Hendrixfor Rational Magic WITHCOMMENTS
Hendrixfor Rational Magic WITHCOMMENTS
Hendrixfor Rational Magic WITHCOMMENTS
Europe
Scott E. Hendrix
Abstract
In the modern world “scientific” is typically equated with “rational,” a
viewpoint that has led modern intellectuals to portray the emergence of
modern science as a process involving the rejection of superstition. For this
reason many historians, philosophers of science, and scientists have depicted
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola and Galileo Galilei as heralds of scientific
rationalism for their “rejection” of superstition in the form of astrology. In
the traditional narrative, Pico’s Disputations Against Astrological Divination
is often described as a landmark on the movement toward modernity.
However, when read carefully it is clear that this work does not present the
wholesale rejection of astrology that many have assumed, and in fact the
evidence indicates that Pico never broadly opposed astrological theory or
practice. Looking forward to Galileo, one of the progenitors of the scientific
method, there is considerable evidence that he was a practitioner of judicial
astrology throughout his life, demonstrating that he never rejected either the
concept of celestial influence on earthly events or the practice of predicting
the future through the use of the discipline. Furthermore, the astrologer’s
model of a mechanistic cosmos functioning with absolute mathematical
regularity may have positively influenced Galileo’s own developing
mechanical philosophy. Therefore, the history of astrology should be
revaluated: well into the early modern period it was not a “superstitious”
belief system that retarded the development of a “modern” worldview, but in
fact may have positively contributed to our current model of scientific
rationalism.
Key Words: Giovanni Pico della Mirandola, Galileo Galilei, Marsilio Ficino,
Albumasar, Jean Gerson, astrology, scientific rationalism, science,
modernity, Disputations Against Astrological Divination.
*****
______________________________________________________________
contrast to that which is not modern? An overall discussion of the topic
would be far beyond the bounds of this paper, but there is a key element that
Sergio Sismundo have said, “The modern world, and perhaps what it means
of two premodern scholars, both Italians, who have been held up as icons of
rejected astrological divination, but instead they shared a belief that the
heavens affect terrestrial creatures and events, which was common to most
celestial influence and the predictive astrology that flowed from this belief
was wholly rational within the context of Renaissance and early modern
to consider two points: the meaning of the terms “rational” and “astrology.”
the nature of evidence and the ontological status of knowledge itself, and I do
not intend to attempt a solution here as that is too far beyond the scope of my
study, and in any case my colleague Brian Feltham has dealt with the larger
questions with far more perspicacity than I could manage in his chapter,
______________________________________________________________
can demonstrate how Renaissance and early modern astrology met the
criteria of rationality.
criteria for deciding what counts as a “good reason” for holding a belief,”
fruitfully by the work of Peter Winch, who argues that there is no single
upon whether or not he or she acts—or thinks—in a way that conforms to the
norms of the culture to which the person belongs.4 This position should not
which objective phenomena are interpreted and understood through the lens
of the basic beliefs of the individual. Such beliefs are constructed upon the
foundational knowledge and ideas the individual has acquired as part of his
or her historical and cultural heritage, and are seen to be held not as a set of
3
Steven Lukes, ‘Some Problems About Rationality,’ Archives of European
Sociology, vol. VIII, 1967, pp. 247-264, 263.
4
Peter Winch, ‘Understanding a Primitive Society,’ American Philosophical
Quarterly, vol. I, 1964, pp. 307-324.
Scott E. Hendrix 5
______________________________________________________________
ideas accepted by choice, but rather as a conceptual framework “forced upon
rationality in any given time and place, we must consider the background and
form of rationality, since there is no single absolute model upon which one
may rely.
thought and language, which is the correlate of a tacit adherence to the stakes
and the rules of the game.”6 By the time of the high Middle Ages the rules of
this game were set through the exercise of institutional capital orchestrated
within the locus of the various universities that had been established across
______________________________________________________________
the natural world through the application of rules established by Greek and
be the very form of what it was to be a rational individual.8 The result was a
through their common education. The component parts of this education that
are most relevant to our current study included the reading of a shared
shared forms of analysis driven by basic assumptions about the world derived
class in Europe.
world; the questions an intellectual asks and the basic contexts within which
data are to be interpreted or ideas are evaluated ordinarily derive from the
ideas, as individuals analyze the world around them through the lens of their
8
Cf. Bourdieu’s analysis of the functioning of investigators within the
modern scientific fields. Bourdieu, p. 8.
9
Helen Longino, Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton, Princeton
University Press, 1990, p. 12.
Scott E. Hendrix 7
______________________________________________________________
education, experiences, religion, and other important aspects of their
over many centuries that had survived repeated challenge and testing.
This brings us, then, to astrology itself. For the purpose of this
study, this term refers to the study of the influences transmitted by the
Babylonians, who by 410 BCE at the latest were casting horoscopes intended
the Babylonian astrological system, but we do know that by the end of the
______________________________________________________________
predictions about future events based on analyses of the future positions of
modelling and theoretical analysis that scholars such as G.E.R. Lloyd have
argued fits the definition of “science” for the complexity and coherence of its
ordering.13
appropriated and adapted these ideas for their own ends. The concept that the
that such forces were responsible for birth and death here on the Earth.14 By
the time the great second-century Hellenistic cosmologist Ptolemy wrote the
12
Otto Neugebauer, The Exact Sciences in Antiquity, Dover Publications,
1969, 2nd edition, pp., 29-30.
13
Geoffrey E.R. Lloyd, ‘On the ‘Origins’ of Science,’ Proceedings of the
British Academy, 105, 2000, pp. 1-16. However, while Lloyd’s point about
the conceptual and theoretical sophistication of this early form of astrology is
well taken, I should note that the application of such terminology seems to
me to be dangerously anachronistic. I develop this argument at some length
in my article, “Natural Philosophy or Science in Premodern Epistemic
Regimes? The Case of the Astrology of Albert the Great and Galileo Galilei.”
