Dumont 2008
Dumont 2008
Dumont 2008
Cover art by Shawn E. Dumont Published by State University of New York Press, Albany 2008 State University of New York All rights reserved Printed in the United States of America No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in writing of the publisher. For information, contact State University of New York Press, Albany, NY www.sunypress.edu Production by Diane Ganeles Marketing by Anne M. Valentine Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Dumont, Clayton W., Jr. 1962 The promise of poststructuralist sociology : marginalized peoples and the problem of knowledge / Clayton W. Dumont p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. isbn 9780791474419 (hardcover : alk. paper) isbn 9780791474426 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Knowledge, Sociology of. 2. Sociology Philosophy. 3. SociologyMethodology. 4. PostmodernismSocial aspects. I. Title. hm651.d86 2008 301.01dc22 2007033816
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
contents
Acknowledgments Introduction Chapter 1: Meeting the Monster: Understanding Poststructuralist Assumptions A Genealogy of the Scientic Self Toward a Post-Christian Ethic of Responsibility in Sociology The American Debate on Postmodernism Whos Understanding Whose Past? Telling the Truth about Native Dead Taking Charge of the Afrmative Action Debate: Social Science and Racial Justice Parting Thoughts Notes References Index vii 1
9 32
Chapter 2: Chapter 3:
54 78
Chapter 4: Chapter 5:
108
Chapter 6:
acknowledgments
This book could not have happened without the love and understanding of my wife Cheri and our sons, Clayton and Jesse, each of whom has been gracious about my absences. Many colleagues read earlier drafts of chapters and provided invaluable feedback. Luiz Barbosa, Chris Bettinger, Marjorie Seashore, Tugrul Ilter, and Rhonda Coleman were particularly helpful. I am indebted to Sandra Luft for her close reading, particularly of chapters 2 and 3. Joanne Barker read the entire manuscript in various drafts and gave hours of criticism and insight. Toms Almaguer, despite his opinions of poststructuralism, has been a wonderful mentor, always honest and encouraging. Two sets of anonymous reviewers were also most helpful, and I thank them for their wisdom and candor. My son, Clayton Andrew, and his grandfather, Clayton Sr., read and commented on early chapters of the book. My brother, Shawn, did the artwork for the book cover. Additional members of the Klamath tribe provided their insights for earlier drafts of chapter 5. My thanks to Donnie Wright, Carmalita Stieger, Nancy (Kates) Midwood, Gale (Hungry) Brenton, Gerald Skelton Jr., Tori Tupper, and Dino Herrera. Luis V. Perez was an eager and capable research assistant for chapter 6. Elizabeth Sedgwick worked hard to produce an index that is helpful to undergraduate students.
introduction
What is Enlightenment? . . . It is not seeking to make possible a metaphysics that has nally become a science; it is seeking to give new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undened work of freedom.
Michel Foucault (1984/1997:101,12526)
arly in our new century, there is still little agreement about what poststructuralism is and what it means for sociology. Indeed, we might say that the label poststructuralist refers to a group of philosophers, social scientists, historians, literary scholars, and linguists whose afnity for each other is more a function of their critics than an assemblage of their own making. Nonetheless, in North America a conversation over the meaning and consequences of poststructuralism began to emerge in the social sciences in the last decades of the twentieth century. Conversation, though, is too nice a word. Angry argument is a more telling description. Racialized, ethnic, and cultural minorities were largely and conspicuously excluded from the debate of previous decades; and I hope this book speaks to that omission. Despite the tremendous impact that Cultural Studies and Postcolonial Criticismtraditions heavily inuenced by poststructuralism and where ethnic and cultural minorities are a major presencehad on anthropology in the 1980s and 1990s, American sociologists mostly resisted these incursions. Consequently, a tremendous opportunity to reinvigorate sociology, making it more relevant for marginalized populations was lost. It is time to rethink that mistake. Writing as a proponent, my position is that a sociology informed by poststructuralist thought will increase sociologists intellectual, civic, and political power. Yet how does one write a book about an intellectual movement that insists upon, indeed celebrates, its own lack of structure? How can one hope to write truthfully about a tradition that willfully and ruthlessly strives to pry open the politics of any truth telling, no matter how esteemed or sacred? And how can newcomers, particularly students, ever hope to comprehend let alone
2 | Introduction
appreciate the mind-bending writings that one of my less than appreciative colleagues disparages as that postmodern gobbledygook? My insistence on revisiting and rethinking a debate that many American sociologists are happy to believe was nished by the late 1990s will draw wary glances from colleagues who want to get on with the business of producing scientic knowledge. Social scientists, after all, continue to develop careers by creating and defending elaborate systems of denitions that they hope help us better understand the social world. Indeed, for generations sociologists have even gone so far as to imagine that these understandings can improve the lives of humanity around the globe. My argument is that leading American sociologists in the 1980s and 1990s largely missed the tremendous intellectual and political potential of poststructuralist philosophy. Their unwillingness or inability to adequately consider the power of poststructuralist criticism stemmed from a self-protecting blindness to their own cultural inheritances and worldview. As a result, they failed to appreciate the reasons behind the appeal that these writings hold for many intellectuals from marginalized populations. I argue that sociologys central organizing principles are inherited from Greek and Christian ancestors and that the lack of attention paid to these philosophical and theological assumptions is at the root of American sociologys overwhelmingly hostile reaction to poststructuralism. Furthermore, had the structure of institutionalized sociology not been so thoroughly inundated with Greek and Christian presuppositions, poststructuralist criticism would not have appealed to intellectuals from marginalized groups to the extent that it has. After all, the disciplined quest for purity of understanding and foundational truthan endeavor that has caused no shortage of pain and suffering for oppressed populations of many kindshas its complex origins in Greek and Christian cultural histories. This quest, in recent centuries having become a scientic undertaking, is at the heart of what motivates contemporary poststructuralist critique. With these European origins in mind, it is important to acknowledge that my own identity is fundamentally related to my afnity for this difcult French philosophy. I am a mixed blood, enrolled member of the Klamath Tribe from southern Oregon. My paternal family is both Klamath and Umpqua (another southern Oregon tribe), and my mothers people are fourth- and fth-generation loggers who homesteaded close to the Klamath reservation early in the last century. When I discovered poststructuralist philosophy, and this happened in spite of the objections of my faculty advisers in sociology, graduate school was salvaged for me. Without Foucault, Jacques Derrida, and later Gayatri Spivak, T. Minh-ha Trinh, Henry Giroux, Judith Butler, and Homi K. Bhabha, I would have dropped out and gone home. With the help of these thinkers, I soon learned to understand myself as a nontraditional student from the margins. Poststructuralism authorized my confrontations with powerful representational strategies deployed by privileged, professional sociologists.
Introduction
| 3
Derrida remains one of the most controversial of the thinkers responsible for unsettling, poststructuralist challenges to traditional Western philosophy (philosophy that is the ancient origin of modern sociology). In an essay published nearly forty years ago, Derrida writes of the difcult birth of this poststructuralist turn in the social sciences.
Here there is a kind of question, let us still call it historical, whose conception, formation, gestation, and labor we are only catching a glimpse of today. I employ these words, I admit, with a glance toward the operations of childbearingbut also with a glance toward those who, in a society from which I do not exclude myself, turn their eyes away when faced by the as yet unnamable which is proclaiming itself and which can do so, as is necessary whenever a birth is in the ofng, only under the species of the nonspecies, in the formless, mute, infant, and terrifying form of monstrosity. (Derrida 1966/1978:293, emphases in original)
Derrida calls the birth a terrifying form of monstrosity. The decades following the publication of his essay bear out this prophecy. Fear and desperation, and outright hatred of the birth, erupted in sociologists professional meetings and in sociological writings. Sociologists pursued at least three distinct albeit overlapping attacks on the terrifying newborn. Perhaps most important is the claim that poststructuralism equals relativism, nihilism, nominalism, solipsism, or subjectivism. Susan Hekman (1986:196) asserts, Derrida and Foucault lead us toward a nihilistic Tower of Babel. Rosalyn W. Bologh and Leonard Mell (1994:83,89) see an ultimate subjectivism that can only end in a Hobbesian version of society as a war of all against all. Stephan Fuchs and Steven Ward (1994:506) worry that the birth of Derridas monstrosity will bring a crisis in solidarity, organizational cohesion, and professional communication. In these and in countless other alarmed sightings there is great fear of destabilizing long institutionalized methods for producing scientic knowledge. Much of this dread stems from the closely related worry that poststructuralism will destroy a prerogative for making political claims that sociologists have gained only with generations of hard, disciplined, scientic scholarship. If the foundations for truth making are overwhelmed, this criticism goes, then sociology loses any authority to claim that its understandings are superior to those of anyone who cares to claim anything. Thus Pauline M. Rosenau (1992:139) maintains that sociologists will be forced to relinquish any global political projects as we struggle to survive in a normative void. Ward (1997:785) goes even further, arguing that this lack of foundation is dangerous. Without the trust and moral commitment which realism generates, he exclaims, all social interaction and communication would break down under the weight of paranoid suspicion. Anxiety, here, tends to be over consequences and not about the merits of poststructuralist arguments per se.
4 | Introduction
A third criticism claims that poststructuralist writings are purposefully unintelligible or a kind of elaborate scam designed to fool people into believing outright nonsense. Jerry L. Lembcke (1993:67) writes of pig Latin while Michael Faia (1993:65) refers to the word salads of the mentally deranged. Randall Collins (1992:184) lampoons that the academic jokester Erving Goffman is probably responsible for the whole charade since the condition of being dead is just a social construct. Todd Gitlin (1998:71) nds in the new birth only the schizophrenic, nihilistic blank stare of the postmodern, while George Ritzer (1997:xvii) describes these works as self-consciously unreadable. Although these attacks are vicious and overstated, it is true that many poststructuralist writings are difcult to decipher. Although that is not my primary motivation, I write with each of these criticisms in mind. Poststructuralist thought is not nonsensical, and missing the great potential found in these admittedly dense texts is far too high a price for scholars to pay for this imsy excuse not to read closely and carefully. Nor does poststructuralist scholarship impede political work. On the contrary, the rigor of poststructuralist analyses promotes a hyper-awareness of the politics found in all knowledge creation. And this awareness is precisely why it appeals to many nontraditional intellectuals. Poststructuralist writings, seriously considered, can help sociology become a far more inclusive and vibrant project. As a poststructuralist, I assume that all knowledge is political. Thus I understand political work as my primary endeavor. Notions of pure knowledge or pure research or knowledge for the sake of knowledge make no sense to meexcept perhaps as historical curiosities. In fact, the very fearful charges of relativism, nihilism, solipsism, and subjectivism that prop up this alleged political paralysis appear to a poststructuralists gaze as profoundly political gestures. Recognizing these accusations as political actions leveled in defense of hardened cultural traditions requires careful exploration of their extended cultural origins. In his famous essay, The Promise (1959), C. Wright Mills argues that sociology ought to help people see the too often unrecognized links between extended history and personal biography. Mills thought that sociology could teach people to understand how social history and individual actions come together in society. In the early chapters of my book, I take this tack. The founding assumptions of our methods for making knowledge (which in the opening chapter students will learn to call epistemology) become, in the pages that follow, sociological phenomena. Understood as cultural forms with long and complex genealogies, familiar social scientic habits are less comforting and the possibility of new intellectual assumptions is less frightful. Relieved of some very enduring superstitions, a poststructuralist-inspired sociology can nally lay claim to the civic duty and public responsibility that generations of sociologists have sought. As differences within and among societies explode, spread, and overlap, the freedom that Enlightenment-era Europeans dreamed about grows more elusive. Only a fearless investigation and
Introduction
| 5
critique of sociologys most cherished epistemological (and culturally inherited) assumptions can sustain sociologists honest participation in that dream for much longer. Coming as I do from a nonacademic background, I learned early in my university education that academics dreams of freedom and equality are often scarcely recognizable to, and at times quite patronizing of, the people and social spaces where I feel most comfortable. The social science I learned from my graduate and undergraduate professors left me unconvinced of its claims and uninspired by its aspirations. I was interested in politics and social issues even as a small boy, but I did not grow up around educated, middle-class people. Academic culture initially struck me as strange. I remember marveling at how seriously professors took themselves and their works. I soon realized that they believed unequivocally in the superiority of their knowledge over that of all other knowing traditions. Because social scientic narrations were given a privileged status by the sociologists from whom I learned, I soon found myself struggling to reconcile those scientic accounts with the narrations of friends and family who often became the unwitting objects of my sociological gaze. Most of my extended family has at some point worked in the timber industry, and most of my maternal family members are quite proud of their time in the woods. During my graduate school years at the University of Oregon, there was an all-out cultural, economic, and political struggle over the fate of the forests of the Pacic Northwest. I very much wanted to understand, and to help others understand, what was happening to our timber-dependent communities. I endeavored to write a doctoral dissertation that would do exactly that. However, explanations of class consciousness, resource mobilizing social movements, or ideal types made me increasingly aware of the fact that sociology and sociologists are themselves thoroughly cultural and political entities. Ironically, then, my familiarity with small, timber town culture was more hindrance than help. I spent countless hours fretting over how my family and friends would react to being sociological categories written about in tones of analytic distance. Ultimately I nished a rather traditional academic dissertation, but I balked at revising it for publication. I simply could not sanction the conspicuously unacknowledged power of the academic renderings that structured the project. By the time I was a junior at Southern Oregon State College, it was painfully clear to me that being Indian was destined to be a constant annoyance should I choose a future in academe. The authority of science was always at work in any academic discussion of Indians and our ways. But social scientists, particularly the anthropologists, were rarely willing to admit that their queries, desires, and ideals were anything but natural and designed to increase a universalized knowledge of humanity. Worse still, they routinely denied they had this power even as they constantly invoked it. During my graduate school years, one professor who knew of my fondness for shing asked me if my Indian side had a problem with my white side putting
6 | Introduction
live bait on a hook. Another wanted to know, what happens to you when you are with other Indians? I wanted to tell him that we get gut-splitting laughter from the telling and retelling of questions like his. But, I refrained and wished someone or something would teach him that his scientic gaze was neither objective nor without consequences. Both of these individuals and their institutions possessed and wielded great power. However their status and that of their institutionsstatus that gave them the power to pronounce judgment on the merit of my workdid not require that they see their scientic ways as cultural and political acts. My academic experiences since leaving graduate school have only strengthened my conviction that scientic knowledge, while powerful and often of monumental benet, must not be allowed the status of extra-cultural, extrapolitical truth. By the time I obtained an academic post at San Francisco State University in 1991, the Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA) of 1990 was federal law. This hard-won statute nally made it illegal for museums and universities to hold and collect the grave contents of deceased Native Americans. The debate over NAGPRA was and is intense. Many in the scientic community continue to believe that the law amounts to destruction of their scientic data. The vast majority of Indians, including myself, tend to see things very differently. In this case, then, the power of scientic narrations is directly confronted by Native reasoning(s) that are often well beyond what many scientists can appreciate or even tolerate. Indeed, successive chairs of the Sociology Department on my own campus repeatedly engaged me in vigorous debate over what they see as the overzealousness of the law. These knowledge politics are taken up in considerable detail in the penultimate chapter of the book. Similarly, chapter 6 stems from my frustration with the assumed authority of academic narrations purporting to depict the reality of afrmative action programs in the United States. Although I have beneted in multiple ways from afrmative action policies, I do not accept any of the accounts contained in the widespread and vigorous debates over these initiatives as descriptions of an empirically veriable reality. Rather, I see these scientic and judicial portrayals as active and politically powerful constructions of me, my family, and many of my friends. These politics, I maintain, are far better navigated by sociologists who understand and appreciate the challenges brought to the academic table by poststructuralist writings. Chapters 56 both demonstrate why and how a poststructuralist-informed sociology can increase the political efcacy of cultural and racialized minorities. My short biographical reections point to politics as an enduring part of all knowledge making, but they are not an argument for a more penetrating, more accurate, more comprehensive sociology. Rather, they point to the contingency of all sense making. In the words of Steven Seidman (1997: 37), they relativize sociology. That is, they support his request that we learn to understand sociology as a local practice with conceptual strategies and
Introduction
| 7
thematic perspectives . . . indicative of a particular tradition rather than . . . a universal language of the social. Sociology should not, as he says, fantastically imagine its conventions as providing a privileged access to the social universe (54). Once again, my argument is that leading American sociologists of the 1980s and 1990s missed a tremendous opportunity to increase the relevance of sociology for a wider, more diverse audience. This failure stemmed from these sociologists unwillingness or inability to think critically about the disciplines Greek and Christian origins. A close examination of cultural assumptions inherited from their Greek and Christian predecessors can help professional sociologists see poststructuralist writings in a less hostile light. This, in turn, will lead to a sociology that can be far more productive for marginalized populations. My argument is made over six chapters. Chapter 1, Meeting The Monster: Understanding Poststructuralist Assumptions, is an extended introduction. Because I want this text to be accessible to undergraduate theory students, I begin with demonstrations and stories from everyday life that provide easily accessible, interpretive context. In these early pages, students and colleagues can both gain access to assumptions routinely made by poststructuralists and recognize how these assumptions are consonant with their everyday experiences. Chapter 2, A Genealogy of the Scientic Self, locates contemporary sociologists epistemological assumptions and political aspirations in much older Greek philosophy and Christian theology. My aim in these pages is to demonstrate that our Greek and Christian predecessors pursued unobtainable, faith-based certainty, and that structuralist sociologists have failed to critically interrogate their allegiance to these divinations. Chapter 3, Toward a Post-Christian Ethic of Responsibility in Sociology, substantiates the Christian origins of contemporary, structuralist sociologists sense of political responsibility. I argue that the biblical Godunderstood as a discipline demanding, hard to know, center of certaintyremains the unexamined source of the assumption that viable political work requires a general, thematically coherent sense of history and society. Ultimately, I conclude that the quest for social and historical structure inhabited by an essential human agency is politically debilitating. Chasing our own theological tales distracts us from developing far more pressing, more earthly, and actually obtainable political acumen. Chapter 4, The American Debate on Postmodernism, retraces some of the heated controversy of the 1980s and 1990s as it unfolded in American sociologists writings about poststructuralism, or postmodernism as these perspectives were routinely labeled. In this chapter I connect the major objections raised by these critics to sociologys culturally inherited and faith-based assumptions explored in chapters 23. I focus, in particular, on these sociologists stated desire to include marginalized others while simultaneously trying to defend their own epistemological beliefs.
8 | Introduction
Chapter 5, Whos Understanding Whose Past? Telling the Truth about Native Dead, is a political document written by a Native sociologist (me) using poststructuralist writings. Anthropologists attacks on NAGPRA, attacks they claim are mounted from their concern for objective truth, are rethought and rearticulated using voices of Native peoples. Acting as a political intervention, the chapter recasts anthropological fables of objectivity as acts of political aggression. Anthropological narrations of Indian histories are routinely awarded the status of facts and evidence, I argue, only because Europeans came to the Americas in overwhelming numbers and carried guns. Thus, far from being a ght over truth, Native American struggles to reclaim our dead are better understood as the most recent confrontation with colonialist power that these physical anthropologists uncritically assume as their birthright. Chapter 6, Taking Charge of the Afrmative Action Debate: Social Science and Racial Justice, is both analysis and political strategy informed by poststructuralism. The central argument of the chapter is that the major components of the debate over afrmative action have no inherent structure. Race, merit, discrimination, individuality, and equal opportunity can never be nally dened, and they will never have their truth laid bare for all right-minded people to witness. Neither afrmative action nor its societal consequences are empirically veriable, in the sense of scientic truth that can end political struggle through appeals to the objective qualities of social structure. These programs and their consequences, I argue, are always constructed, comprehended, and maintained from within the midst of political struggle. Because poststructuralists understand politics, and not discovering the truth about afrmative action, as our primary intellectual duty, I maintain that we are better poised to develop the skills and strategies necessary to defend these programs.
1
meeting the monster
Understanding Poststructuralist Assumptions
To my mind these endless abstractions, at best, are the grindstones of the garrulous; at worst, they are the word salads of the mentally deranged.
Michael Faia (1993:65)
t is my intention that this text be readable and politically relevant from the outset. Although there will necessarily be a substantial amount of abstraction and difcult-sounding terminology to master, these discussions and terms are illustrated with detailed examples grounding them in everyday life. Abstractions are most accessible when surrounded by the context of lived understandings. This said, let me be honest and up-front about obstacles that accompany initial encounters with poststructuralist writings and thinking, including the work you have just begun. For poststructuralists, there is no extra-social access to the world. One can only know reality by using tools (language, imagery, theory, and methodology) that are always socially acquired. Although other social theorists (e.g., the philosopher Immanuel Kant and the sociologist Max Weber) were quite forthright in acknowledging this lack of direct access to the world, poststructuralists have abandoned even the desire for an unmediated approach to reality. Think about this for a moment. Poststructuralists nd even the apparently basic pursuit of objective truth to be an assumption that ought to be questionedan assumption whose social history should be explored and analyzed. Many social scientists nd this unsettling. They speak and write of feeling intellectually paralyzed, as if banished into vastness without any rm ground in which to place even temporary anchors. Yet others, including myself, nd this orchestrated and perennial disturbance to our patterns of understanding enlightening. Nonetheless, questioning the wisdom of pursuing objective truth is a poststructuralist habit that many nd difcult to swallow.
| 11
a global market? Obviously, neither the love of my family nor my environmental and political concerns can be found in my new mug, itself. As an object, the mug has signicance inasmuch as it relates to meanings and concerns that are in excess of its physical presence. To be a post-structuralist (post means after) means to be no longer interested in searching for truths (the real structures) contained in things themselves. The meanings of the objects of the world, including my birthday present, are as varied and unstable as the narrative threads that provide for their interpretation. I could have gone on for some time about how the importance of a simple coffee mug arrives from outside of itself: the meaning of its decorations, of its place of manufacture, the signicance of ceramics, and so forth. No doubt you could add your own list of descriptors to the conversation. But, you may also still be intent on asking, what is the mug really? Doesnt it still have a physical reality that is prior to the narrations within which I have placed it? As I noted, Western intellectuals have traditionally pursued their belief in objective truth by isolating and de-contextualizing parts of our world. Perhaps the most widespread method for doing so is to introduce numerical and geometric representations. After all, an eleven-centimeter-tall piece of circular ceramics is the same regardless of where it is found or in what context it exists. If I am mathematically capable enough, I can gure out the volume held by the mug, its circumference, diameter, and construct a whole host of dening mathematical portrayals. So why would poststructuralists insist on rethinking the desire for numerical representations of reality that seem to be correct despite any temporal (time), cultural, or geographic context? There are two related answers to this question. First, poststructuralists do not necessarily nd fault with this style of knowing itself. Isolating, decontextualizing, and applying numerical representations to existence continues to show itself to be a powerful way of understanding. The problem is rather one of questioning the absolute authority assumed by the users of these styles of understanding. In other words, if we can show that structuralist desires are born in the particular circumstances (many of which we will trace in the following pages) of European history, does it not follow that the spread of these traditions may be more a function of European colonialism and inuence than proof of their obvious and universal correctness? Surely it is foolish to believe that had native Australians or Native Americans occupied and conquered Europe we would now think so highly of the scientic method. No doubt understanding would be a rather different enterprise, and the effects of these alternative modes of thinking would be a profoundly different world. So if the pursuit of the real nature of my coffee mug through de-contextualizing, mathematical calculations is itself a political outcome, a historically arrived at, culturally specic desire, do these geometric, numerical accounts depict a reality contained in the mug itself? Or, do these meanings also come to the object from outside of itself: not unlike my narrations about family and the political economy of coffee?
| 13
position to assess the wisdom contained therein. In the meantime, there are still other initial impediments to understanding poststructuralism. Despite the attempts at comprehensive denitions, there is no single denition of poststructuralism.2 Making any attempt at denitive description still more improbable, in the United States the label is often taken to be synonymous with postmodernism. Together these labels have been used to group a variety of thinkers from varied academic disciplines and national origins who write in different languages for different purposes. Usually, this collection is said to include thinkers ranging from, but not limited to, Derrida, Foucault, Julia Kristeva, Jacques Lacan, Gayatri Spivak, Judith Butler, Joan W. Scott, Homi K. Bhabha, Jean-Francois Lyotard, Henry Giroux, Zygmunt Bauman, Jean Baudrillard, Ernesto Laclau, Chantal Mouffe, Trinh Minh-ha, and Friedrich Nietzsche. The homogenization legislated in the creation of this mega-camp of postmoderns is a function of critics perspectives and not a sign of agreement between theorists and their followers who at times are downright hostile toward each other. Critics who too quickly tag this immense diversity postmodern and then move to the attack, are doing poor scholarship. Lumping together such vast difference certainly helps one dismiss a great deal of thinking in short order, but it does little to promote thoughtful, productive understanding. Even the most cursory of readings reveals that the majority of these thinkers do not use the terms postmodern or poststructuralist in their writings or in descriptions of their own works.3
Recognizing the Monster: The Species of the Nonspecies So how as students and teachers of a poststructuralist sociology are we to deal with this confusion? How can we understand poststructuralism if no one can say for sure what it is? Our answer to this difculty lies in furthering our understanding of the post notation in the label: post-structuralism. Remember, post means after. To think in a poststructuralist way, then, means no longer seeking to document the existence of a structured, at least somewhat stable, and eventually comprehensively understood social reality. It means to think and write at a point after the pursuit of a structured reality has lost its appeal. It means being part of a very different intellectual species. Remember, we live, work, and attend classes at locations in time, culture, and political climates. Sociology never happens in a social vacuum. Whether we are considering the thinking of Emile Durkheim, Karl Marx, or authors labeled poststructuralist, the signicance and meaning of theory shifts with context. For example, over time in the United States prevailing opinions about Marx and his works have varied tremendously. Although several generations of Americans have been taught that Marxism is evil, the intensity level of anticommunist propaganda has waxed and waned throughout the
| 15
what I write here today? What you read here? What you reread here ve years (full of attitude-altering experiences) from now? Is it the critics readings of the thinkers in the above section? My readings of the works of the authors just listed? Or, is it my readings of the critics who have read from that list? Admitting and embracing this overwhelming complexity means recognizing this writing as an articulation (a pronouncement, a giving over of meaning) born of the complicated, changing affairs of my life and the lives of those who inuence and provoke me. In turn, you readers glean meaning from within the instability of your lives, and from the lives of those whose commentaries on postmodernism or poststructuralism you have paid attention to. Thus as a poststructuralist, I understand that this book can only be written, read, and made sense of from within the complexities and contingent qualities of many unstable agendas. Poststructuralist thought cannot be reduced to structure. To attempt such a reduction is to miss a fundamental lesson of poststructuralism. If poststructuralism has no essence, no inherent structure, then it is not a difcult jump to assert that authors who embrace this label also lack a core structure. Why, except due to habit, should we assume that I, as the author of the text, am a stable, essential, self-directing being? This question is at the center of the rst half of this book, and we will take a much more detailed historical approach to its answer in chapter 2. For the moment, though, we can further our introductory discussion by questioning that perhaps most cherished of American beliefs about the nature of being human: individualism. Most Americans like to think that they are individuals who in exercising free will make independent choices in life. But was I born an individual? Should we suppose that the earliest humans understood themselves to be individuals? Or, have we all learned along the way that this is what we are? Given that many societies do not, and have not, championed the idea of individualism, should we assume that everyone has individuality, even if they do not know this is the case? Are those who do not know, and have not known themselves to be individuals, misguided? Misled? No doubt most Americans have little trouble with the assumptions in such logic. Indeed, if we consult one of our societys popular culture icons whose very character is to seek out all that is unknown and different, we nd Star Treks television starship heroes maintaining that not only are all humans everywhere individuals, but even life-forms alien to earth are inherently individual.4 Thus the most easily understood and far too simple answer to questions about why I wrote this book is to say that it was an individual decision. It is also, then, an act of cultural literacy (a learned appropriate behavior) to refer to my free will when asked to explain why I spent so many long hours learning and writing about something as difcult as poststructuralism. If I had to learn that I am an individual and that I have this thing called free will, then these are socially acquired ideas and not innate or naturally occurring perceptions. Indeed, are not the very notions of individualism and free will tantamount to a sentiment that one is not willing to simply be like
| 17
very condition of the possibility of my self-understanding: father. Despite the centrality of this role to my self-perception and to the everyday functioning of tremendous numbers of families making up society, the role has no internal essence. It has no inherent structure. We could have gone through similar discussions for each of the pieces of subjectivity I listed. What does it mean to be a husband, a sociologist, and a friend to this or that friend? Where did I learn how? Are the readings that I continue to do (of narrations that inform my understandings of all of these roles) stable? My point is that I as a subject (as a knower and a doer, as an author) am no more essential, nite, or stable than my coffee mug or poststructuralist theory. I also am not structure. Let us pause to review where we are in our discussion of initial difculties in understanding poststructuralist approaches to the study of social reality. I have argued that despite what too many critics maintain, there is no single, identiable poststructuralism. Poststructuralist writings, like the being now pushing computer keys, have meanings and signicance that are forever unstable. Indeed, I have even gone so far as to suggest that the desire to know in a nal and comprehensive way is itself a profoundly social, albeit long and complex, effect. This, then, is why, as a poststructuralist, I will not supply a simplistic, structuralist description of poststructuralist theory. It is also precisely this unwillingness to assume a structure in subjectivity or in the objects that knowing subjects encounter in life that renders poststructuralist thought difcult to read and comprehend. It is what makes poststructuralism, as we heard Derrida say, a terrifying form of monstrosity. However, once one becomes comfortable with this poststructuralist sentiment, it is emancipating, both intellectually and politically. The initial obstacles to learning to think poststructurally are now on the table, but the claim of increased political efcacy remains to be considered.
Why Should Sociologists Care about Poststructuralism? Given all of this complexity and difculty, why should sociologists and our students care enough to dedicate the hours and effort needed to learn to think poststructurally? Above all, sociology should be socially and politically relevant. Sociology should equip one with tools for understanding and changing society. I believe this style of analysis to have the best chance of improving the lives of underprivileged, impoverished, and systematically abused human beings. Pursuing sociological understanding as if it were an ever-growing stockpile of truths quickly becomes politically debilitating. Chasing truth has a tendency to remove sociologists from the always-evolving and contingent concerns of, for example, my eighty-three-year-old neighbor who struggled with the onset of Alzheimers disease, of the homeless Romanian immigrant whose son plays with my son at the community pool, or of the single mothers whose
| 19
to, theology. Science, positivists argued, should validate only what can be seen and positively measured (sociologists still refer to this as the empirically available world). Because God is not physically present for scientists to observe and measure, belief in the existence of God is a metaphysical assertion. Poststructuralists maintain that believing in essential qualities of objects objects that therefore have inherent meaning (like my coffee mug or my self or a theoretical tradition)requires defending metaphysical positions. Like attempts to describe God, every attempt to isolate and accurately depict a really real world must always fall short. To continue to believe in a structured and ultimately knowable existence, then, is to do so solely on the basis of faith. Thus when I, as a poststructuralist, offer analyses, they are explicitly political interventions (as opposed to attempts at impartial description) and moral arguments. I do not claim that my narrations are based in an objectively structured reality that I can empirically verify. Indeed, I see such claims as akin to those of earlier generations of intellectuals who sought verication of Gods plan. Another example from daily life can add to our appreciation of this important poststructuralist sentiment. How do Bob and Margaret, my elderly neighbors, understand themselves, me, my family, or our city and state? Before Margarets death and his subsequent move to a senior center, Bob often saw me leave home at noon on my way to teach a late afternoon seminar. Having trouble with his memory, he asked me on more than one occasion, do you go to work after noon everyday? From our conversations over cake and ice cream at the boys birthday parties, I know he believes that he pays too many taxes and that public employees deserve a large part of the blame. He feels this way in part because he contextualizes the present using a past where he remembers feeling comfortable. He recalls a California with far fewer people, fewer public services, fewer laws, and from his perspective fewer social problems. He and Margaret talked fondly of the 1940s and 1950s. Things then were made by Americans for Americans; people shared values and community; and despite hardships, during the war years people were dedicated to the certainty and nobility of their purpose. Margaret lost her rst husband in the Korean conict; Bob served in the Air Force and displayed a bumper sticker identifying his war-time unit on their car. When my family and I bought a Toyota car, Bob and Margaret were visibly annoyed. How could such nice young people not realize how important it was to buy American products? From the political conversations Margaret and I had over coffee and beer, I know that her perspectives on patriotism, immigration, education reform, and other important social issues were vastly different from my own. For example, she saw that the United States had lost many young men and spent enormous amounts of money (causing shortages, rationing, and heartache at home) to defeat the Japanese not too many generations ago. Now, she and Bob believed, the United States has helped to rebuild a Japan so economically powerful that it threatens to overwhelm American productivity. Whats more, she and Bob knew that I spend their
| 21
that was at least of historical value. After all, I could have concluded, most of that generation was so shaped and formed by that era, by wartime propaganda, that they could never understand those events from a less-biased perspective. I would glean her words for the value of her rsthand experience, all the while remembering that I understood things from a much wider and more objective viewpoint. But Margaret was smart. She would know immediately if she was being patronized. She had piercing blue eyes that would immediately convey that she knew I was merely listening politely while dismissing the real signicance that she assigned to each sentence rolling off of her tongue. Another option would be to do what I have all too often seen other academics do and insist on setting wrongheaded opponents straight by insisting on the facts. Adopting a pose of displayed profundity, I could wow her into submission by reciting social scientic understandings of the events and their signicance leading up to the war. I could go on for some length about imperialism, colonialism, racism, and state-produced propaganda. I might even secure the victory by researching and presenting statistics illustrating differences between the reality of the American governments behavior and its propaganda claims. There may be still more options (we might admit that we are both partly correct or that we are both completely wrong), but my point remains, if we stick to a structuralist interpretation of existence, there is an essential reality to the events leading up to, and surrounding, the dropping of the bombs, and the argument is over whose account comes closest to truthfulness. On the other hand, if I take a poststructuralist and more humble position, I can be comfortable with Friedrich Nietzsches (1882/1974:32) counsel that conclusions are consolations. There is more than enough room in life for Margaret (who lived very different and longer years than myself) and I to have completely different understandings, and even to celebrate these differences. Understanding that things are more complex than quests for underlying structure can seriously allow for, provides us with a far richer basis for practicing sociology and for doing politics. Perhaps it also suggests the appropriateness and intelligence of genuine respect for the experiences and wisdom of an elder. Recall that our goal in this section is to illustrate why poststructuralist analyses provide for greater political efcacy than do more traditional social scientic quests to verify empirical reality. We now need to add a few more analytic tools. This will take several pages, but by the end of the chapter we will come back to recollect Margarets sense of history within our poststructuralist analysis.
De-centering Subjectivity (Person-hood) A few pages back, I argued that I (as an author or a father) lack structure. I maintained that my subjectivity is unstable and continuously reconstructed. Lets now extend this de-centering to our sociology courses and to the disciplinary training we receive there.
| 23
The New World held countless marvels that severely disrupted this theretofore neatly cataloged, European existence. Before the late fteenth and sixteenth centuries, no known European had ever seen a skunk, tasted corn, heard a Native American language, or smelled the many strange trees, plants, and owers of the Americas. Adding to this confusion, Galileo used his telescope to see beyond the known heavens, and Copernicus and Kepler had asserted that the earth and planets orbit the sun. Long relied upon imagery, including nothing less than the physical locations of heaven and hell, were thrown into doubt. It is this environment of epistemological disarray as well as the resulting intellectual self-doubt that Descartes attempts to conquer.5 The scholastics (the Aristotelian Christians) had gone wrong because they assumed that existence made sense only if one rst understood the logic of the big picture. These medievals assumed that pieces of existence were meaningful because they t deductively within larger, older, and established understandings, and, surmised Descartes, it was their failure to adequately interrogate these grand systems that produced their horrendous errors. Although a devout Christian who was careful not to offend the Church Fathers, Descartes was also inuenced by Plato. By his lifetime, Latin translations of long-lost Platonic dialogues were impacting the intellectual classes of Western Europe. In the pages of these dialogues, Descartes heard Plato call for systematic knowledge of the true forms of the things themselves. To free himself from the elaborate prejudices of the previous centuries, he must doubt everything. Accurate understandings of larger existence depended upon disciplining the self. (Students will recognize this sentiment in their professors encouragement to make a contribution to the discipline.) It is difcult to overstate the impact that Descartes has had on modern, Western knowledge forms. His self-interrogation in the discipline-enshrined pursuit of certainty was almost manic. For example, in his Meditations on First Philosophy ([1641/1984]1994), Descartes allows his readers into the privacy of his study for an up close look at the rigorous, inward-turned skepticism that he heaps upon himself. In an all-out and self-torturing attempt to purify his mental capacity, Descartes says that he will stop his ears, shut his eyes, withdraw all senses, and eliminate all images of bodily things. As for those worldly understandings that he cannot nally purge, he will force himself to regard them as vacuous, false, and worthless (24). Like glimpses into neuroses, for more than sixty pages Descartes treats us to a desperate self-abuse of his perceptions, at one point even contemplating whether he really exists, or whether some demon is at work making him think that he can think. In the end, he falls back upon the only things he is sure of: his God and the goodness of his God. . . . I know by experience that there is in me a faculty of judgment which, like everything else which is in me, I certainly received from
| 25
success, these attempts continue; the old and Western disdain for the self, and the discipline this self-loathing perpetuates, remains active. Only in the last four decades of the twentieth century (with the exception of Nietzsche who was horribly alone in his own era) do we nd thinkers who seriously question the entirety of this metaphysical, theologically inspired, structuralist project. I have already said that poststructuralists understand subjectivity to be a complex effect. Our short discussion of the ongoing impact of Descartes project and the intellectual concerns of his time illustrate how and why this is the case. Descartes self-interrogation and attempt at self-discipline is one important part of the history of scientic subjectivity. Modern subjectivity is, in part, a Cartesian effect. Yet, and as we will see in chapter 2, this notion that there exists an I (a faculty, mind, ego, etc.) that predates its experiences, or any context where it would arrive only later, is much older than Descartes. One need only consider the Christian concept of eternal soul or read the words Plato placed in Socrates mouth to appreciate the ancient origins of what Derrida has for the past forty years called metaphysics of presence. The modern scientist must dream that s/he is (at least in principle) capable of taking on a purity of form that allows her to correctly assess objective reality. S/he must have a stable basis for gathering knowledge. Thus the idea of empirical verication requires that the subject (the knower) be understood as a nonproduced presence. The scientic self must be whole and selfcontained before and after any particular context where it lives for a time. Because if the personhood of the scientist is always only a complex outcome rooted in the many and specic contingencies of her life, her perceptions have no hope of approaching the objective truth that s/he aspires to. If s/he is an effect of long making, an amalgamation of countless and innumerable episodes of social engineering (her failures, triumphs, loves, hatreds, gains, losses, and the appraisals of her authority gures), her subjectivity can never be completely present in any place or moment. Her self is made of affairs that are not present in the instant when she seeks to do her science. The episodes of her life are not physically or temporally present in her research settings, but they are the possibility of her understandings. The history and ongoing construction of her self is far too complex to be controlled for by any regimen of discipline, by any epistemological stance, or by any research design. The Cartesian and scientic attempt to purify the faculty of judgment can never succeed because this faculty can never be simply present to itself, in all of its signicance, all at once. Subjectivity can never be centralized (found whole) in a comprehensive presence. Unless we too agree to believe in Descartes God, the self is not theologically awarded, and it can never succeed in making itself into a metaphysical essence. My point is not that our scientist has rst of all a pure subjectivity and that life then colors this self in innumerable and unpredictable ways. This would only be a reiteration of the primacy of Descartes pure faculty that would allow us to hold out hope for one day arriving (through discipline) at a purity
| 27
place, enough control over the scattered and complex makeup of my (and thus is it really mine?) self to provide a foundation for the gathering and accumulation of truth? The complexity that is the very possibility of any subjectivity is perhaps limitless. It is certainly more than any discipline or piety can hope to control and domesticate. I sometimes relate this to my own students by telling them that they cannot push the same bus they are riding in. If disciplinary selfovercoming is to remain an ethos in European-derived civilizations (for knowledge making or entrance to heaven or overcoming self-indulgence), then it is an unrealizable one. One cannot interrogate, evaluate, and subjugate the social origins of ones self from anyplace other than the unstable perspectives of that same self. I can only evaluate my biases by invoking biases. Because the attempt to discipline ones scientic subjectivity for the purpose of gathering knowledge is already an effect, an outcome of quite researchable political disputes (some of which can be revisited in the pages of Descartes works), then a truly diligent Cartesian is faced with trying to eliminate the prejudices that are the very possibility of the Cartesian project. In other words, the Cartesian attempt to nullify historical contingency in the quest for epistemological certainty is, itself, a historical and cultural contingency.
