DOLEZEL, Lubomir, Extensional and Intensional Worlds
DOLEZEL, Lubomir, Extensional and Intensional Worlds
DOLEZEL, Lubomir, Extensional and Intensional Worlds
EXTENSIONALANDINTENSIONALNARRATIVEWORLDS
LUBOMiRDOLE2EL
Using Frege’s distinction of reference (extension) and sense (intension), as well as some
ideas of possible world semantics, the paper proposes to treat narrative macrostructures in
terms of narrative worlds. The referent of the narrative text is given in the extensional primary
world. This world is linked with an abstract secondary world through individuating functions
which provide a generic (typological) interpretation of the referent. On the other hand, the
extensional primary world is projected into an intensional world through the application of
intensional functions. These functions expressing the regularities of texture are credited with
the macroorganization of sense. Two basic intensional functions - the authentication function
and the explicitness/implicitness function - are discussed in some detail. While the first func-
tion is connected with the problem of truth in narrative worlds, the second one is used to
explain the difference between ‘visible’ and ‘invisible’ narrative worlds.
Theory of literature has been concerned with two fundamental questions: (a)
how are works of literature ‘made’, i.e. what are their formal properties? (b) what
do works of literature mean, i.e. what kind of information do they convey? Lip-ser-
vice has often been paid to the principle of the unity of form and meaning, but
explicit explanations of this unity are hard to come by. The formalist tradition,
focusing on the first question, and the hermeneufic tradition, offering answers to
the second, have been in general developing in isolation, without mutual contact.
This unfortunate situation is recently coming to an end, especially concerning the
theory of narrative texts. It has always been obvious that a theoretical account of
narratives has to incorporate an account of meaning, an account of ‘what happens’
in a story; once students of narrative also realized that narrative works are ‘made’,
i.e. that they display specific narrative forms, the way for a synthetic nurrafive
semantics was open. Unlike traditional hermeneutics, narrative semantics is a study
of meaning expressed in forms, a study of formally organized meaning. Unlike for-
malism, narrative semantics does not claim that the aesthetic effect results from
‘pure’ forms; rather, its source is located in the totality of the literary work.
If meaning is given in the forms of literary texts, then it is an intrinsic property
of these texts. The formal base of meaning warrants the objectivity (inter-subjec-
tivity) of textual meaning. The task of narrative semantics is to recover and to for-
mulate the intrinsic meaning of narrative texts. In this respect, narrative semantics
is in absntllte contrast to subjectivist criticism, which is, in principle, an act of
193
194 L, Doleiel / Extensional and intensional narrative worlds
meaningassignmenr. For the subjectivist critic, the text is just a pretext for triggering
a virtually infinite set of possible ‘interpretations’. For literary semantics, however,
a literary text is a system of restrictions articulating a particular meaning. If, as it is
often claimed by subjectivist criticism, a text can mean anything, then all texts
necessarily mean the same. Literary semantics, conceived as the theory of semantic
restrictions, avoids this counter-intuitive consequence.
A narrative text is a highly complex network of semantic restrictions. Of neces-
sity, narrative semantics formulates, in the first approach, partial models of the
semantic structure of narrative texts. At present, we can hardly see the day when
these partial models will be integrated into a complete model of narrative seman-
tics. ’ In this paper I want to concentrate on some aspects of the macrostructural
model, i.e. on the system of concepts designed for the description of the global
semantic restrictions operating in narrative texts. Logically, macrostructural models
have a priority over microstructural models: a theory of elementary semantic con-
stituents is to be developed in conformity with the general framework provided by
the chosen macrostructual model.