14
S. J. Tester, A History of Western Astrology, Woodbridge, Boydell Press,
1987, p. 177.
Scott E. Hendrix 9
______________________________________________________________
work that would come to be known as the Almagest at Alexandria, interest in
maintained that the celestial bodies are “letters inscribed (and yet moving) in
the heavens,” pouring forth heat on the sub-lunar world and thereby affecting
knowledgeable in astrology could learn much of use for directing one’s life.
the subject, a point that we should keep in mind given the important place
that this work would hold in the study and practice of astrology in the
following centuries.
However, Greek and Hellenistic writers did not simply take the
rationality of astrology for granted. This evaluation was built upon the
premise of the centrality of the earth in the cosmos coupled with the basic
assumption that all heavenly bodies emit a powerful, affecting force in accord
about the role of light as the universal element linking the entire universe
______________________________________________________________
motion was held to influence terrestrial events through the transmission of
rays of light imparted with heavenly power. Aristotle presented this model of
corruptione (On Generation and Corruption); the result was the foundation
for what would become the normative cosmological model in Greek and
Within this cosmological model in which all things are interconnected, the
individual celestial objects, affected the four humors of the human body by
imparting these light rays. This explains why Greek natural philosophy held
16
S. J. Tester, A History of Western Astrology, Woodbridge, Suffolk, Boydell
Press, 1987, chpt. 4.
17
A.J. Festugière, La revelation d'Hermès Trismégiste, avec un appendice
sur l'hermétisme arabe par L. Massignon, Paris, Lecoffre, 1944, vol. 1, p. 89;
North, pp. 45-51.
18
Ptolemy, Tetrabiblos, Loeb Classical Library Edition, F.E. Robbins, ed.
and trans., Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1940, p. 7.
Scott E. Hendrix 11
______________________________________________________________
celestial influence to be one of the most important determining factors for
attractive. As scholars such as Cecil J. Schneer have noted, the major trend in
Greek and Hellenistic thought was to explain the world and events within it
explanations that are both logical and replicable by others trained in Greek
Indeed, the Ptolemaic model was one in which the entire universe functioned
19
Cecil J. Schneer, The Search for Order: The Development of the Major
Ideas in the Physical Sciences from the Earliest Times to the Present, New
York, HarperCollins, 1960, pp. 17-51.
12 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
It was the very rationality of this system coupled with its intrinsic
began in the seventh century of the Common Era. Islam spread first through
the Arabian Peninsula and in the centuries thereafter its followers would
come to dominate the Near East - including much territory that had been
under the control of the Byzantine Empire for centuries - , Northern Africa,
and almost the entirety of the Iberian Peninsula. In this wide-ranging region,
the most important being the Nestorian Christians in Syria who were
persecuted religious minority they had no love for the Byzantines and did not
hesitate to work with their new Muslim masters. However, it was not Greek
poetry or drama that attracted the scholars of the Islamic crescent, but the
fields of knowledge that offered the concretely useful tools that could be
applied to make their lives immediately better through the benefits derived. It
is for this reason that Greek medical knowledge became so highly prized in
treatises until the ninth century, which both limited the practice of astrology
first translation of an astronomical text did not occur until 803, when either
unknown scholar translated Ptolemy’s Almagest to fill the gaps left by the
Sindhind. The Almagest, along with Euclid’s Elements, provided the basis for
astrology.21
instead many developed and added to Greek ideas in creative ways. The most
20
David Pingree, “Astrology,” in Religion, Learning, and Science in the
‘Abbasid Period, ed. M. J. L.Young, J. D. Latham, and R. B. Serjeant,
Cambridge, Eng., Cambridge University Press, 1990, pp. 290- 99.
21
George Saliba, A History of Arabic Astronomy: Planetary Theories during
the Golden Age of Islam, New York: New York University Press, 1994, pp.
67-68.
14 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
important scholar to do so was the ninth-century Persian, Abū Ma'shar al-
was the first to grapple with integrating concepts of celestial influence and
judicial astrology - that is using the art to answer questions about the world,
that at this period still highly valued human free will, as I have analyzed
religiously-motivated attacks. And with good reason, for within the context
of his education and philosophical belief system, to have done so would have
integral to the universe that he observed, as seen through the lens of the best
that Albumasar inherited from the Greek world led him to argue that
provided the basis for the other sciences, while such fields as medicine
22
The most thorough study of Abu Ma’Shar is Richard Lemay’s Abu
Ma'shar and Latin Aristotelianism in the Twelfth Century, Beirut, American
University of Beirut, 1962.
23
Scott E. Hendrix, ‘Reading the Future and Freeing the Will: Astrology of
the Arabic World and Albertus Magnus,’ Hortulus, vol. 2.1, 2006, pp. 30-49.
Scott E. Hendrix 15
______________________________________________________________
merely expanded its principles in a narrowly utilitarian fashion.24 In order to
that all thought was derived from a single antediluvian revelation; thus, by
single “Truth.”26 Although not scientific, and indeed he was working almost a
millennia before the development of the scientific method, his model was
concept of the “rational soul,” or man’s free will coupled with the cognitive
abilities that differentiated him from animals, which was free from the
influence of the stars and distinct from what he saw as the passive potency of
the “intellectual soul” in Platonic traditions.27 This soul, along with all else
descending from the heavens through three spheres: the divine (the sphere of
light), the ethereal (the eight celestial spheres), and the hylic (the sublunar
______________________________________________________________
As with other monotheistic interpreters of Aristotle, Albumasar
associated God with the Aristotelian Prime Mover, who was the efficient
Thus God creates man, provides him with a soul, and influences that “rational
soul” toward actions; but since man has free will, this is an influence,
powerful though it may be, that one can overcome through exercise of the
will. Likewise, as the soul descends from the divine sphere through the eight
each of which affects the initial divine force. These distortions are, in effect,
divine power from the first heaven down to the terrestrial realm, driving us to
act in ways contrary to God’s will. However, since the soul descends from
24
Lemay, Abu Ma’ shar, p. 242.