Appreciating Margaret on Terms Other than My Own Clay Dumont de-centered is a consciousness that recognizes the scattered, overlapping, mutating, unstable conditions of its possibility. A de-centered subjectivity understands the impossibility of self-possession and even learns to enjoy the feeling. My father once told me that people are like the innity of reections that can be seen when we stand between two mirrors. I think that this is as good an analogy as any I have since come across. If we can imagine that each of the reections built upon the one prior to it are not exact replications but rather the variety and differences of perception one encounters in everyday living, then my fathers mirror illustration is a ne one. I am a reection not just of my life but also of those lives who react to me, who mirror myself back to me. I am also the lineage of faded and difcult to see reections that originated long before I had life (complex assemblages of reections that harbor no coherent theological or metaphysical pattern). Surely then it is folly to attempt to identify any center of my (again I have to point out the mistake of claiming possession) self. Margaret and I, as social and historical effects, shared much social genealogy. Like me, she spoke and read English; she was taught to pay attention to many of the same historical events, although from rather different history books; she watched some of the same television programs and often read the same newspapers; we shared an understanding of many customs, traditions, holidays, and of social etiquette. Because we shared all of this, and were able
| 29
a metaphysical center meant that Margaret and I could become fast friends. Defending a center always makes one less amenable to hearing the voices of those defending their own, alternative foundations.
After the Center Structuralism requires a center. We have just recounted Descartes attempt to cultivate a self through extreme discipline. We stressed this important cultural event as an attempt to forge an epistemological center. In the end, we noted, Descartes dream of a fully present faculty (mind) could only be sustained through his faith in his God. Structure can be imagined to be coherent only because it is thought to have a central framework that governs its outlying parts. For example, if I cannot center my reading of a map by locating myself relative to the center of the depicted area, the map is of little use to me. Similarly, one cannot understand any particular Marxian perspective without rst understanding the central notions of dialectical change, materialism, and the labor theory of value. These concepts center Marxian thought. The quality of having structure requires a center. Otherwise in any analysis, the denitions that are insisted upon, the lines of logical reasoning that are sketched out, and the analytic divisions that are detailed have no common point of reference to substantiate their relations, each to the other. Yet, there are many ways to draw a map, many ways to understand labor and production, and innite ways to make sense of living and of the self. To insist on the indispensability of any particular center, or of centering itself, is to deny this innite complexity. We are now ready to revisit Derridas words cited in the opening pages of this chapter. Here is the whole quote again. The center is at the center of totality, and yet, since the center does not belong to the totality (is not part of the totality), the totality has its center elsewhere. The center is not the center. The concept of centered structurealthough it represents coherence itself, the condition of the episteme as philosophy or scienceis contradictorily coherent (1966/1978/:279). Derrida says, The center is at the center of totality. In other words, not only does every structure require a center, but it also requires borders, limits, and outlying areas. The center of the map can be recognized as such only because it is equidistant from each edge of the page, and the edges constitute the borders, the totality of the maps structure. Likewise, the central premises of any theory are recognizable only because limits to theoretical scope are also recognized. For example, if some well-known Marxian scholar decided tomorrow that Marxists should begin focusing on urban water quality or on the energy conversion efciency of hybrid vegetables, cries of consternation would be heard immediately within communities of Marxists. These are no doubt interesting and important topics, the critics would say, but they are too far outside the eld of the central
| 31
trying to free a proposed center from the extended contingencies of living, authority can only always call upon hopelessly contingent understandings. The condition of structuralist trutha centercan never be isolated from all that constantly threatens to reveal it as a merely contingent set of denitions, denitions that themselves always rely on still other far-reaching contingent denitions for their own comprehensibility. Attempts to dene a would-be epistemological center, then, can never succeed. Thus, as Derrida says, the coherence of epistemology is based on contradiction; it is contradictorily coherent. It is a metaphysicians dream.
Summary I have argued that poststructuralism is difcult to comprehend because it calls into question building block assumptions of Western knowledge. Subjects (knowers) and objects (the known) have no inherent structure or essence. Because they can only be understood through the extended instability of human narration, interpretation, and re-collection, they are not empirically veriable. Things and people have meaning only because they can be related to meanings and understandings that lie beyond their (apparent) presences. Because they must endlessly refer to what they are not to understand what they are, subjects and objects cannot be isolated and understood as per the Cartesian project. Every attempt to center understanding in a wholly present (thus metaphysical) mind or faculty must contradict itself. The I, and thus the objects it assesses, cannot be reduced to an a priori presence. From this it follows that sociologists who strive to negate or hide the political bases and consequences of their science are engaged in what is perhaps the most political of all actsthat of persuading others to adhere to their faith. Structuralist pursuits, because they can never achieve nality, are potentially limitless in terms of the intellectual energy they can consume. In chapter 2 we look at some of the ancient origins of Western subjectivity and knowledge making. The modern, structuralist assumptions that continue to govern the business of professional sociology have very old, deeply embedded, cultural roots. Consistent with C. Wright Millss (1959) assessment of the promise of sociology, chapter 2 helps us understand the scientic self as the complicated outcome of much larger and older social forces.
2
a genealogy of the scientific self
Plato? Did the wicked Socrates corrupt him after all? Could Socrates have been a corrupter of youth after all? And have deserved his hemlock?
Friedrich Nietzsche (1886/1990:32)
ur contemporary selfhood has an ancient but traceable genealogy. Europeans have not always understood themselves to be free-thinking, unied, self-responsible, extra-contextual beings. And people who were unlike our modern, Western version of personhood populated most of the worlds cultures dating across the ages in which humans have inhabited the planet. Our modern selves are profoundly Greek and Christian in heritage. Thus the scientic self that seeks to discipline itself for the purpose of gathering knowledge is a sociological phenomenon. Social scientists selfunderstandings are rooted in the ancient cultural politics of the Mediterranean region. Because sociology as a science depends upon the uncontested status of modern subjectivity, few sociologists have honestly explored its social development. Certainly many social theorists, from Emile Durkheim to George Mead to Erving Goffman, have been interested in the self; but almost none (including these famous three) ever seriously entertained the idea that modern, Western subjectivity could be other than basic to the human species. Although sociologists and anthropologists have always understood that other peoples in other times and places viewed themselves in unique ways, the selfperceptions of cultural others were, and are thought to be, underdeveloped, irrational, or superstitious. In contrast, the modern, Western, rational self is understood as a developed, progress-based, outcomeone that other peoples eventually arrive at.1
| 33
In addition to its sheer ethnocentrism, this outlook never seriously considers how the social history of their own version of personhood is implicated in what social scientists think they know. This unwillingness to rethink modern subjectivity as a cultural and political outcome means that the structural sociologist persists in his quest to empirically verify an objectively present reality. The scientist who does not de-center his subjectivity continues to insist that his observations are reections of a real world of essences and truths. On the other hand, if this desire to objectively approximate reality is understood to be rooted in a version of personhood that is itself the complex product of time, place, and culture, then pursuing fully present essences begins to lose its appeal. Said more simply, what one thinks one knows is entirely related to what one thinks oneself to be. Modern, structuralist sociology is possible only because of the assumed and taken-for-granted versions of selfhood that sociologists live with. Destabilizing this subjectivity by exploring its sociological development changes how we think about the sociology we do. Where did this Cartesian faculty, this mind, this self-present intellect derive from? What politics spawned it? What were the cultural conditions of possibility from whence it was born? In short, what ancient genealogy does it conceal?
Inventing the Psyche The mind and the mind-versus-body form of the self did not begin appearing in Greece until the late fth century bc. As Eric A. Havelock (1963:197) describes this situation, in the last twenty-ve years of the fth century the notion was not understood by the majority of men and in their ears the terms in which it was expressed sounded bizarre. Thus as Bruno Snell (1953:16) observes, the belief in the existence of a universal, uniform human mind is a rationalist prejudice. In the time and spoken language of Homer (ca. 950 bc), there was as yet no deep thinking, and never in his recounting of past experiences does Homer attempt to sound their special, non-physical nature (Snell 1953:18). People and things in Homeric Greece were not knowable as ideas. Their specic and physical activity in specic and physical living was their calling card; they possessed no generic, extra-contextual essences. Among the generations before Socrates (Socrates lived from 469 to 399 bc), the body is not even understood as a unied system. Rather, it appears in the Homeric texts as an assemblage of distinct parts (Hirst and Woolley 1982:123). So where we might say his body, Homer says his limbs. Nor is this pre-Socratic subjectivity, which lacks the notion of intellect, a selfresponsible person-hood, at least in the modern sense of the term. Humans are more akin to a location or ending point for the intrusion of dreams, Gods, or various (what appear to us to be) supernatural forces, than autonomous generators of their own behaviors (Dodds 1951:17; Hirst and Woolley 1982:12324).2
| 35
sensual life. Indeed, Homer does not even have a term for person or oneself. These would be abstractions depicting a self that exists independent of lived life, and he has no use for these extra-contextual notions. He does not even possess generic terms for depicting gender: man, woman, male, and female (Simon 1978:61). This is a culture where people and things behave and not one where they are (Cornford 1932/1976:89). As Havelock (1986:94) explains, a spade digs but it is never an implement designed for excavation. People and things do and live but they do not have an is quality to them. The notion that people and things have an abstract beingness or essence is an invention of Socratic and Platonic dialectic, which in ancient Greek meant what modern English calls dialogue. Possessing nothing written by Socrates, what we know of him comes from later literate philosophers, primarily from Plato. Although the execution of Socrates probably occurred when Plato was in his late twenties, he remained an enduring character in the dialogues that Plato authored. It is interesting to consider the fact that Plato wrote dialogues; that is, he used his written alphabet to depict oral conversations. A kind of oral hangover remained, even as the educated classes of Platos Greece had become literate. When this transformation was occurring, during Socrates lifetime, educated Greeks for the rst time were able to see written accounts of oral recollections collected together on the page. This meant that it became possible not just to repeat oral narrations that maintained sensual experiences and memories. With written script, the reader visually sees narrations of more than one event at a time. Because a literate person can read of Odysseus adventures, he can place these experiences side by side in his line of vision and nd similarities and differences. With literacy, then, comes the feeling (slowly at rst) that people and things may have consistency that can migrate from experiential context to experiential context. If I can see, at the same moment, because of the technology of reading, that Odysseus does this and does that and does something else, then I begin to suspect that Odysseus is. Odysseus becomes an abstraction that has existence in excess of the scenes where he lives and feels. Rather than know of Odysseus adventures by allowing the storyteller to help me feel the places where he was (the temperature to my skin, the wind in my hair, the smell of the ocean in my nose, and the heat of the blood from my wounds), I now place individual contexts or episodes from his life one next to the other and compare and contrast them.3 Literacy brought profound sociological transformation to ancient Greece. Because Greek oral society relied upon strong memories, poets were the information storehouses of their time. They were the keepers of the past, of the mythos (of the stories) that functioned as statements of ethos (of the successes and failures of the ancestors). And they tailored this crucial social function to the needs of their listeners bodies. Rhyme and meter were used for their rhythmic qualities, for the beat and tempo that the body of the listener could participate in. Remember, the goal of a good oral storyteller is to
| 37
forces the boy away from feeling Homers stories vicariously and back to himself (his extra-contextual, abstract self) as a self-responsible agent: now do you know what I mean? and do you call him courageous? (Laches 19192, my emphases). These dialogues, this dialectical format, are designed as the antidote to the spell casting of the poets. Indeed, in The Sophist Plato compares this crossexamination to the duty of a physician who expelled the notions within him which obstruct his learning, thus reducing him to a puried condition (230). In dialogue, there is no time in between questions, answers, and more questions for the mood, and the context of a story to envelop the setting. Dialectic breaks the power of the storyteller by disrupting the rhythm that threatens to transport the listener into the time and the place woven by the story. In this way dialectic preserves the idea (and this is a Platonic notion) of things and people as essences that exist before and after the physical contexts they inhabit. The modern words idea and ideal come down to us from Platos Greece. Plato tells us that the good (as in ideal) is tantamount to the essences of things. (Latin translations of the Greek idea become forma or the Forms.) Ideas are (as they remain today) abstractions. But in Socratess day, the notion of an idea emphasized the core forms of things extricated from the tales of the poets. Thus there are many kinds of boats existing in many different contexts and stories, but there is only one essential quality: boat-ness. Now it is not far from the proposing of essential forms (of ideals) to the claim that morality is related to knowledge of these forms. And, indeed, Plato tells us that the Good is contained in the true forms of the world of things. Remember that we are not talking about things as they appear to the senses but about the essences of things as they are understood by what Socrates and Plato called psyche. Although the word is older than Socrates, its evolving meaning becomes institutionalized in the teachings that Plato credits him with. The older word referred to the living breath or to the blood of life, but these signications as yet contained no hint of self-consciousness. As F. N. Cornford (1932/1976:50) describes this understanding, the ordinary Athenian thought of his soulhis psycheas an airy unsubstantial wraith . . . a shadow that, at the moment of death . . . escaped as a breath to be dissipated like smoke in the air. Only later does Platos Socrates instruct that the psyche is akin to a ghost that thinks and that this abstract being should be understood as the seat of moral responsibility (Havelock 1963:197). The abstract, contextually independent self that is institutionalized in Platos dialogues, and that arrives with Greek literacy and in opposition to the oral tradition, is a condition of possibility of modern, scientic personhood as well as of the quest for (abstract) morals. The invention of the psyche, then, changes not only Greece but also eventually most of the world. It becomes the possibility and basis of classical Greek philosophy. (The Greek phil means lover and sophia means wisdom; thus a philosopher is a lover of wisdom.) Platos dialogues are lled with Socratic calls to know thy
In this and in many similar passages, Plato fundamentally links his contrived world of metaphysical abstractions (being dwells without color or shape, that cannot be touched) to a grand morality (justice, its very self, and likewise temperance, and knowledge). The Platonic psyche alone, we are told, can discern the veritable knowledge of being that veritably is. Only the
| 39
disciplined and abstract mind can know essences, and these essences are, for Plato, tantamount to the Good. One approaches divinity by disciplining the body and the emotions and thereby embracing the ideal, which are essences (forms) available only to the mind and not to the senses. Knowledge of the divine (of the good) provides one with a recipe for healthy living. Indeed, Plato tells us (rather ominously) that this veritable knowledge of being that veritably is must be shared with the less enlightened. In The Republic, he links knowledge of the abstract forms to light and sunshine that are known only upon ascending from the depths of a darkened cave of shadows. It is our job as lawgivers, he maintains, to compel the best minds to attain . . . the highest form of knowledge, and to ascend to the vision of the good . . . and when they have achieved this and see well enough, to prevent them behaving as they are now allowed to do (519). Thus Greek philosophy is a fundamental precursor to Christians claims that they have a mission to save the unenlightened from themselves. By the fth century ad, St. Augustine had published The City of God against Pagans (426/1998:14) in which he explains, even the pious should know bitterness in this life if they neglected to be bitter to the wicked. St. Augustine and the other early Church Fathers were heavily inuenced by classical Greece, and by Plato in particular. The theological notion that Christians and Christianity have a hold on truth and a direct contact line to God is rooted in Greek philosophy. The self-aggrandizing zeal of Christian missionaries was nowhere more clearly foretold than in Socrates unapologetic lecture to his accusers, as his life hangs in the balance: . . . it is my belief that no greater good has ever befallen you in this city than my service to my God. For I spend all my time going about trying to persuade you, young and old (Apology 16). As I suggested in the opening pages of the chapter, what one thinks oneself to be is the very possibility of what one thinks s/he knows.
Greek Foundations of Christianity Despite what many modern scientists like to believe, science is unable to cut itself off from two thousand years of Christian cosmology. Christianity remained the basis of Western knowing techniques for roughly fteen centuries. Scientists have only proclaimed (at least publicly) their independence from theology since the nineteenth century, and the metaphysical bases of scientic sociology are still quite Christian. Thus it is important for us to understand (as part of our genealogy of modern subjectivity) some of how classical Greek metaphysics impacted the early Christian church. The church itself (as an institution in a central location with a status hierarchy) does not yet exist in the rst centuries after Christ. Early on, Christianity was something that was practiced by informal small groups and in homes. Sociologists who study religion tell us that early Christianity was a sect or
| 41
as if someone had given me a map for self-appraisal, and I had thereby gained the ability to keep track of my score on some ultimate (extra-earthly) examination card. If God has a purpose for everything, then everything in existence is organized in terms of that purpose. If this plan can be understood (through purication of the self), then existence and life have a discernible order and logic to them. They have a centered structure that I can use to govern and assess my behavior. Similarly, the second term, teleology, is derived from the Greek telos and also refers to an ultimate purpose or nal meaning. Greek philosophy places a uniform purpose into existence (Platos Good), and this purpose is said to be progressively unearthed by those with critical, dialectical mindsthat is to say, by philosophers. This too is metaphysical structure. An unobservable endpoint or culminating, nite logic in existence is assumed, and each of the essential forms of all of the pieces of reality are said to t in an ordered way into this grand plan that correct, disciplined thinking will slowly reveal. In this way, Greek teleology is a model for Christian eschatology. Once Plato infuses existence with eternal and perfect essences, it follows that they are nite in number. If the Creator, as the source of the Good, is perfect, then, of course, he has only placed as many essential forms on the earth as can t in exact fashion. Arthur O. Lovejoy (1936/1965) refers to this positing of a nite structure to existence as a metaphysics of plenitude. That is to say, because existence has essential pieces, and because they t together perfectly in a nite, systematic, and overall structure, patterned structure lls existence. It has complete plenitude (plenty). And indeed, with the Greeks (primarily in the work of Platos student Aristotle) we nd the rst great attempt to catalog the whole of existence into its most basic and substantial patterns. The molders of the early Christian church were thoroughly indoctrinated into these Greek structuralist ideas: essential components making up a nite existence, perfect plenitude in their numbers, and divine planning in their organization that becomes evident at a grand conclusion (self-knowledge, philosophical perfection, death, and the Second Coming of Christ). The core metaphysical tenets of Christianity can be found centuries earlier in the Greek philosophical model. Cornford (1932/1976:65) goes so far as to declare, Plato and Aristotle are among the greatest fathers of the Christian Church. . . . [T]hey might have been canonized in the Middle Ages, had they not happened to be born some centuries before the Christian era. The so-called Patristic Period (through the fourth century) of Christianity is a time when the Church Fathers manage to establish organization, hierarchy, and a degree of uniformity in theological teachings. In this period the church becomes an institution. Clement (150220 ad) reportedly used Greek political ideals as his model for organizing the new church community (Jaeger 1961:21). Origen (185254 ad) and Clement lived in a time when Christians referred to Plato as the Divine Plato who, they believed, had revealed the very Word of God (Jaeger 1961:44,46). They were quite aware of the fact that
Scientic Subjectivity: A Descendant of Greek and Christian Personhood In his last work, Laws (645), Plato writes of the doctrine of a god. In asserting that the philosopher alone is able to discern the order of the universe, he uses the Greek word logos. Logos is the Creators plan expressed. It is the reasoning (the doctrine) that orders existence. Thus it is simultaneously the voice of God and the order of existence revealed. Similarly, for Christians the logos or word of God is revealed to those who make themselves ready to be inhabited by the spirit of God (by the Holy Spirit). As the philosopher
| 43
disciplines his body to develop his mind, the Christian ascetic elevates guilt to a weapon of defense against himself as he strives to cleanse his soul. Thus Christ, as the Son of God, reveals the Holy Logos or Word of God, and he teaches his followers how to behave in the world so that this logos may be revealed to them. The Platonic Good and Christian Truth are both revealed in the word (logos) of the Creator and both can be known only through rigorous self-discipline and self-denial. The modern word logic is a direct etymological (etymology is the study of the history of words) descendant of the Greek and Christian logos. It is not difcult to recognize how our modern sense of the word, as in the logic of things, and as revealed in the sufx attached to many of the sciences (e.g., socio-logy, psycho-logy, anthropo-logy), descends directly from our Christian, intellectual ancestors and from their Greek predecessors. The quest for the divine logos revealed through the Holy Spirit will become a scientic quest for the logic contained in the parts and organization of the Creation. We need only look to the theological inspiration of any of the fathers of modern science to reawaken these afliations. Together with those of Descartes and Galileo, the writings of Sir Francis Bacon (15611626) are among the most inuential in the development of the scientic method. Bacon was both a devout Christian and a proponent of an inductive style of knowledge. As noted in chapter 1, during the Middle Ages Western Christendom was deeply rooted in Aristotelian philosophy. This scholastic style of theology tended to be deductive, starting from knowledge of the logos and tting the pieces of the world into an already understood eschatological/teleological scheme. Knowledge for the Aristotelian Christians was knowledge of things as they t into the larger Chain of Being and this grand system building had been weakened by the telescope, the New World, and by a growth in intellectual debate across national borders and languages.6 Thus Bacon urged knowledge of things rst. To be inductive means to build the larger understanding from the smaller, to understand the whole of the Divine Plan by rst understanding the smaller pieces of the Creation. It is from within this attempt to overcome the deductive and grandiose web spinning of Aristotelians that Bacon emerges as the central gure in the development of experimental methodology and thus of the notion that knowledge advances and accumulates. Science that attempts to build truth from small-scale, individual experiments one piece at a time can be replicated and argued over with much more precision than whole grand cosmic schemes can be debated. In the Advancement of Learning (1605/1952), Bacon quotes from the Scriptures often and regularly, sometimes several times on the same page. In this monumental work that George A. Kourvetaris (1994:314) calls the most inuential book on learning of the seventeenth century, he leaves no doubt that his attack on the schools of Aristotelians is a Christian endeavor. . . . laying before us two books or volumes to study, if we will be secured from
| 45
lamenting the limits, the horrible sensual prejudices of human subjectivity. The self-disdain of Plato and of earlier generations of Christians remains pivotal to the self-conception of the seventeenth-century, European, man of science. The ascetic Christian who cleansed himself of bodily passions thereby allowing the Holy Spirit to reveal Gods word will become a scientic ascetic who also seeks enlightened truth through self-discipline. For the mind of man is far from the nature of a clear and equal glass, wherein the beams of things should reect according to their true incidence; nay, it is rather like an enchanted glass, full of superstition and imposture, if it not be delivered and reduced (Bacon 1605/1952:60). Induction, because it means concentration upon the unitary and not upon the all-inclusive and totalizing, permits the opportunity to repeatedly test results obtained by the senses. My mind need not be enchanted by the senses if I can enlist the help of other scientists and of mechanical instruments to replicate my ndings. Bacon is out to nd God, but he is out to locate him in the detailed logic of his most minuscule workings. And he will not be fooled by a wily nature (full of . . . imposture) that appeals to the senses, pleasures, and superstitions and that his God has instructed him to subdue. This scientic discipline remains Christian asceticism, but it is asceticism aided by inductive method and technology. Aristotelian Christians failed not because they did not understand the dangers of the senses but because their weakness of intellectual powers allowed for deceit that should have been overcome in the manner of collecting and concluding upon the reports of the senses (Bacon 1605/1952:58). A ruler or compass is always more steady than the hand, Bacon tells us, and mechanical instruments must whenever possible be employed to keep watch on the senses. Without the aid of outside, human and nonhuman verications of measurement, the great and wonderful works of God will continue to be shrouded in superstition and imposture (20). Without replication and investigation at the most immediate level (and this is to become the modern scientic quest for only the facts),8 Enlightenment-era scientists will, like their medieval predecessors, rest only in the contemplation of the exterior of them as they rst offer themselves to the senses (20). And in our negligence, we should do a like injury unto the majesty of God, as if we should judge or construe of the store of some excellent jeweller, by that only which is set out toward the street in his shop (20). Bacon, as a father of the scientic ethos, teaches that Christian self-denial and self-purication must be stepped-up, enhanced, and given explicit rigor. Gods truth is hidden in the sensual appeal of a prejudicing natural world (like jewels enchanting the eyes). It would do him an injustice if we did not pursue his creations beyond their sparkle and appeal to the senses (beyond that which is visible or set out toward the street). Thus Christian asceticism becomes the methodological discipline of scientic exploration.
| 47
My goal in this chapter has been more than simple recovery of the cultural and thus theological conditions of the possibility of scientic subjectivity. I want to substantiate claims I began advancing in the introduction and in chapter 1. First, I assert that the desires and techniques of modern, structuralist sociologists mimic theological desires and metaphysical dreams of earlier generations of Christian intellectuals. Second, I claim that these desires rest on a subjectivity, assumed and unquestioned by modern scientic sociologists, which uncritically replays the metaphysical asceticism (a self-disdain) of ancient Platonism and of Christian theologya theological metaphysics that most scientists want to believe they have left behind. Finally, I am asserting that those critics claiming that poststructuralism renders sociologists politically impotent assume these same Greek and Christian imperatives. In other words, because these critics fail to examine the sociological origins of their own normative needs they take for granted that these aspirations are necessary to any affective sociology. Perhaps the most unrecognized yet commonly recited of our Christian inheritances are the following interrelated notions: that we, as scientic sociologists, are in disciplined pursuit of a difcult to uncover world of essential truths, and that these truths are arranged systematically (as patterns, rules, laws, or some other form of internal logic) in some grand, teleological scheme. Consider, for example, the perennially inuential words of Peter Berger (1963/2005) reprinted into a theory course textbook by Joel N. Charon (2005:7): It can be said that the rst wisdom of sociology is thisthings are not what they seem. This too is a deceptively simple statement. It ceases to be simple after a while. Social reality turns out to have many layers of meaning. The discovery of each new layer changes the perception of the whole. . . . In a matter-of-fact tone that suggests the uncontroversial status of his assertion (the rst wisdom of sociology), Berger speaks of many layers that is, in itself, deceptive simplicity, and is thus an understated assessment. There are many layers, so many that some are yet to be discovered; and [T]he discovery of each new layer changes the perception of the whole. Now recall the words of Bacon: it is the duty and virtue of all knowledge to abridge the innity of individual experiences; and, we must remedy the complaint of vita brevis, ars longa; which is performed by uniting the notions and conceptions. . . . The metaphysical inheritance could not be clearer. Berger urges us on to discoveries of the layers that are not what they seem in pursuit of the whole. Bacon likens any failure to pursue these layers to a construal of the store of some excellent jeweller, by that only which is set out toward the street in his shop. Inductively, the whole appears from knowledge of the parts. The parts (including and in excess of that which is visible from the street, or the layers that change our conception of the whole) are arranged according to the logic of the totality (Bacons store and Bergers whole). Berger, and presumably
| 49
and that this inhabitation transformed their very beings, helping them to see in a new light the very world where they too had lived all of their lives. In a tone that sounds hauntingly evangelical, Berger tells us that this new light begotten of scientic integrity is so powerful that it constitutes a transformation of consciousness (6). Because of the strength of this transformation a good sociologist, will nd himself unable to resist this new light. It will, Berger says, have so taken possession of him that he has little choice but to seek for answers (1963/2005:6). Recall that both Platos Socrates and St. Gregory of Nyssa called for such transformations (morphosis and metamorphosis, respectively) in pursuit of a more enlightened moral order. Thus it appears that this scientic self-transformation in pursuit of truth strongly resembles an act of Christian confession. As we know, Christians have for millennia included the confession in their rituals of self-discipline in the pursuit of self-purity. In the Gospel According to St. Mark, we hear that John the Baptist is sent to baptize in the wilderness so as to prepare . . . the way of the Lord (1:4) This baptism is to be a baptism of repentance and a remission of sins (1:4). To prepare the way for the truth of God, John is said to have baptized all the land of Judaea, and they of Jerusalem; all went in the river Jordan, confessing their sins(1:5). Similarly, in Peter (1:16) we are implored to Confess your faults one to another, and pray for one another, that ye may be healed(emphasis in original). For, we are told, the effectual fervent prayer of a righteous man availeth much (1:16). The institutionalization of the Christian confession became a major force in the fashioning of Western personhood. The writings of the early Church Fathers are full of calls to public humility and to the visible and expository renunciation of self-indulgence. As Michel Foucault (1997:22527) discovered in his study of these ancient works:
As verbalization brings to the external light the deep movement of the thought, it also leads, by the same process, the human soul from the reign of Satan to the law of God. This means that verbalization is a way for the conversion (for the rupture of the self), for the conversion to develop itself and to take effect. Since the human being was attached to himself under the reign of Satan, verbalization as a movement toward God is a renunciation to Satan, and a renunciation to oneself. Verbalization is a self-sacrice. . . . And we have to understand this sacrice . . . as the consequence of a formula like this: you will become the subject of the manifestation of truth when and only when you disappear or you destroy yourself as a real body or as a real existence.
If Foucaults reading is accurate, then why should we not accept that the Christian call to renounce the sensual self (to confession of sins) in the pursuit of Gods logos is the cultural prototype of the scientic call to purge ones rational self of all things personal, emotional, and judgment clouding in the pursuit of the logic of existence?10 Nonetheless, and often in tones of anger
| 51
Christian theology and classical Greek philosophy? And, if I am right in this assertion, why should we continue to believe that creating a better world requires us to defend these old superstitions? We can also nd the restoration of the Garden of Eden imagery (the linking of metaphysical truth and moral politics) that gured so prominently in Bacons era functioning in the self-descriptions of modern, structuralist sociologists, including those of Professor Turner. Throughout the European centuries since Platos philosopher kings were assigned to rule in his ideal Republic and since Church Fathers claimed to hear Gods words, speakers of foundational truths have claimed to know not just the fundamental and ordered structures of existence, but also (because of their special, unique, discipline-delivered knowledge) the best way to put this knowledge to use obtaining salvation and happiness. To claim as Platos Socrates did that the discovery of things as they truly are is a good common to all mankind (Charmides 166) and that only the philosopher is qualied to access these things as they truly are is to think very highly of oneself and ones abilities. Similarly, to claim to know the Word of God, and to know how to behave and how not to behave so as to hear and correctly interpret his words (as Christian leaders have done for centuries), is to claim tremendous power for oneself. How, then, should we interpret Turners (1998a:249) lament that we fail to live up to our calling when we do not pursue codied knowledge that will allow us to rightly think of ourselves as social engineers? . . . to the extent sociologists still want to build a better world, they had better begin to think of themselves as social engineers. If we are to give advice and to be listened to, we must gain the respect that comes from having codied knowledge. The advice of a discipline will not be heeded without coherent theories, veried research ndings, and past success at building something that did not fall down. Is not the assertion that a better world will result from truths purchased through unpleasant discipline and the personal sacrice of dedicated ascetics a thoroughly Christian notion? And how far from the zealotry of Christian missionaries have we come? Have we not, for centuries now, been made to listen (often through the force of raw power) to philosophers and theologians who claimed an exclusive right to show us a better way? Why should sociologists accept, uncritically, that our ability to help our fellow beings (our political efcacy) must be tied to this twenty-four-hundred-year-old recitation of self-disdain and metaphysical aspirations? From my poststructuralist perspective, the belief in a world of metaphysical social structure is suspect enough, but then to doggedly persist in the hope that these underlying (Platonist) forms can be veried is simply to maintain (again uncritically) the machinations of theological faith. Worse still, to continue to insist that the less enlightened should heed our codied knowledge is to risk continuing the horrors already visited upon oppressed peoples by centuries of self-assured possessors of metaphysical truth. Sociologists should not be missionaries.
| 53
charging an atheist with making his refusal to believe in God into a newer and better God of the there is no God. Still, like Turner and Hill-Collins, Ward sees no acceptable alternative to continuing the 2,400 year-old pursuit of an essential and structured reality. As he says, without the trust and moral commitment which realism generates, all social interaction and communication would break down under the weight of paranoid suspicion (1997:785). This belief that pursuit of realist truth is a moral imperative that responsible thinkers must defer to is the subject of chapter 3.
Summary My argument thus far is that the longings and techniques of modern, structuralist sociologists assume the theological desires and metaphysical dreams of earlier generations of Greek and Christian thinkers. These assumptions remain unexamined and unacknowledged by the same sociologists who assume that they are imperative to the moral pursuit of political justice. These inheritances include an assumption of (theological and now scientic) dominion; a championing of ascetic discipline; the self-cleansing confession and now scientic expulsion of bias; and an untenable pursuit of singular, nite, and teleological order (structure) in existence. This order, in turn, is assumed to harbor the secrets of moral, ethical life. And nally, intellectuals (Greek, Christian, and now sociological) are asked to spread the faith to the less enlightened. Chapter 3 builds on this argument by adding structuralist sociologists conception of responsibility to our list of Christian inheritances. Remember, our interrogation of this intellectual history is an exercise in sociological imagination. I want us to recognize our scientic biographies as the outcome of much larger political and cultural histories.
3
toward a post-christian ethic of responsibility in sociology
Who will dare call duty a duty that owes nothing, or better . . . that must owe nothing?