This paper is based on the assumption that the global semantic restrictions oper-
ative in narrative texts can be described in terms of narrative worlds. The concept
of narrative world is the basic concept of the macrostructural model of narrative
semantics. The term ‘world’ has been used in literary criticism (in such phrases as:
‘the world of science-fiction’, ‘the Proustian world/universe’, ‘the world of Crime
and f’unishment’, etc.) as one of many critical metaphors. At present we are in a
position to transform this metaphor into a sound theoretical concept by relating it
to the logico-semantic notion of possible worlds. Some recent studies in narrative
theory (van Dijk 1974/75; Doleiel 1976; Pave1 1976) have already opened up
exploration of this link. However, in any confrontation of literary and logical con-
cepts, the different scopes and aims of literary and logical semantics must be borne
in mind. The prime concern of logical semantics has been the notion of truth;
accordingly, the notion of possible worlds has been introduced in order to formal-
ize the assignment of truth-values to propositions (atomic formulae) in modal con-
texts (Hintikka 1973: 198). * In literary semantics, as will be pointed out later, the
t In his recent criticism of some narrative models, van der Eng has emphasized the necessity of
taking into account dynamic aspects of narrative texts (van der Eng 1978). While it is true
that in narrative texts the aspect of change is essential (changes of situation, changes in the
properties and relations of characters), it would be a mistake to underestimate the importance
of ‘static’ models: by formulating the general concepts of narrative semantics, ‘static’ models
offer a theoretical base for ‘dynamic’ models.
* A formal outline of possible-world semantics can be found in Kripke 1963; for literary
semantics, Kripke 1972, and Hintikka 1975, are especially relevant.
L. Doleiel /Extensional and intensional narrative worlds 195
concept of truth is problematic; in any case, meaning in literary texts (and in natu-
ral language texts in general) cannot be reduced to the concept of truth or truth-
conditions.
The necessity of formulating a broader theory of meaning for natural languages
was clearly recognized by G. Frege; his introduction of the well-known distinction
between ‘reference’ (Bedeutung) and ‘sense’ @inn) was meant to provide a basis for
such a theory (Frege 1892). The difference between the logical, truth-based seman-
tics and the Fregean semantics has been explicitly formulated as follows: “From the
standpoint of logic as such, we need an account of the working of language only as
it relates to truth ... . Frege’s philosophical concerns go a long way beyond anything
that is the proper concern of the logician” (Dummett 1973: 83). 3 It is especially
significant for students of literature that Frege singled out works of verbal art
(exemplified by epic poems) as lying outside the domain of truth: “In hearing an
epic poem ... we are interested only in the sense of the sentences and the images
and feelings thereby aroused. The question of truth would cause us to abandon aes-
thetic delight for an attitude of scientific investigation” (Frege 1892: 125; cf. also
Gabriel 1970).
In spite of the essential difference between logical and literary semantics, two
ideas of possible-world semantics seem to me fundamental for formulating the gen-
eral properties of narrative worlds:
(A) While possible-world semantics takes account of the ‘actual’ world, its scope
extends over an infinite set of possihle worlds alternative to the ‘actual’ world.
These alternative worlds are not empirically observable; rather, they are postulated
as logical ‘constructs’ (Adams 1974: 227, Hintikka 1975: 28). 4 This idea clearly
applies to narrative worlds: from the beginning, narratives have been involved in
constructing possible worlds alternative to the ‘actual’ world of human experience.
Narrative worlds can be characterized as specific semiotic ‘constructs’ built from
certain narrative entities. Their existence is textual, stipulated by nothing other
than the existence of the corresponding texts. If we accept the special ontological
status of narrative worlds, two consequences become readily apparent: (a) narrative
world is fuZZydetermined by the text in which it is described (expressed). It is a
product of the text, while at the same time, it is the basis of its meaning;(b) narra-
3 It should be noted that truth-based semantics does not explain meaning in terms of truth-
values, but in terms of truth-conditions. For a recent account of truth-based semantics, see
Kempson 1977; it is symptomatic that Kempson has no use for Frege’s distinction between
sense and reference.