25
David Pingree, The Thousands of Abu Ma’ shar, Leiden: Brill, 1968, pp.
14-18.
26
Ibid., pp. 18, 33.
27
Lemay, Abu Ma’ shar, p. 84.
28
Vicky Armstrong Clark, ‘The Illustrated Abridged Astrological Treatises of
Albumasar: Medieval Astrological Imagery in the West,’ Unpublished Ph.D.
diss., University of Michigan, 1979, p. 22.
29
Lemay, pp. 84-85.
Scott E. Hendrix 17
______________________________________________________________
the divine to the hylic realm, it desires to return, signifying a desire within the
human soul to understand the divinity of God and act in accordance with his
will. But in order to achieve connection with God in the mystical sense, and
to comprehend his divine plan for the universe so that an individual may
order his or her life by it, it is necessary to understand God’s divine plan as
during the soul’s long downward journey so that one can overcome these
compel, human action. Therefore, “the wise man,” meaning one who
stars,” an idea that both preserved the predictive power of astrology to a large
influence his work enjoyed in the Latin Christian West, as we shall see in a
conjunctively with beliefs logically developed or derived from them can lead
30
Hendrix, ‘Reading the Future and Freeing the Will,’ pp. 32-33.
18 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
presumption that Aristotelian physics is the best possible model for
as the Prime Mover transmits his impelling force through he cosmos via the
sense. Working from those base set of assumptions, belief in the predictive
For the individual who accepts the premise that celestial patterns determine
of the influence that the heavens transmit as they move in their perfectly-
of his initial premises. One could legitimately question the entire intellectual
beliefs that are logically consistent and coherent within a closed system
highly contested within the Muslim world due to concerns about potential
conflicts with Islamic tenets. These concerns would lead to a splitting of the
discipline of the study of the heavens that had been joined since antiquity into
involved with these translation activities were vast, as there were neither
either learning Arabic to accomplish their goals or, as was more common,
riches of the Arabic-language world available to the West.33 The texts chosen
31
Richard Swinburne addresses both ‘basic beliefs’ and the ‘conjunctive
nature of ideas’ in his Faith and Reason, pp. 3-24.
32
Hendrix, ‘Reading the Future and Freeing the Will,’ p. 34.
33
Anwar Chejne, ‘The Role of al-Andalus in the Movement of Ideas Between
Islam and the West,’ Islam and the Medieval West, Khalis I. Semaan, ed.,
Albany, State University of New York Press, 1980, pp. 110-133.
20 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
for translation were wide ranging, but among the earliest such works were
that Richard Lemay has argued that these provided the primary vehicle for
aroused great interest among Western intellectuals and were both some of the
astrological practice, exist, but this text also went through six printed editions
as the academic study of astrology began to take off in the West, those who
undertook such study approached the subject through the lens of Arabic
language texts (in translation) that had already grappled with the question of
reconciled with free will. This concern was central to the anger that
34
Lemay, pp. xxx-xxxi.
35
Paul Kunitzsch, ‘Abu Ma’shar, Johannes Hispalensis und Alkameluz,’
Zeitschrift der Deutschen Morgenländischen Gesellschaft, no. 120, 1970, pp.
103-125.
Scott E. Hendrix 21
______________________________________________________________
feverish peak in the thirteenth century. The best examples of this opposition
are to be found in the attacks on the discipline that came to pass in Paris, with
(4) that all that happens here below is subject to the necessity of the
heavenly bodies.
(9) that free will is a passive power, not an active one, and that it is
necessarily moved by the object of desire.37
There is little evidence that ideas with such fatalistic implications ever
circulated, let alone that they were widespread. In fact, the only thirteenth-
belief system that Bishop Tempier attacked was the Tuscan astrologer and
36
John F. Wippel, ‘The Condemnations of 1270 and 1277 at Paris,’ The
Journal of Medieval and Renaissance Studies. vol. 7, no. 2, 1977, pp.169-
201, p. 179.
37
Ibid., p. 179; Henri Denifle and Emile Chatelain, O.P., eds., Chartularium
Universitatis Parisiensis, Paris, Delalain, 1889, vol. I, p. 487.
38
George Sarton, Introduction to the History of Science, Baltimore, Williams
and Wilkins, 1931; reprinted 1961,vol. II, p. 989.
22 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
In fact astrology as it was studied and practiced in medieval Europe
was seen as a discipline that did not conflict with free will, as European
scholars inherited not just the discipline that had been developed by Greek
and Hellenistic writers, but also the defense of astrology that had been
Albert the Great (d. 1280),39 directly appealed to his ninth-century Persian
focusing on the ontological status of the human soul relative to that of the
on his mistaken belief that the Liber de causis (Book about the Causes) was a
system of thought, the stars as corporeal bodies were held to influence the
body directly, but the soul per accidens, indirectly.42 Therefore, the will,
impulses imparted by the stars. To explain this idea Albert appeals directly to
Scott E. Hendrix 23
______________________________________________________________
Albumasar’s Introductorium maius (Greater Introduction), though
erroneously citing Ptolemy as his source, reiterating the maxim, “the wise
man will dominate the stars.”43 Albert elaborates upon this statement to
explain that one learned in the influences of the heavens can avert many
negative things while maximizing positive effects - if one only makes the
willed effort to do so.44 Unfortunately, most people rarely exercise their will
influence. In this way Albert outlines a model of celestial force that allows
It would have been odd for Albert not to defend belief in celestial
such as Albumasar, whom Albert quoted and cited extensively, as well as the
______________________________________________________________
analyzed his world. Thus, his position on astrology was a logical entailment
of his base assumptions and his defense of the discipline was highly rational
his writings on astrology and his defense of the subject helped to embed it
39
For this story, see Scott E. Hendrix, How Albert the Great’s Speculum
astronomiae was Interpreted and Used by Four Centuries of Readers: A
Study in Late Medieval Medicine, Astronomy and Astrology, Lewiston, The
Edwin Mellen Press, 2010.