Jacques Derrida (1993:17)
ike virtually all sociologists, I want sociology to make a tangible difference in the lives of real people. I certainly share this desire with each of the sociologists discussed in the closing pages of chapter 2: Jonathan H. Turner, Peter Berger, Patricia Hill-Collins, and Steven Ward. Our differences, then, lie in our assumptions about how to best reach this goal and about how we understand this ambition as a form of responsibility. Poststructuralists speak of ethics and politics only as part of a rigorously reexive process. We advocate only with an eye toward thinking through not just the potential effects of our advocacy but also the very possibility of the political and ethical positions we stake out. (To be reexive, you will recall, means to think about the social, political, and historical qualities of our thinkingto think about thinking.) Thus our analysis of the ancient philosophical and theological origins of structuralist desires is crucial to the exploration of alternative (nonfaith-based) motivations for doing sociology that we take up in this chapter. Having now understood (reexively) something of the Greek and Christian metaphysical quests that form the underlying and almost always unexamined assumptions of structuralist sociology, we are now in a position to ask
| 55
ourselves about the possibility of political responsibility in poststructuralist sociology. In other words, if our politics and our ethics do not emanate from a pilgrimage for empirically veriable knowledge of the real world then how can professional sociologists assume any responsibility for improving life on earth? In order to answer this question, we must think carefully about the long history of assumptions involved in the idea of responsibility. The words in the title of this chapter, post-Christian, could easily be misunderstood. What would it mean, after all, to be post-Christian? If the inuence of Christianity on science and sociology is as denitive as I claim, then how could one ever hope to escape it? Furthermore, would not the desire to escape be but another tale of (Greek and/or Christian) deliverance? The post of post-Christian responsibility has to be read in the manner of what Derrida for decades called supplement.1 In part, to supplement means to add or even to differ from (but nonetheless to reference as a starting point) that which already exists. Christianity is too pervasive, too permeating a force in modern cultures to be simply replaced. It can only be supplemented. The very idea of responsibility as we understand it today is absolutely rooted in the development of Christian subjectivity. Although, and as we have already noted, Christianity became a force only because its early proselytizers adapted so well to the Greek language, culture, and philosophy, our modern understanding of personal responsibility is properly much more Christian than Greek.2 While it is true that Platos dialogues contain numerous Socratic references to an ethic of self-knowledge and that the last pages of The Republic are even dedicated to a discussion of the afterlife and the repercussions for an eternal soul of responsible or irresponsible lives led upon earth, it is the God of the Holy Bible who raises the stakes of responsible living to a level of sacrice and desperation. While Platonism promised to lift the mind from the darkness of emotion into the intellectual sun (the Good) and into a realm of fully understood and essential objects (forms); the Christian God requires faith, allegiance, and absolute deferral to his omnipresence. The Christian and Judeo-Christian God is a face, an omnipotent Being who sees and hears all. He is not simply a force (like the Platonic Good) that underlies and animates; he is a Being and a Will that awards love and threatens anger, testing the faith of his subjects. Because the God of the Bible is both omnipresent and omnipotent, he sees me and knows me even when I have (only) momentarily forgotten that he is around. Because his power to watch and judge me is total and inescapable, while my ability to recognize him is limited by my mortality, by my earthly delusions, and by any waning of faith, our relationship is wholly unequal. This dissymmetry between an all-knowing God and those who must fear his judgment is more than mere theology; it is a historical and sociological phenomenon that is a condition of the possibility of our modern pursuits of good conscience and of personal responsibility.
| 57
his only son. The extreme nature of his approaching sacrice testies to his absolute dedication to his Gods plan and to the salvation that he believes awaits him if he remains resolute in his responsibility. Derrida (1995) points out that Abraham does not tell Isaac what he is about to do because he knows that neither the boy nor anyone else (except God, of course) can understand or would even be willing to try to understand why this sacrice must occur. The temptation of Abraham lies partly in the fact that mere humans (Abrahams peers) are not equipped to understand God or his plan. Abraham is not about to do something that he alone nds utterly awful; the murder of his son will also shock and sicken the minds of virtually every other mortal. They will never understand. He must proceed with this responsibility to God (who alone represents infallible certainty and consistency in the universe) in secret. His task is lonely and there are always those who would dissuade him. If he let them, they would help him not do what he already does not want to do. His responsibility, then, is a painfully personal responsibility. The entire experience of anxious, personal responsibility to a general ethics (not the pre-Socratic ethos of orally recollected, corporeal experiences of the ancestors, but the later, Platonic and Christian notion of responsibility to abstract and objective moral principals) is built upon faith in an absolute certainty supplied by an unknowable deity. By acting as the absolute, bedrock, foundation of everything, God acts as the initial and nal centering that allows for notions of general responsibility to be entertained. If Gods face was readily visible and immediately interpretable (if he posted grades and held ofce-hours), then his desires would be easily available to everyone who was properly scared enough to show up, listen, and live accordingly. Everyone would know who was behaving morally (consistent with truth) and who was errant. There could be no personal responsibility in the modern or biblical sense of the term because one would simply programmatically apply, act upon mechanically, and enforce habitually the rules insisted upon by an always immediately present, law-enforcing, gradeposting God. It is only and precisely because the God of the Bible does not often exchange looks with mere mortals that our modern notion of responsibility (as something that requires discipline and sacrice as well as perseverance in the face of skeptics whose will and faith are less stead fast than ones own) has come down to us as it has. Because it is difcult to know what the biblical God intends for me (he speaks rarely and only to the most self-effacing), and because he is capable of extreme anger should his will not be followed, one must always set out, on ones own, to understand and adhere to his holy desires to the very best of ones mortal ability. I may seek the counsel of those who I hope know better than I, but the onus is always upon me personally to live up to his gaze that never sleeps.3 There are always those who would lead me astray, those whose interpretations
Political Responsibility and Sociologists Christian Hangover The parallels between this Judeo-Christian theology and the aspirations of modern, structuralist sociologists are clear. Recall that in the last pages of chapter 2 we encountered numerous references to the moral responsibilities of sociologists. I will not recount the desperate and angry calls for ethical responsibility of the sociologists quoted there. Nonetheless, I do want to reiterate these themes to the extent that they must always be part of any programmatic attempts to spell out a general responsibility for sociology. Again, the goal is to make the dual theological and structuralist qualities of these attempts explicit. To aid me in this review, I call upon a volume written by one of Americas most prolic and inuential authors of sociological theory: George Ritzers (1997) Postmodern Social Theory. Ritzers text displays a desire to be both fair-minded and comprehensive in the midst of what he recognizes as a sociological debate that is far from dispassionate (1997:243). As he says, debates about postmodern social theory
| 59
ordinarily generate an enormous amount of heat (243). Because Ritzers theory texts are so well-known by American sociologists, and because he has worked so very hard in the face of this enormous heat to maintain what he calls a reasonably dispassionate portrayal of postmodern social theory (243), his writing provides an additional and perhaps less emotionally charged example of what we have already noted is a common criticism of poststructuralist scholarship. Although his pages do not scream of ames of postmodern hell or of ethical and moral chaos, as do those of Turner and of Hill-Collins, Ritzer too fears that poststructuralism means the end of political responsibility among sociologists who give in to its temptations. In his concluding chapter, Criticisms of, and the Move Beyond, Postmodernism, Ritzer collects, organizes, and gives voice to critics who pronounce what they believe to be the impossibility of ethical responsibility in poststructuralist sociology. Lacking a normative basis, postmodern social theory tends to encourage a babel of tongues. Such a babel of co-equal voices serves the interests of those in power. . . . With so many conicting viewpoints and no clear adversary, those in power are better able to stay right where they are (1997:247). Ritzer and those he speaks for lament that poststructuralists lack a normative basis. Yet because Ritzer has certainly collected and read the writings of the many thinkers (that he here labels postmodern), it is reasonable to expect that he recognizes the explicitly partisan and specically political (normative) qualities of many, if not most, of these writings. And, indeed, he takes us on a rich tour of the particular political projects of several of these postmodern theorists. So, given Ritzers quite forthright replication of the specically political (one could even say polemical) intentions of these postmodern projects, we can read his frustration (lacking a normative basis) as signaling a disappointment over a lack of a general or comprehensively foundational basis for knowledge and therefore, he thinks, for doing politics. Ritzer wants some location for certainty, some bottom line, an absolute reference point from where to assess how sociologists are fairing in our responsibility to improve lives. He desires a depiction of a proposed perfection, a centering teleological endpoint (the perfect society, perhaps) that our scientic responsibility ought to be dedicated to achieving. Recall he tells us that poststructuralists have no clear adversary. Once again, we have to suspect that he means an adversary who is adversarial because s/he works against some larger, ultimate, and good (normative) society. For, as we just noted, it is clear that he recognizes the specic political antagonists of, for example, Michel Foucault. . . . the reader has no theoretical idea why Foucault is so upset at what he nds in the realms of madness, crime, medicine, and sexuality. That is, in formal terms he fails to offer us a vision of the normative framework (Ritzer 1997:247).
| 61
something other than a desperate duty to an ultimate end and, indeed, an ultimate end that involves (and thus essentially denes) all of us with equal force? De-centering subjectivity means recognizing and abandoning our faith in a biblical God who continues, unexamined and unrecognized, to dictate structuralist sociologists sense of responsibility. If responsibility is no longer conceived of as a duty to know some underlying theological or sociological structure, some Holy Plan or vision of a normative framework, then responsibility is a far more complex and difcult issue to consider. Rejecting theology that centers all persons by cementing them into a personal relationship with a hard-to-know yet singularly authoritative God is not the same thing as ending all sociological interest in the self. This is an important point because Ritzer and many others conclude that a de-centered sociological subjectivity lacks any basis for responsible political activism. Even as they drop any conscious appeal to Christianitys one God, these sociologists insist that something God-like must save them from the babel of tongues. Some metaphysical foundation must be found to ll the void that deism no longer protects them from. The theological structure depicted in the story of Abraham and Issac (a subjectivity dened nally and ultimately by its unwavering faith in, and relation to, a master plan) remains intact. Ritzer (1997:248) reads the poststructuralist rejection of centered subjectivity (of the theological self) as a rejection of an interest in the subject and subjectivity. Because poststructuralists lack a theory of agency, he surmises, we generally lack any vision of the future (248). I remind readers that it is not Ritzer alone who is responsible for these extreme sentiments. His accounting reads as a kind of synopsis of the outrage (an enormous amount of heat) felt by a long list of sociologists, many of whom Ritzer quotes in considerable detail. How could so many accomplished thinkers conclude, and in unison, that the intellectual practice of decentering subjectivity spells a wholesale rejection of interest in the subject and subjectivity and that this supposed rejection can only equal a general lack of any vision of the future? It seems that the only viable answer to this question is that a strong theological hangover continues to make such extreme sentiment appear merely practical? The Christian foundations of sociologists scientic subjectivity, it would seem, remain shamefully poorly examined. Thinking critically about this theological desire for a centering metaphysics, we might read Ritzers (1997: 249) accusation that [p]ostmodern social theory leads to profound pessimism in reverse fashion. Embracing what need not be an ache of uncertainty, we can assert, with Friedrich Nietzsche (1895/1968:182), that with the Beyond one kills life. Why after all must I accept that responsibility to some phantom certainty must be the dutiful source of my motivation in life and as a sociologist? With Nietzsche (1895/1968:182), I can turn the table on this structuralist pessimism and propose that [n]ihilist and Christian: they rhyme.4 It is correct to say
Embracing Complexity Derrida (1968/1982) has long since proposed that structuralist desire can be undone by the play of what he calls diffrance. The term diffrance is a French language neologism (an invented word) incorporating the English differ and defer. The quest for essences, he argues, is untenable because no denition can be referenced except through an economy of differences and deferrals. For example, the computer that I now sit in front of is an old Macintosh machine. My machine is recognizable and has meaning for me because I know that Bill Gatess company did not manufacture it. The machine and Macintosh (the company) are different from Microsoft and their computers. It is recognizable because of what it is not. Since my old machine is the one I work on while I am at home and home is where I do most of my writing, I am sometimes faced with university machines that will not run my old Macintosh software. On these occasions I am forced to nd my way around another computer environment by understanding how it differs from what I do at home. Thus I start my work at the university not by starting from some unbiased beginning point but only by asking myself, how is this different from what I know already? My computer and everything else that is can have meaning only through its differences with every other thing that is. A simpler example might be to say that I can only know what a cat is because I understand how cats are different from dogs. Thus my old Macintosh is what it is on any given day precisely because it is different from whatever new technology I am struggling with on that day. Likewise, cats are cats because I understand how they
| 63
differ from not only dogs but from mice and birds. Again, then, all things inhabit an economy of difference, and these perpetual relations of difference are part of what Derrida intends with his diffrance neologism. As they differ or are spaced in language, meanings also actively defer to or call upon still other meanings. My computer is an old Macintosh but a Mac nonetheless. It differs from the machines made by Microsoft, but it is also not wholly unlike (it defers to) newer Macs. Similarly, a dog is different from a cat, but I also know what a dog is because I know how it is related to (defers to) a puppy. That this economy of differing and deferring is the very possibility of meaning making can be shown by looking at the most foundational of meaning-making directories, that is, a dictionary. Looking up dog, I nd this denition: a domesticated canine mammal related to foxes and wolves. To be domesticated means to be of the home, to be tame, and to be safe. Thus the term domesticated and thereby dog function by deferring to notions of protection, safety, and comfort. On the other hand, domestic also means what it does because we know how it differs from that which is wild, untamed, and fear provoking. Every denition of anything can be understood using the Derridean tool of diffrance. Diffrance also incorporates time and thus the impossibility that anything can be absolutely present or wholly in the moment. If my computer is knowable because of diffrance, should I imagine that this economy of differing and deferring can be made to cease functioning? The computer is old: an LCII. But this oldness can be, indeed must be, continually reassembled from long chains of diffrance. When I bought it, my old Mac was much newer than the Commodore machine that my grandmother bought to get me through graduate school. It was obviously and vastly different. However, now it seems to have much more in common with my old Commodore 64 than with the new Macintosh G5 that my university just purchased for me to use. And because the newer Macs are increasingly more compatible with the machines and software that Gatess company sells, the differences that I used to rely upon to give my machine meaning are fading. In another twenty-ve years my old machine may share a museum shelf with a slide rule and an abacus. The relationships of difference and similarity that allow my machine its signicance are always being altered, are constantly regrouping differently, and therefore remain unstable. These ceaseless reweavings of differences and deferrals make the passage of time interpretable. I think in time using diffrance. I understand that time is passing because the economy of differences and deferrals (like those that continue to rewrite the reality of my old computer) are shifting as I sit writing. The temporal (time) quality of this thinking is hinted at in Derridas (1968/1982:3) analogies comparing diffrance to the complex structure of weaving, to a woven sheaf, and later to a text as in textiles, and to a tissue of differences (1972/1981:33). This weave of meaningmaking text, then, can be understood as . . . an interlacing which permits the different threads and different lines of meaningor of forceto go off
| 65
changes in the (diffrance-generated) signicance of our existences. If we could avoid thinking of change as a thing (as something with a denable structure), we might say that diffrance is change. But things are still more complex. Time passes. However, the recognition of time passing is never as simple as tracing a neatly evolving trajectory of diffrance. Time is not reducible to structure (beginnings and endings/eschatologies and teleologies). Diffrance is not a theme. It is not a ghost of history nor ink for the written recounting of the march of progress; nor is it the hidden logos that can reveal the gradual unfolding of Gods plan. Undoing structure, remember, is the strategic purpose of diffrance. In Derridas (1968/1982:6) words: . . . there is nowhere to begin to trace the sheaf of the graphics of diffrance. For what is put into question is precisely the quest for a rightful beginning, an absolute point of departure, a principal responsibility (emphasis in original). Derrida says that there is nowhere to begin. I cannot speak in simple terms of the evolution of meanings through diffrance (of marking time in this way) because diffrance is at work even as I try to recount any history of diffrance. Let me illustrate with an example. My family and I are devoted fans of the Star Trek television series. We sometimes compare the various incarnations of Star Trek that have appeared through the years, beginning with the 1960s version and episodes. Anyone who looks even casually at the old episodes with Captain Kirk, Spock, and the rst Enterprise ship, will notice that the imagined twenty-third century of this program has a distinctly 1960s America tenor to it. The shows producers tried to create characters whose appearance was futuristic. The actors speak into com badges that double as symbols for a future Federation of Planets, have an evolved capacity to argue playfully over the merits or detriment of absolute rationality (Spocks logic and McCoys dislike for it), and regularly use terminology that is meant to infer a far-advanced scientic understanding of the cosmos (a rip in the space/time continuum!). Yet, the women wear the miniskirts and beehive hairdos popular in the United States in the 1960s. The men wear large-heeled boot-like shoes, also fashionable in the era the program originated, with bell-bottom pants tucked neatly into them. Clearly this is a future created from a 1960s departure. Still more telling are the moralizing themes. In one episode the crew discovers a planet full of otherworldly and otherwise named Native Americans who look, speak, and act like the images of Indians that were romantically and routinely recounted in 1960s American popular culture. In another episode, the crew saves two dissimilar groups of aliens from what looks a lot like the racial discord of the American civil rights era. From this example we can glean something of the impossibility of mapping times passing through an expectation that diffrance functions as an empirically available structure. The creators of the original Star Trek imagined the future. From the styles and cultural lessons contained in the show, we recognize how they imagined the twenty-third century from (as Derrida just said) a
| 67
the future, they gave signicance to their present. They knew who they were because they could describe how they differed from some who came before and how they were like some who were yet to come. There is nowhere to begin, Derrida says. This is because every moment owes its interpretability to traces of other meanings from other moments. Some of these meanings are weaker or stronger in their current inuence; some are closer in time or more distant. But there is no center, no beginning point, no absolute point of departure. Once comfortable with the realization that no deity is going to tell me who I really am, and after the belief in a centered, empirically veriable, structured existence where I can nd myself begins to appear simplistic, subjectivity and responsibility take on the decentered, diffrance-laden qualities of poststructuralism. As Derrida (1968/1982:6) writes in the previous quotation: what is put into question is precisely the quest for a rightful beginning, an absolute point of departure, a principal responsibility.
Post-Christian Responsibility in Sociology Because a poststructuralists responsibility has no stories of rightful beginning to be dutiful toward, no nality born of a Second Coming or from a some-day-to-be-arrived-at perfect society to dream of, the sacrices we make are not justied in the name of metaphysical principals. Unlike Abrahams sacrice of Isaac to his God, our sacrices carry the much greater weight of responsibility to the earthly. Every choice of an intellectual project, every analysis that I could have come at differently, and every potential effect of the analyses I do, amount to the sacrice of all that I did not choose to study and of all those who might be affected by my choices and by the method and scope of analysis that I bring to a social problem or issue.
In terms of the moral of morality, let us here insist upon what is too often forgotten by the moralizing moralists and good consciences who preach to us with assurance every morning and every week, in newspapers and magazines, on the radio and on television, about the sense of ethical or political responsibility. Philosophers who dont write ethics are failing in their duty, one often hears, and the rst duty of the philosopher is to think about ethics. . . . What the knights of good conscience dont realize, is that the sacrice of Isaac illustrates the most common and everyday experience of responsibility. (Derrida 1995:67)
A poststructuralists duty or responsibility is not to any essential subjectivity or to any battle on behalf of absolute subjectivity. Our politics are not humanist in the sense of working toward a society based on some theory of a human nature. Poststructuralist work is more akin to strategic intervention. While our work may be rigorously empirical, this research is aimed at understanding the
| 69
subjectivities whose identities must remain interminable. All subjectivities are political and I must recognize the responsibility that comes with interrupting functioning political narrations and steering them in directions that can never be fully anticipated or controlled. Who does my work ignore? What interests do my analyses relegate to the margins? Who do I simplify and thus establish some narrated political control over? Who am I sacricing and for what ultimately unknowable ends? (What the knights of good conscience dont realize is that the sacrice of Isaac illustrates . . . the most common and everyday experience of responsibility.) With the Christian God dead and sociologists relieved of the burden of a Beyond, our human responsibility is now to each other and to our planet. Doing academic work as a political participant who recognizes and embraces this complexity is how a poststructuralist understands responsibility. There is no more single voice of God for Abraham to obey. Responsibility for our lives cannot be reduced to the logos or to any thematic and normative logic. There can be no more theology. Who will dare call duty a duty that owes nothing, or better . . . that must owe nothing? It is necessary, therefore, that the decision and responsibility for it be taken, interrupting the relation to any presentable determination but still maintaining a presentable relation to the interruption and to what it interrupts. Is that possible? (Derrida 1993:17, emphases in original) To interrupt a metaphysicians claim to a truthful telling, but not by arguing for a better, more accurate truth is to interrupt without trying to establish a relation to any presentable determination. I want to interrupt what the archaeologists say about Indians, but I do not want to ght anymore on their cultural terrain than I have to. I will not argue over science, over presentable determinations of truth with them; but I will present their scientic narrations in terms that make sense from another point of departure. I will interrupt their narratives, and my renarration will constitute an alternative relation to what it interrupts (archaeological claims to Native dead). My battle is a political battle (a presentable relation) that owes nothing to fantasies of extra-political truth. Another way to say this is that I intend to interrupt the archaeologists privilege. I intend to attack their assumed and taken for granted power to narrate. As Foucault has taught us, power works by naturalizing the terms of its own gaze, by instituting its meaning making procedures as a regime of truth (Foucault 1977:133).
Closing the Missions: Beyond Good and Evil Because Greek philosophy and Christian theology teach that existence is tolerable only to the extent that it can be reduced to metaphysical themes, too much of the past twenty-four hundred years of intellectual work has been devoted to delineating who are friends of truth and to dening what it is exactly
| 71
elucidate specic domains of language (discourses) that produce normalcy. Power lies precisely in the efcacy of these discourses, in their ability to constitute subjectivities and to establish relations based upon these narrated versions of personhood. As he wrote, its not a matter of a battle on behalf of the truth, but of a battle about the status of truth and the economic and political role it plays (133). History, for Foucault, is not some gradual unfolding of human potential. Human existence has never amounted to a linear unfolding of logically interconnected occurrences; it has no pattern or constant agent that would permit progress to be measured. Rather, history is about struggles for the right to narrate reality, about interpretations heaped upon interpretations and about the real-life effects (a battle about the status of truth and the economic and political role it plays) of these narrations. Empowered discourses dene people as they facilitate what appear to be mere self-denitions. Discourses order the world, including ones place in it. At the most mundane and daily levels people learn to assess themselves, to apply corrective measures, and to feel that they are good, bad, healthy, or productive by referencing functioning discourse. For example, when students receive grades on their exams or report-cards, they are being provided with a means for what they believe to be selfassessment. There is a whole domain of language and meaning making at work that includes, for example, notions of intelligence, of the value of hard work, and of the importance of education. This textual weave of meaning-makingterms is held together by a logic that relates each piece to the others. For example, hard work produces good grades that indicate an intelligence that needs and desires education. This text of diffrance that provides signicance to grades becomes a technology used like a lens or grid for diagnoses of achievement, of ability, and therefore also of lack of potential, or lack of applied effort. We teach students to take up this discourse, to make it their own, and to narrate life in and around educational settings in terms of this perception grid that orders, normalizes, and pathologizes. Alternative discourses are always possible. For example, there is no law in history that says that human beings will evaluate their worth based upon examinations of academic knowledges that have grown up within an institution that is itself a complicated amalgamation dating back at least to Platos Academy. Viewed in contradistinction to all of the other possibilities for understanding oneself that might have developed and that did develop particularly among non-Europeans, modern test taking and grading is an arbitrary and socially arrived at outcome. Things might have been otherwise. To assess power, then, means to understand who benets from the habitualization (the reication or normalization) of discourse about education, and, therefore, from the institutionalization of subjectivities (professor, student, or good or poor intellect) maintained in and by this discourse. Consider that the importance of good grades still varies across American subcultures. Some fathers are more concerned with how well their sons hit
Political Responsibility as Genealogy The ghts over truth found in these histories are, as Foucault and Nietzsche say, the genealogy of the contemporary discourses that these students rely upon to describe who [they] are. Where the soul pretends unication or the self fabricates a coherent identity, the genealogist sets out to study the
| 73
beginningnumberless beginnings whose faint traces and hints of color are readily seen by an historical eye. The analysis of descent permits the dissociation of the self, its recognition and displacement as an empty synthesis, in liberating a profusion of lost events (Foucault 1971/1977:14546). Understanding the conditions of the possibility of functioning discourse (of technologies of power that are able to write particular forms of subjectivity into existence and to even force subjects to discipline themselves according to the strictures of these discursive narrations) requires, Foucault tells us, liberating a profusion of lost events. When a genealogist hears authority claimed in the name of the pursuit of truth, s/he wants to recover the lost events that will restore the political scars that such pursuits always try to wash away and to forget. Here we see what Ritzer, and so many others, miss in Foucaults critique of subjectivity. When he argues that sociologists need a theory of agency, he means to say that we need a theory about the nature of a truthful subjectivity that precedes and exceeds mere political battles. But there can be no (general) theory of agency when all subjectivities can be traced to focused concerns found among specic antagonists who were part of lost [we might say strategically forgotten] events. The purveyors of these general truths have to forget, to fabricate, and to pretend that their pronouncements are not born in the dirt and blood of earthly politics because remembering would not allow them to claim unication and coherence for some universal human agency. To recall (as a proponent and ally would insist upon recalling) those who struggled against the victors and the victors narrations would mean admitting a suppressed difference within such fabricated and coherent identity. To liberate a profusion of lost events, then, is to recover the dissent that has been narrated away or tamed in the discourses spoken by the victors and by the grandchildren of the victors. It is to dissociate and displace what has always only been an empty synthesis conjured by those with the power to spin truths. A genealogist wants to reappreciate the sites of struggles (the numberless beginnings whose faint traces and hints of color are readily seen by an historical eye) because s/he wants to reconnect these truth stories with the often-wretched politics that spawned them. Understood as a thing of this world, truth-telling discourse can be confronted by those whose normalcy it tries to institutionalize. Genealogy exposes the power to narrate existence as a political inheritance. Those who project a single form of human subjectivity (e.g., a soul, species being, human nature, or theory of agency) across the cornucopia of ages, cultures, and languages (promulgating an empty synthesis), and thereby nd some culmination of progressing development outlined in their own structural narrations, irresponsibly fail to interrogate this inheritance. In placing present needs at the origin, the metaphysician would convince us of an obscure purpose that seeks its realization at the moment it
Power, Assessment, and Terror When discursive accounts are institutionalized, enforced, and believed, they are inscribed on the day-to-day lives of everyday folks. One need only consider the history of being black, brown, female, or gay in the United States to understand that the power to dene normalcy is an immense one. The history of truth is a history of terror. Truth has been the basis of every racism, sexism, homophobia, and political witch-hunt. Slaveholders did not justify their ownership of other human beings as simply the result of greater military power or as a strength born of superior numbers. These racists believed that they possessed truth about the races and justied the horror they produced with science and religion. The bigots claimed (as they do today) to speak on behalf of truth.
| 75
The most horror-lled murders and indignities have been visited upon the persons of those who succumbed (as the biblical Isaac almost did) to those who believed (like Abraham) that they had a responsibility to truth. Women being naturally unsuited to working outside the home, to enduring strenuous athletic competitions, or to pursuing higher math and science was truth not politics. Claims that gay men and lesbians make unt mothers and fathers are still justied as truthnot politics. Claims that Indians do not understand the value of archaeology are asserted as truthnot politics. Claims that afrmative action equals special privileges for people of color are everyday awarded the status of truthnot politics. Truth is dangerous, then, precisely because its tellers seek to relieve themselves of their political responsibility. By insisting that an extra-social and extra-political center demands their devotion, they minimize the far bigger burden that poststructuralists are willing to bear. Overcoming the history of terror fomented by pursuits of structuralist truth means recognizing that all assessments are political acts. Making sense and asking others to listen to that sense-making is an invocation of political power. As I have already said, this request brings grave responsibility. It brings a sense of responsibility that can no longer tolerate deferrals to some metaphysicswhich amounts to an irresponsibility, a cowering and hiding from the immensity of post-Christian responsibility. To know is to participate in the ceaseless rendering of existence. A poststructuralist has to understand something of the conditions of possibility (the genealogy) of his/her narrations and to be aware of what effects might be set in motion by her/his analyses. As a poststructuralist, the whole point of my sociology is the possibility contained in a political transgression.
. . . criticism is no longer going to be practiced in the search for formal structures with universal value, but rather as a historical investigation into the events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying. . . . And this critique will be genealogical in the sense that it will not deduce from the form of what we are what it is impossible for us to do and to know; but it will separate out, from the contingency that has made us what we are, the possibility of no longer being, doing, or thinking what we are, do, or think. . . . It is seeking to give new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undened work of freedom. (Foucault 1984/1997:12526)
Freed from the obligation to pursue unobtainable structure in existence, sociologists can turn all of our attention to the study, interrogation, and manipulation of productions of truth (events that have led us to constitute ourselves . . . as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying) that adversely affect those we care for and want desperately to defend. Think of the amount of time and energy that has been spent chasing what never existed!
| 77
Biblical estimations of responsibility have now been added to our earlier genealogical accounting of the founding assumptions that continue to constitute the subjectivity of modern sociologists. Claims of political paralysis supposedly brought on by poststructuralist philosophy reect the unexamined and metaphysical desires inherited from Greek philosophy and Christian theology. These inheritances have been taken up in detail in this chapter. My strategy has been to turn the tables on structuralist declarations, arguing instead that aspirations for sociological agency, normative frameworks, and essential centers of power are overly simple, faith-based longings inherited from theology. Such reductions work to deny the abundance of possibilities that make life rich with never fully estimable experiences. On the other hand, an appreciation for poststructuralist arguments accomplishes exactly what the critics fear will be lost. The capacity for, and awareness of, civic responsibility is dramatically increased with the demise of Christian-derived notions of responsibility to fanciful, metaphysical ideals. Poststructuralists have a much greater chance of effecting real political change because we understand all knowledge to be political and therefore assume political work to be our rst and most important intellectual activity. We no longer harbor even the distracting desire for the old notions of objectivity in the pursuit of an extra-political social structure in existence. This chapter renders the power that these structuralist cultural inheritances wield in the lives of contemporary sociologists less compelling because, as C. Wright Mills (1959:12) wrote, we can now grasp history and biography and the relations between the two within society. Although no longer interested in, as Foucault (1984/1997:126) put it, seeking to make possible a metaphysics that has nally become a science, we continue to be very much interested in making the history of power available to those who continue to understand themselves (unwittingly) only as the marginalized effects of its narrations. Thus we intend to give new impetus, as far and wide as possible, to the undened work of freedom. Chapters 5 and 6 are examples of a sociology informed by poststructuralism. Each takes responsibility as a political intervention on behalf of racialized, ethnic, and cultural minorities in the United States. However, before engaging in that political work, we will take the time to reread the American sociological debate of the 1980s and 1990s, using the insights to poststructuralist philosophy that we have gained in chapters 13.
4
the american debate on postmodernism
It is in view of justice and ethics as undeconstructible, as experiences of the impossible, that legal and political decisions must be made, empirically scrupulous but philosophically errant.
Gayatri Spivak (1999:427)
Instead of appealing to reality to judge the truth of my social discourse, I propose that we judge our social stories by their consequences.
Steven Seidman (1991b:188)
n the 1980s and 1990s, American sociologists embroiled themselves in an anxious and bitter discussion of poststructuralism and what it meant for the discipline. Yet, the voices of ethnic and racialized minorities were conspicuously absent from these conversations. This debate mostly consisted of denouncements and attempts to control damage to the status of sociology as disciplinary science. Almost always, these writings were the outcome of hurried readings that missed the more radical elements of Foucaultian genealogy and Derridean deconstruction. Consequently, a tremendous opportunity to open up professional sociology to a far more diverse audience was missed. During the same period, Cultural Studies scholars and Postcolonial Critics many of whom were racialized, ethnic, and cultural minorities wielding tools gleaned from reading Michel Foucault and Jacques Derridahad begun intense and productive discussions with American and British anthropology.1 But American sociologists rarely saw these new elds as anything but threatening. Indeed, the reactions of American sociologists routinely treated the tenets of structuralist epistemology as if they were so obviously necessary as to be beyond the pale of serious discussion.
| 79
Although unable to recount the entire debate, here I work through some of the major appraisals made by some of the most prominent American theorists.2 These years saw a series of pronouncements about the dangers or limited utility of postmodernism. I begin with arguments published in one of the disciplines most prestigious journals, the American Sociological Associations Sociological Theory.3 I then critically assess writings by Patricia T. Clough (1992a, 1992b), Norman K. Denzin (1986, 1990, 1994, 1997, 2001), Charles Lemert (1997), and Yvonna S. Lincoln and Norman K. Denzin (2000). The combined inuence of these works on American sociologists is hard to overstate. These discussions became postmodernism in American sociological circles.
The Sociological Theory Debate A central concern of these thinkers was to dene difcult poststructuralist works. If they were to be controlled, the challenges presented by poststructuralist philosophers had to be denitively assessed and mined for any possible positive contributions. Thus Richard H. Brown (1990) announced what he termed the postmodern turn in sociological theory and wrote of hope for the creation of a new ethical ontology and normative epistemology (188). Here we see the now familiar structuralist assumption that meaningful sociological analyses require an epistemological center. Brown suggests the necessity of a new and postmodern center as the potential foundation of any moral society that this difcult philosophy might help us to build. . . . even after deconstructive criticism has done its work, we still are faced with the challenge of establishing cognitive authority and inventing positive values as central elements of any rational moral polity (1990:188). Brown has missed the more radical features of deconstruction. He seems unaware that it is the very notion of an epistemological center that is under attack in Derridas writings. Nor does he seem to appreciate the contradiction between his call for inventing positive values that would govern any rational moral polity and Foucaults devastating attacks on authoritative productions of healthy, sane, and moral subjectivities. Indeed for Brown, the Platonic and Cartesian selfunderstood as a selfcontained and complete presence, as a self-directing agencyremains wholly intact. Because individuals are the loci from which practices take their empowerment, Brown (1990: 19394) tells us, the ontological status of human agents is a central condition for rhetorical awareness and practice. Poststructuralism, as it is articulated here, amounts to little more than a new addition to an already well-established Interactionist tradition in American sociology. In fact, Brown explicitly links what he labels the rhetorical or textualist metaphor (1990:194) to the writings of George Mead, Erving Goffman, and Harold Garnkel. Reality, in this tradition, is an accomplishment,
| 81
eight to ten Indians. Finally, my friend Raven had had enough. Taking a big swig of beer and setting his glass emphatically on the table, he proclaimed: you dont know shit! The Natives erupted in laughter, the graduate student looked embarrassed, and the conversation quickly veered in a new direction. Seidmans poststructuralism spoke directly to this cultural gap between professional sociologists and the populations we all hope our work helps. As he wrote, When one appeals solely to the truth of a discourse to authorize it intellectually and socially, one represses reection on its practical-moral meaning and its social consequences. A discourse that justies itself solely by epistemic appeals will not be compelled to defend its conceptual decisions on moral and political grounds (1991a:135). Seidman pointed to the cultural and discursive properties of sociological writings. As narrative, he argued, sociology is inherently no more correct than those supplied in the languages of other cultural representations. Seidman understands that sociologists political and civic efcacy are compromised by insisting on the centrality of our own discourses (by continuing to insist on the possibility of epistemology). And, he pointed to the logically subsequent understanding that claims to speak the truth on behalf of all of humanity have always been inextricably linked to colonialist politics. Although Seidman writes convincingly in these journal articles of the benet of abandoning the fruitless search for essential and universal human agency, his critique remains dependent on the imagery of a rational, freethinking, individualism. Consider the following quotations: We need to shift from an essentialist language of self and agency to conceiving of the self as having multiple and contradictory identities, community afliations, and social interests (1991a:142). And then, Our value would be both in providing socially informed analyses that would be useful to partisans and in promoting uncoerced public moral discussion in the face of various partisans who repeatedly act to restrict such elaborated discourse. We would become defenders of an elaborated reason against the partisans of closure and orthodoxy, and of all those who try to circumvent open public moral debate by partisan or foundational appeals (143). But how can one have multiple and contradictory identities and also be uncoerced? The latter quote seems to suggest some neutral site for conversation, some place where elaborated reason would be uniformly recognizable and appreciated by all those championing open public moral debate. Yet, if Michel Foucault and Jacques Derrida are correct, there is no uncoerced space, no centered forum of elaborated reasoning where open debate can happen. All reasoning functions textually and genealogically. All persuasive articulations are fundamentally political. Indeed, this is precisely why we have multiple and contradictory identities. We exist in multiple and competing social relationships, and those relationships, maintained textually and discursively, are the possibility of any agency.
| 83
writings amounted to rhetoric and metatheoretical gesticulations best explained by poststructuralists own professional locations, including their relative disengagement from undergraduates. Given the well-documented attraction of many racialized, sexualized, ethnic, immigrant, and cultural minorities to poststructuralist writings, this was, and is, a brazenly uninformed attack. Indeed, Rogers has to all but ignore Seidmans (1991b) extended and eloquent explanation of why and how poststructuralist philosophy helped him conceptualize a more sophisticated and egalitarian political understanding of the diversity in gay communities. His analysis is explicitly and rigorously linked to the gaps he nds between on the ground political organizing in these communities and the content of professional sociology journals and meetings. And, Seidman (1992:255) points out, the most emphatic structuralists are themselves famous precisely because of their tie[s] to the elite conference/journal circuit. This said, Seidmans (1992) response to Rogers more substantive criticism is not entirely satisfying. He reads her attack as being primarily about linguistic inconsistency (1992:256). Modernism and Postmodernism, here, appear as two distinct and discreet historical periods whose constituent languages, in a perfect academic world, would be clearly separated one from the other. Thus he admits to being mired in language and concepts that he nonetheless hopes one day to leave behind. Rogers, I think, would agree that a discursive strategy whose aim it is to depart from the dominant conventions will often draw on these conventions. This is so because there is often a lag or a strain between conceptual innovation and linguistic usage (256). No such disjuncture is possible. We cannot escape the modern and remove ourselves to a purity of the postmodern anymore than we might render ourselves denitively post-Christian. The desire for escape to a place of new clarity is more productively understood as a replaying of Greek and Christian metaphysical aspirations (as well as what I have called selfloathing), and precisely at the moment when these faith-based desires should be thrown into crisis. The quest also implies that as theorists we might adopt some disciplined (epistemological) vantage from where to assess what is modern and what is postmodern, not unlike some Marxian claims to assess modes of production from a privileged site of dialectical totality.6 Jeffrey C. Alexanders (1991) contribution to the Sociological Theory debate might be considered the prototype for another of the recurring structuralist attacks of later years. His claim is that structuralists epistemological beliefs are equal to the very possibility of meaningful knowledge and therefore politics. Labeling the challenges from poststructuralist philosophy as a discourse of suspicion (149), Alexander insists on a thoroughly indefensible line of demarcation between the theorists particular lifeworld and the particular perspective of his or her social group (147). Maintaining that the policing of this separation is basic to any claim to reason, and thus to the real nature of sociological theory, he argues that within this (metaphysical) dream lies
| 85
the fundamental point. Force is all there has ever been. Empiricist claims to objectively describe the real (impersonal) in existence have never existed outside the parameters of power. On the contrary, the far-reaching, permeating power of structuralists rule of force can still be measured by the extent to which this ruse goes unquestioned. To claim that ones ways are what should be natural and normal for everyone is to claim great power over others, and such claims are a foundation of colonialism. Surely, ethnic and cultural minorities of many marginalized stripes are justied in asking: how dare Alexander refer to social science that has categorized us, dened us, and brutally governed us as impersonal? The power that colonizers enjoy has always been justied through their ability to deny the cultural and political qualities of their own narratives. Robert J. Antonios (1991) reaction to Seidmans provocations, published in the same round of Sociological Theory editions, represents a more careful reading of poststructuralist challenges. Antonio understands what is at stake. Nevertheless, he tends to echo Alexanders assumption that structuralist epistemology is the only possible basis for civic efcacy among sociologists. Antonios response can be read as what would become still another standard reaction by American sociologists to poststructuralist writings. Antonio is not bothered by poststructuralist philosophy per se; rather, it is the consequences of the postmodern turn that he nds unacceptable. Much of his reaction, then, is focused on articulating the dangers of poststructuralist criticisms and the consequent need to encircle and contain them by protecting established sociological epistemologies. Antonios initial and most forceful move is to tear what he calls radical postmodernism away from other less frightening theorists. Although he points, only in passing, to scholarly circles that embrace truth-seeking norms, scholars who might therefore forge an authentically postmodern attitude, he never tells us exactly who these less than radical postmodernists are (1991:159). And we are left to wonder what the self-contradicting phrase authentically postmodern could mean. For Antonio, the attack on essentialist subjectivities and pursuits of objective truth is radical postmodernism. Despite the fact that these sentiments are broadly shared by many poststructuralists from various academic disciplines, Antonio proceeds as if this radical strand is reducible to the works of Jean Baudrillard (1983a, 1983b, 1987). We can get a feel for the avor of Antonios objections by quoting a long passage in which he summarizes postmodern culture.