4 Strictly speaking, the differentiation of the empirically observable ‘actual’ world and the
constructed possible worlds is characteristic only of the ontological position designated as actu-
alisrn (Adams 1974); the opposite position - possibilism - assumes no ontological difference
between the ‘actual’ world and its possible alternatives. While the latter position might be justi-
tied for some purposes of format logic, only the former position offers a sound basis for literary
(as well as scientific) semantics.
196 L. Dolez'el/ Extensional and intensional narrative uorlds
’ In possible-world semantics the set of individuals of a particular world is called its ‘domain’
(Kripke 1963: 80.5).
L. Doleiel /Extensional and intensional narrative worlds 197
agents from different primary worlds. Clearly, the empirical criterion of compossi-
bility is given by reference to corresponding texts: this is in accord with our general
claim that a narrative world is constructed in the text.
A full understanding of the concept of primary NW requires a brief discussion of
yet another aspect: for every narrative text, the set of its agents can be given by
simple enumeration; in other words, the set is defined by extension. Moreover, we
assume that in the primary world the agents exist as entities independently of any
kind of designation which can be assigned to them. Later, we shall consider the
problem of speaking about such purely referential entities. Now let us merely note
that the postulated properties - enumerability of its members and their indepen-
dence of designation - characterize the primary NW as an extensional concept.
6
We shall speak simply about extensional primary narrative worlds.
While cornpossibility of agents is the most general restriction imposed on pri-
mary NWs, other less general restrictions operate in such a way as to partition the
set of agents of a primary NW into distinct subsets. Thus, for example, by taking
the relationship to the ‘hero’ as the partitioning criterion, we split the set of agents
of a primary world into three subsets: the hero, his ‘allies’ and his ‘enemies’ (a
fourth set of ‘neutrals’ can be also envisaged). Let us note that this kind of parti-
tioning of the extensional world is itself extensional: the world is split into sub-
worlds by splitting the enumerable set of agents into enumerable subsets. The
extensional character of this partitioning indicates the theoretical importance of the
operation: the system of extensional subworlds with its possible relations and hier-
archies represents the organization of meaning in narrative texts on the level of
Fregean reference.
For the definition of the primary NW, the most readily available narrative entity,
that of agent, has been chosen. However, the definition can be expanded to incor-
porate actions and properties of agents as well. Every agent performs a certain set
of actions - let’s call this set his action scope, and he is assigned a certain set of
properties - his property set. ’ The expanded definition of the extensional primary
NW then includes the set of compossible agents together with the corresponding
action scopes and property sets. Actions and properties are assigned to agents in the
form of propositional functions. The extensional primary NW then appears as a set
of propositional functions defined over the set of compossible agents. ’
We have to emphasize once more that agents, their actions and their properties
qua entities of extensional worlds are given independently of any designation
(name, description, expression). However, in extensional narrative semantics we
have to speak about these entities, we have to identify and differentiate them. For
this purpose, we need a strictly extensional language characterized by one-to-one
correspondence between the narrative entities and their designations. We should
add that we are here faced with a problem which is not specific for narrative seman-
tics; it is a fundamental problem of general semantic theory. At present, the task of
constructing a purely extensional language has not been resolved satisfactorily. Per-
haps most appropriate for the purposes of narrative semantics is the system of seman-
tic representations reflecting the ‘logical forms of sentences’, as developed by linguis-
tic semantics. In this language propositional functions can be expressed in the form
of predications. If narrative predications are called motifs, 9 we arrive at the final
modification of our definition: extensional primary NW is a set of motifs with argu-
ment variables ranging over the set of compossible agents and predicate variables
ranging over their action scopes and property sets. We shall use this definition
whenever the need arises to speak about identified and differentiated narrative enti-
ties.
lo The term ‘actant’ originates in French linguistics (cf. Tesniere 1959); Greimas has intro-
duced it into narrative semantics (Greimas 1966). It should be emphasized that individuating
functions of narrative semantics are not necessarily binary; that means that one and the same
agent can embody more than one actant and vice versa (cf. Greimas 1970: 157-183).