40
Albert the Great, De causis et processu universitatis a prima causa II:
Opera omnia, Winfrid Fauser, s.j., ed., Monasterii Westfalorum,
Aschendorff, 1993, vol. XVII, p. 57; Albert the Great, De caelo et mundo,.
vol. V, p. 114; Albert the Great, Liber de natura et origine animae: Opera
omnia, Bernhard Geyer, ed., Monasterii Westfalorum, Aschendorff, 1971, ed.
XII, p. 12.
41
Alain De Libera, Albert le Grand et la Philosophie, Paris: J. Vrin, 1990,
pp. 55-59. This mistake was universal prior to Thomas of Moerbeke’s
completion of a new translation directly from the Greek in 1268. See
Ferdinand Van Steenberghen, The Philosophical Movement in the Thirteenth
Century, Edinburgh, Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1955, p. 40.
42
Albert the Great, Speculum astronomiae, The Speculum Astronomiae and
its Enigma: Astrology, Theology, and Science in Albertus Magnus and his
Contemporaries, Paola Zambelli, ed. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic
Publishers, 1992 pp. 220; 250-256, chpts. 3; 12.
43
Paola Zambelli, ‘Albert le Grand et l’astrologie,’ Recherches de théologie
ancienne et medieval 49 (1982) 141-58, pp. 146-147.
44
Albert, Speculum, pp. 258-261, ch. 13.
Scott E. Hendrix 25
______________________________________________________________
thirteenth-century Europe, he would utterly fail to win conservative
theologians over. The most important opponent of the study of astrology was
after the pope issued his request.47 While not primarily directed at astrology,
personalities and gifts, that anyone’s health or sickness is dependent upon the
locations of heavenly bodies, or even that the stars might indirectly affect an
45
Albert’s reputation led Ulrich of Strasbourg to refer to him as ‘a man so
superior in every science, that he can fittingly be called the wonder and
miracle of our time.’ Daguillon, Ulrich de Strasbourg, La “Summa de
bono.”Livre I , Paris, J. Vrin, 1930, p. 139. Even Roger Bacon, by no means
friendly toward Albert, stated that Albert was known as an authority in Paris
on a par with Aristotle, Avicenna, and Averroes. Jeremiah Hackett, “The
Attitude of Roger Bacon to the Scientia of Albertus Magnus,” Albertus
Magnus and the Sciences, James A. Weisheipl, ed., Toronto, Pontifical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1980, pp. 53-72.
26 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
astrological beliefs.48 However, he was fighting an uphill struggle from the
simple fact made it a certainty that interest in the study of the heavens and
and beyond: All medieval intellectuals who wrote in the wake of the twelfth-
motions of heavenly bodies. Beginning from the base belief that influence
pouring forth from stars, planets, and other heavenly bodies has an impact on
ways was a concept accepted not only by those who embraced astrology,
such as Pietro d’Abano (c.1250-1318), but even by those who opposed its
Despite the failure of those who opposed the study and practice of
used by those who studied the heavens.50 However, during the high and late
accuracy.51 This text, which was actually drawn from a number of Arabic and
While the source of the data was spurious, the incipient empirical impulse
true place within the rational worldview of Renaissance and Early Modern
______________________________________________________________
Albert the Great are directly relevant to developments in this later period.
With the passing of the middle ages, one of the most important figures in the
nor consistent with the contexts within which Pico worked. As a true
on foundational works, but also of translations as well. It was for this reason
that the Italian scholar studied Arabic and sought out the works of the most
46
Ferdinand Van Steenberghen, The Philosophical Movement in the
Thirteenth Century, Edinburgh, Thomas Nelson and Sons, 1955, p. 96.
47
For Pope John XXI’s request, see Denifle and Chatelain, vol. I, p. 541. On
Tempier’s commission and the resultant condemnations, see Etienne Gilson,
History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages, New York, Random
House, 1955, pp. 405-406; Leff, pp. 231-238. The poorly worked out nature
of the condemnations did not escape the notice of contemporaries. For
example, Godefroid de Fontaines complained that some articles contradicted
one another, some were dubious, and others were simply “impossible and
irrational.” Even a member of Tempier's commission, Henry of Ghent
(c.1217-1293), expressed “great embarrassment” over some of the
condemnations. See Roland Hissette, Enquête sur les 219 articles condamnés
à Paris le 7 mars 1277, Louvain, Publications Universitaires, 1977, p. 9.
48
Denifle-Chatelain, vol. I, pp. 551-555.
49
Hendrix, How Albert the Great’s Speculum astronomiae was Interpreted
and Used by Four Centuries of Readers, chpt. IV.