The explosive and nearly random production of signs, information, events, and spectacles in the new media-generated semiotic orders transforms culture into a mere precession of images detached from any underlying social realities. History, politics, power, and social reality itself are all dissolved in the vortex of disembodied simulacra. Normative and empirical truth claims
Antonio cannot help but associate the loss of epistemological certainty with frightening (explosive and vortex of disembodied) chaos. Instability in textual economies of meaning becomes a nearly random production of signs. But Antonio is wrong to suggest that a lack of certainty equals randomness. Foucault and Nietzsche certainly intended no such conclusion. Indeed, the opening sentence of Foucaults essay on genealogy begins: Genealogy is gray, meticulous, and patiently documentary (1971/1977:139). Likewise, Spivak (1999:427), in the epigraph to this chapter, describes political decisions as empirically scrupulous. Documenting the history of European cultural phantasms is rigorously empirical work, and this important interrogation does not mean that these elaborate creations lose all power to signify. Disputing the Platonic, Christian, and Cartesian subject/object ontology is not the same thing as claiming that all is random and relative. Just because I come to understand that this binary and its many replications are always social constructions does not mean that all commonly shared understandings suddenly and summarily dissolve. Although the subject/object ontology might at rst glance seem like something that smart people cannot do without, the alarm in Antonios reaction is more productively understood as a loss of comfort. Disrupting the ontological status of this binary is not, as he portends, the end of all human reasoning. If the debunking of imaginary centers were as devastating as Antonio believes, atheism would have long since destroyed the world. The nineteenth centurys scientic successes were built on teachings of seventeenth century philosophers whose motivations poured forth from the depths of their theological aspirations; yet, the later thinkers open attacks on God did not result in a random production of signs. Similarly, poststructuralists teach that the disciplined search for foundational epistemology is an unrealizable and faith-based quest; but we do not accept that the critique of its metaphysical premises results in a normative void (no meaning or authority). In fact, it is precisely the meticulous and patiently documentary study of these European superstitions that allows poststructuralists work to resonate with intellectuals from marginalized communities. The poststructuralist critique of structuralist social science will result (is already resulting) in supplementations of older assumptions, but it would be foolish to think it will or should result in some pure poststructuralism (postmodern culture), purged of all that was structural. Our ability to doubt the Christian Gods status as underlying . . . reality remains the condition of possibility of our intelligent examination of the political consequences of others faith in this God. And, the deconstruction of essential subjects and objects is the possibility of our productive analyses of the
| 87
consequences of belief in this old binary. If we simply assume the necessity and correctness of these Greek and Christian inheritances (as Alexander and Antonio do), we relinquish our ability to think critically about epistemology and its effects. This, it seems to me, is irresponsible. And, again, our interrogations will not lead to a relativistic inability to share signs, symbols, and meaning. Antonio extrapolates the loss of epistemological certainty to a vortex of disembodied simulacra. A vortex is a centered place of violent swirling water or air where things disappear and are lost. A reality of material subjects and objects may still exist, Antonio warns, but they are in danger of being swallowed up and lost to a postmodern swirl of unstable discourse. Simulacra are images of other images. So, Antonio is upset that the presumed distinction and relationship between mere images (signs, symbols, and phrases) and the real, essential, physical pieces of reality that they are said to represent is being questioned. As I have already said, Antonio does not argue with poststructuralist analysis per se; it is the outcome that scares him. The subject/object binary is now written as ideal/material. Objectivity, here, is said to exist not in the abstract world of ideas but in the material experiences of the physical body. Many structuralist sociologists, most notably Marxists, who are themselves indebted to Aristotelian attacks on Platonic idealism, have reversed the order of preference in the binary. In either instance, the premises remain the same. Antonio might well lament the loss of a very old cultural presumption, but he should not imagine that the material/ideal binary is basic to our civic future. To fear that all will become disembodied simulacra is to cling to an ancient theological duality that it is high time sociologists learned to seriously question. Labeling poststructuralism radical perspectivism, Antonio worries that the loss of centered epistemological foundations reduces sociology to the supercial and vacuous. Without its Greek and Christian cultural inheritances, sociology becomes primarily . . . a projection of assertive selfexpression giv[ing] license to undisciplined, self-indulgent, whimsical, and grossly partisan points of view (158). This loss of substance, in turn, cannot help but foster a climate of ennui (1991:155). Like Alexander, Antonio maintains that sociologists political efcacy is tied to a successful defense of structuralist epistemology. Without the status and power that comes with placing their cultural inheritances beyond doubt, cynicism and despair (ennui) follow. Another way to think critically about these accusations is to turn them back on the accusers. For example, as we will see in chapter 5, these sentiments sound a great deal like those of American Indians who are outraged by what they perceive to be white scientists arrogance and narcissism. Native activists have no difculty labeling scientists claims to being the sole proprietors of truth as self-indulgent and grossly partisan. And ennui is far too tame a term for the deep despair that Indian people feel over European American scientists refusal to return our dead to their gravesa refusal that scientists locate rmly in the assumed priority of their quest for objective
| 89
endorsement of individual Indians who I admire, think to be intelligent, and who believe not only in ghosts but also in the proclivity of the dead for visiting in nocturnal dreams. The result was a shared embarrassmentmy classmates for me and mine for over my own confusion.7 If I had any lingering doubts, after that moment I never again failed to recognize sociology as a thoroughly cultural enterprise. Can I believe that my oldest and dearest friend, who has been dead for years, visits me in my sleep, and be a sociologist? If being a sociologist means that I must spend my life in pursuit of an objective truth that all right-minded intellectuals can see and verify, then the answer is a resounding no. How could sociologists like Alexander and Antonio ever accept the veracity of my dead friends visits? Their faith demands that they not believe in what they cannot recognize from within the dictates of their own disciplined epistemology. What then of a cross-cultural duty to justice and ethics? When my young nephew died, one of our Klamath elders stood before his still open grave and spoke to a group of about fty Indians and white folks who know and understand Klamath people. He told us my nephew would guide his mom and dad if they would let him. My brother and our father nodded appreciatively. No one laughed. No one snickered. No one whispered any doubts. If anyone thought our elder primitive or backward, they didnt give any indication that they felt that way. How could the ndings of structuralist sociology ever center a just and ethical society that could treat these Klamath Indians as other than curious outliers with no real capacity for serious work on serious matters? Sociology that insists on the primacy of its own extended, cultural inheritances will never be able to treat cultural others as equals. The issue has never been truth and falsity, as Foucault repeatedly and carefully (scrupulously) documents. The crux of the matter has always been raw power. Alexander and Antonio are protecting a regime of truth (Foucault 1977:133). They are protecting their privilege, their power, and their dominance over other peoples. As such, they should not imagine that they are substantially different from the many colonial truth tellers who preceded them. Justice and ethics, as they must be thought where inclusion of difference is genuine, cannot be the exclusive domain of Alexander, Antonio, and their structuralist colleagues. Moral laws cannot be formulated; morality, where cultural others are present, cannot exist as a calculus or centered system. As Greek, Christian, and social scientic foundations, justice and ethics are impossible. Moral and ethical behaviors in intercultural domains are, structurally speaking, experiences of the impossible. When Indians and anthropologists sit down to talk as equals, they do so in openended, discursive spaces, and these interactions take place without guarantees. They are never reducible to philosophical laws, to centers. They are undeconstructable because they defy a concrete, extra-cultural, extra-political location.8
Lemert: Kissing Postmodern Freaks and Frogs Lemerts (1991, 1992, 1997) writings on poststructuralist challenges to American sociology are well known and widely read. Although he contributed to this journal debate, I have chosen to focus my remarks on a later book, where his thoughts about postmodernism are more comprehensively provided. In Postmodernism Is Not What You Think (1997), Lemert assesses the tremendous hostility with which poststructuralist philosophy was rejected in American sociology departments in the 1980s and 1990s. In his opening chapter, Beasts, Frogs, Freaks, and Other Postmodern Things, Lemert outlines and chides these attacks for being overwrought, overdone, and somewhat misguided. Though the number of professional sociologists who claim actually to be postmodernists is small in ratio to the whole, the number of occasions upon which the subject is mentioned, often oddly out of context, is great. It is not uncommon for solicited reviews of scholarly articles or books, even of tenure and promotion cases, to contain unsolicited evaluations judging the merits of a case by the degree of its perceived proximity to (bad!) or from (good!) postmodernism (1997:56). Lemert wants his colleagues to stop being afraid of these writings. He thinks this rashness that often is expressed as a loathing stops American sociologists from learning from cultural others writing outside of sociology departments. (He singles out Edward Said as one example of these important thinkers.) This fear is rooted, Lemert surmises, in a lack of careful, sociological assessment. Like myself, Lemert invokes Mills concept of the sociological imagination as a method for reading the erceness of the American attack on French poststructuralism. He recognizes that a loss of privilege is underway, and he even suggests Derridas Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences9 as the moment when this de-centering of privilege was announced.
| 91
Structuralist social science was centered in the experiences of white, middleclass, men. Consequently, Lemert maintains, the subsequent assault on supposed epistemological agreementcarried out by cultural others wielding weapons provided by Derrida, and his teacher, Foucaultwas inevitable. In the tradition of Mills, Lemert wants his privileged colleagues to understand their hostility as an outgrowth of larger social and historical circumstances. We who are thus set apart, having formerly set ourselves above, watch with fear, anger, or anxious understanding the othersthose peoples who, having suffered the indignity of the dominant cultures imposition of its culture on them, break the silence: feminists, ethnic rebels, gays and lesbians. . . . Identity politics, even when not called by this name is a near universal possibility whenever an imperium, having succeeded for a while, even a long while, loses its grip on the silence in which it once thrived (1997:13031). But Lemert resigns himself to the disruptions brought by these new voices only begrudgingly. He hopes for a third way. He shares in the lament of the nostalgics who wish for a return to an ideal past, but he also respects the epiphanies of the feminist, queer, race-based, ethnic . . . identity politics which he playfully but paternalistically labels postmodernish freaks and frogs (1997:148). The alternative is what Lemert calls prophetic visionaries (1997:15253). These third-way prophets are said to be visionary because they successfully merge the competing visions of cultural others with the old, liberal dreams of unied, moral structures. These thinkers (the most well-known among sociologists being William Julius Wilson) are said to embrace practical reason and the entrepreneurial rationality of the modern order (15253). Although Lemert concludes his text by acknowledging that postmodernism cannot be thought through (1996:164), the book nonetheless reads as an attempt to dene, and thereby contain, the poststructuralist impulse among marginalized peoples. The postmodern, for Lemert, is little more than a large and pain-inicting bump in the historical road traveled by the glorious Western civilizations. And he can invoke this tone only because he hears the protests of the marginalized as a recent awakening (epiphanies). Our silence, Lemert suggests, was ours and it was self-chosen. He seems not to understand the very real difference between silence at the margins and systematically maintained deafness at the center. People of color have always spoken and spoken loudly and strongly. Lemert mostly misses this history. He suggests, and this feels patronizing, that all will be well if his privileged colleagues will just invite the margins into the center. As he says, they are the frogs that might become the princes of some other good world, if only we could kiss them (1997:164). The liberal dream of e pluribus unum, then, can be renegotiated and reinvigorated if the big tent of the republic, and American sociology, can simply be expanded. Again, this means that Lemert and other privileged members must do their moral duty and help those of us from the cultural wilderness nd
| 93
believe that the meanings of things reside within them (as inherent essences). He attributes this mistake to the apparent self-presence found in the voice (logocentrism). The knower (subject) and the known (object) are always only unstable outcomes of extended and never fully present text. Thus the spoken voice and the complete presence it seems to suggest also rely on writing-like relationships (diffrance) to other meanings that are not present. The pursuit of the real meaning of things, then, can never be satised. It must be endlessly deferred. This unrealizable desire for essence is what makes the quest superstitious and metaphysical. Lemert, though, reads something very different in Derridas analysis.
Derrida believes that the difference (take note) between speech and writing is that in writing the meaning of what is being said is deferred. Americans really did not get the meaning of the Gettysburg Address until long after it was spoken. Most of those present on November 19, 1863 at Gettysburg could not even hear Lincoln. . . . A follower of Derrida, thus, might say that Lincolns address was actually a piece of writing that called forth at a later time the historical writing or inscription of the moral meaning of the Civil War and its most famous battle in the American psyche. (1997:46)
Lemert appears not to understand that Derridas work is not about actual or nal meanings. He thinks that Derrida simply means that true meanings show up later, after the fact. Because he does not get that they never show up, he can hold out hope for a politically liberal sociology rooted in scientic, albeit more inclusive, epistemology. In Lemerts tamed and contained postmodernism, we need only incorporate additional standpoints into the pursuit of objectivity and the moral order that he hopes will follow. There is nothing particularly wrong with sociology that cant be cured. We need, rst of all, to work through the collective representations that so exaggerate our limited capacity to be a real science, and thus come back to sociology as it was intended by its founders to be (1997:136). Because Lemert misses Derridas critique of Greek and Christian metaphysics of presence, he attempts to tell us what poststructuralism really is. He attempts to assess and document a structure in poststructuralism. He is not alone in this mistaken mission.
Denzin: Sociology in The Seventh Moment Perhaps no American sociologist has written more about postmodernism and poststructuralism than Denzin (1986, 1990, 1994, 1997, 2001a, 2001b; Lincoln and Denzin 2000). His writings are both philosophy of social science and civically applied arguments. Although I share both of these interests, the source of our motivations is quite different. My primary concern is to enhance
| 95
images. The line between reality and representation blurs and nally disappears. In the postmodern era, there are only representations of other and previous representations. This is the sociological space where Denzin operates most affectively. His analyses of visual culture, particularly of cinema, are insightful, brilliantly argued, and politically useful (1994, 2001, 2002). In a reader friendly style, Denzin maps out where and how popular lms draw upon already existing images (racializations, sexualizations, and gendered stereotypes) to produce story lines that are easily recognized. Drawing on Cloughs (1992a) feminist and psychoanalytic poststructuralism (discussed in the next section), he underscores that these narratives produce closure and structured coherence in what is otherwise a postmodern onslaught of competing interpretive possibilities. For example, Denzin points out that the main characters in the lm The Morning After serve as semiotic links to existing and reactionary discourses about homosexuality, alcoholism, femininity, racism, and masculinity. The male hero is racist and homophobic, but he is also heroically masculinea strong, stoic, protector of the tragic (alcoholic) female character. In allowing these hegemonic readings to stand, the viewer (and the critic) become willing accomplices in support of a conservative feminism that pleads (yet hides) its ideological biases in the name of a story which locates a woman in the company of a good man who has aws (Denzin 1994:195). Denzins analysis teaches us that viewers want to identify with the struggles of the heroic male. Other narratives, those that question patriarchy, white privilege, or hetero-normativity are shut out by the empathy the audience has for this good but awed man. The story grants a respite to those who pine for the old order. Reactionary attitudes are allowed to retreat, escape into the comforts of the lms familiar narratives, avoiding the postmodern, civic spaces where struggles to narrate differently take place. The difcult new world lled with cultural others is simplied and coheres in the experiences that the audience shares with the storys heroic male. The refuge provided by this simplication functions as a surreptitious validation of racist and homophobic patriarchy. It allows the audience comfort within the reauthorization of its politically reactionary story line. This is valuable sociology. But Denzins writings also betray a deeply structuralist impulse. He constantly denes and redenes what poststructuralism is.11 He creates long lists of characteristics that are said to encompass poststructuralist critique.12 He assumes a supra-historical vantage from where he un-reexively narrates the developing, progressing history of social scientic epistemologies. Poststructuralism and postmodernism become part of later moments within this narrative. In 1997, he proclaimed sociology to be in the sixth moment and by 2000 he announces the seventh moment (Denzin 1997; Lincoln and Denzin 2000). Curiously, this circumscribing, evolutionary timeline of sociological development contradicts Denzins own description of the seventh moment.
| 97
In the old days, going native meant taking on the beliefs and reasoning patterns of those being objectied, studied. It meant forgetting that one was a scientist in the service of knowledge and not a member of the peoples chosen as objects of sociological investigations. Now, in Denzins new, center-less center of the seventh moment, sociologists must acknowledge that their writings are interested, political, and power-based. Academics are a cultural group writing about another cultural group. Yet, the lure of an elusive center emerging in this tension-riddled enterprise of sociologys seventh moment persists. Denzin understands the folly of presuming to speak objectively about cultural others, but he cannot give up his desire to hear the purity of their voices. Like Lemert, he welcomes including the other, but (and this is the source of his foreboding tone) he senses the impossibility of nding the real other. (Can we ever hope to speak authentically of the experience of the Other, or an Other?) This is why Denzins Other is said to loom. Sociologists are tension-riddled because they want to do the right thing. They struggle to hear the experience of the other. But, they remain unwilling, or as yet unable, to question the Greek and Christian superstitions that they still imagine are indispensable to really knowing anything about anyone else. Denzin wants to bring the others into a big sociological tent, but he does not want them to tear down its walls in an attack on its central premises. Lordes warning about the masters tools waits like the silence between lovers behind his longing for an epistemological center that can include all of us. Denzin (1994) too misreads and ignores Derridas deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence. This shortcoming is readily visible in his overly brief analysis of T. Minh-ha Trinhs (1989) Woman, Native, Other. Because Denzin continues to covet an authentic, fully present other, he cannot help but reduce Trinhs text to merely another standpoint epistemology (1997:54). Describing and citing what he calls the storytelling model of Trinh (234), he claims that these models are pivotal because they authorize the turn to narrative, offering methods that ensure the truth and accuracy of a text and its interpretation (see Trinh 1989:14243). Trinhs method, Denzin tells us, is superior to that of older, empiricist sociologists who do not hear the story as it was told. The goal, he says, is to recover these lost stories. . . . (1997:249). For Denzin, Trinhs story-telling model is an experimental method. It is an attempt to capture and accurately record the experience of the other. As such, it is a good faith stab at an elusive center. But Denzin misses that Trinhs (1989:142) postcolonial criticism aggressively attacks what she calls nativist discourse. Turning to those pages of Trinhs text that Denzin identies as his source, we nd:
Looking for the structure of their narratives so as to tell it the way they tell it is an attempt at remedying this ignorance of other ways of telling and listening (and, obviously, at re-validating the nativist discourse). . . . Rare are those who
What then of Denzins insistence that Trinh is offering a model that can ensure the truth and accuracy of a text? How is it that from Trinhs explicit warning against seeking to tell it the way they tell it in an attempt at remedying ignorance of other ways Denzin draws the conclusion that sociologists need to hear the story as it was told . . . to recover these lost stories? Trinhs admonition could not be any clearer. Denzins motive, she predicts in her text published nearly a decade before his, will obviously be an attempt at revalidating . . . nativist discourse. Perhaps if Denzin had more carefully read earlier pages of the chapter he cites, he would have understood why Trinh refers to the story as a living thing. My story, no doubt, is me, but it is also, no doubt, older than me. Younger than me, older than the humanized. Unmeasurable, uncontainable, so immense that it exceeds all attempts at humanizing. . . . Truth does not make sense; it exceeds meaning and exceeds measure. It exceeds all regimes of truth (1989:123). There is no metaphysics of presence assumed here. Neither the story nor the teller has an inherent, essential meaning. As is true of storytellers in many oral societies, Trinhs teller understands that the story is not really hers. She is not the author, in the sense of someone who creates and owns. Rather, the story is the very possibility of her person-hood. The narrative, a very old, extended, living, story, is the source of its tellers signicance. The story is me, but it is also . . . older than me. The storytellers people know themselves and understand their extended identities and histories, because of the stories. The stories cannot be measured, after the fashion that social scientists measure (hunt down and consign meaning) to objects. Because no one possesses the narratives, and because they are far older than those who now tell and hear them, no one expects that the stories mean the same thing to everyone, everywhere, all the time. Rather, Trinh, teaches, these are the assumptions of nativism. The stories are living, organic things that evolve and adapt as the people live and change (younger than me). But the social scientists see no life. They see only objects. Because they refuse to see that epistemology is only their way, the scientists insist on lling the stories with their own marks and markings. In this way, they try to lay claim to what is uncontainable and immeasurable. Until Denzin and the other structuralists are able and willing to seriously interrogate their own metaphysical beliefs, they will insist on admitting cultural others to their conversations only on terms that reinforce, and do not
| 99
break down, the colonialist impulse in sociology. They will insist that when we others address them we speak as authentic scientic objects. (Can we ever hope to speak authentically of the experience of the Other?) And, as Trinh forewarns, they will claim that their arrogance is an attempt at remedying this ignorance of other ways of telling and listening. Indeed, Denzin even imagines that Trinh is supplying him with a new epistemological model that will reconrm what has inconveniently become an elusive center. The progress of sociology, now in its seventh moment, marches on. The freaks and frogs, the cultural others that loom, are told that we must learn over time to awaken [our]selves to a world in which questions and talk are, at least, relatively free of risk. But when we put poststructuralist perspectives to work in our own service, writings that nally, nally allow us to point out that the masters tools are his own cultural heritage, we are scorned and feared. As Lincoln and Denzin put us on notice, Endless self-referential criticisms by the poststructuralist can produce mountains of texts, with few referents to concrete human experience. Such are not needed (2000:1050). Denzin requires an other who will speak as an authentic presence.13 He assumes epistemology. He does not recognize it as one set of cultural assumptions among many other earthly possibilities. Denzin recognizes that cultural minorities are increasingly a part of academic institutions. It is the institutionalized Other who speaks, he and his co-author tell us, as s/he gains access to the knowledge-producing corridors of power and achieves entre into the particular group of elites known as intellectuals and academics or faculty (2000:1051). But when these others show up and speak, our texts, he apparently thinks, contain few referents to concrete human experience? Certainly Trinh is not anyones academic lightweight. As Denzins engagement with her text proves, thinkers of this caliber are hard to ignore. So why, given our increasing, and sometimes formidable presence in academic corridors, do Lemert and Denzin persist in not hearing those who question their epistemology, as the Other? Why is Lemert telling us that we must learn over time to awaken [our]selves to a world in which questions and talk are, at least, relatively free of risk while he and Denzin rush to dene, minimize, and dismiss the damage they fear we might do to their science? As I have said repeatedly, the answer lies in their refusal to de-center the Greek and Christian self. Before he wrote about postmodernism and poststructuralism, Denzin became famous as a preeminent Symbolic Interactionist. The integrity of a universal, selfsame, human agency is foundational to that tradition. Without the ontology of a free-thinking, self-contained individual, Symbolic Interactionism as an intellectual tradition falters.14 It should come as no surprise, then, that Denzin can only tolerate those others who speak as a self-same, fully present constant that merely wears different identity hats (gendered, racial, cultural, class-based, etc.) in different settings.
| 101
openly acknowledges that his quest for an elusive center is contradictory and tension-riddled, he will not give up insisting that it is emerging. In the end he must retreat, like Jonathan H. Turner and Peter Berger, into theological imagery. Of course there are no real biographical subjects independent of the stories told about them . . . we can never get back, to raw biographical experience. The closest we can ever get is when a subject, in epiphanic moments, moves from one social world to another. In these instances the subject is in between interpretive frameworks. When this happens experience is described in words that have yet to be contaminated by the cultural understandings of a new group (1990:1213). Epiphanic moments? Pure interpretation (raw biographical experience) is still being fantasized as the optimum foundation of Denzins sociology, even as he must admit that no real biographical subjects independent of the stories told about them will ever be found. Recall that Lemert also writes of his respect for epiphanies of feminist, queer, race-based, ethnic others. As I understand the word, an epiphany is a divine instance of pure perception. It is often described as a moment of theological inspiration brought by a deity who appears for ones personal edication. Denzin wants an authentic self that has experiences. He wants to know about experience that has yet to be contaminated by . . . cultural understandings. But this belief in pure experience (epiphanic) has only always been theology. As such, it is a cultural understanding. It is the same pious pilgrimage (albeit now dressed up for Denzins seventh moment) that motivated the ancient Greeks and Christians that came later. Despite Denzins faith, the self is never not under construction. It is never not cultural. The self has experiences only because it understands (feels, interprets, and experiences) through language that is always acquired culturally. The act of describing an experience simultaneously (re-)creates that experience and does so using shared (cultural) language. Once one has language, s/he is never again between interpretive frameworks. And there are no signs that say, now leaving your old interpretive framework: forget all that you used to knowa predicament that we institutionalized cultural others are all too aware of. Agency is an effect, a consequence of the culturally authorized language that makes every social setting possible. And this does not mean that selves do not have agency. I can make decisions about what I am because of language. I have agency, but it is an agency that is dependent upon the rich discursive, textual, economies of language that I use to think about and describe all that I know. Denzins attempt to institute a minimalist sociology, then, is a misguided attempt at salvaging a metaphysical center that never really existed. He is homesick. If grand, overarching, sociological narratives of the past were mere stories that kept us from really knowing the authentically social experiences of the other, then it is to the purity of those experiences, Denzin says, that sociology must go. The authentic working people, the ethnic,
| 103
a sacred ethnography that celebrates the small performance rituals that bring us together in the natural world (2000:1055). Whose rituals? Which natural world? As interpreted by whom? Who is us and how is us dened? But Denizin seems to think that because it is sacred, it is somehow so obviously foundational as to be easily recognized and understood by everyone everywhere. As he describes, a sacred, existential epistemology places us in a noncompetitive, nonhierarchical relationship to the earth, to nature, and to the larger world (1052) and it seeks to . . . illuminate the unity of the self in its relationship to the reconstructed, moral, and sacred natural world (1052). This is hauntingly religious language. It homogenizes human differences. It reinvigorates and celebrates deeply oppressive, universalizing moral systems. It is quite probably a prescription for a replaying of the horrors visited upon humanity by centuries of Platonists and Christian Aristotelians (albeit here called by other names). The constant and continuing danger is that Denzin still seeks to remove politics from the relationship between professional sociologists and those we write about. Despite his claim that his epistemological desires are postructural to the core (1997:26), his writings are, on the contrary, a desperate attempt to re-center sociology.15
Clough: The Ethnographic Search for Self-Validation Clough (1992; 1992b), with Siedman, is one of the few American sociologists to understand the productive potential of poststructuralist philosophy for sociology. She rereads the empiricist quest for objectivity through a feminist, psychoanalytic lens. Explicitly concerned with ethnography, as a tradition where researchers imagine themselves in a heroic struggle to lay bare culturally alien worlds, Clough recasts these narratives as Oedipal struggles for the recovery of a lost maternal security. As this Freudian story unfolds, the male separation from his mother, a separation insisted upon by his father, produces a pre-conscious longing and emotional lacking in men. Thus the ethnographer, like all adult men, is engaged in an unconscious quest for security and self-reconciliation. Never quite able to recover what we have lost, we compensate for our insecurity through defensive attempts at mastery of the many threatening differences we inevitably encounter. In other words, if as poststructuralists claim, the self is always already decentered and never fully present to itself, then Clough would have us see this situation as a kind of unconscious, festering, psycho-emotional wound. The metaphysical dream of self-presence is here gured as a painfully deep (ultimately sexualized) need for restful securityfor a promised foundation in epistemological certainty. Previous generations longing for the warm unity of the one God, for a primal return to the Garden of Eden, is now a desperate scientic attempt at (masculine) mastery of an unruly and unpredictable (feminine) existence.16 Structuralist sociology, so very male in its origins and
| 105
Again, this quest for dominance is the outcome of repressed fear and longing that ultimately becomes the colonial and masculine loathing of the feminine and non-European. But the desire of the man of science for unity lost, for the complete and centered subjectivity that was provided and guaranteed in the maternal embrace of infancy, is always already displaced into uncontainable diffrance, into a centerless text that haunts him as the only possibility of his insecure existence. The structuralist, in his metaphysical desire for his own complete selfpresence, must reduce the subjectivities of the colonized to manageable simplications. And these simplications, after all, are the textual referents that allow him his own imagined, self-congratulatory, superiority. He is what the other is not. Consequently, structuralist sociology must always trafc in crude . . . opposition[s] (Clough 1992a:104): masculine/feminine, white/ethnic, straight/gay, rational/irrational, truth/narrative, civilized/primitive, and modern/postmodern. For Clough (107), these reductions, these simplistic binaries, are the projected possibility of an Oedipal logic of realist narrativity. These fantasized essences are always informed by the primacy of Oedipal gender roles. The preferred halves of these binaries are projected and coveted from within the masculine hope for security and controlfrom within an unconscious desire for reunication with the feminine. But because the self is decentered and constituted from within ceaseless and insecure amalgamations of textual traces, no such selfsame presence has ever been possible. Subjectivity is not something that, as Foucault (1977:170) maintains, anyone can glory in . . . since it always occurs in the interstice.17 The self is an effect without inherent structure, and, for Clough, this always unnished quest for closure is productively understood as frustrated, masculine desire. The goal, Clough says, should be to redirect sociology toward constructing itself as social criticism rather than as empirical science (1992a:134). Where I have written of civic duty for sociologists that is no longer haunted and shackled by the theological phantasm of Christian responsibility to God, she nds structuralist sociology to be encumbered by an unconscious, masculine ache for the security of a lost, centering, and nally despised femininity. Where I call for understanding the textual complexes that animate the politics or social problems that we are set to intervene in, she envisions a poststructural cultural criticism . . . to make visible the itineraries of desire in diagrams of power/knowledge (1992b:550). Both imaginaries are politically and intellectually useful. Both are in the spirit of Derridas invocation of the Levi-Straussian notion of bricolage. Both are consistent with Nietzsches observation that knowledge production is always a Will to Power. We both understand scholarship as political action designed to confront power. As Clough (1992a: 137) describes her vision of poststructuralist sociology: It is to urge a social criticism that gives up on data collection and instead offers rereadings of representations in every form of information processing, empirical science, literature, lm, television, and computer simulation.
Summary The appeal of poststructuralist writings for many of us from many backgroundsnonacademic, ethnically diverse, working class, feminine, immigrant, queer, and racializedlies in their uncontainable attacks on epistemological centers and ontological foundations. These writings are potent intellectual weapons that we can put to use in our own political defense. A poststructuralist sociology will be inclusive of difference because it will not be consumed by the need to protect any epistemological center. These difference-embracing sociologists will not insist on an extra-cultural, extrapolitical, pure origin as the foundation of their academic appraisals. Responsibility, here, is no longer theological. In summarizing chapter 3, I suggested that Millss essay, The Promise, provides an apt way to conceptualize the reexive work that structuralist sociologists can do to rethink their angst and anger over poststructuralist criticisms. I suggested that sociological investigations into the cultural history of scientic assumptions could teach sociologists to be less intransigent in their defense of
| 107
what I claim are metaphysical superstitions. I also want to point out the limits of that prescription. A poststructuralist sociology of sociology must ultimately come up against its own possibility. It must undo itself, and, in a less fearful academic climate, this is quite okay. Millss analysis, centered as it is on biography and history (on structure) cannot pass beyond its founding assumptions. De-centering the self and attacking grand, overarching narratives undercuts the twin pillars of Millss thought. This recognition does not make his analytic devices useless. Refusing to award these concepts metaphysical status is not the same as saying they are without utility. Derrida, citing the ancient Greeks, uses the word aporia to describe these productive, self-reexive moments when critical thinking comes up against its own limits. The post of poststructuralist sociology, if it is to signal an empirically scrupulous embrace of the other in a pursuit of ethics and justice, cannot tolerate denitions that move to reassert centers.
5
whos understanding whose past?
Telling the Truth about Native Dead
A clear and accurate understanding of the ancient past is something that the American public has a right to know about.
Doug Owsley, Curator of Anthropology at the Smithsonian Institution
I wish every scientist across this nation would say there is no scientic reason to hold these remains. This ought to be a standard.
Lawrence Hart, Traditional Spiritual Leader of the Cheyenne Nation and NAGPRA Review Committee Member
hile his intent is clear, Mr. Hart might more accurately have declared that there are only scientic reasons to hold the remains of deceased Native Americans in museums closets and university laboratories. Native Americans struggles with members of the scientic community for control of our dead ancestors continue with great ferocity into the new century.1 Many anthropologists, archaeologists, and osteologists remain outraged by what they see as an irreplaceable loss of scientic data to apparently backward tribal peoples who display little or no appreciation for the importance that this scientic research is said to hold for humanity as a whole. The overwhelming majority of American Indians see things quite differently. For Native peoples, the struggle to return dead family to the earth of their
| 109
homelands is just another sordid chapter in a ve-hundred-year-old struggle against colonialism. My argument in this chapter is explicitly political. My intent is that of an activist. My responsibility is for aiding in the struggle to see all deceased Native peoples returned to the care of their closest living descendants. The chapter recovers important and often systematically ignored genealogy of contemporary scientic claims to Indian dead. The scholarly goal of this recovery is to expose these scientic claims as wholly political pronouncements. The truth narrated in the accounts of scientists actively resisting the repatriation of our ancestors to our communities are recollected as a thing of this world. My aim is to demolish these scientists ability to insist on their own metaphysical agendaan agenda they insist on even as Native Americans actively resist capture in their anthropological tales. The political history of contemporary scientic claims is recovered so that their power to subjugate both living and dead Indians with pretensions to extra-political truth can be affectively arrested.