*’ Many revisions of Propp’s system of actants have been proposed; however, they do not
affect the general point discussed here.
200 L. Dole?el ! Extensional and intensional narrative worlds
formal properties. In all these systems, the potentially unlimited number of narra-
tive agents of a potentially unlimited set of primary narrative worlds is reduced to a
limited number of actants of a specified
__~_~ _.._~ secondary world. And in all these systems,
narrative agents receive an interpretution in terms of actants, and primary narrative
worlds in terms of the postulated secondary world. The ‘interpretative’ function is
nothing else than the converse of the individuating function, a function from agents
to actants, from primary worlds to secondary worlds. Clearly, all ‘interpretative’
systems of narrative semantics are based on cross-world identification formally des-
cribed by the concept of secondary worlds with corresponding individuating func-
tions.
In the case of secondary narrative worlds, their extensional character is even
more readily apparent than in the case of primary worlds: the set of actants is
clearly enumerable since it is postulated by the analyst. The designations of the sec-
ondary world entities, designations of actants, ‘functions’, ‘motifemes’, etc., are
purely extensional, since they are given as unambiguous terms of the proposed sys-
tem. ‘Interpretative’ systems of narrative semantics are mappings of one extensional
world into another extensional world; they do not leave the space of Fregean
reference.
It should be noted that the theoretical concepts just discussed do not provide
any empirical criteria for ‘interpretative’ narrative semantics. In considering the
primary NW, we could formulate an empirical criterion for determining the set of
its agents: this set is equivalent to the set of agents given in the corresponding text.
Secondary narrative worlds do not correspond to particular narrative texts; rather,
they correspond to text classes. But the set of actants of a secondary world cannot
be given as the set of all agents of the text class; in such a case, we would abandon
the operation of cross-world indentification. Consequently, the set of actants has to
be suggested as a hypothesis. What is more embarrassing is that we have no empiri-
cal criteria of individuating functions; the decision as to which agent(s) of the pri-
mary narrative worlds will be selected as the embodiment of a particular actant is
largely intuitive. Consequently, no exact procedure for testing a proposed ‘inter-
pretative’ system is available. For these reasons, ‘interpretative’ narrative semantics
is a field where sound hypotheses easily mix with products of pure imagination.
Our model does not offer a cure for these empirical defects; however, by formulat-
ing the theoretical framework of ‘interpretative’ narrative semantics, it calls atten-
tion to these defects.
We have based the concepts of primary narrative world, as well as that of the sec-
ondary world, on the principles of extensionality. These concepts have been
defined in such a way as to fall within the space of Fregean reference. But since we
have accepted Frege’s idea about the prime importance of sense in literature, we are
L. Doleiel /Extensional and intensional narrative worIds 201
12 In this respect Frege’s example from the language of geometry is even more instructive than
his famous ‘morning star’-‘evening star’ example. In view of this, it is difficult to understand
the claim, according to which “senses.. . are not linguistic entities” (Grossmann 1969: 156);
not surprisingly, Grossmann comes to the conclusion “that there are no such entities as senses”
(1969: 164).
202 L. Dokfel /Extensional and intensional narrative worlds
Extensional Intensional
world world
~~~~J
13 Intensional functions are not necessarily two-valued; many-valued intensional functions arise
whenever the choice between more than two forms of expression is given.