Scott E. Hendrix 29
______________________________________________________________
language in order to gain a direct understanding of their content.53
human free will encapsulated in that dictum, “the wise man dominates the
stars,” would have been quite familiar to Pico and its importance would have
been reinforced through his reading of Albert the Great’s works.54 Both the
Pico would have found the efforts of Albumasar and Albert to make
astrological belief congruent with the concept of free will very useful. His
own veneration for human freedom has been enshrined in his justly-famed
Oration on the Dignity of Man, which proclaims that “to man it is allowed to
that Pico wrote this Oration to serve as the preface to his 900 Theses. This
work came under papal ban in 1486 in part because of the reverence for
astrological influence that Pico exhibits throughout the work, driving the
specific types of intellect develop their appropriate human skills through the
human freedom - which may well have been intended to counteract expected
30 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
criticism to the theses - the papacy viewed this as an argument in favor of
agreement of his ideas with both “true astrology” and “true theology”58 did
believed that celestial influence had greater force in human life than many of
his contemporaries, but it had been centuries since anyone had voiced an
outright rejection of the power of the stars. Even such critics of astrology as
voiced concerns about potential abuses of the discipline while arguing that
than rejecting the idea that the heavens influence terrestrial events - a key
50
Julius W. Friend, What Science Really Means, London, Dyson Press, 2007,
pp. 26-29.
51
Richard Kieckhefer, Magic in the Middle Ages, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 2000, 5th printing, pp. 129-130; Anthony Grafton,
Cardano’s Cosmos: The Worlds and Works of a Renaissance Astrologer,
Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press, 1999, pp. 199-202.
52
Charles Burnett and David Pingree, The Liber Aristotilis of Hugo of
Santalla, London, Warburg Institute, 1997, introduction.
Scott E. Hendrix 31
______________________________________________________________
understanding celestial influence upon humans that he was forced to defend
his views before Pope Innocent VIII (1484-1492) in 1489, a task that he
handled with greater effectiveness than Pico when called before the same
pope.60 Ficino did not arouse papal suspicion because his belief in the force
heavenly bodies imparted to terrestrial objects was in any way unusual, but
God.61 While such a statement might sound odd, all he really meant was that
celestial forces influence people to act in ways that are not always consistent
with what God would want by imparting impulses such as lust or gluttony.
But if we understand the source of these impulses then we can more easily
resist them and act in accord with our intellectual, rather than our physical
desires.62 In the end Pope Innocent VIII agreed that this was a conventional
argument that was entirely in keeping with the theological opinions of the
sainted Thomas Aquinas and his professor and mentor, Albert the Great.63
very solid ground. By the time of his writing, more than two centuries of
tradition supported the notion that the heavens affect humankind’s corporeal
essence, influencing the soul secondarily through the body’s “pulling and
tugging” upon the soul.64 By the fifteenth century the idea that everything on
______________________________________________________________
established that no natural philosopher would have argued against the point
to ply their trade without a thorough command of the discipline and almost
every court across Europe had at least one astrologer in residence.65 Clearly,
while in his 900 Theses Ficino’s colleague Pico might have gone too far in
his stress upon the role of celestial influence in human life, his belief in the
power of the stars to affect humankind was entirely within the mainstream of
Given the intellectual climate within which Pico worked, and the
strong support for astrology evidenced in Pico’s 900 Theses, one would think
that there would be little need to argue in favor of the importance of the
addressing Pico's thought has confused the issue, mostly due to a work Pico
wrote in the last years of his life that has been seen to greatly complicate his
view of astrology. This work was published posthumously under the title
53
Paul Oskar Kristeller, Renaissance Thought and its Sources, New York,
Columbia University Press, 1981, p. 206.
54
Paola Zambelli, ‘Albert le Grand et l’astrologie,’ Recherches de Théologie
Ancienne et Médiévale, vol. 49, 1982, pp. 146-147.
55
Pearl Kibre, The Library of Pico della Mirandola, New York: Columbia
University Press, 1936, pp. 62, 70, 86.
Scott E. Hendrix 33
______________________________________________________________
Disputationes adversus astrologiam divinatricem (Disputations Against
The assessment of a great many scholars - including the modern editor of the
volume, Eugenio Garin - have certainly seen it that way, repeatedly stressing
close reading of the text itself, a fact that recent scholarship is beginning to
acknowledge.68
Pico died the work was unfinished and unpublished. Therefore, the version
together with Pico’s personal physician and it is altogether likely that the
finished product has been heavily influenced by their work.69 While this
______________________________________________________________
ridiculed by saints, forbidden by popes and sacrosanct synods.”70 However,
In a word, no. Rather, Pico accepted that the heavens transmitted influence to
except with light having carried it,”71 a point that he notes is supported by the
while warning that this part of the discipline could lead the unwary into
vehicle - light - that is easily blocked.74 However, one will look in vain for a
seems to be concerned that astrologers will lead people into a focus upon
worldly forces, and away from an attentive regard for God.76 This is much the
same concern that had led Jean Gerson earlier to reject astrology; the fear that
it might lead those who practiced and put faith in it into idolatry.
Scott E. Hendrix 35
______________________________________________________________
A complete analysis of Pico’s attitude toward astrology would be
too far beyond the scope of this study, but it should be noted that a rejection
of the discipline in its entirety would have been quite a departure from
Europe. Universities across the continent routinely taught the subject - which
was only minimally distinct from astronomy - as part of the liberal arts
more than ever in the fifteenth century.77 Far from retreating from the
59
Jean Gerson, Tricelogium astrologiae theologizatae, in Oeuvres Complètes,
edited by Mgr. P. Glorieux, Paris: Desclée, 1962,caput X, pp. 111-112. Note
Gerson’s opening statement on celestial influence: ‘Admisso quod caelum in
talibus initiis fortius agit aut influit.’
60
Paul Oskar Kristeller, Eight Philosophers of the Italian Renaissance,
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1964, pp. 37-53. For a consideration of
Pico and Ficino’s sometimes strained relationship, see H. Darrell Rutkin,
‘Astrology, Natural Philosophy and the History of Science, c. 1250-1700:
Studies Toward an Interpretation of Giovanni Pico della Mirandola’s
Disputationes adversus astrologiam divinatricem,’ Indiana University,
Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, 2002, pp. 261-263.