Some Conditions of Possibility: Noble Indians and Politics It is important to note that this debate, despite Indian outrage remaining constant since our dead rst began to be collected by European Americans, could not have taken place as recently as the mid-twentieth century. Tremendous changes in public understandings of American history, most notably the civil rights movement, are the conditions of possibility of Indian requests for the return of our dead being taken seriously. Although Indians, like most peoples, have never shied away from a ght to have our dead left alone, the rehabilitation of Indian people in the minds of the American public over the past thirty years has facilitated our measured political successes in the last decades. Through the 1950s, Indians remained in the public imaginary unsophisticated descendants of savages or remnant populations of a subjugated wilderness. The racializations still relied upon by sports mascots were then the dominant image of Indian people held by most Americans. Although almost as patronizing as the old constructs were insulting, the romantic at one with nature discourses of the 1960s and 1970s made savagery noble. Hordes of activists seeking to get back to nature and defend the earth as a new national ecological awareness took root, suddenly loved and admired Indians. I can vividly remember my own grandmother rolling her eyes and putting off these awestruck advances by declaring herself a sidewalk Indian. Grandma wore dresses exclusively and was never without diamond jewelry. When she took me shing, she stayed in the car or sat in a chair by the road. She had no romance with nature. Nevertheless, this remaking of Indian people in the public consciousness, imagery that Indians still get called to
Powerful Scientists What political privilege, we can ask, is concealed in Owsleys invocation and declaration of his power, in his claim to speak truthfully about the status of these remains? Where did he get this power? How was it awarded to him? How, exactly, did his scientic narration come to have more power than competing narrations made, for centuries now, by Indian people? In chapter 3, I wrote of restoring the political scars that those who claim to speak on behalf of truth must forget or erase when they invoke their powers. These political struggles (the contested history of his truth claims) must be strategically erased if Owsley is to speak with authority (has a right to know) on behalf of all of us (the American public). He must insist that there is only one correct way to remember. Thus he writes with no visible selfinterrogation of a singularly retrievable past (A clear and accurate understanding). There is only one past and Owsley claims the authority to articulate the ancient past. He and his colleagues must insist on what Judith Butler (1993:8), although in the context of a rather different discussion, calls a violent foreclosure. The scientists must place their status beyond political contest, and this is a violent act achievable only through raw power. The anger and pain contained in the pleadings of Indian people testifying at the June 2001 Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA) Review Committee Meeting reveals the violent quality of scientists attempts to close off Indian sense makings from the debate, to foreclose on any contests to scientic legitimacy that we might muster. One Pomo leader spoke of the curator at California State University as being like Hitlers great-grandson. Declaring that the university ofcial keeps his relatives locked up like they were his own private property, the former tribal chair went on to sarcastically lament, the great thing about white people is that when they steal they make a record of it. A Hopi ofcial of the
| 111
Cultural Preservation Ofce called his peoples ght for reburial a moral duty. Another native woman asserted, the dead are crying. As Butler describes this violence that I am here locating in scientists claims to speak as a singular voice of legitimacy for all of us: This delimitation, which often is enacted as an untheorized presupposition in any act of description, marks a boundary that includes and excludes, that decides, as it were, what will and will not be the stuff of the object to which we then refer. This marking off will have some normative force and, indeed, some violence, for it can construct only through erasing . . . (1993:110). The attempt to refer uncritically (as if everyone agreed with this description) to Indian remains as scientic data, as the stuff of a clear and accurate understanding, is an attempt to place ones own understanding into the realm of the extra-political. Owsley either believes or is pretending he believes that he is not acting politically. He is simply describing what the remains are and thus what they mean. He refuses to acknowledge the constitutive qualities of his description, thus removing them from the debate. He would have the American public believe that his description is only as Butler says, the stuff of the object to which we refer and not a violent political pronouncement designed to close debate about what the ancestors may be for others. You will notice that by referring to ancestors, and not to scientic objects, I insist on keeping the debate open. Very different, and strategically vital, textual relationships of diffrance inhabit these descriptors. I insist that these are people and family and not objects because, as Butler indicates, description has normative force and is therefore never simply description. For centuries scientists have attempted to close off these politics by erasing competing Indian claims. In the mouths of the scientists, our dead family members have routinely become specimens, artifacts, collections, the archaeological record, and other humiliating euphemisms. The goal in this chapter, then, is to forcefully return the scientic community to the ugly politics that continue to construct only through erasing. We will revisit (as Michel Foucault instructed in chapter 3) the profusion of lost events that are the very conditions of possibility of Owsleys power. We shall see that, like Indians, Owsley is a mere mortal. He possesses no universally valid ability or qualications that make him an authority (for all people) about the status of our dead, of what are after all Indian dead. He enjoys the power to narrate as successfully as he does only because his own ancestors came in overwhelming numbers and carried guns. We can assess and challenge this political power by interrogating the weave-like text of diffrance that Jacques Derrida, in chapter 3, taught us can never be closed off or arrested. Tracing the textual history (the genealogy) of scientic claims will not only undo the scientists ability to speak for a truth that they would have us award the status of a metaphysical presence; more importantly, this genealogy will empower us to force the textual politics of this
NAGPRA and Implementation: Where Things Stand Now In 1990 Congress passed the Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act. This law was preceded by the 1989 National Museum of the American Indian Act (NMAIA), which was aimed specically at the Smithsonian Institutions Museums. These laws were passed with the intention of forcing federally funded museums and universities to return human remains, funerary objects (items placed into graves with the dead), sacred objects, and objects of cultural patrimony (objects having ongoing historical, traditional, or cultural importance) to the tribes and to Native Hawaiians. No one knows for certain how many Native dead were taken to the countrys museums and universities by generations of collectors, but the Native American Rights Fund (NARF) estimate of 600,000 bodies is a frequently cited gure (Preston 1989:67; Thornton 1998:387). However, in testimony before the United States Senate Select Committee on Indian Affairs leading up to the passage of NAGPRA, the NARF indicated that as many as two million Native people have been dug up from their graves in the United States and are now held in the nations universities, museums, state and federal agencies, and tourist attractions (Echo-Hawk 1990:185). In addition, thousands of individuals were taken by the agents of European museums or sold by American anthropologists to the large museums of the United Kingdom, France, and Germany (Cole 1985; Nihipali 1993:17681). The Organization of American Indians Against Desecration estimates that European institutions continue to hold 500,000 dead Indian people (Hubert 1988:3). When the NMAIA became law in 1989, the largest American holder, the Smithsonian held (by its own estimates), the bodies of roughly 14,500 dead Indians. In addition, the museum was the curator of 4,000 severed Indian heads. NAGPRA directs institutions receiving federal funds to complete inventories of dead Indians and of the objects found in their graves and to report their holdings to the tribes within ve years. Sacred objects, objects of cultural patrimony, and grave contents that could not be identied as belonging to a specic deceased individual were to be inventoried within three years. All of these museums and universities were then to return the ancestors and the contents of their graves to the tribes expeditiously. Furthermore, these inventories were to be completed in consultation with tribal government and Native
| 113
Hawaiian organization ofcials and traditional religious leaders. In those cases when records do not clearly indicate the origins of remains or objects, or when ownership is in dispute, these institutions were directed to follow the preponderance . . . of evidence. Because of tireless Indian lobbying, the law states explicitly that this Act shall not be construed to be an authorization for the initiation of new scientic studies of such remains and associated funerary objects or other means of acquiring or preserving additional scientic information from such remains and objects. Indeed, tribes were specically guaranteed that they could show a preponderance of the evidence in many forms, including Native ways. Native American human remains and funerary objects shall be expeditiously returned where the requesting Indian tribe or Native Hawaiian organization can show cultural afliation by a preponderance of the evidence based upon geographical, kinship, biological, archaeological, anthropological, linguistic, folkloric, oral traditional, historical, or other relevant information or expert opinion (25 USC 3005, Sec. 7[a]4). By the time the three-year deadline for reporting objects and grave contents that could not be linked to specic ancestors came and went in 1993, the tribes had heard from only four institutions. In the cases of the Peabody Museum of Archaeology and Ethnology, the Heard Museum, and the Field Museum of Natural History, these inventories listed a grand total of one item each (National NAGPRA Online Databases: 2001). Although, as I have already said, no accurate numbers exist for cataloging the extent of the plunder of Indian country that has been stored up over the centuries in the nations museums and universities, tens of millions of pieces is a conservative estimate. Notices of inventory completion of human remains have also been slow to meet the legislated deadline. Fifty-eight institutions failed to meet the 1995 deadline and were granted extensions by the secretary of interior. By 1998, when these extensions were due, six institutions holding large numbers of remains still were in noncompliance and requesting further extensions. These extensions were denied and the institutions were given the status of forbearance that meant that civil penalties were to begin accruing. These six institutions are the American Museum of Natural History, the Phoebe A. Hearst Museum of Anthropology, the Ohio Historical Society, the New York State Museum, the Texas Archaeological Research Laboratory, and Harvard Universitys Peabody Museum of Archaeology and Ethnology. In May of 1999, the assistant secretary of the interior informed these museums and laboratories that they could avoid civil penalties by meeting their legal responsibilities by dates assigned in individual letters. Five of the six did so. The last of the six, Harvards Peabody Museum, submitted its inventory to the NAGPRA Review Committee on June 2, 2001, almost eleven years after the passage of the law. These last six institutions to come into compliance estimated that they possessed 34,764 individuals (U.S. Department of Interior: 6/2/2001). In addition, a Peabody representative testifying
| 115
Many in the scientic community continue to react with anger, disgust, and threats as reburials reach serious numbers. Those who are most openly contemptuous depict Indians as incapable or unwilling to understand that humanity can benet from the scientic stewardship of Indian dead. In this discourse, Indians are portrayed as obstinate reactionaries who, like religious and political zealots of other times and places, are holding up the advancement of knowledge with our backward superstitions. These academics see genuine appreciation of cultural others as merely an unfortunate political fashion that must be held at bay until the danger to science (as the only source of real progress) passes. Like modern day Galileos, they believe that they will emerge as true champions of human advancement and be celebrated for their perseverance by generations of scholars to come. Among the most outspoken is Clement W. Meighan who, until his recent death, was Emeritus Professor of Anthropology at UCLA. Referring to Indians as an allegedly oppressed minority whose perspectives are hostile to Western science itself (1993:13), he suggests that anthropologists who do not actively contest reburials have abandoned scholarly ethics in favor of being respectful and sensitive to non-scholars and anti-intellectuals. When the current round of controversy is over, this loss of scientic integrity will be heavily condemned (1992:706). As Meighan understands the conict with Indians, he and his colleagues are the singularly legitimate authorities who alone are capable of correctly interpreting the history of the Americas. He thus moves quickly and decisively to erase his competition. The real issue is who disowns the real past so they can sell you their mythology or other received wisdom which cannot be challenged by evidence (1996:3). As heir to a great scientic tradition, it makes perfect sense to Meighan that dead Indians are data left in the trust of current generations of anthropologists and that reburial amounts to a complete betrayal of professional responsibility. Since we commonly proclaim that archaeological collections are unique and irreplaceable, how can we ever justify the conscious and acquiescent destruction of our data? (1992:705). Professor Meighans contempt for repatriation is far from unique. Granly (1996), who is the former curator at the Buffalo Museum of Science, angrily denounces this whole idea, interjecting these unimportant considerations into science. Kennedy (1996) proclaims that myth might give you some clues as to ancestry, but in nine times out of ten, mythology is not supported by scientic endeavors. Beth Walton (1999:5) demands that: [l]ocal political considerations must be balanced with maintaining a wider view of prehistory and asserts that [i]t is the obligation of federal archaeologists to protect this archaeological material and related data. Archaeologists duty to science must be forcefully stated, Walton maintains, because [w]ith the increasing demand for the return of remains to tribal representatives (frequently without
| 117
that the tribes ght against further testing . . . is based on fear, fear that if someone else was here before they were, their status as sovereign nations, and all that comes with ittreaty rights and lucrative casinos like this one on the Umatilla reservation [camera shows a blackjack game with 100 dollar bills fanned widely across a blackjack table]could be at risk. The questions put to the scientists and to Armand Minthorn (who is a Umatilla spiritual leader and, at the time, was chair of the NAGPRA Review Committee) are purportedly those of an objective journalist trying to get at the objective truth about the scientists attempts to pursue the objective past. Yet the structure of the questions and the editing of the program were clearly designed to glorify anthropology and to disparage Indian cultures. Adopting a tone of voice used by adults when they explain what they believe to be difcult concepts to young children, Stahl leans forward in her chair, opens her eyes a little wider, and speaks ever so slowly to Chair Minthorn. Do you see why the scientists, do you understand why they want to know more about it, that they want to know everything there is to know about someone who lived 9,000 years ago, that bones can tell? Conversely, Stahls questions to the anthropologists are designed to fashion answers that frame the story in sensational and thus politically effective terms. Professors Owsley and Chatters quickly recognize the platform. At one point the reporter asks Chatters, do you think this is an attempt on the Indians part to control history? Jumping on the opportunity, the anthropologist responds: Yes, in a word I do. Theyve got a history now, the way its laid out, that ts their present-day political needs quite effectively. If that history changes, it may not t so well. The questions she asked of Owsley are equally uncritical and generous. Not once does she ask about the importance of respecting the worldviews of other cultures or seriously questioning whether science is itself a set of beliefs with a cultural history. On the contrary, she guides the anthropologist with all of the skill of the great public relations artist that she is. She unfolds proanthropology narrations of the conict and asks for validation, which the scientists eagerly provide. For example: did you not think wow this could be a signicant major nd in my eld? And, we are talking about our history? And, if its a religion [Indian views] its faith? In 2000, the Public Broadcasting Service series, NOVA, aired an equally one-sided program. The title, The Mystery of the First Americans, was indicative of the programs agenda, which was to provide a forum for scientists to attack Indian claims that our ancestors inhabited the Americas before Europeans. Of the 53 minutes of footage contained in the program, Indians got approximately 40 seconds of airtime. The program takes the form of an apologetic explanation for what is now, all too conveniently, deemed errant anthropology carried out over the last several decades (what one anthropologist interviewed refers to as our gospel). The problem for these scientists is that thousands of pages of anthropological
Friendly Anthropologists Particularly insidious are those scientists who portray themselves as friends of Indians, and therefore as less acrimonious than the openly hostile individuals just cited, while they ght Indian wishes. For example, Thomas W. Killion and Tamara L. Bray (1994:4) claim, since the conscious shedding of the colonial mantle, anthropologists have frequently assumed the role of advocate for the disenfranchised with whom they traditionally work. These archaeologists tend to see themselves as misunderstood victims. They are really the political and intellectual champions of Indians, they argue, but Indians and those inuenced
| 119
by the public comments of Indians tend not to appreciate their goodwill. Thus, these Indian-loving scientists say that the need for stepped up public relations campaigns is more urgent than ever before. Asserting, Perhaps the single greatest challenge facing archaeological preservationists is the need to become involved with primetime, as well as educational, television, Robert Mallouf (1996:2067) implores:
Do they honestly believe that scientic ndings, which have proven so important in dispelling the prejudiced European concepts of the barbarous savage are somehow deleterious to their well-being? . . . The ancient cultures that are brought back to life by archaeologists through studies of their carefully excavated artifacts provide critical linkages for Native Americans to their past. Through the act of reburial, our only hard evidence of the existence of some ancient cultures will be permanently expunged from the archaeological record. Are proponents of repatriation really correct in assuming that future generations of Native Americans will approve of what is transpiring today? Again, these are important questions that are best considered outside the sphere of emotional debate, and without pressing external inuences.
Referring to dead Indians as hard evidence that can teach live Indians about Indian history is common sentiment among this group of selfproclaimed, friendly archaeologists and physical anthropologists. Although they regularly suggest that no simple statement can explain all the reasons why they require long-term study of Native dead that they insist on calling direct tangible evidence of our [their] history (Landau and Steele 1996:20910), they have offered limited lists of those reasons they consider most important. Maintaining that an innate need to know is universally characteristic of all humans, that physical anthropologists are willing to comply with NAGPRAs terms, but the need remains for long-term study of some skeletal collections before repatriation, and that physical anthropologists have an interest in learning just who humans are, Patricia Landau and D. Gentry Steele (1996:209) offer one such list of reasons. It is critically important, these scholars suggest, to know if Europeans brought venereal diseases to the Americas or whether they already existed among Native Americans before Europeans arrived. Although not able to solve their puzzle, they note, Syphilis spread rapidly and tragically among Native American populations as they came into contact with Europeans. Native remains, they argue, provide humankind with one of the best documented records of complex origin, spread, and reinfestation of venereal syphilis (Landau and Steele 1996:21112). Next, Landau and Steele inform us that some Mississippi Valley Indians intentionally altered the cranial development of their young by tying bands or at surfaces to the heads of growing children. Without the study of living Indians dead ancestors, they worry,
Anthropologists Take Their Friends to Court Two of these anthropologists, Steele and Owsley, have joined six of their colleagues in ling a lawsuit against the federal government and ve Indian nations
| 121
that is designed to render major provisions of NAGPRA effectively useless to Native people. If allowed to stand, the February 4, 2004 decision (Bonnichsen, Robson v. United States of America) issued by the Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals, provides ample opportunity for anthropologists to halt the return of hundreds of thousands of our ancestors. Perhaps most frustrating about this challenge is that it was fully anticipated by the Native activists who fought to get NAGPRA passed in the rst place. Recall that the law specically states that cultural afliation between tribes and our dead can be demonstrated by a preponderance of evidence and that this evidence absolutely includes folkloric, and oral traditional knowledge. Clearly, the intention of lawmakers was to validate Native ways of knowing and, at the behest of the bills Indian proponents, to guard against any future attack on oral cultures. Although I cited this language, it is worth reiterating here. To be certain their intentions were clear, and that scientists could not use Indian requests for documentation of museum and laboratory holdings as an excuse to further denigrate dead ancestors, the law includes the following language. Such term [documentation] does not mean, and this Act shall not be construed to be an authorization for, the initiation of new scientic studies of such remains and associated funerary objects or other means of acquiring or preserving additional scientic information from such remains and objects (25 USC 3003, 2a). Nevertheless, in ruling that the Ancient One must be handed over to the anthropologists, Judge Ronald M. Gould devalues and ignores the Native oral histories brought before his court. He values and legitimates only the European American anthropologists ways of knowing and explicitly dismisses those parts of the law designed to protect Indians from scientists. Indians, then, are put in the dubious position of needing scientists and science to prove that our dead are worthy of being protected from science and scientists.
. . . we conclude that these accounts are just not specic enough or reliable enough or relevant enough to show a signicant relationship of the Tribal Claimants with Kennewick Man. Because oral accounts have been inevitably changed in context of transmission, because the traditions include myths that cannot be considered as factual histories, because the value of such accounts is limited by concerns of authenticity, reliability, and accuracy, and because the record as a whole does not show where historical fact ends and mythic tale begins, we do not think that the oral traditions of interest . . . were adequate to show the required signicant relationship of Kennewick Mans remains to the Tribal Claimants (Bonnichsen, Robson v. United States of America 14:1607).
One of the archaeological organizations repeatedly declaring its friendship with Indians is the Society for American Archaeology (SAA). This group has sixty-six hundred members and is the largest organization of professional archaeologists in North America. In a 1995 publication, Ethics in American
If our friends and advocates in the anthropological community succeed in helping federal judges hold that only anthropology is qualied to determine which of our ancestors living Indians are related to, then NAGPRAfor the hundreds of thousands of our dead and over a million funerary objects that have yet to be returnedmay be worth little more than the paper it is written on. The Bonnichsen, Robson v. United States of America ruling and the supporting anthropological briefs are particularly galling given that the Code of Federal Regulations (CFR) developed to enforce NAGPRA were designed specifically to safeguard against Congress concern for exactly this scientic attack on Native cultures. The regulations clearly state: the connection between the claimant and the material being claimed . . . should not be precluded solely because of some gaps in the record; and that geographical, kinship . . . linguistic, folklore, oral tradition all constitute evidence of cultural afliation; and nally claimants do not have to establish cultural afliation with scientic certainty (Dept. of the Interior, CFR 10.14 [d], [e], [f]). Despite the law and these regulations, Indians are made to endure Judge Goulds (2003:14,1607 fn. 23) explicit thanks for the authority of anthropologists who brazenly insist that their scientic certainty is only and exactly what
| 123
is required: we nd of considerable help the explanations of the uses and limits on oral narratives as explained and documented with scholarly authority. And, these anthropologists are quite forthright about their low opinion of Native ways. Nor do they mince words about the rightful place of anthropology as the ultimate arbiter of any disputes between competing cultural traditions. Asserting that these evaluations must be as objective as possible, Andrei Simic and Harry G. Custred Jr. (2003:8,11) claim: Scholars have learned that the authenticity, reliability and accuracy of any oral tradition must be determined through appropriate analysis and evaluation. In the absence of careful study, oral traditions cannot be accepted as reliable evidence of past events. . . . The tribes made no attempt to test their oral tradition evidence to determine whether it is authentic, credible and accurate. Because of that failure the evidence and any conclusions based on it should have been rejected. In an epigraph to this chapter, we heard a Department of Interior ofcial warn, We dont police NAGPRA. We work with materials sent to us. Clearly, if these anthropologists have their way, and only time will tell whether the courts will continue to reinforce their colonialist power, they alone will police NAGPRA.5
Forever Culturally Unidentiable? Over 600 of the nations museums and universities have declared 118,400 Native dead and 852,641 items taken from their graves as culturally unidentiable. This means roughly three times the number of Indians who have been returned to their communities by all federally funded institutions except the NMAI remain stranded, away from their graves and families (National NAGPRA Online Databases 2007). Speaking before the September 2004 NAGPRA Review Committee, Suzan Harjo (Cheyenne and Hodulgee Muscogee) worried about the consequences of federal regulations being developed to govern so many ancestors. She noted that the draft regulations characterize human beings as the property of the repositories that hold them. She went on to call for greater consultation with the tribes, pointing out that these relatives are unidentied and not unidentiable. Considered together, scientic attacks on the oral history clause of NAGPRA and the placement of the vast majority of our dead into an unidentiable status begin to look like a strategy. Should anthropologists succeed in forcing through a judicial reading of NAGPRA that validates only scientic ways of knowing, we will not see these ancestors returned anytime soon. The stakes for insisting on the thoroughly cultural and political qualities of science and scientists could not be much higher. The language and numbers cited thus far provide us with a clear sample of objections to repatriation that scientists continue to raise in their writings,
Victims Re-collections: How Indians Became the Archaeological Record No one can seriously suggest that had Indians won the nineteenth century wars with Europeans we would now be ghting to have the remains of our dead returned to us. Only with military victories came the power to narrate the history of the continent and the reality of its rst inhabitants. Even the name Indian is of course the result of Christopher Columbuss misreading his location by about half the span of the globe. Europeans brought their ways of knowing and their understandings of their history with them, and they have almost always used these cultural phenomena as if they were somehow obviously and naturally, indeed universally, applicable. In short, to this day most archaeologists fail to see their own culture as culture, preferring to elevate their own understandings to the status of the real and to demote all others to mythology, superstition, and religion. An innate need to know, Landau and Steele tell us, is universally characteristic of all humans. How are we to read the discrepancy between this assertion of a comprehensive need and hundreds of years of Indian statements of exactly the opposite sentiment? When Landau and Steele testify that physical anthropologists have an interest in knowing just who humans are, are they not putting us on notice that knowing is only their domain? There is really no conceivable way that these scientists could not have heard the repeated and angry rebuttals of Native peoples from the Atlantic Coast to the Hawaiian Islands. As Bronco Lebeau (1996), who is repatriation ofcer for the Lakota, characterizes this attitude, I want to tell you something sir. My ancestors are not a book. When I die and am placed in the ground I dont want to be dug up and thought of as a book (according to you guys traditions). We think it is very arrogant or ignorant (could be a combination of both). Where do you guys get off saying you know who we are? We know who we are. We know where we came from. This need to know is universally human but Indians (who these Indianadoring scientists certainly count as human and cannot avoid hearing from) dont possess this need to dig up our dead. As Lebeau and countless other Indians over the centuries have repeated, we know who we are and we know where we came from. Thus the only credible reading of these scientists words is that they do not recognize Indians accounts as worthy of serious consideration. Like Stahl in the 60
| 125
Minutes program just discussed, and like generations of benevolent white politicians, Landau and Steele are asserting that apparently unsophisticated Indians do not understand what is good for us. Because we are, like stubborn children, incapable of understanding what we really want, they must force us to accept what they (our parent-like superiors) know is good for us. Since this need to know is a universal human characteristic, it follows that only uncivilized or unenlightened or primitive (and the reader can here choose to insert any of the old colonialist labels) peoples do not recognize the obviously legitimate beseeching of anthropologists who, in the self-aggrandizing ethnocentrism of their colonialist logic, are the only ones capable of understanding just who humans are. Again, it seems that there is no other way to read these remarks. Either Indians are child-like inferiors of anthropologists or the scientists are ethnocentric colonialists. The attack on Indian graves that continues in the pronouncements of Landau and Steele (a colonial attack that Lebeau, in quite un-child-like fashion, clearly recognizes as patronizing) began almost immediately after Europeans set foot in the Americas. We know from their own diaries that in 1620 Pilgrims looted the grave of an Indian child, making off with sundry of the prettiest things (Thornton 1998:387). We also know that President Thomas Jefferson opened thousands of Indian graves, collecting their contents as data for use in his anthropological debates with French intellectuals over the evolutionary potential of the New World environment (Beider 1990:1;1996:168; D. H. Thomas 2000:3035). Anthropology in the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries was the work of unabashed racists who never tired of pointing out the scholarly qualities of their studies. Like the other ora and fauna of the New World, these thinkers surmised, Indians had to be placed within an Aristotelian and Christian taxonomy of natural history. Predictably, Indians and the other dark-skinned peoples of the planet fell somewhere below white Europeans in the logic of the Christian Creation. Europeans were thought to most closely resemble the rst human beings. That is, they were closest to the perfection of Gods Creation. Often this argument was based on evidence as suspect as the presumed landing of Noahs Ark. Given that this point was said to be in the Caucasus Mountains of Europe, Caucasians (having been least impacted by distant environments) were assumed to be the most immediate to Gods archetype (D. H. Thomas 2000:37). On the other hand, the theory put forth by Dr. Samuel Morton (one of the early workers and pioneers praised by Ubelaker and Grant) proposed that there were really multiple gene pools derived of multiple creations. This argument avoided the messy business of documenting exactly how the non-white races had deteriorated since the time of the Creation or since their ancestors wandered away from Noahs beached Ark. Morton surmised that the deciencies of dark-skinned peoples were original, and he made it his business to scientifically document the differences between the races, particularly those relating to intelligence and temperament.
| 127
planet, natural selection ensured that the strongest and thus most advanced survived while weaker genetic strains died out. This was to become the logic of Manifest Destiny, justifying the usurping of the Americas as the inherent destiny of a more advanced European civilization. Anthropologists of the last half of the nineteenth and rst decades of the twentieth centuries were sure that Indians would soon be extinct and that little could be done to arrest the laws of evolution. Although perhaps sad, it became their academic duty to record these doomed lifestyles and to preserve evidence of the physiological deciencies leading to Indians demise for future generations to ogle and ponder. Given this growing anthropological responsibility, in 1868 the surgeon general of the United States issued an order to troops in the eld informing them that
a craniological collection was commenced last year at the Army Medical Museum and it already includes 143 specimens of skulls. The chief purpose . . . in forming this collection is to aid in the progress of anthropological science by obtaining measurements of a large number of skulls of aboriginal races of North America. Medical ofcers stationed in Indian country or in the vicinity of ancient mounds or cemeteries . . . have peculiar facilities for promoting this undertaking. They have already enriched the Mortonian and other magnicent craniological cabinets by their contributions and it is hoped that they will evince even greater zeal in collecting for their own museum. (cited in Bieder 1990:319)
Retrieving this federal order, we can see that Indian communities are justiably outraged when anthropologists and archaeologists refer to our war dead as our [their] collections. Thousands of bodies and severed heads were removed from battleelds and tribal cemeteries as a direct result of this federal policy during years of armed conict. Personnel aboard naval vessels patrolling the West Coast also took the opportunity to empty graves when they could be found and shipped the contents eastward. Surely, contemporary members of the scientic community do not expect that Indians will accept that these dead warriors and their families, which amount to morbid spoils of war, are collections assembled by early workers. As Russell Thornton (1998:394) has argued, what would be the reaction if the Republic of Vietnam refused to return the remains of American service men and women killed there? What if they said: we want to keep them and study them. They have much scientic value? The systematic desecration of Indian graves by generations of anthropologists and their hired help was thought to be nothing less than a calling, and this attitude continued well into the twentieth century. Museums and their wealthy contributors spent hundreds of thousands of dollars for collection expeditions into Indian country. These men knew that Indians did not want their dead taken from the ground. They acknowledged this openly in their
| 129
spoke as a nonpolitical proponent of truth, she would not know whether to laugh, cry, or scream. Yet, this is the preposterous position she is advancing. Walton writes, Local political considerations must be balanced with maintaining a wider view of prehistory. Indians who want our desecrated, looted ancestors back, and tribes that want to see our war heroes returned to our homelands, are local political considerations. Walton, on the other hand, is capable of maintaining (even in the face of overly emotional Indians pining away for our dead) a less narrow, wider view. By my (admittedly emotional reading), it does not seem unfair to suggest that Lebeaus rather astonished analysis is an astute one: Arrogance or ignorance? Could be a combination of both. Given what appears the obvious superiority of the Indian faculty of memory, at least relative to that of these scientists, Professor Mallouf (also cited above) ought to understand our hesitation when he suggests, through the act of reburial our only hard evidence . . . will be permanently expunged from the archaeological record. To expunge, of course, means to erase or blot out something that has a prior presence. To suggest that reburial will permanently expunge from the archaeological record is to give this anthropological invention (the contested history of which we are now tracing) a preexisting and nonpolitical reality. The archaeological record exists, Mallouf is saying, and Indians are trying to erase it. Mallouf must forget or ignore that what he wants to call an archaeological record is a highly contested narration and one that is born in the racist projects of his scientic predecessors. He must forget that this racist science is exactly the same racism that resulted in the widespread anthropological grave-robbing that brought him his hard evidence in the rst place. Once again Indians have to ask, who is expunging what here? Recall that Mallouf asks, do they honestly believe that scientic ndings, which have proven so important in dispelling the prejudiced European concepts of the barbarous savage are somehow deleterious to their well-being? Yet barely a hundred years prior, we heard the president of the American Association for the Advancement of Science clamor for the profound and prolonged investigation of savage tribes. Relying on Indian memories (which current generations of anthropologists need not do since their predecessors kept records of their own barbarous savagery and stored it in libraries and museums all over the country), it seems obvious that science has, on the contrary, produced and not dispelled prejudiced European concepts. Surely, then, it is compounded foolishness to suggest that dead Indians, removed from their graves in an attempt to prove prejudiced European concepts, should now be kept from the tribes because they have saved us from these same prejudiced European concepts? Indians, then have a right to inquire, does Mallouf honestly believe that his claim that ancient cultures are brought back to life by archaeologists through studies of their carefully excavated artifacts does not bear a striking
| 131
guns, hired a lawyer to press their grievance. Predictably Boas and his helpers escaped any legal sanctions; they also managed to purloin the remains out of British Columbia by falsifying shipping invoices. In 1899, Boas wrote to Chief Hamasaka insisting that the Kwakiutl have no better friend than I. Yet by early 1901 he was scolding his agent in the eld for not doing his level best to send to the Museum material enough to justify our continued expenses (quoted in Cole 1985:159). The Indians were not stupid and before long Boass agent, by then a known body stealer, was forbidden entry to tribal lands. Nonetheless, and as always owing to Boass bribes and upbraidings, the contents of a large Indian mausoleum were collected in 1904. Boass agent was able to buy off two of the locals, but, as part of the deal, he agreed to be seen pretending to leave town so as to reduce the vigilance of suspicious tribal members. To seal the backroom agreement, Boas and his agent agreed to wait until most of the tribe had left for seasonal work at the canneries when the theft could be more easily accomplished (15862). Even worse than Boas, and among Indian people perhaps the most notorious cemetery thief of all, was Dr. Ales Hrdlicka, still referred to by some tribal elders as Old Hard Liquor. Despite his infamy in Indian country, Hrdlicka was showered with the praise of his anthropological colleagues both during his lifetime and posthumously. Another of Ubelaker and Grants early workers and pioneers, his list of honors and accomplishments includes being elected the rst president of the American Association of Physical Anthropology and being appointed chair and curator of the Anthropology Department at the Smithsonian Institution. He was elected president of the Washington Academy of Sciences, was awarded the Huxley Memorial Medal of the Royal Institute of Anthropology of Great Britain and Ireland, and even had one of the U.S. liberty ships built during World War II commissioned in his name. In 1969 his countrymen at the Czechoslovak Academy of Sciences dedicated their entire Annual Anthropological Congress to his memory on the one hundredth anniversary of his birth. The same year, the United States National Museum opened its new Anthropological Exhibit Hall complete with a celebratory bust of Hrdlicka looking down upon the dedication. In 1904, Professor Hrdlicka published his Directions for Collecting Information and Specimens for Physical Anthropology. Perhaps recognizing that his instructions for travelers might prove to be too gruesome for the less than anthropologically inclined to carry out, Hrdlicka sought to steel them with praise for the coming atrocities.
[T]here are . . . men to whom science has often been indebted, whose good will, when opportunities arise, might result in much benet to physical anthropology. Among these are foreign missionaries and teachers, particularly among other peoples than the whites; explorers, primarily interested in other sciences; miners, prospectors, and surveyors and engineers of railroads; men engaged in trades
Although he refers to ancient burial place[s], Hrdlicka makes it clear that the newly deceased are not only valued by his institution but even preferred. He urges, [t]he fresher the product the better; but even if decomposition is advancing the body is still of undiminished value (1904:17). He provides instructions for combating the smell and emphasizes that he is absolutely wanting in such parts of the body as the brain, or other soft organs and in racial fetal material (67). Dead children and babies, or as Hrdlicka prefers to say, embryological and infant material, are especially prized. This is because [i]t is this material alone from which may be learned racial differences or similarities in the early phases of development, and it is this material alone which can give instructive developmental series of brains, bones of the skull and skeleton, teeth, etc., for Museum exhibits (17). Admitting that robbing Indian graves, including those of children and babies is certain to produce outrage (labeling his delement delicate and difcult), he nonetheless went on to provide precise and macabre instructions for extracting Indian brains.
In taking out the brain, make a scalp cut from ear to ear over the top of the head and push and dissect the skin backward and forward until most of the skull-cap is exposed. Mark your proposed cut with a knife. Cut the bone right above the supraorbital ridges and low along the sides, nishing below the occipital protuberance. Use all care not to injure the brain (it will be of value, however, even if slightly injured). To avoid cuts of the brain substance do not saw the bone wholly through, but help to detach the cap with hammer and chisel. . . . When the skull cap is lifted, cover the sharp edges of the back part of the skull with cotton or cloth. . . . Begin to remove the brain from the front. Cut nerves and, nally, the spinal cord . . . and helping with one hand from within, receive the brain into the palm of the other hand. If there is any possibility of doing so, weigh the brain immediately after extraction. (1904:16, emphasis in original)
This revered man of anthropology concludes his instructions by coaching his ghouls to hide their work by wiring the skull back together and by combing the hair over all. Finally, he attaches a copy of the color standards published by Pierre-Paul Broca (yet another of Ubelaker and Grants pioneers). It is important, Hrdlicka explains, for the brain to be labeled with the exact skin color of the corpse.
| 133
Hrdlicka was certainly not above carrying out his own thefts. In 1929 he wrote in his eld notes of an irate widow who appeared to be provoked as he made off with her husbands body. He also recorded that he opened graves where the remains are too fresh yet, and of packing bones in a new heavy pail thrown out probably on the occasion of the last funeral (quoted in Pullar 1994:2122). In another self-recorded atrocity, Hrdlicka went so far as to help stage a fake burial for a deceased Greenlander (whose son was fully taken in by the sham) only to later boil the esh from the bones that he then studied and displayed. The duped son learned of the real fate of his father only after he came across his skeleton years later in a museum display case (Preston 1989:71). But Hrdlickas most well-known transgressions took place between 1931 and 1936 on Kodiak Island in Alaska. The reason for this notoriety, however, has little to do with the extent or specic character of the plunder that took place there. Rather, the struggle for the dead of Larsen Bay, Alaska is infamous because it involved the Smithsonian and because the institutions Anthropology Department struggled mightily to avoid returning what two of their members noted amounted to nearly 5 percent of the Smithsonians skeletal collection from North America and thus threatened the loss of an important biological collection (Bray and Killion 1994:5). In the fall of 1987, the chair of the department responded to tribal elders request for the return of the relatives that Hrdlicka had removed from their graves sixty years prior. The patronizing tone and claims to power contained in Dr. Kaepplers letter are by now familiar. As you are no doubt aware, the issue of deaccession is a complex one, which the Smithsonian must consider in light of the Institutions responsibility to hold its collections in trust for the benet of all people, not just discrete interest groups. Before we can seriously consider such a request, we must be presented with compelling legal reasons justifying the transfer of remains from our collections (quoted in Bray and Killion 1994:188). Kaeppler labels the Indians request an issue of deaccession. Taken literally, what this narration says is that Indian dead have always been accessible to her and to her colleagues, and the people of Larsen Bay want to terminate her access. By this logic the whole of existence, as long as it can be said to have scientic value, could be claimed for anthropological access. Access, as Kaeppler uses the term, is not something violently assumed by those with the power to insist upon it. Yet, and this is also now all too familiar, Kaeppler puts us on notice that those of us who disagree with her right to access had better be ready with compelling legal reasons. By claiming to be the champion of all people, Kaeppler is of course claiming that her motives are not political maneuverings; but if her actions were not political ones (if she really spoke for some selfsame category, all people), would she really need the weight of politically legislated laws (compelling legal reasons) to protect what she must secretly believe to be her peoples possessions from other (Indian) people?
| 135
these Indian requests to stand out from all other requests. The Larsen Bay request is special in Kaepplers eyes and not because she has any basis for claiming that these bodies came from other than a Larsen Bay tribal burial ground. Without saying so explicitly, she has claimed as her own prerogative, the right to narrate what is commonplace and obvious and what is extraordinary. The tribes request, then, is such a request precisely because in the world Kaeppler inherited (where she and her anthropologist colleagues have always enjoyed the power to narrate truth), her status (she who speaks for the benet of all people) is so obvious as to apparently not even require explanation. After all, is it not only a power so taken-for-granted as to not require any explicit justication that could allow Kaeppler to not appear ridiculous to herself when she moves to label the families of Hrdlickas victims a discreet interest group? The crux of the problem, then, is that these naive Natives have the audacity not to recognize the assumed obviousness of Kaepplers status. This indiscretion (forcing her to make her power explicit) is what makes the Indian request special, as in such a request. In placing the Indians failure to pay homage to her power beyond the realm of what is normal, she insists upon normalizing her anthropological discourse and cultural setting as the legitimate forum where requests must be made (or at least those that are to be taken seriously). Native families nally reburied approximately a thousand of Hrdlickas victims in October of 1991, four years after the tribes request and two years after the NMAI act nally provided Kaeppler with her compelling legal reasons. Yet another of the nations most famous anthropologists, and one who is also infamous among many Indians, was Dr. George Dorsey. Dorsey was awarded Harvards rst Ph.D. in anthropology and went on to become the curator of the Chicago Field Museum. In part, Dorseys infamy stems from his penchant for seeking out and robbing the graves of Indian spiritual leaders. One of these violations took place in 1897 in Tlingit country.
At ten oclock we started toward the east again. We . . . [were] disappointed in not nding the grave of a Shaman or medicine man. . . . We had been slowly working away at the oars, for the wind had completely died away, and were rounding a point on Duke Island, when we espied one of these little houses perched far up on a rocky point which was piled high with innumerable drift. We were soon ashore . . . and found ourselves well repaid for our pains. The house was about thirty years old, and its roof was covered with a thick growth of moss. . . . Removing a portion of the one of the walls, we could see the body, which had been carefully tied into a neat bundle with stout cedar-bark rope. . . . Removing the wrapping still further, we disclosed the desiccated body of a woman doctor. In one hand she clasped a long knife, its steel blade entirely wasted away, leaving only the handle. In the other hand was a beautifully carved wooden pipe inlaid with nely polished abalone shells. (Dorsey 1898:17273)
Storing and Protecting Data Indians have great difculty reconciling the kind of steal, hide, and run operations carried out by Boas, Hrdlicka, and Dorsey with the claims to careful storage and cataloging made by modern archaeologists. Recall that Mallouf refers to our ancestors as carefully excavated artifacts, and Landau and Steele characterize these dead as having been assembled by early workers like Hrdlicka and Morton. Similarly, Amy Danise (2000), an anthropologist from the Nevada State Museum (NSM), reacts with indignation to suggestions that scientists are not good stewards, claiming the NSMs bodies are always carefully stored. Scientists opposing reburial rarely miss an opportunity to congratulate themselves on the detailed and immaculate ends to which they go to document and care for Indian remains, even referring to this effort, as does Dr. Walton, as her obligation to protect . . . archaeological material and related data. For many Native people, these claims are both bothersome and amusing. First of all, they assume that the scientists concern for careful storage makes the desecration of our dead less revolting. But the claims themselves are also difcult to believe. If the most famous of anthropologists had to evade and deceive as they went about their collecting, why should we assume that innumerable and less famous body snatchers were any less harried and any more careful in their eld work? How can these dead Natives be both carefully excavated and assembled and culturally unidentiable? And if after all these years Indians are now being told that these museums and laboratories have little or no clues as to the identities or origins of nearly 120,000 bodies, on what basis are we to believe that they have been fawned over by generations of caring anthropological hands?