L. DoleIe/ / Extensional and intensional narrative \corlds 203
Extensional Intensional
Secondary worlds Primary worlds
world
O individ? ($ Inten!: 0
Fig. 2.
the problem, expressed rather skeptical opinions. I4 Two varieties of this skepticism
can be distinguished: (a) the Fregean position assumes that literary sentences are
“neither true, nor false” (cf. Gabriel 1970: 1 If.). This position is generally inter-
preted in such a way that a three-value logic is postulated (with values: true; false;
neither true, nor false). Is (b) The classical structuralist position finds no use for
the concept of truth in literary theory: “the question of truthfulness does not make
any sense in poetry” (Mukaiovsky 1948: vol. I, 82). This position corresponds
closely to Austin’s radical solution: there are classes of sentences which cannot
be said to be true or false and, therefore, cannot be called statements; specifi-
cally, sentences which are ‘part of a work of fiction’ are excluded from the class of
statements and from the domain of truth values (Austin 1961: 99).
It seems that after hearing these opinions, we can hardly find a place for the con-
cept of truth of the corresponding theory in literary theory. There is, however, one
aspect of narrative sentences to which the assigment of truth value (in some sense)
seems quite natural; recently, this aspect has been discussed by Pave1 (1976) and,
independently, by Chateaux (forthcoming). According to Chateaux the sentence
Emma BovaTyjinit par se suicider has to be characterized as true, while the sentence
Charles Bovary est unijambiste must be designated as false. Pavel, in fact, makes this
account more precise by stating that ‘true’ or ‘false’ can be said only of ersatz-sen-
tences, i.e. sentences taken outside their literary context. Significantly, both
authors relate the concept of truth to possible-world semantics: statements (atomic
formulae) are designated as true or false in or of a possible world. The first
Chateaux’s example can be said to be true in the ‘fictional’ world of Emma Bovay,
while the second example is false in it.
It is clear that the relativized concept of truth in possible-world semantics is not
equivalent to truth ‘on empirical grounds’. Actual ‘states of affairs’ exist indepen-
dently of the statements (sentences) which can be made about them. In contrast,
alternative possible worlds (including the ‘fictional’ worlds of narrative) are ‘artifi-
cial’ constructs. To say that a proposition is true in or of a possible world and, at
the same time, to say that a possible world is constructed from propositions true in
it, brings us to the brink of circularity.
What is obviously needed is an account of the concept of existence (in a possi-
ble world) without recourse to the concept of truth. I believe that for narrative
semantics such an account can be given by the theory of authentication. The theory
postulates a special intensional function - called authentication function - which
operates in such a way as to assign to narrative sentences either the value ‘authentic’
or the value ‘non-authentic’. By claiming that authentication has the status of inten-
l4 In pronouncements of this kind, we find often the term ‘poetry’; it should be understood in
its broad sense as meaning ‘artistic literature’ (corresponding to the German term Dichtung).
Is In fact, such an interpretation cannot be derived from Fregc (1892); here, Frege insists that
“the truth-value of a sentence . . . is true or false. There are no further truth values” (1892:
123). Literary sentences are without truth-value, since they lack reference.
206 L. Dole51 / Extensiotlal and intcnsional narrative \rorlds
ture, they are paraphrases expressing extensional meaning. However, we are now in
a position to explain why the ersatz-sentence Emma Bovavfinished by suicide can
be proclaimed ‘true’, while the ersatz-sentence Charles Bovary was one-legged has to
be designated as ‘false’. The reason is that the first ersatz-sentence is a paraphrase of
authentic narrative sentences, while the second is not (to be exact, the second
ersatz-sentence has no equivalent narrative sentence in Flaubert’s text). The assign-
ment of truth-values to ersatz-sentences is made on the basis of authenticity values
of corresponding narrative sentences, as given in the texture. ‘Truth’ in narratives is
derived from ‘authenticity’ and, as such, it has a clearly different meaning than the
concept of truth in the correspondence theory. In the final account, the concept of
truth in narrative semantics seems redundant and dispensable.
Explicitness/implicitness function
*a The formulation indicates that besides explicitness and implicitness, a redundant (more than
explicit) form of expression is possible.
t9 We take the term ‘allusion’ in its broadest sense, corresponding roughly to ‘hint’; in poetics,
the term has usually been used more narrowly, designating the semantic links of one literary
text to other texts, art works, etc. (cf. Preminger 1974’: 18).
