege lata, the answer will often be negative [ . . . ]. (Eng 2000, 247)
Another possibility is that the lawyer who says “Jones has the right to be
compensated by Smith” is making a statement with undecided modality. In
this case the lawyer is not confused. He understands very well that his state-
ment can be used to make different claims about the law, and the logical
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004.
Fused Modality or Confused Modality? 83
difference between these claims are perfectly clear to him. He just has not
decided what he wants to claim. This kind of behaviour can serve a tactical
purpose in litigation. As far as our investigation is concerned, however,
statements like these are without interest. Eng’s theory is about the subjec-
tive meaning of legal statements, and a statement with undecided modality
has no subjective meaning. Strictly speaking, a statement with undecided
modality is not a proposition at all.
When Eng talks about a proposition with “fused modality” he is not
talking about a statement with separable propositions with different modal-
ities, and he cannot be talking about a statement with undecided modality.
This leaves Eng with two options. He could either be talking about exactly
the same thing that others would call a “confused statement,” or he could
be talking about a proposition that does not fit into any of the categories
listed above. The first option is devastating for Eng’s theory. If “fused modal-
ity” is just a new term for confused modality, Eng’s observations are nothing
but trivialities in a misrepresented form. Eng therefore goes for the second
option.
Fusion is not caused by the speaker’s failure to realize or decide what he wants to
say. It is caused by the speaker’s decision to refrain from the extreme points on the
gradual dimension. (Eng 1998, 343)
Eng argues that the fact that the speaker “uses all degrees and combinations”
in his reaction to a discrepancy shows that we are dealing with a “fused”
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004.
84 Christian Dahlman
proposition (Eng 1998, 311). This is not very convincing. That the speaker
“uses all combinations” means that the speaker’s reaction could be (1) an
adjustment of his proposition, (2) an effort to adjust reality, or (3) an adjust-
ment of his proposition as well as an effort to adjust reality. This excludes the
possibility that the proposition in question is one with a single modality, but
it does not exclude the possibility that we are dealing with a separable com-
bination of modalities, or the possibility that the speaker is confused.
That the speaker “uses all degrees” in his reaction is a claim that goes
back to Eng’s idea that “fused” propositions can be placed on a graduated
dimension between the “purely descriptive” and the “purely normative”
(Eng 2000, 251). Eng seems to think that this “concept of degree” is charac-
teristic for “fused” propositions, and separates such propositions from other
propositions. But what does it mean that a statement, that contains a descrip-
tive element as well as a normative element, is descriptive “to a higher
degree”? What does it mean that a statement is “more descriptive than nor-
mative”? Unfortunately this is never explained in Eng’s theory. That a state-
ment is “70% descriptive” could not possibly mean that it does not make its
descriptive claim to 100%. Such a “concept of degree” would be unintelli-
gible. So what does it mean? The fact that Eng leaves us in the dark on this
crucial issue is reason enough to dismiss the theory of “fused modality,” until
he can come up with an explanation. But, for the sake of philosophical argu-
ment, I will make a comment on the idea that I guess Eng has in mind.
Eng uses reactions to discrepancy as a criterion for determining subjec-
tive meaning, and this indicates that the graduate dimension we are looking
for is the dimension of “importance.” If this interpretation is correct, the
meaning of a statement being “more descriptive than normative” is, that the
descriptive proposition is more important for the speaker. It means that
the speaker’s preference against a discrepancy between proposition and
reality is stronger when it comes to the descriptive proposition. This could
for example be the case when Jones’s attorney says “Jones has the right to
be compensated by Smith” to voice the belief that the purpose of the law is
violated if Jones loses the case, as well as the belief that Jones will win the
case. The descriptive element in this statement is more important to Jones’s
attorney than the normative. Jones’s attorney wants the court to accept his
recommendation concerning the purpose of the law, but it is more impor-
tant for him that the prediction about Jones winning the case will turn out
to be true. He would prefer the court to judge in Jones’s favour for some
other reason than promoting the law’s purpose, to the court judging in
favour of Smith although it agrees that this violates the purpose of the law.
If this is the “concept of degree” that Eng has in mind, it does not support
his theory. That a certain statement is “more descriptive than normative” in
this sense does not rule out the possibility that the statement contains a sep-
arable combination of propositions with different modalities, or the possi-
bility that it is a statement with confused modality.
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004.
Fused Modality or Confused Modality? 85
What Eng is saying here is that due to the conditions under which lawyers
make statements about the law (“the doctrine of the sources of law”, etc.),
there are bound to be propositions with a “fused modality,” and that it there-
fore should be accepted that lawyers make such propositions. This norma-
tive claim challenges a keystone in the theories of philosophers like John
Austin, Oliver Wendell Holmes and Herbert Hart: the idea that logical
clarity is always desirable. As we have seen, the propositions Eng calls
“fused” are no different from the propositions that Austin, Holmes and Hart
would refer to as confused. The normative conclusion in Eng’s theory is that
we should not always demand logical clarity from lawyers.
This normative conclusion, however, is unsupported by the findings in
Eng’s investigation. The observations concerning “fused modality”/”con-
fused modality” do not show that there are situations where the conditions
under which lawyers make propositions about the law make it practically
impossible to keep “is” and “ought” separate. At most, Eng’s observation
shows that such propositions are frequently “fused”/”confused,” and that
it is therefore unrealistic to expect that lawyers will ever stay out of
“fusion”/”confusion” without exception. But this is no reason to stop
demanding that lawyers should try to be clear about what they mean.
Demands for clarity are not always effective. Some people refuse to make
clear whether they claim that something “is” or “ought to be” the case, no
matter how many times we ask them. This is a fact of life, familiar to every-
one who has tried to have a rational conversation with a person who resorts
to authority rather than reason. This kind of behaviour is acceptable from a
police officer on patrol duty, who informs people about their rights and obli-
gations, but it should never be tolerated from a legal counsellor, judge or
© Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2004.
86 Christian Dahlman
Lund University
Faculty of Law
P.O. Box 207
SE-22100 LUND
Sweden
References
Austin, John. 1998. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. Aldershot: Ashgate.
Bindreiter, Uta U. 2001. Descriptive Normativity. Associations 5: 71–94.
Dalberg-Larsen, Jørgen. 1999. Book review of Svein Eng: U/enighetsanalyse.
Tidsskrift for Rettsvitenskap 3: 473–8.
Eng, Svein. 1998. U/enighetsanalyse—med saerlig sikte pa jus og allmenn rettsteori. Oslo:
Universitetsforlaget.
——— . 2000. Fusion of Descriptive and Normative Propositions. The Concepts of
“Descriptive Proposition” and “Normative Proposition” as Concepts of Degree.
Ratio Juris 13: 236–60.
Hart, Herbert L. A. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.
Holmes, Oliver Wendell. 1996. The Path of the Law. Bedford, MA: Applewood.
Hägerström, Axel. 1953. Inquiries into the Nature of Law and Morals. Uppsala:
Almqvist.
Peczenik, Aleksander. 1998. Book review of Eng, Svein: U/enighetsanalyse. Retfaerd
83: 84–8.