| 137
Douglas Preston (1989), who was former manager of the Department of Publications at the Smithsonians Museum of Natural History, has written of opening the door to his ofce and being nearly knocked down by the smell of mothballs. Investigating further, he soon learned that he shared an adjoining wall with the Anthropology Department and that the cheap plasterboard was no match for the overwhelming odor of paradichlorobenzene crystals that were used to keep the bodies free of insects. To his further dismay, Preston (66,71) soon learned that there were stacks of human bones and mummied body parts that languished unstudied, for the most part, in museum drawers. Dont anthropologists need to know whom they have and where they came from, if our dead are to be of some use to them? Otherwise, wont any old body do? They need dead Indians, they claim, but then they tell us that they do not know which Indians they have, where they came from, or when their graves were disturbed. How is this careful study? Consider the following example of scientic rigor as revealed in a NAGPRA Notice of Inventory Completion published by the University of Nebraska. The university admits to holding at least 313 individuals and knows all of the following about them, At an unknown date, human remains . . . were recovered from an unknown location by person(s) unknown under unknown circumstances. They were acquired by the University of Nebraska State Museum at an unknown date under unknown circumstances. No known individual was identied. . . . The assigned number 68/1929 has no known documentation (Federal Register 2000, 65:191:58805) Why should anthropologists be allowed to have it both ways? Are Native dead hard evidence, carefully excavated artifacts, and an archaeological record, that can be brought back to life, or are they culturally unidentiable? If the anthropologists dont know what cultures these dead are derived from, how can they simultaneously claim that continuing to hold them will ensure that this history is not lost? If scientists really want to be friends with Indians, they ought to simply admit to the shameful quality of much of what they now wish to call careful storage. More importantly, they should not use the shabby record keeping of their predecessors as a tool to stall the return of our dead. They should help Indians get into their institutions. They should listen to what our elders have to say about whatever records do exist. And they should not dismiss our oral recollections as myths, or as not factual. They should never use their own uncertainty as a strategy for holding onto our stolen ancestors. Indians should decide where Indian dead belong. An additional impediment to repatriation is that NAGPRA does not legally force anthropologists and museums to return the ancestors of those tribes that were never federally recognized or that have had their recognition terminated. This is a much larger problem in some statesfor example, California and Ohiothan it is in others. In central California, the ferocity of
| 139
already occurred, the AIM members physically removed shovels from the groups hands, lled in graves, and burned archaeologists notes. In other instances, lands long inhabited by the tribes (and therefore full of old villages and burials) were made into national parks, thus guaranteeing federal protection of grave desecrations by university and museum personnel. One particularly outrageous example occurred in Mesa Verde National Park in Colorado where NAGPRA will soon force the repatriation to the southwestern tribes of more than 1,500 dead Natives and more than 4,800 items taken from their graves. The Federal Register Report required by NAGPRA (1999 64 [166]:46936949) is a full 28 pages long and details excavations lasting from 1909 to 1990. With the blessing of the National Park Service, the interred remains of an entire civilization was (as we heard Brinton promise that it would be) dug up and carted off to southwestern museums and universities. It is also untrue that modern anthropologists have only been interested in digging up ancient burials. The Wisconsin Archaeological Society has opened graves of the Menominee that contained such ancient artifacts as combs, earrings, and brooches. In 1972, The State Museum of Pennsylvania violated the nal resting places of 86 Native people, removing snuffboxes, mouth harps, perfume bottles, cuff links, spectacles, coins, mirrors, thimbles, pieces of shoes, a vanity box, and even a crucix from the graves. In 2001, NAGPRA forced the Nevada State Museum to admit that it held the bones of a very unancient Native person as well as the shoes, clothing (four different fabric types), and ring she wore to her funeral. The NSM scientists even took the kitchen knife that she was buried with (Federal Register 2000 65, 207:6388687; 2001 66,58:1649092; 2001 66,18:7398). New burials were not placed off-limits to archaeologists until the passage of the Archaeological Resources Protection Act (ARPA) of 1979. Nevertheless, as the name of the act suggests, the law was difcult for Indian people to celebrate. Although it stated that no item shall be treated as an archaeological resource . . . unless such item is at least 100 years of age (16 U.S.C. 470aa470mm. Public Law 9695:10/31/1979), it also gave unprecedented legal codication to scientic narrations of Natives graves. The term archaeological resource means any material remains of past human life or activities which are of archaeological interest . . . such determination shall include, not be limited to: pottery, basketry, bottles, weapons, projectiles, tools, structures, or portions of structures, pit houses, rock paintings, rock carvings, intaglios, graves, human skeletal materials, or any portion of the forgoing items (16 US.C. 470aa-470mm. Public Law 9695:10/31/79). Indeed the law is best read as a political maneuver designed to combat growing Indian organization against grave robbing, in part by attempting to distance archaeology from its long history of politically damaging, Frankenstein-like habits. If the phrase any material remains . . . which are of archaeological interest is not sufcient indication of the real purpose of the act, other passages
| 141
We know from chapters 2 and 3 that the nineteenth-century claim to have severed knowledge from religious faith fails to adequately interrogate the metaphysical desires that seventeenth-century progenitors of science imported from theology and Greek philosophy. But the problem here is greater than simply not recognizing the conditions of possibility of ones own sense-makings. The much larger intellectual shell-game contained in attempts to roll back Indian claims to Indian dead by branding our outrage religious is that those wielding these attacks do not recognize that they are smearing us with the blood of political slogans fashioned during the European Enlightenmenta massive and foreign sociopolitical reorganization that Indians had absolutely nothing to do with. We can make this point by recalling two previously cited assaults on the ostensibly religious qualities of Indian beliefs. Quoting a host of archaeologists, the October 22, 1996 front page of the New York Times announced: Indian Tribes Creationists Thwart Archaeologists. The article went on to insist that adhering to their own creationist accounts as adamantly as biblical creationists adhere to the book of Genesis, Indian tribes have stopped important archaeological research on hundreds of prehistoric remains. We also heard the president of the Friends of Americas Past organization threaten the NAGPRA committee with lawsuits for violating the rst amendment should they use religious beliefs to make secular decisions. Referring to a growing chasm between tribal views and the scientic and public interest in the past, President Hawkinson went on to equate her organizations call for meaningful standards with common sense. The power of these arguments to move public opinion stems from their artful enlisting of victorious political rhetoric taken over from much older European political struggles, struggles subsequently institutionalized into the founding documents of the American Republic. Virtually every American has been taught something of the cultural clashes contained in the overcoming of the European Dark Ages by the European Enlightenment. From the earliest days of our formal education, Americans are taught to admire the wisdom of those who constitutionally separated church and state. Nearly every American child also knows of the religious fanatics who settled the east coast of North America and burned innocents at the stake. Indeed the logic of this lunacy is so well-known that we now refer to any unjust inquiry as a witch-hunt. This popular culture is reinforced by less well-known but still substantial understandings of the horrors perpetrated under the theological authority of the European Inquisition. Most Americans know, for example, that church leaders persecuted Galileo for suggesting that the earth revolves around the sun. If this history is insufcient to remind us of how far we have progressed, there is never any shortage of religious zealots about who delight in shouting offensive buffoonery. (Recall, for example, the Reverends Fallwell and Robertson who asserted in the wake of the September 11 attacks on the World
| 143
Americans have quite appropriately learned to oppose as religious. Indian understandings may be many things, but they are not reducible to the ongoing folly of Christendom. They are not the European religion overcome by European Enlightenment. This unwillingness or inability to intellectually interrogate the colonialist imposition found in the conation of European political history and precontact Native understandings is signaled by the ease with which, in an earlier passage, we heard Hawkinson reduce the maneuver to one of common sense. In plain English, if you use religious beliefs to make secular recommendations, the decisions resulting from your recommendations are vulnerable to challenge for violating the rst amendment. . . . It is time for the committee to bridge the growing chasm between tribal views and the scientic and public interest in the past. We must uphold the constitution, create meaningful standards, and apply them fairly using common sense (2001). Hawkinson is asserting her power in no uncertain terms. She is warning the committee, lecturing them, threatening, and insulting this distinguished group that includes venerated Native elders and spiritual leaders. Her narration and her history, she insists, are the only possible common ground (the scientic and public interest in the past), and the indignity she feels from the challenge (a growing chasm) to her power is detectable in her tone (In plain English. . . .). The irony of claiming European political history as her basis for not acting politically, of being scientic, borders on the absurd when Hawkinson insists that the founding political document of the American republic should be obviously and easily recognized as common ground. How can someone whose profession is to study cultures fail so very miserably in her analysis of what is rstly and fundamentally a struggle between competing cultures? Why is the Constitution common when not only different cultures but different nations are at the table? The arrogance and ignorance found in these archaeological attacks on Indian ways is not always a matter of conating European history with all peoples histories. Often scientists simply move to, as we heard Butler warn in the early pages of this chapter, erase the perspectives of cultural others. Recall that Hawkinson instructed the NAGPRA committee members that they may not accept evidence that links religious stories with historical events to show that those religious beliefs point to a pre-history that is true. If history is true then pre-history, by denition, is what exists before the real authorities arrive. Archaeological writings are replete with this insult. These scientists do not say Native understandings or Indian history. On the contrary, Indian understandings of the centuries that passed before the rather recently ashore anthropologists got off of the boat, are deemed prehistory. To say that those times are pre-history is literally to say that there were no Europeans around to correctly record them. (The real issue is who disowns the real past, Meighan asserts.) If the only stories that count as true
Genealogy as Political Work Social scientists, politicians, policy writers, and anyone interested in NAGPRA have a difcult but clear-cut choice to make. Because Native people are forcefully insisting on reclaiming Native dead, and because these relatives were taken from their graves against the wishes of multiple generations of Native people, there really is no middle ground to be had. Either archaeology came with the colonizers and has its metaphysical imperatives rooted in their history, or it is a universally superior form of assessing the true signicance of dead Indians and should be forced on unwilling and still unsophisticated, living Indians. On the other hand, to stand with the tribes in this struggle is to acknowledge the cultural, historical, and political qualities of scientic desires. Science, here, cannot be the basis for politics. Science is politics. Indeed it is precisely the failure to critically interrogate the history of inherited metaphysical desireslike those we heard structuralist sociologists defend in each of the previous chaptersthat has caused this long, ugly, cultural clash. One wonders how Patricia Hill-Collins (1997:36) might have us understand the ght over NAGPRA, even as she blames racism on faculty members whose objectivity failed. Objectivity? Native peoples struggles with anthropologists point unequivocally to the danger of continued faith in this cultural fantasy. Her calls for renewing and strengthening this faith are exactly the opposite of what might nally solve this intercultural debacle. Jonathan H. Turners (1998a:256) urging to push ideology to the background is equally useless. Whose ideology? Not only do many Native people see science as ideology, we tend to see it as imposed ideology. It is an ideology of self-loathing discipline in the pursuit of no ideology, which, as I have repeatedly said, is a self-contradicting dream sustainable only through theologylike faith. Similarly, Peter Bergers (1963/2005:34) boast that the sociologist tries to see what is there despite hopes or fears concerning what he may nd has no meaningful application to this political debate. Sociology is a powerful way of knowing, but it is a child of the European Enlightenment and it comes with deeply ingrained European assumptions about humans and existence. To speak in this intercultural context of overcoming hopes and fears in pursuit of
| 145
what is [really] there makes no more sense than calling for guidance from Olympic Gods or praying to Christ on his cross. Foucault (1971/1977:148) warned, the metaphysician will try to place his or her own present needs at the origin, seeking to convince us of an obscure purpose that seeks its realization at the moment it arises. NAGPRA-opposing anthropologists do exactly this. These scientists want us to believe that their own metaphysical desires gather their urgency from needs that have always been present for everyone everywhere. An innate need to know is universally characteristic of all humans, we heard Landau and Steele implore. Genealogy, Friedrich Nietzsche and Foucault teach, differs from traditional history in that it does not see a theme or spirit in the passing of time. There is no truth, no obscure purpose, no what is there, despite hopes and fears, being slowly uncovered through scientic discipline and responsibility to any imagined intellectual nality. Genealogists (and poststructuralist sociology) can confront and embrace this complexity. Genealogy can help us understand this complexity because it seeks to reestablish the various systems of subjection . . . the hazardous play of dominations (Foucault 1971/1977:148). I have waited until now to report recorded sentiments of fellow Klamath tribal members (who graciously agreed to submit to my questions and to the tape recorder) because I wanted rst to resurrect and interrogate genealogy that is erased in an interpretive context that is too often simply assumed when non-Natives pass judgment on Native arguments. With this genealogy, I seek to transform this debate from one imagined to be on behalf of truth, into one about the political role it plays (Foucault 1977:133).
Klamath Narrations The Klamath tribes have had, and continue to have, our share of outrageous interactions with scientists, scientic institutions, and relic hunters. In the early 1980s, one of our tribal cemeteries was looted.6 My great-grandparents, great-uncles, and many other relatives are buried there. Not long afterward, someone was foolish and bold enough to approach my uncle and offer to sell him an Indian skull. Not very many years after that, the Smithsonian nally repatriated the severed heads of our executed war leaders. The University of California at Davis still refuses to return one of our dead to the tribes, claiming that our culture and heritage ofcers are not competent to determine the cultural afliation of a burial that the universitys scientists raided in the 1970s. In the course of a March 2002 interview, the former head of our Culture and Heritage Department asks incredulously of the anthropologist leading the resistance to the return of our ancestor, this guy is telling us what kind of burials our people did? The current director adds, I call it grave robbing;
| 147
you if we went over Jacksonville? Hey they got 1800s graves in there. They do. . . . Dig em up all in the name of science. Couldnt we (pause), long as theyre Induns though. . . . They dont see it because theyre not spiritual. They dont have the spiritualness that we have within us; they dont. . . . Thats why it hurts us and makes us angry, cause we understand. . . . We see what theyre doing. . . .
Beyond any doubt, these Klamath recognize scientic narrations of Indian dead to be political phenomena. They quite readily associate contemporary archaeological desire with a long history of colonial arrogance. (Theyve never considered us equals.) They also see quite clearly that the debate is between cultures (They dont see it because theyre not spiritual) and that double standards have always been employed (Dig em all up in the name of science . . . long as theyre Induns though). They are equally unequivocal in their assessment that the struggle is, and has always been, about power (theyd put me in jail; the European society think that they are superior in everything). Indeed, as if to highlight the role of power, they show that they are quite capable of erasing the signicance of scientic claims (they dont know what theyre doing. . . . They mean nothing).
6
taking charge of the affirmative action debate
Social Science and Racial Justice
The preference lobby constantly talks about victims. But they are nameless and faceless and dont exist except as theoretical speculations.
Ward Connerly (2000:225)
There were few cries of we are all individuals from the 99 percent white worksite of the 1950s.
Troy Duster (1998:120)
ssues of race and ethnicity were easily the single biggest source of social and political unrest in the United States in the twentieth century.1 At the beginning of the twenty-rst century, we are far better off as a nation with regard to issues of color and ethnic diversity than we were as the nineteenth century closed. Gigantic and progressive strides have been made. To state only the most obvious, legally mandated segregation of public facilities and institutions in the South is now a thing of our older generations memories. Many children all across the country are taught everyday to be proud of their ethnic heritages and to respect and admire those of their neighbors. University campuses, Parent Teacher Association meetings, and after work social gatherings are in ever more locations quite comfortably integrated. It is increasingly normal (particularly among the young) for friendships and romantic relationships to not only cross racial and ethnic boundaries but to do so without those involved seeing this as a signicant issue. Perhaps most
| 151
agree with the statement that the criminal justice system is biased against them. Meanwhile a 1999 Seattle Times poll found that 75 percent of white Americans agree with the statement: Unqualied minorities get hired over qualied whites (Pincus 2001/2:33). Finally, surveying students at a large, private, urban university, Kimberly Arriola and Elizabeth R. Cole (2001: 2475) observe that even among European Americans describing themselves as politically moderate or liberal, 60 percent of respondents advocate the complete abolition of afrmative action programs.2 To initiate our discussion of these immense disparities, I ask students to reect on their perceptions of race and racial politics. How prevalent is racism today? Is racial equality a reality? Is afrmative action still necessary? What exactly is afrmative action and what is it not? Are some African Americans speech patterns seen as a sign of ignorance? If yes, is this fair? Is immigration a problem or an asset for the United States? Should immigrants proudly hold onto the language and customs of their former nations, or should they strive to leave these ways behind in pursuit of being American? Why are black and brown men locked up in numbers far exceeding their proportions of the overall population? (African Americans are about 12 percent of the population and nearly 50 percent of the incarcerated population, in California about one of every three African American men in their 20s is behind bars, and American Indians are less than 1 percent of the population but about 6 percent of the jailed population.) And nally, how difcult is it to honestly discuss these issues in ethnically mixed groups? Given that Americans feel so strongly about racial issues, the potential for civility to vanish and for violence to replace discussion in this country remains very real. Racial injustice clearly perceived and deeply felt by millions of citizens is dangerous for our society. When added to the millions more who believe that race is no longer a signicant problem, the combination becomes potentially explosive. On the one hand, that skin pigmentation and other physiological aspects of our appearanceswhat Paul Gilroy (2000), among others, calls racialization 3is signicant to the daily experiences of so many, testies to the currency and urgency of complex and seemingly intractable sociological problems. On the other hand, this chronic crisis begs the frustrating question: how could the single largest social problem of the last century remain so poorly understood? How is it that sociologists have not yet laid bare the underlying structure of these dangerous difculties? Where are the scientic conclusions about this empirical reality that should by now have been generated by the legions of the most disciplined of social scientists, scientists whose work on race and ethnicity can be found in virtually endless stacks of studies that cover acres of library shelves? Why have the promises of civic responsibility made by structuralist sociologists not yet been fullled? (Recall that Jonathan H. Turner wrote of sociologists obligation to acquire a standard body of knowledge, to learn the general theoretical
| 153
political contest over these key terms, I argue, is what progressive sociologists should focus on. How do we decide who is or is not part of a race? What does it mean to be an individual who therefore can be judged on the basis of merit? How does anyone know when discrimination has occurred? Powerful political strategies now laying claim to these terms, strategies employed by both proponents and opponents of afrmative action, are analyzed as textual phenomena. Finally, poststructuralist tactics designed to secure a future for afrmative action are suggested.
Early Political Contexts and Key Language President John F. Kennedy is most often credited with rst using the term afrmative action. In the years following the U.S. Supreme Courts Brown v. Board of Education (1954) decision, which overturned the so-called separate but equal doctrine that sustained legal, forced segregation in public education and in other government administered facilities, it became all too apparent to proponents of racial justice that court decisions alone would not end discrimination in public institutions. Indeed, a full ten years after this landmark decision, 98 percent of Southern blacks remained in forcibly segregated schools (Dye and Zeigler 1978:344). Reacting to this intransigence, on March 6, 1961 Kennedy issued Executive Order 10925. In its introductory paragraphs, the president cites frustration with the lack of progress as the basis for his directive to end discrimination in federal contracting. A review of existing . . . compliance with existing non-discrimination contract provisions reveals an urgent need for expansion and strengthening of efforts to promote full equality of employment opportunity. With the same order, Kennedy created the Presidents Committee on Equal Employment Opportunity, which subsequently became the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC), and gave the new agency the power to force all entities contracting with the federal government to Take afrmative action to ensure that applicants are employed, and that employees are treated during employment, without regard to their race, creed, color, or national origin (Part III:1). It is important to remember that the racism that this order was attempting to arrest was deeply ingrained in the fabric of social life, particularly in the South. This was the era that would soon be recorded in black-and-white lm footage of civil rights activists being beaten by white police ofcers. African Americans attempting to use whites only rest rooms and drinking fountains in government buildings, attempting to swim in public pools or at public beaches, sitting in front seats on public buses, and showing up to enroll in public universities (all of this desegregation having been ordered by the Supreme Court) were attacked by water canons, police dogs, electric cattle prods, and violent mobs of white segregationists. This was also the era when governor
| 155
Court Justice Ruth Ginsburg (2000:2) has called trade union nepotism. Large federal contracts (high-wage work being paid for by taxpayers, including ethnic minorities) have over the years been routinely monopolized by white business owners who were awarded contracts from federal agencies run by white men who then proceeded to hire other white men for the best-paying positions. Being locked out of union pay scales meant that people of color were also locked out of the many privileges of middle-class status. Again, these include good schools, crime-free neighborhoods, environmentally uncontaminated communities, healthy lifestyles born of adequate educations, and social networks made up of the wealthy and powerful. By 1969, President Richard Nixon had put in place his Philadelphia Plan that aimed to desegregate the Philadelphia construction industry. For the rst time, the nepotism problem was to be addressed through goals and timetables established by industry ofcials themselves but under the watchful scrutiny of the Department of Labor. As the president explained: The civil rights policy to which this administration is committed is one of demonstrable deedsfocused where they count. One of the things that counts most is earning power. Nothing is more unfair than that the same Americans who pay taxes should by any pattern of discriminatory practices be deprived of an equal opportunity to work on Federal construction projects (Presidential Papers: 494: 12/19/69). The call for goals and timetables contained in the Philadelphia Plan immediately brought the now familiar charge that the program was really about hiring quotas that were sure to result in contracts being awarded to unqualied minorities. Those wanting to maintain the segregated status quo argued that because the plan considered race, it violated the 1964 Civil Rights Act. Although this Philadelphia afrmative action was attacked in both Houses of Congress and challenged in the courts, Nixon held rm.5 The Philadelphia Plan does not set quotas; it points to goals. It does not presume automatic violation of law if the goals are not met; it does require afrmative action if a review of the totality of a contractors employment practices shows that he is not affording equal employment opportunity (Presidential Papers 494:12/19/69, my emphases). The 1970s were a time of expanding programs, increasing opportunities for racialized minorities. A series of Supreme Court rulings recognized the importance of what came to be called disparity studies. These analyses of hiring practices looked for a disparate impact on minority populations. In other words, the Court asked whether the hiring methods of companies negatively impacted minorities and women at a higher rate than white males. The logic of disparate impact assumed that qualied minorities and women should advance through hiring processes at the same rate as qualied white men. Thus qualied females and minorities should advance at a rate of no less than 80 percent of the rate of advancement of qualied white males. For example, if a hiring committee was presented with a pool of 50 qualied women and 100 qualied white men, in the absence of discrimination (conscious or
| 157
Although, to the best of my knowledge, there have never been any federal afrmative action policies governing admission to educational institutions, by the 1970s universities and colleges were increasingly concerned with enlarging the enrollments of underrepresented, ethnic minorities and women.7 In 1974, the California State Legislature passed a statute declaring, the undergraduate student body at the University of California should reect the general ethnic, gender, and economic composition of the states high school graduates (Douglass 2001:126). No doubt the (too often forced) diversication of university faculty contributed to the subsequently growing diversity among undergraduates at the nations colleges and universities. For example, from 1970 to 1980 the countrys population of African American undergraduates grew by 14 percent and by 1990 had increased by 30 percent (Eisaguirre 1999:13). By 1980, the political climate of the country had changed dramatically. Ronald Reagans presidential campaign marks the beginning of an era of successful attacks on afrmative action. Despite the clearly cut language of the CFR, Reagan repeatedly branded these anti-discrimination laws as bureaucratic regulations which rely on quotas, ratios, and numerical requirements (quoted in Kelly and Dobbin 2001:95). Once elected, the new president truncated enforcement of EEOC guidelines, even appointing the ultraconservative and afrmative-action-despising Clarence Thomas as chair of the commission. Judge Thomas quickly and quietly instructed his charges not to approve programs containing goals and timetables (Kelly and Dobbin 2001:9596). Under his leadership, the time it took to process discrimination claims went from ve months to nine months, and the backlog of uninvestigated cases doubled (Lipsitz 1998:148). Throughout his tenure as president, Reagan appointed judges to the federal bench who opposed afrmative action, and his administration went to court on the opposite side of policies staked out and defended by previous presidents. Reagans appointments to the Supreme Court also extended a string of conservative nods that had begun in 1970 and would extend to 1991. As Paul Ong (1999:14) points out, this pattern would eventually mean that Republican Presidents appointed all nine additions to the Supreme Court from 1970 to 1991. As early as 1978, the impact of these right-wing appointments was becoming apparent as the Courts rulings began to pare back afrmative action programs.
Supreme Court Cases In the University of California v. Bakke case of 1978, the Court ruled that the universitys Davis Medical School allowed their outreach programs to go too far. While expressly allowing for race and ethnicity to be considered as a plus factor in admissions decisions, the majority found that the schools policy that 16 percent of new students be ethnic minorities, violated the Fourteenth Amendment of the Constitution.8
This logic signals a retreat from the attack on institutionalized racism that we heard Presidents Johnson and Nixon articulate. OConnor is ordering that specic evidence of specic and past instances of discrimination against specic ethnic groups in a specic industry has become the threshold for justifying the taking of afrmative action to remedy ongoing inequality of opportunity. Continuing and institutionalized inequities in access to satisfactory education; to competent health care providers and adequately funded health care facilities; to affordable, quality legal representation; to decent housing; to the networks of businesspeople where deals are made; and to the dignity that comes with all of this access is, from the standpoint of this Court decision, insufcient proof of discrimination. This gross inequality of opportunity for (as Nixon labeled it) earning power no longer indicates the presence of discrimination. In Richmond v. Cronson, the conservative majority pushes through denitions of discrimination so narrow as to make the logic of taking afrmative action constitutionally indefensible. Narrowly tailored afrmative action is, by denition, forbidden from attacking institutionalized and current inequality of opportunity, as it exists on a broad array of social and political frontsunless it can be strictly located in a long list of specic historical events narrowly dened. Six years later, in Adarand Constructors v. Secretary of Transportation Pena (1995), the majority (again, 5 to 4) made its lack of appreciation for the relevance of institutionalized discrimination against racially categorized groups
| 159
explicit. Writing for the majority and citing Justice Powell, OConnor explained. If it is the individual who is entitled to judicial protection against classications based upon his racial or ethnic background because such distinctions impinge upon personal rights, rather than the individual only because of his membership in a particular group, then the constitutional standards may be applied consistently (515 U.S. 200: 931841). OConnor and Powell are seeking to protect what they call the individual against the discriminatory capacity of racial labeling. They argue that the right to due process contained in the Fifth Amendment (which states that no person shall be deprived of. . . .) is a right guaranteed only to individuals and that considerations of race (as an aggregation) therefore violate this right guaranteed only to individuals and not to groups. To award signicance to group identities is to do harm to individual identities, which are, after all, the only identities protected by the Fifth Amendment. This is an intriguing turn of logic. The majority ruling is that the Fourteenth Amendment, again a primary purpose of which was to prevent racial discrimination against former slaves, is enforceable only by protecting the always already racialized from race. Protection against racial discrimination, this line of reasoning maintains, requires that racial identity and individual identity be understood as structurally distinct. As OConnor continues:
The basic principle [is] that the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to the Constitution protect persons, not groups. It follows from that principle that all government action based on racea group classication long recognized as in most circumstances irrelevant and therefore prohibitedshould be subjected to detailed judiciary inquiry to ensure that the personal right to equal protection of the laws has not been infringed. . . . We hold today that all racial classications, imposed by whatever federal, state, or local government actor, must be analyzed by a reviewing court under strict scrutiny (515 U.S. 200:931841, emphases in original)
Race-less Discrimination The majoritys words mark a site of crisis for structuralists defense of afrmative action. The Courts attempt to tease out racialized individuals, as distinct from their demographic categories, signals the instability of what many on the left assume are empirically veriable structures of racial inequality. With this discursive turn, the Court moved to fundamentally alter the meaning of racialized subjectivities. This logic, this legal narrative attempts to restructure the meaning of race in American society. As a poststructuralist, my analytic strategy is not to simply reemphasize and insist upon the group-based inequalities that I nd morally compelling. I will
| 161
very possibility of discrimination being interpretable as racial discrimination) is not well thought out. One wonders how long it will it be before an enterprising attorney insists on the complete irrelevance of the large and voluminous history of racial discrimination to an individual instance of discrimination at an individual workplace. At what point would the court majority have us draw the line between an individuals experience and the long history of group experience that make racial discrimination recognizable in the rst place? Said another way, if discrimination only happens to individuals (It is the individual who is entitled to judicial protection. . . .), what exactly is the individual to be protected from? Racism, after all, is not something that originates in the psyche of an individual discriminator or that is uniquely comprehendible (as racial discrimination) by individual victims. Racism cannot be contained or dened from within any isolated, singular set of circumstances. There can be no personal right to equal protection of the laws that is not always already a protection based on ones membership in a group. Indeed, if this sociological problem was or had ever been about individuals needing protection, the Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution would have been unnecessary and the Civil Rights Act would be completely nonsensical. Despite what OConnor may desire, racialized individuals do not have a reality without the groups that constitute and maintain their societal signicance and self-perceptions. This is very old sociological insight. As George Mead (1934/1961:740) observed seventy years ago: the individual is what he is, as a conscious and individual personality, just in as far as he is a member of society, involved in the social process of experience and activity, and thereby socially controlled in his conduct. In a dissenting opinion, Justice Ginsburg fears for progress made against the ongoing consequences of group-based racism. The lead opinion uses one term strict scrutiny to describe the standard of judicial review for all governmental classications by race. But that opinions elaboration strongly suggests that the strict standard announced is indeed fatal for classications burdening groups that have suffered discrimination in our society (515 U.S. 200:931841). Either identities, including those believed to exist outside and in excess of groups, are shared group phenomena (classications burdening groups) or they are somehow truly personal. I am claiming that there is no empirically veriable, structurally identiable point where OConnor can separate individual experiences from group experiences. Considered carefully, legal interpretation and enforcement of this separation is at least impractical. At worst, it is, as Justice Ginsburg suggests, fatal to afrmative action taken in defense of equality of opportunity. Where can strictly scrutinized remedies be intellectually severed from the group-based possibility of these supposedly, individualized racial experiences? Every individuals perception of race is only socially possible. As I instruct my students, relying on (the again rather old) sociological insights of in this
| 163
Could we also include larger circles of friends and acquaintances which, over the years, have participated in the maintenance of racialized identities among these passive participants whose inuence continues to keep the Richmond construction industry segregated? If a respected family elder helps a city ofcial see himself (acts as a looking glass) as fair-minded and just, despite his dismal record on issues of racial equity, does this make the family member a participant? What if the ofcial watches the evening news and hears a right-wing politician intone about the evils of race-based quotas? Should this only remotely available politician, or the news program, or the network that carried it, or even the European American voters to whom the politician is responding be considered participants in an extended and obviously complex text of racialization that is the very possibility of any individual minority contractor in Richmond, Virginia, having a racial experience? At what point, exactly, does passive participation become not recognizing or caring that race is an issue? And, where is the empirical structure here? In Grutter v. Bollinger et al. (2003), OConnors intellectually tenuous demarcation between individuals and groups remains a prominent part of the majoritys appraisal. Eight years after her insistence on the primacy of individual rights in Adarand v. Pena, she is again struggling with the impossibility of this metaphysical separation. Arguing for the majority that had just upheld the constitutionality of the University of Michigan Law Schools afrmative action program, OConnor writes: Just as growing up in a particular region or having particular professional experiences is likely to affect an individuals views, so too is ones own, unique experience of being a racial minority in a society. . . . (539 U.S.:21 2003). These experiences are said to be unique and particular, but they result from being a racial minority in a society. So, where do these individuals, these personhoods, these subjectivities that are only subsequently affected come from? What could OConnor mean by ones own unique experience of being a racial minority? Being a racial minority means being a member of a group and having experiences that other members of that group share; otherwise, the experience of being a racial minority has no meaning. Thus the depiction: ones own unique experience of being a racial minority, driven to its logical end, proves to be nonsensical. However untenable, OConnors words at least allow us to fantasize a metaphysical space where racial identities could be both individual and group phenomena while also remaining neatly separable.11 She has not closed the door completely on the sociological reality of race in the lives of everyday Americans. Nonetheless, at bottom her individualist argument owes its appeal to the same de-racialized phantasms inhabiting her colleague Justice Scalias much more unsettling imaginary. Scalia, remember, maintained in an earlier dissenting opinion that we are all just one race here. By claiming that this one race is American he is textually linking his view to the patriotic pageantry routinely heaped upon the republics celebrated documents. He claims, under
| 165
these audit studies (in, e.g., Denver, San Diego, Washington D.C., Newark, and Chicago) reveal that folks of different colors sent to test the responses of the same potential employers receive very different treatment (Cross et. al. 1990; Fix and Struyk 1993; Kenney and Wissoker 1994; Reskin 1998:27; Stephanopoulous and Edley 1995; Wellman 1997). These disparities result in tragedy disproportionately visited upon minority populations. For example, black babies die at 250 percent the rate of white babies, and whites avoid and quit smoking in greater numbers due to better educations and greater access to health care (Meckler 2002; McKenna 2002). And, social problems born of racialized inequality breed racist perceptions among courts and police. For example, in August of 2002, the state of Delaware announced that its police force was creating a database of people they feel are likely to break the law. Although the exact process for collecting the addresses and photographs remains sketchy, most of those listed are minorities from poor neighborhoods. Many have spotless police records, having been simply stopped for loitering and were photographed and released (San Francisco Chronicle 8/26/02:A7). Defending afrmative action programs means facing the alarming and curious need to insist on the reality of racialized identities that Americans fail to acknowledge with consistency. How is it that judges and other intelligent citizens remain so divided in their appraisals of what I claimed was the single biggest source of political unrest of the last century?13 If problems of race are so very important to so many people, why have their objective qualities not been long since uncovered and solved? These competing realities make it abundantly clear that to speak and write of racial discrimination is to always already enter into irreducibly political and social (poststructural) contests. Appeals to empirically veriable truths will not lead us out of this dangerous predicament.
Seeing and Not Seeing: The Elusiveness of Discrimination and Merit In chapter 3, we heard Michel Foucault (1984/1997:12526) characterize genealogical scholarship as No longer . . . practiced in the search for formal structures with universal value, but rather as a historical investigation into the events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize ourselves as subjects of what we are doing, thinking, saying. Americans do race and recognize race in a variety of ways. These ways of doing and reading race are what mark us, socially, as racial groups. Social performances (where we act racially and react to the racial performances of others) maintain the signicance and interpretability of our merely physical differences. In other words, the importance of differences in skin pigmentation is fundamentally tied to selfpresentations that are only socially learned and always socially perpetuated. These racially marked practices, habits, and styles (doing, thinking, saying)
| 167
black teachers working so hard to correct the African American English spoken by their students?14 I am suggesting that this designation of middleclass white English as standard American English should be understood as what Nixon called a pattern of discriminatory practices. This is a groupbased and group-enforced decision, and it routinely denies equal opportunity to African Americans. Black English is not heard as legitimately professional language simply because those who have always been professional, who set the standard for how to do professional, and (most importantly) who maintain the boundaries of admission to becoming professional have nearly always been middle-class whites and/or elite whites. This standard English (which I too insist that my students learn and practice) is only standard because it has always been the vernacular of those communities enjoying economic dominance. Yet this disdain for black English and reverence for middle-class, white English is almost never understood as discrimination. Indeed, this group held belief (so rooted in the history of inequality between those who speak these racially marked dialects) all too easily becomes a sign of who is and who is not qualied. When job interviewers remark of a standard English- speaking black candidate that s/he sounded so professional, we are witnessing one of Foucaults events that have led us to constitute ourselves and to recognize ourselves. The ability to inscribe such an event as being about professional qualications is a direct result of social and economic powerthe power to dene who we are and who they are. So, are such events racialized experiences, or are they explicitly and emphatically not about race? The answer will always depend upon whose group enjoys the power to narrate with legitimacy. Far from being a question of disciplined social scientists uncovering objective social structure, the key question is who wields the power to skillfully narrate the reality of key interactions and to have those depictions center the debate. How might an African American who believed she had lost a contest over a coveted job because of her speech patterns go about proving that this was an example of racial discrimination that is prohibited by the Civil Rights Act and by the Constitution? Consider a situation where three very professional white men have interviewed an African American woman as part of her application for a highly sought after job. For the sake of argument, let us say that this woman sailed through the pre-interview parts of the application process. She also feels that the initial part of her meeting with these men went well, but noticed that one of them tightened his face on a few occasions when she pronounced certain words in ways that she later realized may have sounded black. Is there a non-group-based way to determine whether her forthcoming rejection is an act of discrimination? The men on this hiring committee may well argue that polished speaking skills are an important part of this highprole, public position. No doubt, they believe they have made a decision based simply on merit.
The Unreliability of Experience We spent many pages in the rst few chapters discussing why it is always too simple to comprehend subjectivity as something that has experiences. The self is a location that does not cease always being constituted. It is not structure but rather relies upon always underway, overlapping, and competing discourses for its always only apparent semblance. Discourses, those domains of language whose logics and meanings are linked textually, are the possibility of recognizing experience. One does not describe experience without constituting that experience in the act of description. Once one has language, experience will remain rooted in it. Language organizes the world, including ones place in it, and discourses compete for our collective cognitive embrace. Scalia and millions of Americans who do not see racialized inequality speak and think in discourses of individualism (replete with notions of merit) that justify and even eliminate the signicance of gross inequality of opportunity.
| 169
And let us be perfectly aware of this. Despite our outrage, there is nothing inherent to this inequality that makes our focusing on it any less political than Scalias claim to be color-blind. As members of racialized groups, and as progressive sociologists, we speak and think with different conceptual apparatuses, different discourses that highlight and foreground different textual connections. We have different experiences. As Joan W. Scott (1992:34) describes this relationship between language and experience: It is to refuse a separation between experience and language and to instead insist on the productive quality of discourse. Subjects are constituted discursively but there are conicts among discursive systems, contradictions within any of them, multiple meanings possible for the concepts they deploy. And subjects have agency. They are not unied, autonomous individuals exercising free will, but rather subjects whose agency is created through situations and statuses conferred on them. We have, then, not a ght over the empirical reality of afrmative action, not a struggle over some objective structures of people or policies or deployed concepts, but rather a contest over the language of afrmative action and over the productive, constituting qualities of that language. Afrmative action is what it becomes in arguments over its future, in forecasts that themselves depend upon strategic recollections. These arguments, these denitional contests, will initiate and give signicance to whatever policies we can successfully defend. When I describe or experience an event as an act of discrimination, I inscribe it with the structure of what I know to be discrimination. This is not to say that the understanding of discrimination originated from within me (from the inner depths of a pre-social I) or that the effects of racism are any less despicable because I participate in the maintenance of its recognized denitions. Understanding institutionalized discrimination as a discursively enacted and protracted phenomenon, and not as an assemblage of Platonic essences or objective facts that can be intellectually contained in a description of what one individual does to another, does not make it any less horrible. However, wielding a poststructuralist eye means recognizing that the signicance of ongoing inequalitiesas they are understood and experienced across color lineswill not be proven through appeals to self-representing truth or to the obviousness of the tragedy. Scholarly debates over audit studies are one example of social scientists inability to agree upon objective qualities of discrimination. These research projects send mixed teams of qualied minorities and whites to apply for job openings or to inquire about rental properties. George Galster (1990:172) compiled evidence from fty such studies and concluded that racial discrimination continues to be a dominant feature of metropolitan housing markets in the 1980s. John Yinger (1993,1995), working for the U.S. Department of Housing and Urban Development, found that housing was repeatedly made more available to whites and that whites were often offered more favorable
| 171
or credit decisions (109). Employers and landlords do prefer whites and minorities at different rates, but this pattern is only coincidental. These preferences correlate with nonracial and somewhat visible qualities that are the real (and presumably legitimate) bases for treating people unequally. Even more troublesome, these unnamed qualications that employers and landlords can see but which social scientists conducting auditing studies systematically miss may come with different levels of variance for different racial groups. Heckman makes this point with an analogy to a high-jumping contest:
. . . think of pairing up black and white high jumpers to see if they can clear a bar set at a certain height. There is no discrimination, in the sense that they both use the same equipment and have the bar set at the same level. Suppose now that the chance of a jumper (of any race) clearing the bar depends on two additive factors: the persons height and their jumping technique. We can pair up black and white jumpers so that they have identical heights, but we cant directly observe their technique. Let us make the generous assumption, implicit in the entire audit literature, that the mean jumping technique is equal for the two groups. Then, if the variance of technique is also the same for white and black high-jumpers, we would nd that the two racial groups are equally likely to clear the bar. On the other hand, if the variance differs, then whether the black or white pair is more likely to clear the bar will depend on how the bar is set relative to their common height, and which racial group has a higher variance in jumping technique. If the bar is set at a low level so that most people of the given height are likely to clear the bar, then the group with the lower variance will be more likely to clear the bar. If the bar is set at a very high level relative to the given height, then the group with a higher variance in jumping technique will be more likely to clear the bar. A limitation of the audit method is readily apparent from this analogy: there is no discrimination, yet the two groups have different probabilities of clearing the bar. (1998:11011)
In Heckmans high-jumping analogy we see a not so subtle shift from an attack on what he deems to be poor research methodology to a suggestion of genuine differences between minority groups and white Americans. Although his discussion of variance in jumping technique is indirect, he is clearly suggesting that the ranges of qualications within racial groups differ. It is this difference in the scope of qualications (higher variance for whites), acting as spurious variables functioning below the radar of researchers that results in the unequal treatment that the social scientists wrongly confuse with racial discrimination. Regardless of Heckmans capacity for obscuring his charges in sports analogies or statistical jargon, he is nonetheless positing real differences between racial groups. And, if these differences are to legitimate unequal treatment, we have a right to know exactly what they are and what their origin is. Heckman never supplies this information. He says only that ability as it crystallizes at
| 173
inequality. There is no organized political or intellectual lobby on behalf of incompetence. But many who are committed to a doctrine of the natural equality of groups nd it incomprehensible that fair procedures would not produce what they view as the necessary outcome of proportional representation (1995:296). In tones that work to discursively recapture and rearticulate older justications for racial inequality in language appealing to contemporary audiences, DSouza redeploys nineteenth-century images of civilization and barbarity. The differences between us and them are real, and those not blinded by fashionable liberal prejudices see that they are real. Writing of the Pathologies of Black Culture (as one of his chapters is subtitled), DSouza describes an objective reality (a breakdown of civilization within the African American community) that ideology-blinded liberals refuse to talk honestly about. This breakdown is characterized by extremely high rates of criminal activity, by the normalization of illegitimacy, by the predominance of single-parent families, by high levels of addiction to alcohol and drugs, by a parasitic reliance on government provision, by a hostility to academic achievement, and by a scarcity of independent enterprises (1995:477). What we nd, here, is not a refusal to acknowledge inequality. Racial inequality is real enough for DSouza, but these facts are not centrally important.16 DSouzas worldview is constructed and maintained by discourses of equal opportunity, merit-based advancement, and legally guaranteed assurances that racial discrimination will not be tolerated. He is not drawn to inequality-depicting statistics (as civil rights activists are) because they are not part of the discursive imaginary that animates his existence, that underwrites his signicance to himself and to others whose opinions he values. As the title of his book, Whats So Great about America (2002), suggests, DSouzas civic experiences are had in patriotic fervor that long since awarded the founding documents of the republic a sacred status. Agape with awe, the quite earth-bound details of their political production evade him. Institutionalized inequalities that do not reect the sacred story are not visible through his discursive lenses. In most countries in the world, your fate and your identity are handed to you; in America, you determine them for yourself. America is a country where you get to write the script of your own life. Your life is like a blank sheet of paper, and you are the artist. This notion of being the architect of your own destiny is the incredibly powerful idea that is behind the worldwide appeal of America (2003: D6). Such American folklore enshrines the republics founding in an idealism that acts as a potent genealogical force, a force strategically deployed by critics of afrmative action. If equality of opportunity exists, if American society is true to the ideals DSouza feels well up in his being when he stands for the national anthem, then racialized groups who claim otherwise are not victims but perpetrators of a giant institutionalized fraud.