208 L. Dolr?el /Extensional and intensional narratiw worlds
tence in which the allusion is given. Allusion triggers the activation of its presuppo-
sitions, or, more exactly, the activation of the presuppositions of the sentence in
which the allusion is given. These activated presuppositions, not stated in the tex-
ture, but necessitated by it, represent the missing form of the motifs expression.
While allusion is part of the texture, its presuppositions are not. In such a way, the
seemingly contradictory conditions of implicitness, formulated earlier, are recon-
ciled: while the motif is not expressed in the texture, it is recoverable from it due
to the recall of presuppositions, triggered by the allusion given in the texture.
Since we assume that presuppositions play an essential role in the implicit forms
of texture, we need a clear concept of presuppositions. Unfortunately. in spite of
the many discussions which have been devoted to it, the concept is muddled (for a
recent survey of various approaches, see Lyons 1977: 592-606, vol. II). In order to
make the concept useful for narrative semantics, two requirements should be ob-
served: (a) presupposition should be clearly distinguished from entailment and
other possible implication relations between sentences. The best way to do it is to
respect the original logico-semantic definition of presupposition. a0 For the
purposes of narrative semantics, the criterion of presupposition can be formulated
as follows: a set of sentences which is necessitated by a narrative sentence repre-
sents the presuppositions of this sentence if and only if the set is the same for the
asserted and for the negated sentence. (b) Presuppositions should be postulated as
objective (intersubjective) semantic facts; every competent speaker has the ability
to recall the presuppositions of sentences expressed in his language. Ducrot’s fine
distinction between the presuppost of a texts and its sowentendu (the former
being a fact of langue, the latter of parole) (Ducrot 1972) reflects the postulate of
objectivity. As objective semantic facts, presuppositions can enter the formation of
the objective text sense.
In order to make our discussion more perspicuous, let us invoke one example of
the allusion technique. In Kafka’s The Trial the arrest of Joseph K. is announced in
the following performative act of one of the warders: “You are arrested. . . . BYI-
ceedings have been instituted against you”. Moreover, the warder speaks about his
authorization and his instructions. Significantly, the name of the agent(s) who gave
the authorization and instructions and who ordered Josef K.‘s arrest is witheld by
consistent manipulations of the texture. Consequently, a conspicuous semantic gap
is created. The sentences of the warder function as allusions; their full semantic
interpretation requires the recall of their presuppositions. These presuppositions
can be formulated as follows: there exists an agent (or a group of agents) different
from the warder and he (they) ordered Joseph K. ‘s arrest. These presuppositions
represent the implicit expression of the corresponding motifs of Kafka’s The Tt-i>l.
We shall keep this example in mind when we proceed to consider briefly the con-
2o The definition is given by van Fraassen: “A presupposes B if and only if: (a) A necessitates
B, (b) not-A necessitates B.” The semantic relation of necessitation means that the argument
from A to B (and, of course, also from not-A to B) is valid (van Fraassen 1968: 138).
L. DoleIel / Extensional and intensional narrative worlds 209
sequences of the E/I function for the organization of sense in narrative texts. Obvi-
ously, the E/I function splits the intensional NW into an explicit and an implicit
subworld; this partitioning is the base of the organization of sense by the applica-
tion of the E/I function. Before we say something more specific about this sense
organization, we have to consider the possibility that the E/I function, unlike the
authentication function, is not universal. It seems that the E/I function is applied
rather unevenly in different narrative texts: many texts prefer to express all (or
practically all) of their motifs explicitly; others are full of allusions and implicit mo-
tifs. This empirical fact gives us a reason to believe that also the consequences of
the E/I function for the organization of sense are text (or text-class) specific, rather
than universal. Such differences could be related to the different degrees of impor-
tance of the function and/or to its ‘teaming’ with other intensional functions. Thus
in some narrative texts, the explicit and the implicit intensional subworlds provide a
base for differentiating the ‘foreground’ and the ‘background’ of the story. In some
modern texts, such as in Kafka’s The Trial and The Castle, the organization of the
intensional world can be described as an opposition between the ‘visible’ and the
‘invisible’ worlds (cf. also Doleiel forthcoming). While the explicit subworld pro-
vides a base of the ‘invisible’ world, the implicit subworld, due to its vagueness and
indefiniteness, is a natural base of the ‘invisible’ world. If our interpretation is, in
principle, correct, then the sense organization effected by the E/I function might be
one of the most interesting phenomena of modem fiction.