61
Frances Yates, Giordano Bruno and the Hermetic Tradition, Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 1991, p. 56.
62
Marsilio Ficino, Three Books of Life, Carol V. Kaske and John R. Clark,
eds., Binghamton, The Renaissance Society of America, 1989, caput,
3.12.122.
63
Thomas Aquinas had been canonized in 1323. Although Albert was
beatified in 1622, the process of his canonization would not be complete until
1931.
36 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
Renaissance, with both Lucio Bellanti (d.1499) and Giovanni Pontano (d.
times, while in the following century Johannes Kepler (d. 1630) not only
firmly rejected any attack on astrology’s efficacy, but also provided empirical
modern authors such as Eugenio Garin may find Pico’s belief in the influence
of the heavens upon terrestrial affairs to be odd, it would have been odder
still if he had actually diverged from the common intellectual habitus of his
day in order to reject a belief in celestial influence and the art - astrology -
analyses. But Pico stayed perfectly in step with educated opinion of his day,
64
Perhaps the strongest proponent of this notion was Albert the Great, who
expressed this viewpoint in almost everything he wrote. See chapter 2 of
Hendrix, Albert the Great’s Speculum Astronomiae.
65
On alchemy, see Bruce T. Moran, Distilling Knowledge: Alchemy,
Astrology, and the Scientific Revolution, Cambridge, Harvard University
Press, 2006, chapter 1. For medicine, see Hilary Carey, Astrology at the
English Court and University in the Later Middle Ages, London, Macmillan
Academic and Professional, 1992, pp. 49-51.
Scott E. Hendrix 37
______________________________________________________________
Renaissance habitus. Therefore, in the context of late Renaissance thought,
The context of what Pico was and was not arguing against in his
editor, Eugenio Garin, has attempted to establish a direct link between the
text’s arguments and the work of a later Italian intellectual - Galileo Galilei.
been an article of faith among not only scientists but also historians that
This attitude toward Galileo has also been common among philosophers of
science such as Karl Popper as well as scientists such as Carl Sagan. 81 For
these intellectuals, the story arc runs from Pico’s rationalist “rejection” of
However, such positions are only possible if one ignores the context within
celestial divination, Galileo was even less inclined to oppose the discipline.
66
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola. Disputationes Adversus Astrologiam
Divinatricem, Eugenio Garin. ed., Florence, Vallecchi Editore, 1946.
67
Louis Dupré, Passage to Modernity: An Essay in the Hermeneutics of
Nature and Culture, New Haven, Yale University Press, 1995, pp. 56-57.
68
Both H. Darrel Rutkin and Steven Vanden Broecke develop this idea in
their work.
38 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
The nineteenth-century editor of Galileo’s collected works, Antonio
conclusions were tentative and he suggested that perhaps Galileo had lost
interest in astrology as he aged, the evidence presented leaves the reader with
no doubt that Galileo frequently cast horoscopes. We see this not only
through such things as the natal chart Galileo cast for the Grand Duke
which Galileo engaged with important but distant figures such as the
would wish it to be.87 If we take the time to examine the horoscopes that
Galileo cast there can be no doubt that he was completely earnest in his belief
support of a patron - such as the aforementioned one for Cosimo II - but also
those that Galileo did for himself, his daughters, and twenty as yet to be
identified people.88 Rutkin has devoted some time to analyzing the natal
______________________________________________________________
her time of birth - for Galileo’s daughters as well as for his friend Giovanni
Francesco Sagredo, noting the care with which these charts are constructed.
These charts are now available on the website Skyscript and using Galileo’s
point that goes unmentioned in Rutkin’s work that reinforces his argument -
76
For a much more comprehensive consideration of Pico’s attitude toward
astrology see Rutkin, pp. 230-305.
77
Beginning in 1405 medical students at the University of Bologna (where a
chair of astrology still existed as late as 1799) were required to study
astrology for four years. Tester, p. 184; Hilary Carey, Astrology at the
English Court and University in the Later Middle Ages, London, Macmillan
Academic and Professional, 1992, p. 51.
80
Eugenio Garin, Astrology in the Renaissance: The Zodiac of Life, Carolyn
Jackson and June Allen, trans., Routledge, 1983, p. 10.
81
Karl Popper, Objective Knowledge: an Evolutionary Approach, Oxford,
Oxford University Press, 1975, p. 176; ‘The Harmony of the Worlds,’
Cosmos, Carl Sagan, PBS, 1980.
82
Antonio Favaro, ‘Galileo Astrologo,’ Julianne Evans, trans., Galileo’s
Astrology, special issue of Culture and Cosmos, vol. 7, no. 1, 2003, pp. 9-19.
83
Ibid., pp. 11-13.
84
Richard Tarnass, The Passion of the Western Mind, New York, Random
House, 1993, p.295.
85
Wade Rowland, Galileo's Mistake: A New Look at the Epic Confrontation
Between Galileo and the Church, New York, Arcade Publishing, 2003, p.
295.
86
Peter K. Machamer, The Cambridge Companion to Galileo, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1995, passim.
Scott E. Hendrix 41
______________________________________________________________
the corrective notes that one finds throughout the chart. In the upper left-hand
on each of the planets plus the sun and the moon as well as the “head of the
Dragon,” meaning the north node of the moon. There are then four rows
below the symbol for each astronomical point detailing its motion on the day
in question using noon as a reference point. The important thing is that there
are mathematical corrections visible under the headings for both Saturn and
Mars, as well as on the body of the horoscope itself.89 If Galileo had cast
horoscopes merely for the purpose of patronage or to earn money, why would
he have been so concerned with accuracy when creating charts for family,
friends, and for himself? The purpose of such charts could not possibly have
87
H. Darrel Rutkin, ‘Galileo Astrologer:’ Astrology and Mathematical
Practice in the Late Sixteenth and Early Seventeenth Centuries,’ Galilaena,
vol. II, 2005, p. 143.