The discursive text organizing DSouzas perceptions is not even shaken, as we might reasonably expect, by the observations of people of color who by no stretch of the imagination can be located within the cultural pathologies he claims to describe. Faced with rst-person accounts of racialized experiences sustained by welleducated, middle-class, professionals as chronicled by Joe Feagin and Melvin Sikes (1994), DSouza nds only evidence of individual psychological pathologies to accompany his earlier discussion of cultural pathology. Far from being evidence of ongoing, racially organized social interactions that systematically work to disadvantage non-whites, DSouza gains only illuminating insight into some blacks questionable grip on reality (1995:491). Characterizing these extensive accounts as cases of people who live in a world of make-believe, he thinks it absolutely rational that whites would not want to work in too close proximity (492). In DSouzas reality, when discrimination happens, it is completely rational, and in settings where it would not be rational, it is make-believe. Other critics of afrmative action explain the concentration of minorities in low-income and low-prestige occupationsas juxtaposed with the fact that 97 percent of the senior managers of Fortune 1000 industrial and Fortune 500 companies are white and 97 percent are male (Reich 1995:iii-iv)as simply a matter of free will. Careers are freely chosen. While these choices may reect cultural inclinations, occupational segregation has nothing to do with nepotism or with a proclivity for hiring those who are most like oneself. As John Skrentny (2001:10) describes this situation, It seems clear that different minority groups have different tendencies to go into business and that discrimination cannot be the sole cause of the variation. Arch Puddington (1996:82) is more explicit. The problem is that those who advance this argument seem to assume that only white males rely on personal relationships or kinship. Yet as we have learned from the experience of immigrants throughout American history, every racial and ethnic group values family and group ties. Korean-American shop owners enlist their families, Haitian-American taxi eets hire their friends. Although Puddington writes here of Americans with different national ancestries, afrmative action programs are rarely so precise. Critics of afrmative action have seized upon the ambiguities contained in racial classications as a basis for attacking progressive attempts to confront ongoing group inequalities. Opponents of afrmative action not only deny the reality of racialized
| 175
experiences, they deny the sociological reality of the classication schemes that these experiences originate from.
Policing the Racial Borders While many social scientists (Almaguer 1994; Davis 1991; Espiritu 1992) persuasively document the long history of imposed racial-classication schemes designed to maintain white privilege, opponents use this same lack of structure to attack afrmative action policies meant to remedy inequality perpetrated through these same constructs. In other words, race has always been a cultural and political construction. Locating differences in biology was a brutal strategy used for centuries to subjugate non-whites. Yet, modern recognition of the biological nullity of race is now used to discredit afrmative action programs that necessarily rely on those old classications. Sociologists of color cannot have it both ways. We cannot expect to argue that race is a social and political construct and believe that our opponents will not do the same. Destroying the stability of these categories means becoming intellectually comfortable and politically capable within a thoroughly poststructuralist confrontation. Before taking up these politics in earnest, let me be more explicit about why race can never be simply a biological reality. At issue is the irreducibly social nature (and thus instability) of agreements that divide physiological differences into biological groupings. As Karen Rosenblum and Toni-Michelle Travis (2000:18) note, biological variability exists but this variability does not conform to discrete packages labeled races. Ultimately the lines that one draws for inclusion or exclusion of discreet groups of peoples in any race is arbitrary in as much as another decision could have been rationally made. Sharon Begley (1995:67,68) further illustrates this lack of structure.
If our eyes could perceive more than the supercial, we might nd race in chromosome 11: there lies the gene for hemoglobin. If you divide humankind by which of the two forms of the gene each person has, then equatorial Africans, Italians, and Greeks fall into the sickle-cell race; Swedes and South Africas Xhosas (Nelson Mandelas ethnic group) are in the healthy hemoglobin race. Or do you prefer to group people by whether they have epicanthic eye folds, which produce the Asian eye? Then the !Kung San (Bushmen) belong with the Japanese and Chinese. . . . [D]epending on which traits you pick, you can form very surprising races. Take the scooped-out shape of the back of the front teeth, a standard Asian trait. Native Americans and Swedes have these shovel-shaped incisors, too, and so would fall in the same race. Is biochemistry better? Norwegians, Arabians, north Indians, and the Fulani of northern Nigeria . . . fall into the lactase race (the lactase enzyme digests milk sugar). Everyone elseother Africans, Japanese, native Americansform the lactase-deprived race.
| 177
States but not in Brazil (Degler 1971). Similarly, the terms Hispanic and Latino group people of very different ethnic backgrounds. Puerto Ricans, Cuban Americans, Mexican Americans, and Peruvian Americans are lumped together into a single, overly homogeneous racial classication that hides tremendous differences in culture and economic power. And although Italian Americans are now commonly assumed to be white, this has not always been the case. Indeed, Texas Democrats once explicitly forbade Italian Americans from voting in their primaries on the grounds that they were not white (New York Times 4/12/04). As I said, the contested status of these categories is not exclusively apparent to those who recognize them as tools of historical oppression. With academic skill and political acumen, opponents of afrmative action move to turn this lack of structure to their own ends. These critics point to the porousness of racial boundaries, to underinclusion and overinclusion in every attempt to draw racial demarcations. These political foes, including members of the state and federal judiciary, seize upon differences within, and similarities across, categories as a strategy designed to make the impossibility of objectivity in the administration of the policy fatal to the policy. As a U.S. district court, having had Adarand v. Pena (515 U.S. 200) remanded to it by the U.S. Supreme Court, concluded: [We] nd it difcult to envisage a race based classication that is narrowly tailored. By its very nature, such a program is both underinclusive and overinclusive. This seemingly contradictory result suggests the criteria are lacking in substance as well as in reason (quoted in La Noue and Sullivan 2001:85). The opponents who cite this court opinion conclude that categories as they function in afrmative action policies are not closely tied (narrowly tailored) to the discrimination that they are supposed to remedy. Lawmakers, they maintain, have never carefully considered the problem of dening who is, and who is not, included in denitions of protected groups. Rather, these choices have always been made for political expedience and away from public view. Furthermore, sustained by the momentum of a rapidly growing federal bureaucracy, there was almost never any independent examination of whether the federally dened groups t any theory of social justice or equity (La Noue and Sullivan 2001:71). George La Noue and John Sullivan have hit upon the insight that a lack of objective structure in racial-classication systems also indicates a lack of objective structure in racialized experiences. For the link between discrimination-caused social disadvantage and categories of protected peoples to be made, they claim, there must be a provable commonality of experiences that lead rationally to the formation of a demographic category as a protected category. And they nd no such proof. What if some Hispanic and some Asian American groups are above and some are below the mean? What if some white groups are below some Hispanic or some Asian groups? Both possibilities would suggest that there was no commonality of experiences of
La Noue and Sullivan (2001:85) conclude, if the courts are going to reexamine the composition of the afrmative action categories, it will be important for social scientists to produce better data than currently exist. The epistemological faith of these political opponents has not yet waned. As we shall see, we can use this shortcoming to our advantage. To summarize, the central features of these heated debatesrace, discrimination, individual, and meritlack mutually identiable structure. Intelligent people disagree about what these concepts mean and nd little common basis for their measurement. European Americans and people of color, in frighteningly large proportions, disagree about the signicance of color in early twenty-rst-century America. The interpretive possibilities for assigning signicance to racialized experiences are overwhelmingly complex and competing. An efcacious defense of afrmative action must accept this lack of structure and embrace its textual and genealogical complexity.
Taking Charge of the Afrmative Action Debate Defending Afrmative Action: Understanding the Sustaining Genealogies
| 179
Both critics and proponents of afrmative action seek to produce a realist normalcy for their viewpoints and to render those of their opponents deviant and unnatural. Typically, a detailed normativity is spelled out and used as the basis for constructing its own foil. Through a binary logic, ones opponents are painted as threats to venerated cultural narrations that operate with the power of folklore in Americans self-understandings. All sides appeal to older, sacred images and narratives. These genes (this genealogy) are the conditions of possibility of the most politically powerful arguments for and against afrmative action. Scholars also work within these unstable discourses. Academic works necessarily take their point of departure from the logics that these culturally specic, discursive-formations maintain.17 From March of 1995 until November of 1996, I collected hundreds of newspaper articles, magazine features, talk-show recordings, and news programs focused on afrmative action. This period includes the November 1996 passage of a state ballot measure (#209) overturning afrmative action policies in California and the July 1995 end to afrmative action programs on all nine University of California campuses. I also recorded nearly ve hours of testimony from many dignitaries who spoke before the University Board of Regents prior to that decision. I found four binary themes to be regular features of the debate. Opponents of afrmative action speak and write regularly of merit versus special preferences and quotas; and of unity (read Americans) versus racial divisiveness. Proponents repeatedly articulate their positions as equal opportunity versus continuing discrimination and as inclusion of diversity versus policies of exclusion.18 Affective, politically focused sociology calls for being aware of these binary politics, their genealogical possibility, and devising, accordingly, specic textual strategies.19 In an essay on genealogy and history, Foucault recounts the fundamental link between interpretive work and politics.
If interpretation were the slow exposure of meaning hidden in an origin, then only metaphysics could interpret the development of humanity. But if interpretation is the violent or surreptitious appropriation of a system of rules, which in itself has no essential meaning, in order to impose a direction, to bend it to a new will, to force participation in a different game, and to subject it to secondary rules, then the development of humanity is a series of interpretations. The role of genealogy is to record its history: the history of morals, ideals, and metaphysical concepts, the history of the concept of liberty or of the ascetic life; as they stand for the emergence of different interpretations, they must be made to appear as events on the stage of historical process. (1971/1977:15152)
In both citations we nd the now familiar abandonment of any search for metaphysical truth, the abandonment of ontotheology (of any theologically constant theme underlying human existence). Derridas interpretation of interpretation celebrates the recognition that analysis always happens within textual economies of diffrance. Far from deciphering a truth or an origin, analysis poststructuralist style does not dream of the full presence of studied objects. We have no dream of an epistemology that escapes play [of diffrance] and the order of the sign. Because poststructuralists understand that we are constituted in this play, we are not exiles. We do not long to stand outside of politics. We are cultural and political workers for social change. We turn now to the genealogy that sustains the binary themes just outlined. We begin with the merit versus special preferences/quotas binary. For centuries, Americans have been taught to value our unique abilities, to celebrate individual accomplishment, and to emulate those with drive and determination. In his classic work, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Max Weber (19045/1996) traces this veneration of self-created accomplishment to the seventeenth-century, Puritan settlements of eastern North America. The Calvinist doctrine of predestination taught that all were saved or damned from birth and that created immense anxiety among Puritans. This
| 181
ever-present angst found its only relief in vigilant industriousness. Since the Puritan God did not exchange glances with his subjects, did not post grades or hold ofce hours, evidence of ones salvation or damnation was to be found only in the earthly blessings that he bestowed. Those who believed without question and waning faith was a sure sign that one was not among the savedled ascetic, disciplined lives. When hard work and thriftiness brought earthly rewards, the faithful knew that God was pleased and that they were among the chosen. By the colonial period, Weber teaches, the doctrine of predestination had died away, but the cultural ethos that equated hard work and frugality (asceticism) in the pursuit of earthly accomplishment with the highest moral behavior had been institutionalized. The self-made man or, as Weber says, the man of vocation had by the late eighteenth century become an American ideal. Weber hears the epitome of this cultural ethic in the words of Benjamin Franklin. Although Americans may not be able to trace the pithy, sometimes rhyming moral maxims of Franklin to the man himself, most of us have heard them, can repeat them from memory, and understand them intuitively. Who has not heard: A penny saved is a penny earned; time is money; and early to bed and early to rise make a man healthy, wealthy, and wise? This cultural lore of self-made success and failure is a widespread theme in our childrens stories. As kids, virtually all of us heard the story of the industrious ant that worked all summer while the happy-go-lucky grasshopper ddled and sang through the long months of sunshine when prudence demanded he should have been workingsaving for a rainy day as another colloquial example of the same mythos describes. We know of the slow but sure dedication of the tortoise and the overcondent, over-indulgences of the hare who our shell-encumbered hero beat to the nish line. And how many of us smiled in our youth when Charlie, the only economically unspoiled kid in the group, handed over the ill-gotten everlasting gob-stopper to Mr. Wonka, thereby earning his rightful place as heir to the throne of a candy dreamland? Although the following list is far from comprehensive, it contains movie titles, musical lyrics, epigrams, and popular quotations: Pull yourself up by your own bootstraps. The Lord helps those who help themselves. If at rst you dont succeed, try, try again. Winners never quit and quitters never win. Full of pith and vigor. You have to want it more than the other guy. Only the strong survive. The Right Stuff. You cant keep a good man down. We all get what we deserve. Never put off until tomorrow what you can do today. Got everything I own by the sweat of my brow.
| 183
the president of the National Association of Scholars charging afrmative action to be conspicuously at odds with evaluating the intellectual merit of individual students, scholars, and ideas (Balch 1996:A44). Although not mentioning afrmative action specically, Newt Gingrich made political use of textual imagery featuring race and merit by blaming a brutal triple murder on a welfare system which subsidized people for doing nothing (Associated Press 1995). Puddington (1996:7677) asserted, thousands of whites have . . . been passed over for civil-service jobs and university admissions because of outright quotas for racial minorities. And, to vote against a ballot measure eradicating the taking of afrmative action to force compliance with the Civil Rights Act, progressives found themselves rejecting ballot language that mimicked that same Civil Rights Act. Imagine voting to protect a policy designed to force compliance with federal antidiscrimination legislation by voting against language contained in that same legislation! Those of us on the losing side of this struggle were forced to mark no next to a ballot measure that read in part, Generally prohibits discrimination or preferential treatment based on race, sex, color, ethnicity, or national origin in public employment, education, and contracting. This example alone should sufce to prove that afrmative action itself has no inherent structure, no essential meaning, beyond the discursive struggles to narrate its reality. What it is and what it is understood to accomplish or promote are always already part of structure, of sign, and of play. Indeed what critics have done so successfully in their attack on afrmative action is to hijack the discursive formations of the civil rights movement and bend [them] to a new will, forc[ing] participation in a different game. This highly successful maneuver continues, and afrmative action beneciaries are everyday painted as undeserving recipients of special preferences that steal opportunities rightfully belonging to more meritorious white men. Consider, for example, the following linking of racial prejudices to patriotism: One of the patriotic Americans who ew a bombing mission over Afghanistan last Sunday was a guy named Vinnie. A few more bombing raids and President Bush will be able to cruise over Afghanistan in a Piper Cub puddle-jumper without risk. But guys like Vinnie are discriminated against by their own government in favor of Pakistani immigrants named Osama (Coulter 2001:7). It is folly to attempt to combat these attacks by trying to prove who and what is most meritorious. Every attempt to measure something as elusive as merit is doomed to simply reveal its designers political choices. There is no structure here and the search for one is a waste of political and intellectual energy. What is required is an understanding of the discursive combat surrounding the concept. What we ought to be asking is how we might seize, strategically, this series of interpretations and return its genealogical power to our side. With this in mind, it is no great feat to portray middle-class whites as the largest beneciaries of special preferences. The goal of progressive social scientists should be to place these depictions before the public in nonacademic,
This lack of perception of their own advantages should be publicly linked to the economic power that whites continue to disproportionately enjoy. For example, isnt growing up in a stable household with well-educated parents who can provide for ones every material need a special preference? Should attending and assuming that one has the right to attend the wealthiest schools, even as the grossest inequalities exist in neighboring school districts populated largely by ethnic minorities, be considered a special preference? What about the fact that disproportionately greater percentages of black and brown children are exposed everyday to street violence and to the mistakes of overzealous police forces? Do the cozy suburban nights of middle-class, white kids constitute special preferences? And what of the behaviors modeled by well-educated, well-adjusted, suburban parents? Do these kids, because they are less often forced to witness (in the most stark terms born of immediate proximity) the self-destructive behaviors of neighbors, parents, siblings, and friends enjoy a special preference? When these re-articulations are placed front and center in the debate over afrmative action, notions of merit and special preferences are redeployed against those whose advantages must not be allowed to remain conspicuously absent from the fray. Defenders of afrmative action (civically
| 185
minded sociologists) need to apprehend and redirect the invisibility of white privilege into the plain view of those who benet from it each and every day. To combat the long and deeply rooted textual chains called forth by discourses of meritocracy, defenders of afrmative action resurrect equally powerful genealogies that recollect the vast imagery of American ideals of fair play. Belief in the sanctity of equal opportunity and disdain for the racial segregation that fomented the civil rights movement remain powerful emotions for modern Americans. The equal opportunity versus continuing discrimination binary proves to be an efcacious discursive weapon. Once again, I offer a list of textual inscriptions. This one includes slogans, excerpts from famous speeches and documents, moral maxims, a song title, and other folkloric elements. We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal. I have a dream! Every little boy can be president. Prime-time television and cinema movies featuring all-white juries and black defendants. Good ol boys. Old lm clips of police and dogs attacking civil rights activists in Southern cities. A fair ght. Healthy competition. A level playing eld. Pull for the underdog. Watch out for the little guy. An equal opportunity employer. We shall overcome. Cheaters never win. A chance to prove myself. Defenders of afrmative action testifying before the University of California Board of Regents prior to the vote overturning that universitys admissions policy spoke eloquently from painful memories of discrimination. They recalled the humiliation visited upon Japanese Americans by World War II internment camps, the genocide carried out against Native Americans, and shared many personally endured examples of contemporary racism. In one particularly dramatic moment, Jesse Jackson linked former governor George Wallace of Alabama to the quietly listening governor Wilson of California. Urging Wilson to stand on the right side of history, Jackson (with remorse in his eyes and honesty in his voice) insisted that the withholding of equal educational opportunities was the platform for Wallace in Alabama and now, Mr. Governor, it is the platform for you here in California. Looking directly into Wilsons eyes, he urged the governor to look back on the images
| 187
bigger. They will abandon them . . . the bad ones will abandon them. . . . They have no intention of looking for a job. (Wilson 1996:126)
Feagin and Sikes (1994) have published an equally impressive collection of interviews with hundreds of middle-class, African American professionals. The indignities recorded there illustrate that middle-class status does not ensure equal treatment. Consider, for example, the ignominious hassle a news anchorperson has while attempting to do something as simple as rent a car over the telephone.
I could get a wonderful, enthusiastic reaction. . . . I would work that up to such a point that this person would probably shower me with roses once they got to see me. And then when I would show up, and theyre surprised to see that Im black, I sort of remind them in conversation how welcome my [business] was, to . . . embarrass . . . them, and I go through with my dealings. In fact, once my sister criticized me for putting [what] she calls my white on white voice on to get a rental car. . . . I knew that if I could get this guy to think that he was talking to some blonde, rather than, you know, so . . . I dont have to deal with that, I want to get the car. (Feagin and Sikes 1994:5455)
And an African American professor, speaking of the need for careful interaction with police, offers the following insight:
[One problem with] being black in America is that you have to spend so much time thinking about stuff that most white people just dont even have to think about. I worry when I get pulled over by a cop. I worry because the person that I live with is a black male, and I have a teen-aged son. I worry what some white cop is going to think when he walks over to our car, because hes holding onto a gun. And Im very aware of how many black folks accidentally get shot by cops. I worry when I walk into a store, that someones going to think Im in there shoplifting. And I have to worry about that because Im not free to ignore it. And so, that thing thats supposed to be guaranteed to all Americans, the freedom to just be yourself is a fallacious idea. And I get resentful that I have to think about things that a lot of people, even my very close white friends . . . simply dont have to worry about. (Feagin and Sikes 1994:68)
In a sadly humorous passage, Feagin and Sikes (1994:53) recount how then presidential candidate Jesse Jackson was mistaken for a bellhop and tipped by a white woman awaiting the same elevator in an upscale New York hotel. Although Jackson was impeccably dressed and a regular feature of the national news, she reportedly handed him a dollar bill and gushed, I couldnt have made it downstairs without you. Increasingly, social scientists have sought to solidify a broader more comprehensive account of afrmative action and its societal effects. Barbara Reskin
In an equally comprehensive review of the economics scholarship on afrmative action, Harry Holzer and David Neumark (2000:499500) are only slightly less enthusiastic:
. . . it is our view that increasingly subtle arguments are needed to explain away evidence consistent with discrimination as newer, more reliable evidence is obtained in response to earlier criticisms. In contrast, a uniform, relatively simple behaviordiscriminationcan explain much of both the older and newer evidence. . . . [A] reasonable conclusion from all of the evidence that the playing eld in the labor market is not yet level across the various groups.
These are the authoritative pronouncements of scientists adorned with impressive credentials, but they are not enough to secure political victory. We cannot afford to assume that the equal opportunity versus continuing discrimination binary is securely in our bag of discursive weapons. Opponents of afrmative action are willing and quite capable of identifying and attacking the political decisions that go into all scientic research. Indeed, as we heard
| 189
in the opening epigraph to the chapter, Connerly (2000: 225) refers to victims of discrimination as theoretical speculations. As a key architect of the scrapping of afrmative action in California and a leading spokesperson for similar attempts in other states, Connerly is a highly prominent gure in this battle. In his autobiographical text, Creating Equal, he asserts that his cause is the rightful heir to the civil rights movement. In one impassioned passage, he maintains that it is defenders of afrmative action who are the heirs of George Wallace. As such, he claims, we are protecting a corrupt and outmoded way of life. Calling us bitter-enders, he accuses us of furthering a modern echo of Wallaces infamous words: Preferences today! Preferences tomorrow! Preferences forever! (2000: 241). Connerlys strategy is not uncommon. Color blindness is the only fair avenue to advancement and achievement in the modern United States, this argument proceeds, regardless of what inequality statistics might indicate about the present. These detractors seek nothing less than to turn powerful civil rights genealogy against modern day civil rights activists. For example, color blindness, they claim, was the real goal of Martin Luther King Jr.; and, accordingly, they used Kings 1997 birthday to announce the formation of their American Civil Rights Institute. This is a bold tactic but one that can be soundly defeated, if proponents are intelligent in our rejoinders. First of all, we have the elders of that great ght for equality squarely in our camp. We also have the familial heirs of those leaders, including Martin Luther King III, publicly expressing their outrage over this turn of events. In the days after the stunt on his fathers birthday, King III exclaimed that he was appalled at the audacity (Lempinen 1997:A 17) of Connerly and of the other foes of afrmative action. Second, we need to publicly and resolutely interrogate Connerly about the dubiousness of his color blindness ideal. Does he really believe that his own status as a person of color has nothing to do with how his words play in the minds of his white supporters? Does Connerly not see that were his supporters as color blind as they claim he would not now be the prominent anti-afrmative action spokesperson that he is? Indeed, it is precisely because they are not at all color blind that Connerly gets the press that he does. No white businessperson, politician, or activist saying the things that Connerly says would receive the same attention. His political utility (and those of other reactionary people of color) is that he makes the arguments that right-wingers want to hear and that he is a person of color making them. Seeking to combat the power of social scientic narrations of racial inequality, opponents of afrmative action argue that they are in favor of equality of opportunity but opposed to any forced equality of results. This is, of course, an attempt to turn the discussion back to the genealogical terrain of merit, where their advantage is a distinct one. However, to force this re-articulation, they are increasingly required to acknowledge that poverty regardless of the color of its victimsis a serious impediment to merit-based competition. Accordingly, we have begun to hear opponents of afrmative
| 191
discussions. For example, and as I have already said, we should make special preferencesa sound-byte-length phrase repeated again and again in objective media appraisals of afrmative actionabout middle-class white folks. Again, the point is that our intellectual attention should be turned to assessing political discourse and our capacity to manipulate it for our own ends. Opponents of afrmative action portray themselves as champions of unity/Americans and as opponents of racial divisiveness. Being colorblind, they insist, means celebrating our commonality as citizens of the greatest nation on the planet. As former Republican nominee for president Robert Dole argues, we must return as a people to the original concept of what it means to be an American. Apparently aware of the fact that his comment was overly vague, even for a political speech, he added that as president he would work to ban college courses aimed at instilling ethnic pride in what he called the embarrassed to be American crowd (Shogan 1995). Similarly, former governor Wilson of California has referred to afrmative action as a virus that is leading to the tribalisation of America (Gunnison 1996). Like the arguments organized through each of the other binary themes, these charges have political efcacy because they recall and strategically deploy (via diffrance) a larger and temporally extensive complex of discursive genes. The following examples of this textual weave include the title of the former rst ladys book, slogans that have been used to the point of clich, additional famous words from a founding document of the republic, and an image of a crowd enveloped by the power of group-exacerbated patriotism. One nation, under God, indivisible with liberty and justice for all. E pluribus unum. United we stand and divided we fall. There is no I in team. Dont ght among yourselves. Just one big happy family. I got your back. Divide and conquer. No man is an island. Take one for the team. It Takes a Village. 60,000 standing baseball fans facing the ag, hats in hands, singing the National Anthem the day after the bombing of Baghdad. The appeal of unity, of common bonds is most likely even older than the ideology of meritocracy. Probably, it has its origins in the communal roots of all human beings. Whatever its extended and species-wide origins, unity and teamwork are old and constant themes in American life. Our leaders sell themselves by wrapping their personas in red, white, and blue contexts and by incessantly reciting patriotic platitudes designed to evoke what social
| 193
the months leading up to the passage of the Social Security Act of 1935. I wonder how many Americans realize that this foundation of modern American citizenship was engineered to exclude agricultural workers and domestic servants? Agricultural workers and domestic servants were of course overwhelmingly racialized minorities. We should ask, then, how many of todays white critics of afrmative action have beneted from their grandparents inclusion in this institutionalized system of labor protections and wealth building? Conversely, how many black and brown grandchildren of eld hands and servants have begun at a systematic disadvantage due to this government-imposed shackling of their grandparents? And what of the organized and methodical exclusion of racial minorities from labor unions and legalized collective bargaining? Obviously, the statutory exclusion of minorities from the American Federation of Labor and from other strong unions until the late 1950s gives the descendants of white unionized laborers a distinct advantage (a special preference) in the modern competition for jobs and university admissions. But again, how many Americans know this history? Of the few that do, how many can place this recollection side by side in the same cognitive process with their individualist aversion to afrmative action? Massey and Dentons (1993) detailing of the great lengths gone to by white politicians, real-estate agents, and neighborhood associations to ensure that blacks remained excluded from neighborhoods where home ownership and good schools acted as the foundation for wealth building in the twentieth century is equally damning to the argument that racial unity is somehow threatened by afrmative action. They convincingly demonstrate that black isolation in impoverished ghettos is the work of systematic and tireless manipulations by whites over several decades of the last century. With a thoughtful political deployment, such carefully gleaned evidence will reduce Governor Wilsons accusation that afrmative action is a virus that is leading to the tribalisation of America to an ugly display of blatant lying or to a reckless exhibit of historical ignorance. Despite the signicant progress made in race relations over the last century, nothing close to American unity has ever existed in the United States. Social science, stripped of its metaphysical desires and couched in the language of the political moment, can help make this ongoing racial apartheid into a prominent part of the struggle to maintain afrmative action. The American celebration of diversity is our greatest genealogical weapon in this civic struggle. The westward migrating pioneers of the last century continue to be celebrated in our folklore as free spirits. Tough guys ranging from martial arts experts to interstellar techno-warriors play out the clich of the lone hero riding into the sunset over and over again in our movie houses. An asserted right to be different remains central to the socialization of our young. Some of this celebration of diversity is captured in the following list of textual elements:
| 195
many of her viewers as a sign of social competence. Diversity in high places will make this type of challenge to institutionalized and discriminatory social agreements into a common occurrence. In other words, diversity in inuential settings among high-status participants cannot help but set off denitional contests over merit, qualications, and the meaning and signicance of race. Promoting familiarity with a wide range of discursive constructions of identity from many competing perspectives is key to widespread public recognition of differences of experience based on color. The political efcacy of poststructuralist sociology, here, is the ability and will to understand subjectivity (and not a theory of agency or a human nature or any ontotheology) as a consequence of genealogical power struggles. What a racialized being is or is not has nothing to do with empirically veriable structure. We are, rather, the effects of the many struggles that are, as Foucault says, the history of morals, ideals, and metaphysical concepts. Recognizing racializing discourses as political outcomes is civically empowering. Understood as discursive politics, identity can be publicly challenged and changed.
Coming Out of the Afrmative Action Closet: Real Wo/men Do Need these Programs Scholars of color who have enjoyed opportunity because of afrmative action need to get ourselves to the front of the line where politically expedient stories can be publicly given to other racialized Americans, allies who otherwise are at the mercy of the offensively debilitating, racializing discourses of our opponents. Should our detractors succeed in painting afrmative action as the illbegotten award of the underqualied, young people of color in this country will inevitably internalize the belief that real wo/men dont need afrmative action.21 Powerful lore that teaches that strong individuals overcome all is effectively countered when successful racialized and cultural others proudly and unabashedly proclaim (in all the colorful and painful details) that afrmative action made it possible for us to overcome great obstacles. Ironically, this long American tradition of naive individualism too often impedes the willingness of successful minorities to publicly confront this cultural lore. Accordingly, it is high time to come out of the afrmative action closet. The following biographical narrative promotes an alternative appraisal of afrmative action, of what it does and what it is. Although my story could go back many more generations, I will take you only to 1940 and to the birth of my father on the Klamath Indian Reservation in southern Oregon. As a preschool age child he suffered the deep emotional traumas that come with being surrounded by raging alcoholism, violence, and other poverty-related social ills. He and his twin brother were often left at home alone for as much as a week at a time while my grandparents stayed drunk. Sometimes there was not
| 197
and was proud of the job that he did. By the 1970s, dad had given up his bluecollar job and became an extremely successful sporting goods salesperson. I loved to travel with him to the schools where he befriended and sold products to coaches and parents. He was an amazing salesman, brimming with condence and intelligence. Later, he went to work selling insurance for New York Life and was, off and on, among the most successful in his ofce. Indeed, I vividly recall watching him in his suit and tie receiving an award at a large convention as he was applauded by hundreds of his fellow salespeople. I cannot say absolutely that my fathers employers were following federal guidelines and desegregating their workforces, but it was the era when federal enforcement was at its strongest. Although neither dad nor I was in the room when decisions to hire him were made, they were made. His successes at those jobs lasted through my early teenage years. I can tell you both as his son and as a sociologist that seeing him excel was fundamental to my own self-development. Although the good years did not last for our family, my fathers chance to show what he could do when given the opportunity was profoundly important to me. Nevertheless, no one could completely overcome the trauma that as a sociologist I can locate in the racialized inequality of his origins. Those scars are deep, and, at least from my perspective, they are the reason why dad and I had a strained relationship for many years. There is a long history of racial conict between our tribe and the white police, merchants, and farmers who live on and around our traditional lands. We suffered a forced termination, and when my father and others of his generation were paid for those lands, stealing that money became something of a local sport. For example, when my parents tried to buy land that was to become valuable lakefront property, the paternalistic bank agent responsible for dispersing my dads money would not agree to the sale because it was a bad investment. Nevertheless, Indians routinely paid more than white folks for all manners of consumer goodsmost notably cars. My mother vividly recalls a local pharmacist who brazenly invented charges for our family bill, and the current struggles over water in the region have dredged up all of the old racial antagonism anew. Although my Klamath friends and family might look at things differently, I feel that I have escaped from much of that life. The lives of my two sons are light years away from the hellish scenes that my father endured. Clayton and Jesse also live a much more stable and nurturing existence than my brother and I experienced. I was the rst in my family to graduate from college. I do not know if afrmative action played a role in my admission to Southern Oregon State College, but I graduated with a better than B average and a double major in political science and sociology. Although I certainly did not envision myself as the sort of person who would go to graduate schoolI did not even take my undergraduate education very seriouslymy professors and my grandmother urged me to apply. Because the alternative was working at a local grocery store
| 199
less tumultuous childhood, I would not have needed afrmative action. But I had to work those hours. I needed the opportunity that only afrmative action made possible. I clearly recognize, now, the direct connection between afrmative action and the transformation in self-appraisal that I underwent in graduate school and since joining the faculty at San Francisco State University. I also strongly suspect that my childhood pride for my fathers transformation was directly connected to afrmative action. Without afrmative action, my life and my sons lives would now be completely different. My boys go to decent schools, live in a stable home environment in a good neighborhood, and watch their parents strive for success in professional careers. They now have the special preferences that other middle-class kids have always had. My story re-inscribes notions of merit, race, and equal opportunity. The importance of diversity is also communicated in my narrative. When those of us who have beneted from afrmative action tell our stories publicly, we engage a powerful political tactic.
Summary In this chapter, I again argued that sociologists, and particularly racialized intellectuals, are most effective when we reject the metaphysical imperatives of structuralist sociology. The key components of afrmative action politics race, merit, individuality, and discriminationhave no essential structure. These regular features of the debate are textual inscriptions linked discursively to older genealogical trajectories. Thus their reality will not be revealed through disciplined epistemological stances. I provided a poststructuralist analysis of how discursive political articulations create and maintain understandings of afrmative action. I have sought to reveal some of the long, complex genealogy that provides arguments for and against afrmative action with political power. I also offered a series of suggestions for how racialized and progressive sociologists can manipulate textual terrain for political gain. In direct opposition to claims of critics of poststructuralism, I argued that freedom from metaphysical longings enhances sociologists capacity for civic work. In the tradition of C. Wright Mills, the promise of poststructuralist sociology lies in understanding how our theological and philosophical inheritances limit us. In the tradition of Friedrich Nietzsche, Foucault, and Jacques Derrida, it is also the chance to imagine going beyond those inheritances. With poststructuralism, as we heard Foucault say in the opening epigraph of the book, lies our best chance for achieving the undened work of freedom.
parting thoughts
A modern democratic political community should be conceived, as a discursive surface, not as an empirical referent.
Chantal Mouffe (1992:14)
have argued that structuralist dreams of a fully present and empirically available reality are faith-based inheritances that ultimately impede sociologists capacity for formidable political inuence. The hope that a perfect society will one day bloom from the understandings of scientic sociology is theological fantasy. There are no deeply hidden secrets of social life that disciplined duty to science will one day reveal as a logical, centered, and coherently structured foundation for moral living. The Greek and Christian location of morality in the phantasm of essential truths was, and is, folly. An inclusive society of respect, dignity, equality, and opportunity cannot be founded on faith in objectivity. This recognition is not politically debilitating. Epistemology may now appear to be fundamental to sociologists capacity to produce valued understandings, but its assumptions are not basic to our species. An ideal/ material binary was beyond question for the great thinkers of European historyincluding Plato, Aristotle, Sir Francis Bacon, Rene Descartes, Georg W. Hegel, and Karl Marx but it is not a pan-human ontology. It is a political and sociological effect with a long and complex genealogy. And the widespread assumption that it is the only possible avenue for meaningful intellectual work is a consequence of the history of European colonialism. Intellectuals from marginalized sectors of society, including racialized and cultural minorities, have much to gain from this realization. If objectivity is not about truth, then it has only always been about a will to power. We are not, and are not anytime soon, likely to be the most powerful groups in American society, and the disciplined pursuit of objective truth will not save us from right-wing, reactionary politics. As scholars from marginalized populations,
Parting Thoughts
| 201
we long for the simplicity of structuralist answers to our most pressing political problems at our own peril. Political successes will come only with an increased focus on discursive warfare. As academics from the margins, our responsibility in the battle for a better world is best conceived as a contest over the power to narrate. The challenge is to conceptualize research strategies that further our politics and to attack those of our opponents in decidedly public ways. We need to pay careful attention to the political potential of our conceptual choices. Our research designs should be crafted in language that interrupts and redirects the narratives of our adversaries. Our sociological accounts should be constructed for the purpose of impacting public debates. We should look to appropriate the narratives of our opponents and recast them, strategically, within textual logics that will work for the benet of our own peoples. Our sociology must be crafted for politics. Responsibility, here, is no simple matter. Because we can no longer claim responsibility to metaphysical ideals, our work must be for living, breathing, feeling people with immediate problems. We must take explicit political responsibility for the political consequences of our research and writings. What simplications do we further or create? Who do we consign to the conceptual margins and at what price? Finally, understanding that effective politics means looking for textual openings in discursive logics and bending them to our own narrative advantage must also mean recognizing that our opponents can do the same. As poststructuralists, we need to be vigilant about our own professional well-being in academic environments. How are we to explain our research designs to the organizations with the dollars necessary to fund our research projects? How do we talk to our colleagues about our work that openly aunts our loss of faith in scientic sociology? Heresy has its costs. Much like early Christian intellectuals needed to speak and write Greek before they could legitimize their academics, poststructuralist sociologists need to be thoroughly versed in the classical epistemological arguments of our eld. If we are to make intellectual headway with our structuralist colleagues, we must know Max Webers Methodology of the Social Sciences, Emile Durkheims Rules of Sociological Method, and Marxs German Ideology and Theses on Feuerbach. We need to be able to point with precision to their shortcomings, as well as to their utility, for scholarly renderings of our most pressing political problems. We will need to publicly insist that these works, and many other epistemological classics, remain valuable resources. Poststructuralist sociology, as I have tried to make clear throughout this book, cannot simply abandon the great corpus of structuralist sociology. No such break is possible or desirable. Only the status of these works as testaments to metaphysical dreams must be left behind. The question then is one of learning how to value and productively employ these resources without buying into their metaphysical aspirations.
notes
Chapter 1 1. The view from nowhere is also the title of a book by a modern and inuential philosopher who insists that we are in a sense trying to climb outside our own minds, an effort that some would regard as insane and that I regard as philosophically fundamental (Nagel 1986: 11). 2. In addition to Gitlin (1998) and Ritzer (1997), who we have already cited, Lemert (1997) and Denzin (1997) have also attempted such denitions. We will look closely at Rizters criticisms of poststructuralism in chapter 3 and spend many pages with Lemerts and Denzins move to dene these difcult writings in chapter 4. 3. Butler (1992) describes this diversity in greater detail. I prefer the term poststructuralist because it is less conated with opponents attacks on what they homogenize as postmodernism. 4. Perhaps most famously, Captain Janeway spent big parts of a whole series trying to help the Borg, who were said to consider themselves a collective, rediscover their long lost but always inherent individuality. 5. For discussions of these destabilizing events and the medieval intellectual systems that they disrupted, see Berman (1981/1989: 1126), Greenblatt (1991), Hulme (1986/1992), and Lovejoy (1936/1985). 6. Binary means having two (bi) parts: the knower (subject) and the known (object).