If we assume that such semantic macrostructures as ‘visible’ and ‘invisible’
worlds are intensional phenomena, then they are, by definition, determined by the
texture. Any change of the texture affecting the E/I function will change the char-
acter and the relation of the two worlds. If the changes of texture were so radical as
to eliminate the E/I function (if everything was expressed explicitly), the ‘invisible’
world would be destroyed. This reflection leads us back to the initial and basic idea
of our paper: the inextricable link between form and meaning which is made
explicit in the theory of sense represents the most important problem of narrative
semantics. However, intensional semantics presupposes a well-established exten-
sional semantics; consequently, both the intensional and the extensional semantics
of narrative texts require systematic attention.
The difficulties of intensional semantics are well known; they are given by the
fact that sense cannot be adequately formulated in a paraphrase. The difficulties
have been obvious in the domain of literary micro-semantics, in the study of such
intensional phenomena as metaphor, symbol, etc.; they increase substantially when
we proceed to macro-structural intensional semantics, to the study of global princi-
ples of sense organization. Here, we are faced with sense constituents en masse and
with unlimited possibilies of their organization. Obviously, such problems require a
theoretical treatment in terms of sets and functional relations between sets. Our
concepts of intensional narrative world and of intensional function are based - as
can easily be seen - on these formal notions. If the perennial problem of ‘truth’ in
literature 9-4 the important contrast between explicitness and implicitness has
received some elucidation within this theoretical framework, our attempt to link
problems of narrative semantics to those of logical semantics has not been in vain.
References
Pavcl, Thomas C. 1976. ‘Possible worlds in literary semantics. The Journal of Acsthctics and
Art Criticism 34 (2): 165-176.
Prcminger, Alex. Ed. 1974’. Princeton encyclopedia of poetry and poetics. Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press.
Propp, Vladimir. 1928. Morfologija skazki. MOSCOW.
Tarski, Alfred. 1944. The semantic conception of truth and the foundations of semantics. Phi-
losophy and Phcnomcnological Research IV: 341-375. Quoted from Zabeeh. Klcmkc and
Jacobson, 677-711.
Tesnicrc, Lucicn. 1959. I:IL:mcnts de syntaxe structuralr. Paris: Klincksicck.
warnock, C.J. 1963. ‘Truth and corrcspondencc’. In: C.D. Rollins, ed., Knowlcdgc and capcri-
encc. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburg Press, 11-20. Quoted from Zabeeh, KIcmkc and
Jacobson, 733-742.
Zabceh, Farhang, li.D. Klemke and Arthur Jacobson, eds. 1974. Readings in semantics. Urbana-
Chicago-London: University of Illinois Press.
Lzrbonrir Doleiel, formerly a rcscarch fellow of the Czechoslovak Academy of Sciences, is pro-
fessor at the University of Toronto in the Dcpartmcnt of Slavic Languages and Literatures. He
has published numerous works in stylistics, poetics and statistical linguistics. Among his recent
publications in narrative theory arc: Narrative modes in Czech liferanrre (Toronto. 1973); ‘Nar-
rative semantics’ and “Die Hundcblumc’, or poetic narrative’ (both in PTL 1976); ‘Narrative
modalities’ (Journal of Literary Semantics 1976).