78
Wayne Shumaker, The Occult Sciences in the Renaissance: A Study in
Intellectual Patterns, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1972, pp. 28-
31.
79
Shumaker, p. 31; Sheila K. Rabin, ‘Kepler’s Attitude Toward Pico and the
Anti-Astrology Polemic,’Renaissance Quarterly, vol. 50, no. 3, 1997: 750-
770.
88
Ibid., p. 117.
89
http://www.skyscript.co.uk/galchart.html, accessed 4 Jan. 2010.
42 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
Clearly, the existence of this sizeable number of carefully
scientist was not at all unfamiliar with the workings of judicial astrology, and
that when he did construct a chart he demonstrated both a great deal of care
as well as ability. It is true that these horoscopes all seem to date to the late
1580s and 1590s while he was at Padua, but there is nothing to suggest that
he changed his mind about the discipline after his appointment to the position
likely that other concerns simply kept him too busy for such pursuits,
point, the astrologer’s worldview was one in which the cosmos existed as an
interlinked whole, as distant celestial bodies interacted with one another and
90
Mario Biagioli, Galileo, Courtier: The Practice of Science in the Culture of
Absolutism, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1994, chapter 1.
Scott E. Hendrix 43
______________________________________________________________
philosophers placed the beginning of the system of influences with God, but
91
John North, The Norton History of Astronomy and Cosmology, New York,
W.W. Norton, 1995, p. 265.
Bibliography
Primary Sources
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola. Disputationes Adversus Astrologiam
Divinatricem. Eugenio Garin (ed.) Florence, Vallecchi Editore, 1946.
Marsilio Ficino. Three Books of Life, Carol V. Kaske and John R. Clark
(eds.), Binghamton, The Renaissance Society of America, 1989.
Secondary Sources
Biagioli, M. Galileo, Courtier: The Practice of Science in the Culture of
Absolutism, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1994.
Broecke, S.V. The Limits of Influence: Pico, Louvain, and the Crisis of
Renaissance Astrology. Leiden, Brill, 2006.
Carey, H. Astrology at the English Court and University in the Later Middle
Ages, London, Macmillan Academic and Professional, 1992.
______________________________________________________________
upon the influence of the mechanical aspects of this model upon Galileo’s
astrologers and defenders of astrology would have made Galileo quite aware
data to support his claims. If nothing else, interest in astrology and the desire
Hendrix, S.E. Albert the Great’s Speculum Astronomiae and Four Centuries
of Readers. Lewiston, The Edwin Mellen Press, 2010.
–––, ‘Reading the Future and Freeing the Will: Astrology of the Arabic
World and Albertus Magnus.’ Hortulus, vol. 2.1, 2006, 30-49.
Kristeller, P.O. Renaissance Thought and its Sources. New York, Columbia
University Press, 1981.
Galileo to think deeply about the motions of the heavens. Regardless of the
positive influences that his role as an astrologer may or may not have had,
______________________________________________________________
there can be no doubt that it is anachronistic to look for a rejection of
astrology during this period as a sign of scientific rationalism. After all, for
Galileo just as for Pico, Albert, and all who had developed their approach to
rational.
Schneer, C.J. The Search for Order: The Development of the Major Ideas in
the Physical Sciences from the Earliest Times to the Present. New York,
HarperCollins, 1960.
Tarnass, R. The Passion of the Western Mind. New York, Random House,
1993.
Notes
Hendrix focuses; second, this will lead to some reflections on the viability
and combinability of particular modes of thought; however, I shall end on a
more mystical/spiritual note.?
______________________________________________________________
inspired concept of a habitus should still be treated with great caution. I shall
mention two worries.
thought, and see who was working in which traditions of thought. But these
reflections give us a way (one way) of sharpening a central question: Are the
features of a scientific mode of thought radically different to those which
sustained astrology? This opens up a range of interesting possibilities; some
historical, some analytical. Historically, for example, we might say that
scientific rationalism grew out of the pre-modern rationality which had
sustained astrology. But this is consistent with the following three analytical
hypotheses: 1) that scientific rationalism is discontinuous with “astrological
rationalism”; 2) that scientific rationalism is in some way incompatible with
“astrological rationalism” (perhaps in the sense that anyone employing both
concurrently is irrational); 3) that one of these modes of thought is seriously
flawed, and can be shown to be so either internally (employing its own
content) or externally (employing the content of the other one, or some
further mode(-s) of thought).
______________________________________________________________
that pre-modern resources themselves could raise doubt here; but certainly
scientific rationalism can do so. We might (and many would) say that this
particular habitus is irrational. The people doing the reasoning might be
relatively rational, given the limitations of their circumstances, but their basic
mode of thought might be said to be rationally flawed. This would be most
plausible if we could isolate an internal inconsistency; but even without such
a coup de grace, it is still a charge worth addressing.
disprove. However, for the basic point I want to make, we needn’t claim so
much. We could simply focus on the spiritual gains of thinking of oneself as
inclined but not compelled, etc. So, the last idea I want to raise is that there
may well be a non- (not un-) scientific astrology that is, so far as science
goes, as rationally unimpeachable in a contemporary scientifically educated
person as it would have been in Pico, or Albert, or Albumasar.
______________________________________________________________
Let us begin with the first issue. It is indeed to the point that Hendrix
addresses the question of how it is possible that the hyper-rational Greeks
retained thoughts of astrology in their inquiries. That this should be an issue
of concern is made clear by the fact that almost all the major intellectual
figures of Greek thought were of this proclivity; Plato, Ptolemy, Aristotle
and, when we look further, we also see the Stoics, Pythagoras and Pilo of
Alexandria amongst others portraying this characteristic. The question in this
connection, however, is this: what was so appealing in astrology that made
these intellectual heavyweights not abandon this whole system altogether?
accounts for this kind of view? This elaboration seems important even though
I agree with Hendrix’s explanation of the reason for this situation. Scott’s
explanation is that “it was precisely because of their rationality that
intellectuals from Plato to Ptolemy found astrology to be so attractive.” He
noted further with scholars like Cecil J. Schneer that “the major trend in
Greek and Hellenistic thought was to explain the world and events within it
through the interaction of physical rather than supernatural forces.”
______________________________________________________________
astrology from a religious point of view failed because it was not based on
any claims to truth about astrology as pseudo science but on the tendency to
preclude by all means a different framework of knowledge that threatened the
monopoly of truth by religion.
The second point that this brief comment set out to elaborate has to
do with the issue of Pico, Albert the Great and Galileo’s appropriation of the
astrologer’s model. First, it is important to point out how this was done. In
Hendrix’s consideration, the common-place consideration that Pico’s
approach to astrology was antagonistic is either not well-founded or
consistent with the context within which he worked. The truth of this claim
was demonstrated very adequately by Hendrix through his consideration of
background of Pico’s celebrated work titled Oration on the Dignity of Man
where Pico underscored the centrality of freedom to human nature. By
considering how Pico had to navigate around the powerful censorship of the
papacy during the reign of Innocent VIII before whom he had to defend
himself, Hendrix provided a prelude to the explication of why Pico cannot be
said to be antagonistic to astrology. As Hendrix shows, “Pico might have
gone too far in his stress upon the role of celestial influence in human life,
[but] his belief in the power of the stars to affect humankind was entirely
within the mainstream of learned opinion of his day.”
______________________________________________________________
Pico, Albert, and all who had developed their approach to natural philosophy
based on Greek precedents, belief in astrology was rational,” can hardly be
bettered.
Did you check your horoscope today? Even if you don’t believe in
the astrological principles might it not make you feel better to know that the
stars predict your monetary income, a journey or an interesting meeting? Or
you might feel a slight discomfort if the planets foretell a work injury, or if
they recommend that you should drive more carefully today, or if (indeed)
they announce a new acquaintance for your partner?
“opponent”.
______________________________________________________________
Galileo still delved into astrological traditions and may have also been
contributors. That’s exactly what Scott Hendrix’s study is about.
Author’s response:
Brian Feltham raises the altogether logical concern “that using the
notion of a habitus of the kind described [by Hendrix] risks obscuring certain
60 Rational Astrology and Empiricism, From Pico to Galileo
______________________________________________________________
Take the example of Albert Einstein and the ether. For many
decades the best scientific minds of the nineteenth and early twentieth
centuries assumed this poorly understood substance first described by
Aristotle must serve as the plenum through which light, among other things,
travelled. Unseen and resistant to all attempts to measure it, every failed
experiment intended to understand it resulted only in ever greater theoretical
elaboration about why its untestability proved its existence. Even Albert
Einstein accepted the existence of the ether and assumed that his scientific
colleagues’ explanations for why one could not uncover evidence of it were
correct, until, in wrestling with problems related to time and the speed of
light, he eventually had an epiphany that time and speed could not be
Scott E. Hendrix 61
______________________________________________________________
______________________________________________________________
within the boundaries of a habitus that saw logic as the essential tool for
knowledge production, there was no reason not to accept the validity of
astrological beliefs. Furthermore, these beliefs were inherently useful,
representing a powerful anxiety-reduction mechanism, to borrow a phrase
from the anthropologist Bronislaw Malinowski, providing a means of
explanation for things that were otherwise unexplainable. Given its
compatibility with the premodern habitus coupled with their usefulness, what
could have been more rational than to hold astrological beliefs? True to
Feltham’s closing comments, astrologers were not, and I would argue still are
not, “performing” science, and therefore by the standards of scientific
rationalism would (are?) not involved in a scientifically rational exercise. But
as Steven Lukes has argued, we should not assume that there is only one
model of rationality.
______________________________________________________________
the discipline has experienced over the years in terms of its reputation then
the modern fascination is easier to understand. With the close of the
Renaissance, even before Galileo cast horoscopes in Italy, the subject began
to become tainted in France due to associations with unrest and public
disorder during the years of the French Wars of Religion (1562-1598), as
Denis Crouzet argues in his two-volume Les Guerriers de Dieu. Its negative
reputation only worsened during the years of the British Civil Wars (1642-46
and 1648), leading to astrology’s marginalization until a revival of interest
occurred in the latter years of the nineteenth century thanks largely to the
efforts of William Frederick Allen, known to the world as Alan Leo. This
history is far too complex to do more than mention here, but the point is that
with the coming of modernity and all its complexities, including the loss of
faith that many experienced in regards to traditional religions, astrology stood
ready to provide an alternative belief system complete with the same anxiety-
reducing benefits that it had provided to centuries of premodern believers.
My final words on the subject- here at any rate- begin from the
presumption that there is no such thing as “rationality,” in my estimation, but
rather there are “rationalities.” Differing eras have differing constructs of
what rationality is and what it is to be rational, imparted to individual
members of society through a hegemonic discourse that inculcates a habitus
within the individual. This is explicitly not a rigid set of beliefs from which
one cannot diverge, but rather a set of starting assumptions that typically
(though not always) go unexamined, influencing but never mandating how
people will view the world. However, one does not have to dig very deep to
find modern people who hold esoteric beliefs. Sometimes these are held in
addition to or apart from those ideas that are part of the discourse of scientific
rationality-such as we find with the rusje whom Sinani has studied-or
Scott E. Hendrix 65
______________________________________________________________