Chapter 2 1. A notable exception to this ethnocentrism is the work of Hirst and Woolley. In Social Relations and Human Attributes (1982), these sociologists demonstrate not only how social dynamics inuence biological development but, more importantly, how biology can only always be understood through social lenses. 2. Cornford (1932/1976:17) maintains that as early as the sixth century bc a few advanced intellects among the Ionians were already confronting nature as an impersonal world of things. However, he stops short of claiming that they had developed autonomous subjectivities. 3. The history of the word abstract depicts this sociological transformation. The prex ab means to move away or be pulled away from. A tract is a path or trail,
4.
5.
6. 7.
8. 9.
10.
Chapter 3 1. Once scientic subjectivity and the objects s/he studies are no longer conceived of as Platonic/Christian/Cartesian essences and purities (once they are de-centered), we can recognize that their description is forever incomplete. Every portrayal needs to be supplemented, both because it must call upon other (never fully present) meanings for its own coherence and because no account can ever fulll metaphysicians dreams of comprehensive description. 2. Macmullen (1997) notes that by the fourth century ad even the words philosopher and philosophize were thoroughly Christianized. They had come to designate ascetic piety. 3. Certainly, the Protestant Reformation played a large role in reinvigorating this biblical storys emphasis on personal responsibility. Although his scholarly motivations are very different, Webers (1930/1996) recollection of this important genealogical source substantiates my claim that our modern conception of responsibility is fundamentally theological in origin. 4. In German these words do rhyme, but of course Nietzsches sarcasm is aimed at a much greater afnity than rhyming.
Notes to Chapter 4
| 205
5. While Nietzche felt that the reduction of living into disciplinary regimens designed to produce good and to avoid evil was as ridiculous as it was dangerous in its imposed forms, he also felt that this desire signaled the revenge of the weak. He singled out Christianity for transforming all that was daring, strong, and sensually rewarding into something considered ugly, and he argued that Christians did so out of jealousy of those who were unafraid to enjoy life. See, in particular, the rst essay of his book, On the Genealogy of Morals (1887/1969). 6. Derrida (1966/1978:285), rereading and redeploying a term borrowed from LeviStrauss (1966), describes this work with the French word bricoleur. The bricoleur . . . is someone who uses the means at hand, that is, the instruments he nds at his disposition around him, those which are already there, which had not been especially conceived with an eye to the operation for which they are to be used. . . .
Chapter 4 1. These elds are far too large to summarize. Works that I have found useful include Bhabha (1994); Ferguson et al. (1990); Giroux (1992); Grewal and Kaplan (1994); Guha and Spivak (1988); Nandy (1983); Radhakrishnan (1987); Root (1996); Spivak (1987, 1990, 1993); Takagi (1994); and Trinh (1989, 1991). Useful anthropological contributions include Clifford (1988), Clifford and Marcus (1986), and Marcus and Fischer (1986). 2. I cited and briey discussed additional American critics in the introduction and in chapters 12. 3. The American Sociological Review, another of the disciplines most venerated journals, also ran a debate on deconstruction. Agger (1994), writing as a proponent, had only 5 pages and was sandwiched between the 25 pages awarded to Fuchs and Ward (1994a,1994b) who attacked what they called radical DECONSTRUCTION. Although I do not have the space to deal with this exchange in a more complete way, I can say that Fuchs and Ward were intent on containing deconstruction and protecting the epistemological premises of structuralist sociology. To do so, they tried to locate deconstruction within a Kuhnian (1962) paradigm shift. They assert that the more radical version of DECONSTRUCTION, which they claim is rare, is destined to be just one more fad. As Agger (1994:501) quite rightly asserts, Fuchs and Ward have got deconstruction wrong and they have got Derrida wrong. In assuming the indispensability of structuralist epistemology, they miss the most productively provocative aspects of Derridas work. This assumption is not unique to Fuchs and Ward, and I will deal with it in considerable detail in this chapter. 4. Students may want to know that Interactionist sociology became popular in American circles in the late 1960s and 1970s. It was largely seen as a reaction to what Blumer (1969) claimed was the structural determinism of existing psychological and sociological explanations. In other words, people were wrongly treated as only effects or consequences of sociological and/or psychological structures. That is, people were believed to behave as they had been molded to behave, by, for example, schools, churches, or struggles between the Freudian Id and Superego. Individual behaviors, then, were caused by forces largely beyond the control
5.
6.
7. 8.
9. 10.
11.
12. 13.
14. 15.
Notes to Chapter 5
| 207
discourse of Lyotard, Baurdrillard, and Jameson; the recent antifoundational turn in social theory; poststructural and postmodern feminist discourse; the critical Marxism of cultural studies; the interpretive and postmodern turn in anthropological theory and ethnography; and materialist critical ethnography. A reviewer [of Denzins work] suggests the term poststructural critical social science. 16. See also Bordo (1987). 17. An interstice is an in-between place. Recalling our discussion of text and diffrance, the meaning of things and people are never inherent to those things. They are never Platonic essences. Rather, their interpretability is a function of textually related meanings. Thus meaning comes from the unstable signicance of relationships between pieces of text. Male and female are related meanings, and each meaning is the possibility of any of us understanding the other. However, because their relationship is unstable (think about how our understandings of gender uctuate across time, culture, and geography), their individual meanings cannot be contained within either of them. Maleness and femaleness are constituted from the relationship (the in between, the interstice) of the two.
Chapter 5 1. Obviously there is no single scientic community or complete agreement about this issue among Native Americans, either within or across tribes. 2. These numbers are compiled from the Notices of Inventory Completion published in the Federal Register, from published reports of the NAGPRA Review Committee, and from documents obtained at meetings of the NAGPRA Review Committee. Although I have made every effort to ensure their accuracy, it is best to consider them as a strong estimate. 3. National Museum of the American Indian (1/21/07) at: http://www.nmai.si.edu /subpage.cfm?subpage=collaboration&second=repatriation. 4. For a provocative discussion of how the only centuries-old notion of race was used by scientists to claim a person nearly nine thousand years old, and an exchange between one of the Native leaders of the repatriation movement and perhaps the most progressive of senior American archaeologists, see Echo-Hawk and Zimmerman (2006). 5. Other archaeological organizations ling briefs on behalf of the plaintiffs in the Bonnichsen, Robson v. United States of America decision include two of the slowest to comply with NAGPRA. The Ohio Historical Society (OHS) maintains that because the Umatilla do not link the Ancient One to an archaeological phase, their claim to cultural afliation amounts to rank speculation (OHS 2003:8); the Texas Historical Commission (THC), worrying about tribal claims on old remains from what is now Texas, is still more dismissive, without adequate testing, the THC has no way to determine if any Native American Tribe is entitled to consultation (THC 2003:67). 6. The Klamath tribes include the Klamath, Modoc, and Yahooskin Indians. 7. A more developed account of this interview can be found in Dumont (2002).
Notes to Chapter 6
| 209
11. OConnors dissenting colleagues do not miss the vulnerability of her position. In the rst page of his opinion, Justice Scalia refers to her argument as a mystical . . . justication that challenges even the most gullible mind (539 U.S.:1 2003). 12. In a dissenting opinion in Grutter v. Lee et al. (2003), Justice Thomas also indicates his belief in the completely self-contained meaning of the Constitution: . . . the Constitution means the same thing today that it will mean in 300 months (539 U.S.:3 2003). 13. In dissent, Justices Ginsburg and Stevens each offer spirited analyses validating group-based afrmative action programs. Stevens writes of ongoing racial caste systems. See 515 U.S. 200 (931841). 14. In recent years school districts in both Oakland and Los Angeles have endured strident internal battles over the meaning of black English. In Oakland, Jesse Jackson insisted on the continued pursuit of standard English for all students (Asimov and Olszewski 1997). 15. That DSouza can read Boass morbid preoccupation with the remains of dead American Indians as the early origins of what would become an institutionalized ideology of equality testies to the lack of inherent meaning in that old anthropology. Indeed, DSouza specically cites Boass craniometry as the basis of what he takes to be misguided modern doctrines of equality. (See chapter 4, The Invention of Prejudice, pp.14448, in End of Racism [1995]). 16. DSouza does, however, make highly dubious claims. For example, he says that black women at all levels of education earn about the same as white women with comparable credentials and that black women with college degrees earn more than white women with college degrees (1995:301). Most social scientists will conclude that these are disingenuous interpretations designed to deceive or that he is simply wrong. 17. Some might confuse this situation with the Herculean efforts to protect and maintain epistemology found in Webers classic essay on Objectivity in the Social Sciences. In the empirical social sciences . . . the possibility of meaningful knowledge of what is essential for us in the innite richness of events is bound up with the unremitting application of viewpoints of a specically particularized character, which, in the last analysis, are oriented on the basis of evaluative ideas (1904/1949:111). Weber pursued as much objectivity as he dared hope for. While he was quite forthright about the impediments that sociologists face in the quest for objectivity, he was nowhere near our present point of declaring the pursuit to be a metaphysical tale chasing. Webers epistemological difculties led him to his famous (Platonic) logic of Ideal Types. Although too complex to describe in detail here, sufce it to say that he argued for a limited objectivity built upon the admittedly subjective choices of research topics made by sociologists. He understood that sociological concepts could never mirror empirical reality, but he hoped these conceptual simplications could be objectively compared to a far more complex objective reality. In addition to his Objectivity in the Social Sciences (1904/1949), see also Hekmans (1983) Weber, The Ideal Type, and Social Theory. 18. Gamson and Modigliani (1987) have done similar work, but their epistemological imaginary is quite different from the explicitly political emphasis of my poststructuralist analysis. They seek to document politics, not act politically. Their work is in the tradition of frame analysis laid out by Goffman (1974) and Gitlin (1980), identifying packages of afrmative action discourse with longitudinal, temporal
references
Abouali, Diana. 2002. Afrmative Actions Uncertain Future. Black Issues in Higher Education 19(3):1213. Alexander, Jeffrey C. 1991. Sociological Theory and the Claim to Reason. Sociological Theory 9(2):14753. Almaguer, Tomas. 1994. Racial Fault Lines. Berkeley: University of California Press. Antonio, Robert J. 1991. Postmodern Storytelling Versus Pragmatic Truth-Seeking. Sociological Theory 9(2):15463. Anzaldua, Gloria E. and Analouise Keating. 2002. This Bridge We Call Home.New York: Routledge. Archeological Resources Protection Act of 1979. 16 U.S.C.470. Public Law 9695. Arriola, Kimberly R. Jacob and Elizabeth R. Cole. 2001. Framing the Afrmative Action Debate: Attitudes Toward Out-group Members and White Identity. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 31(12):246283. Augustine. 426/1998. The City of God against Pagans. New York: Cambridge University Press. Asimov, Nanette and Lori Olszewski. 1997. Tempered Ebonics Resolution Unveiled for L.A. District. San Francisco Chronicle (1/14/97:A19). Associated Press. 1995. Gingrich Implicates Welfare in Triple Killing. San Francisco Chronicle (11/22/95:A12). Bacon, Francis, Sir. 1605/1952. Advancement of Learning. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica. Balch, Stephen. 1996. A Troubling Defense of Group Preferences. Chronicle of Higher Education (6/21/96:A44). Barker, Joanne and Clayton W. Dumont. 2006. Contested Conversations: Presentations, Expectations, and Responsibility at the National Museum of the American Indian. American Indian Culture and Research Journal 30(2):11140. Baudrillard, Jean. 1975. The Mirror of Production. St. Louis: Telos Press. .1983a. Simulations. New York: Semiotext(e). . 1983b. In the Shadow of the Silent Majorities, or The End of the Social and Other Es says. New York: Semiotext(e). . 1987. The Ecstasy of Communication. New York: Semiotext(e). . 1988. America. New York: Verso. Begley, Sharon. 1995. Three is Not Enough. Pp. 6769 in Newsweek (2/13/95).
212 | References
Berger, Peter. 1963/2005. Sociology as a Passion to Understand. Pp. 27 in The Meaning of Sociology. Ed. J. Charon. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Berman, Morris. 1981/1989. The Reenchantment of the World. New York: Cornell University Press. Bhabha, Homi K. 1994. The Location of Culture. Routledge: New York. Bieder, Robert. 1990. A Brief Historical Survey of the Expropriation of American Indian Remains. Pp. 278356 in Hearing before the Select Committee on Indian Affairs. U.S. Congress. Senate. One Hundred First Cong., 2nd Sess. On S.1021 and S.1980. S HRG>101952. Native American Grave and Burial Protection Act (Repatriation), Native American Repatriation of Cultural Patrimony Act, and Heard Museum Report. _____. 1996. The Representation of Indian Bodies in Nineteenth-Century American Anthropology. American Indian Quarterly 20(2):16579. Birnbaum, Jeffrey. 1995. Turning Back the Clock. Time (3/20/95: 145[11]). Blauner, Bob. 1992. Talking Past Each Other: Black and White Languages of Race. American Prospect (Summer):63. Blumer, Herbert. 1969. Symbolic Interactionism. Berkeley: University of California Press. Bologh, Rosalyn W. and Leonard Mell. 1994. Modernism, Postmodernism, and the New World (Dis)order: A Dialectical Analysis and Alternative. Critical Sociology 20(2):81120. Bonnichsen, Robson, et al. vs. United States of America, et al., and the Confederated Tribes of the Colville Reservation, et al. 2004. United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit. No. 0235994, D.C. No.CV-9601481-JE. Bordo, Susan. 1987. The Flight to Objectivity. Albany: SUNY Press. Bray, Tamara and Thomas Killion. 1994. Reckoning With the Dead. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press. Brown, Richard H. 1990. Rhetoric, Textuality, and the Postmodern Turn in Sociological Theory. Sociological Theory 8(2):18897. Brinton, Daniel G. 1895. The Aims of Anthropology. Science 2(35):24152. Burner, David, Genovese, Eugene D., and Forrest McDonald. 1980. The American People. St. James, NY: Revisionary Press. Butler, Judith. 1992. Contingent Foundations: Feminism and the Question of Postmodernism. Pp. 321 in Feminists Theorize the Political. Eds. J. Butler and J. Scott. New York: Routledge. . 1993. Bodies That Matter. New York: Routledge. California Civil Rights Initiative. 1996. http://www.canet.com:80/ccri/facts.htm (3/1/96). Charon, Joel M. Ed. 2005. The Meaning of Sociology. 8th ed. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall. Chatters, James. 1998. Kennewick Man. 60 Minutes (Television Program): October. Clough, Patricia T. 1992a. The End(s) of Ethnography. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. . 1992b. Poststructuralism and Postmodernism: The Desire for Criticism. The ory and Society 21: 54352. Cohen, Adam. 1999. Afrmative Action Face-Off. Time 154(5):58. Cole, Douglas. 1985. Captured Heritage. Norman: University of Oklahoma Press. Colish, Marcia L. 1997. Medieval Foundations of the Western Intellectual Tradition 4001400. New Haven: Yale University Press.
References
| 213
Cornford, F. M. 1932/1976. Before and After Socrates. New York: Cambridge University Press. Coulter, Ann. 2001. Afrmative Action for Osama. Human Events 57(38):7. Collins, Randall. 1992. The Confusion of the Modes of Sociology. Pp. 17998 in Postmodernism and Social Theory. Eds. S. Seidman and D. Wagner. Cambridge: Blackwell. Connerly, Ward. 2000. Creating Equal. San Francisco: Encounter Books. Cooley, Charles. 1902/1961. The Social Self. Pp. 82228 in Theories of Society. Eds. T. Parsons, E. Shils, K. Naegele, and J. Pitts. New York: Free Press. Cose, Ellis. 1995. The Myth of Meritocracy. Newsweek (4/3/95:34). Cross, Harry, Genevieve Kenny, Jane Mell, and Wendy Zimmerman. 1990. Employer Hiring Practices: Different Treatment of Hispanic and Anglo Job Seekers. Washington, DC: Urban Institute. Darwin, Charles. 1859/1909. Origin of Species. New York: P. F. Collier. Davis, James. 1991. Who Is Black? University Park: Pennsylvania State Press. DSouza, Dinesh. 1995. The End of Racism. New York: Free Press. . 2002. Whats So Great about America. Washington, DC: Regnery. . 2003. Why Im an Anti-Anti-American. San Francisco Chronicle (6/29/2003:D1,D6). Danise, Amy. 2000. The Mystery of the First Americans. Nova. Daston, Lorraine. 1991. Baconian Facts, Academic Civility, and the Prehistory of Objectivity. Annals of Scholarship 8:33763. Daston, Lorraine and Peter Galison, 1992. The Image of Objectivity. Representations 40:81128. Degler, Carl. 1971. Neither Black Nor White. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Deloria, Vine. 1972/1994. God Is Red. Golden, CO: Fulcrum Publishing. Denzin, Norman K. 1986. Postmodern Social Theory. Sociological Theory 4(2): 194204. . 1990. The Sociological Imagination Revisited. Sociological Quarterly 31(1):122. . 1994. Postmodernism and Deconstructionism. Pp. 182202 in Postmodernism and Social Inquiry. Eds. David R. Dickens and Andrea Fontana. . 1997. Interpretive Ethnography. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. . 2001. Symbolic Interactionism, Poststructuralism, and the Racial Subject. Symbolic Interaction 24(2):24349. . 2002. Reading Race. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Department of Interior. 1995. 43 CFR Part 10. RIN 1024-ACO7. Federal Register (60) 232:6213469. Derrida, Jacques. 1966/1978. Writing and Difference. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1968/1982. Margins of Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1972/1981. Positions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1993. Aporias. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. . 1995. The Gift of Death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Descartes, Rene. 1641/1984/1994. Meditations on First Philosophy, Pp. 1262 in The Philosophical Writings of Descartes. Vol. 2. New York: Cambridge University Press. Dickens, David R. and Andrea Fontanta. 1994. Postmodernism and Social Inquiry. New York: Guilford Press.
214 | References
Dodds, E. R. 1951. The Greeks and the Irrational. Berkeley: University of California Press. Dorsey, George A. 1898. A Cruise Among Haida and Tlingit Villages About Dixons Entrance. Popular Science Monthly 53(13):16074. Douglass, John. 2001. Anatomy of Conict: The Making and Unmaking of Afrmative Action at the University of California. Pp. 118144 in Color Lines. Ed. J. Skrentny. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Dumont, Clayton. 1995. Toward a Multicultural Sociology: Bringing Postmodernism into the Classroom. Teaching Sociology 23(4):30720. . 1998. The Analytical and Political Utility of Poststructuralism: Considering Afrmative Action. Canadian Journal of Sociology 23(23):21737. . 2002. Dead Family or Archaeological Collections. Race, Gender, and Class 9(2):831. Durkheim, Emile. 1895/1982. The Rules of Sociological Method. New York: The Free Press. Duster, Troy. 1998. Individual Fairness, Group Preferences, and the California Strategy. Pp.11133 in Race and Representation: Afrmative Action. Eds. R. Post and M. Rogin. New York: Zone Books. Dye, Thomas and L. Harmon Zeigler. 1978. The Irony of Democracy. North Scituate, MA: Duxbury Press. Echo-Hawk, Roger and Larry J. Zimmerman. 2006. Beyond Racism: Some Opinions about Racialism and American Archaeology. American Indian Quarterly 30 (34): 46185. Echo-Hawk, Walter. 1990. Testimony Before the Senate Select Committee on Indian Affairs on the Native American Repatriation of Cultural Patrimony Act. Pp. 17499 in Hearing Before the Select Committee on Indian Affairs. U.S. Congress. Senate. One Hundred First Cong. 2nd Sess. On S.1021 and S.1980 S HRG>101952. Native American Grave and Burial Protection Act (Repatriation), Native American Repatriation of Cultural Patrimony Act, and Heard Museum Report. Eisaguirre, Lynne. 1999. Afrmative Action: A Reference Handbook. Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-CLIO. Espiritu, Yen Le. 1992. Asian American Panethnicity. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Faia, Michael. 1993. Whats Wrong with the Social Sciences?: The Perils of the Postmodern. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Feagin, Joe and Melvin Sikes. 1994. Living with Racism. Boston: Beacon Press. Federal Glass Ceiling Commission. 1995. Good For Business: Making Full Use of the Nations Human Capital: A Fact-Finding Report of the Federal Glass Ceiling Commission. Washington, DC. Federal Register. 1999, 2000. http://www.gpoaccess.gov/fr/index.html. Ferguson, Russel, Martha Gever, Trinh T. Minh-ha, and Cornel West. 1990. Out There: Marginalization and Contemporary Cultures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Fix, Michael and Raymond J. Struyk. Eds. 1993. Clear and Convincing Evidence. Measurement of Discrimination in America. Washington, DC: Urban Institute. Foucault, Michel. 1971/1977. Nietzsche, Genealogy, History. Language, CounterMemory, Practice. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. . 1977. Power/Knowledge. New York: Pantheon Books.
References
| 215
.1980/1997. Christianity and Confession. The Politics of Truth. New York: Semiotext(e). .1984/1997. What is Enlightenment. The Politics of Truth. New York: Semi otext(e). Fuchs, Stephan and Steven Ward. 1994a. Deconstruction: Making Facts in Science, Building Cases in Law. American Sociological Review 59(4):481500. . 1994b. The Sociology and Paradoxes of Deconstruction. American Socio logical Review 59(4):50610. Galster, George. 1990. Racial Discrimination in Housing Markets during the 1980s. Journal of Planning Education and Research 9:16575. Gamson, William A. and Andre Modigliani 1987. The Changing Culture of Afrmative Action. Research in Political Sociology 3:13777. Gilroy, Paul. 2000. Against Race. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Ginsburg, Ruth. 2000. A Considered Opinion. Brookings Review 18(1):23. Giroux, Henry. 1992. Border Crossings. New York: Routledge. Gitlin, Todd. 1980. The Whole World Is Watching. Berkeley: University of California Press. . 1998. Postmodernism: What Are They Talking About? Pp. 5873 in The Postmodern Presence. Ed. A. Berger. Walnut Creek, CA: Alta Mira Press. Goffman, Erving. 1974. Frame Analysis. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Gramm, Phil 1995. Televised Speech broadcast live on CSPAN (9/8/95). Granly, R. M. 1996. Science or Sacrilege: Native Americans, Archaeology, and the Law. (VHS Tape) University of California Extension Center for Media and Independent Learning. Greenblatt, Stephen. 1991. Marvelous Possessions: The Wonder of the New World. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Grewal, Inderpal and Caren Kaplan. 1994. Transnational Feminist Practices and Questions of Postmodernity. Scattered Hegemonies. Eds. Grewal and Kaplan. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Guha, Ranajit and Gayatri Spivak. 1988. Selected Subaltern Studies. New York: Oxford University Press. Gunnison, Robert. 1996. Demons All the Rage in Politics. San Francisco Chronicle (2/19/96:A1). Harding, Nancy. 1986. The Science Question in Feminism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. . 1998. Is Science Multi-Cultural? Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Havelock, Eric A. 1963. Preface to Plato. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. . 1978. The Greek Concept of Justice from Its Shadow in Homer to Its Substance in Plato. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. . 1986. The Muse Learns to Write. New Haven: Yale University Press. Hawkinson, Cleone. 2001. Testimony before the NAGPRA Review Committee. Kelseyville, CA: June 2. Tape on File with Author. Heckman, James J. 1998. Detecting Discrimination. Journal of Economic Perspectives 12(2):10116. Hekman, Susan. 1983. Weber, The Ideal Type, and Contemporary Social Theory. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press. . 1986. Hermeneutics and the Sociology of Knowledge. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press.
216 | References
Henslin, James. 2002. Sociology. San Francisco: Allyn and Bacon. Hill-Collins, Patricia. 1990. Black Feminst Thought. Boston: Unwin Hyman. . 1997. Open Letter to my Sociological Colleagues. Perspectives: ASA Theory Section Newsletter 19(1):36. Hirst, Paul and Penny Woolley. 1982. Social Relations and Human Attributes. New York: Tavistock Publications. Holzer, Harry and David Neumark. 2000. Assessing Afrmative Action. Journal of Economic Literature 38(3):483568. Hrdlicka, Ales. 1904. Directions for Collecting Information and Specimens for Physical Anthropology. Washington, DC: Government Printing Ofce. Hubert, J. 1988. The Disposition of the Dead. World Archaeological Bulletin. http://avebury.arch.soton.ac.uk/wac/bulletin/wab2/Hubert.html. Hulme, Peter. 1986/1992. Colonial Encounters: Europe and the Native Caribbean 14921797. New York: Routledge. Ilter, Tugrul. 1995. Disciplinary Sociology in the United Methods of Empiricism. Current Perspectives in Social Theory 15(1):131. Jaeger, Werner. 1961. Early Christianity and Greek Paideia. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Johnson, George. 1996. Indian Tribes Creationists Thwart Archaeologists New York Times (10/22:A1). Johnson, Lyndon B. 09/24/1965. Executive Order 11246. Equal Employment Opportunity. Karabel, Jerome. 1997. Can Afrmative Action Survive? Tikkun 12(5):2930. Kelly, Erin and Frank Dobbin. 2001. How Afrmative Action Became Diversity Management: Employer Response to Antidiscrimination Law, 19611996. Pp. 87117 in Color Lines. Ed. J. Skrentny. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kellner, Douglas. 1988. Postmodernism as Social Theory: Some Challenges and Problems. Theory, Culture, and Society 5:23969. Kennedy, John F. 03/06/1961. Executive Order 10925. Establishing the Presidents Committee on Equal Employment Opportunity. Kennedy, K. 1996. Science or Sacrilege: Native Americans, Archaeology, and the Law. Op. cit. Kenney, Genevieve and Douglas Wissoker. 1994. An Analysis of the Correlates of Discrimination Facing Young Hispanic Job-Seekers. American Economic Review 84:67483. Killion, Thomas W. and Tamara L. Bray. 1994. Looking Toward Larsen Bay: Evolving Attitudes at the Smithsonian Institution. Pp. 39 in Reckoning with the Dead. Eds. T. L. Bray and T. W. Killion. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press. Kimmel, Michael S. 2003. Toward a Pedagogy of the Oppressor. Pp. 112 in Privilege. Eds. Michael Kimmel and Abby L. Ferber. Cambridge: Westview Press. Kinder, D. R. and L. Sanders. 1996. Divided by Color: Racial Politics and Democratic Ideals. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kluegel, James. 1990. Trends in Whites Explanations of the Black-White Gap in Socioeconomic Status, 19771989. American Sociological Review 55(4):51225. Kourvetaris, George A. 1994. Social Thought. Lanham, MD: University Press of America. Krupat, Arnold. 1992. Ethnocriticism. Berkeley: University of California Press. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962/1970. The Structure of Scientic Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Landau, Patricia and D. Gentry Steele. 1996. Why Anthropologists Study Human Remains American Indian Quarterly 20(2):20928.
References
| 217
La Noue, George and John Sullivan. 2001. Deconstructing Afrmative Action Categories. Pp. 7186 in Color Lines. Ed. J. Skrentny. Chicago: Univerisity of Chicago Press. Lebeau, Bronco. 1996. Science or Sacrilege: Native Americans, Archaeology, and the Law. (VHS Tape) University of California Extension Center for Media and Independent Learning. Leiter, Samuel and William Leiter. 2002. Afrmative Action in Anti-Discrimination Law and Policy. Albany: SUNY Press. Lembcke, Jerry L. 1993. Classical Theory, Postmodernism, and the Sociology Liberal Arts Curriculum. American Sociologist 24(1):5567. Lemert, Charles. 1991. The End of Ideology, Really. Sociological Theory 9(2): 16472. . 1992. Sez Who? Sociological Theory 10(2):24446. . 1997. Postmodernism Is Not What You Think. Malden, MA: Blackwell. Lempinen, Edward. 1997. Connerly Widens Anti-Afrmative Action Campaign. San Francisco Chronicle (1/16/97: A17). Levi-Strauss, Claude. 1966. The Savage Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lincoln, Yvonna S. and Norman K. Denzin. 2000. The Seventh Moment. Pp. 104763 in Handbook of Qualitative Research. Eds. Lincoln and Denzin. Lipsitz, George. 1998. The Possessive Investment in Whiteness. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Lorde, Audre. 1994. The Maters Tools Will Never Dismantle the Maters House. Pp. 98101 in Borderlands/La Frontera. Ed. Gloria Anzaldua. Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1936/1965. The Great Chain of Being. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Lukacs, Georg. 1922/1985. History and Class Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press. Macmullen, Ramsay. 1997. Christianity and Paganism in the Fourth to Eighth Centuries. New Haven: Yale University Press. Mallouf, Robert. 1996. An Unraveling Rope: The Looting of Americas Past. American Indian Quarterly 20(2):197208. Mannheim, Karl. 1936/1985. Ideology and Utopia. New York: Harcourt. Marx, Karl. 1888/1978. Theses on Feuerbach. Pp. 143145 in The Marx-Engels Reader. Ed. Robert C. Tucker. . 1932/1978. The German Ideology Part 1. Pp. 146200 in The Marx-Engels Reader. Ed. Robert C. Tucker. Massey, Douglas S. and Nancy A. Denton. 1993. American Apartheid. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Massey, Douglas S. and Garvey Lundy. 2001. Use of Black English and Racial Discrimination in Urban Housing Markets. Urban Affairs Review 36(4):45269. McKenna, M. A. J. 2002. Smokers Who Try to Quit Likely to get Burned. San Francisco Chronicle (7/26/2002:A9). Mead, George. 1934/1961. Taking the Role of the Other. Pp.739740 in Theories of Society. Eds. T. Parsons, E. Shils, K. Naegele, and J. Pitts. New York: Free Press. Meckler, Laura. 2002. Study Finds Kids Lives Improving, but Infant Health Varies by Race. San Francisco Chronicle (7/12/2002:A3). Meighan, Clement W. 1992. Some Scholars Views on Reburial. American Antiquity 57:70410. . 1993. The Burial of American Archaeology. Academic Questions 6(3):919. .1996. Disowning the Past. Social Facts 3:15.
218 | References
Mills, C. Wright. 1959. The Sociological Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press. Mouffe, Chantal. 1992. Democratic Politics Today. Pp. 116 in Dimensions of Radical Democracy. Ed. C. Mouffe. New York: Verso. Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press. Nandy, Ashis. 1983. The Intimate Enemy. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. National NAGPRA Online Databases. http://www.nps.gov/history/nagpra/ONLINEDB /INDEX.HTM. National NAGPRA FY 2005 Final Report. U.S. Park Service: U.S. Department of the Interior. National Urban League. 2001. National Urban League State of Black America 2001 Survey. http://www.nul.org/soba2001/sobasurvey.html (7/22/2002). Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act (25 U.S.C. 3001) Public Law 101601 (November 16, 1990). New York Times. 1904. Mexicans Ranked as Negroes (4/12/04). Nicholson, Linda J., Ed. 1990. Feminism/Postmodernism. New York: Routledge. Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1873/1954. On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense. Pp. 4247 in The Portable Nietzsche. Ed. Walter Kaufman. New York: Viking Press. . 1882/1974. The Gay Science. New York: Random House. . 1886/1990. Beyond Good and Evil. New York: Penguin Books. .1887/1969. On the Genealogy of Morals. New York: Vintage Books. . 1889/1968. Twilight of the Idols. Baltimore: Penguin Books. . 1895/1968. The Anti-Christ. Baltimore: Penguin Books. . 1901/1967. The Will to Power. New York: Vintage Books. Nihipali, Kunani. 1993. Testimony Before the Honorable John McCain, Vice Chairman Senate Select Committee on Indian Affairs. Pp. 10897 in Hearing Before the Committee on Indian Affairs. U.S. Congress. Senate. One Hundred Third Cong. 1st Sess. On Oversight Hearing on Understanding How the Native American Grave Protection and Repatriation Act is Being Implemented. Nixon, Richard M. 12/19/1969. Statement Urging Senate and House Conferees to Permit Continued Implementation of the Philadelphia Plan. Presidential Papers. http://www.nixonfoundation.org/Research_Center/1969_pdf_les/1969_0494.pdf. Nova. 2000. (Television Broadcast). The Mystery of the First Americans. Ohio Historical Society. 2003. Member organization of The Ohio Archaeological Council. Amicus Brief of the Ohio Archaeological Council in Support of PlaintiffsApellees. Bonnichesen vs. United States. Case No. 0235996. (District Court No. 961481 JE[D.Or.]) Ong, Paul. 1999. Impacts of Afrmative Action: Policies and Consequences in California. Walnut Creek, CA: Alta Mira Press. Owen, David, Ed. 1997. Sociology After Postmodernism. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Pincus, Fred. 2001/2002. The Social Construction of Reverse Discrimination: The Impact of Afrmative Action on Whites. Journal of Intergroup Relations 38(4):3343. Plato. c. 427347 bc/1989. The Collected Dialogues of Plato. Eds. Hamilton, Edith and Huntington Cairns. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. . Socrates Defense (Apology). Tr. Hugh Tredennick, Pp. 326 in Eds. Hamil ton and Huntington.
References
| 219
. Charmides. Tr. Benjamin Jowett, Pp. 99122 in Eds. Hamilton and Huntington. . Laches. Tr. Benjamin Jowett, Pp. 12344 in Eds. Hamilton and Huntington. . Phaedrus. Tr. R. Hackforth, Pp. 475525 in Eds. Hamilton and Huntington. . Laws. Tr. A. E. Taylor, Pp. 12251516 in Eds. Hamilton and Huntington. Plato. c. 427347 bc/1974. The Republic. Tr. Desmond Lee. New York, NY: Penguin Books. Preston, Douglas. 1989. Skeletons in our Museums Closets. Harpers Magazine 278:6675. Puddington, Arch. 1996. Afrmative Action Should Be Eliminated. Pp. 7083 in Afrmative Action. Ed. A. Sadler. San Diego: Greenhaven Press. Pullar, Gordon. 1994. The Qikertarmiut and the Scientist: Fifty Years of Clashing World Views. Pp.1525 in Reckoning with the Dead. Eds. T. Killion and T. Bray. Washington, DC: Smithsonian Institution Press. Radhakrishnan, R. 1987. Ethnic Identity and Post-Structuralist Differance. Cultural Critique 6:199220. Reich, Robert. 1995. Message from the Chairman. Pp. iii-v in Good for Business: Making Full Use of the Nations Human Capital: A Fact Finding Report of the Federal Glass Ceiling Commission. Reskin, Barbara. 1998. The Realities of Afrmative Action in Employment. Washington, DC: American Sociological Association. Riding In, James. 1992. Without Ethics and Morality: A Historical Overview of Imperial Archaeology and American Indians. Arizona State Law Review 24:1134. Ritzer, George. 1997. Postmodern Social Theory. New York: McGraw-Hill. Rogers, Mary F. 1992. Teaching, Theorizing, Storytelling: Postmodern Rhetoric and Modern Dreams. Sociological Theory 10(2):23140. Root, Deborah. 1996. Cannibal Culture. Boulder, CO: Westview. Rosenau, Pauline M. 1992. Post-Modernism and the Social Sciences. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Rosenblum, Karen and Toni-Michelle Travis. 2000. The Meaning of Difference. New York: McGraw-Hill. Rubenstein, Richard E. 2003. Aristotles Children. Orlando, Florida: Harcourt Inc. Ryan, William. 1981. Equality. New York: Pantheon Books. San Francisco Chronicle. 2002. Police List Those They Believe Will Break Laws. San Francisco Chronicle (8/26/02: A7). Schuman, Howard, Charlotte Steeh, Lawrence Bobo, and M. Krysan. 1997. Racial Attitudes in America: Trends and Interpretations. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Scott, Joan W. 1992. Experience. Pp. 2340 in Feminists Theorize the Political. Eds. Judith Butler and Joan Scott. New York: Routledge. Seidman, Steven. 1991a. The End of Sociological Theory: The Postmodern Hope. Sociological Theory 9(2):13146. . 1991b. Postmodern Anxiety: The Politics of Epistemology. Sociological The ory (9)2:18090. . 1992. Word Power: Is Rhetoric All There Is? Sociological Theory 10(2):25558. . 1997. Relativizing Sociology: The Challenge of Cultural Studies. Pp. 3761 in From Cultural Studies to Sociology. Ed. E. Long. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
220 | References
Shogan, Robert. 1995. Dole Wants to End Bilingual Classes in U.S. San Francisco Chronicle (9/5/95:A1). Simic, Andrei and Harry G. Custred Jr. 2003. Motion for Leave to File Brief of Amicus Curiae in support of the Plaintiff_Appellees. Bonnichesen vs. United States. Nos 0235996 District Court N0. 961481JE (D.Or.) Simon, Bennet. 1978. Mind and Madness in Ancient Greece. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Simons, Herbert W. and Michael Billig. 1994. After Postmodernism. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications. Skrentny, John. 2001. Introduction. Pp. 128 in Color Lines: Afrmative Action, Immigration, and Civil Rights Options for America. Ed. J. Skrentny. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Smith, Dorothy. 1987. The Everyday World as Problematic. Boston: Northeastern University Press. Smithsonian Institution. National Museum of Natural History Repatriation Ofce. Table of Completed Repatriations. April 2, 2007. http://www.nmnh.si.edu/anthro/ repatriation/faq/index.htm#collect04. Snell, Bruno. 1953. The Discovery of the Mind. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Society for American Archaeology. 2003. Brief of Amicus Curiae in Support of the Plaintiffs-Appellees. Bonnichsen vs. United States. Court No. 961481JE (D. Or.). Sowell, Thomas. 1994. Race and Culture. New York: Basic Books. Spivak, Gayatri. 1987. In Other Worlds. Routledge: New York. .1990. The Postcolonial Critic. Routledge: New York. . 1993. Outside in the Teaching Machine. New York: Routledge. . 1999. A Critique of Postcolonial Reason. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Stephanopoulos, George and Christopher Edley Jr. 1995. Afrmative Action Review: Report to the President. Washington, DC. Supreme Court of the United States. 1989. City of Richmond v. J. A. Cronson Co. No. 87998, 488 U.S. 469. . 1995. Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Federico Pena, Secretary of Transportation, et al. No. 931841, 515 U.S. 200. . 2003. Barbara Grutter v. Lee Bollinger, et al. No. 02241,539 U.S. 306. Swain, Carol, Green, Kyra, and Christine Min Wotipka. 2001. Understanding Racial Polarization on Afrmative Action. Pp. 21438 in Color Lines. Ed. J. Skrentny. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Symposium on the Social History of Objectivity. 1992. Social Studies of Science 22. Texas Historical Commission. 2003. Brief of Amicus Curiae in Support of Appellees. Bonnichsen vs. United States. Nos. 0235994&0235996. Related Case DC 961481JE (D.Or.) Thomas, David H. 2000. Skull Wars. New York: Basic Books. Thomas, Paulette. 1991. U.S. Examiners Will Scrutinize Banks with Poor MinorityLending Histories Wall Street Journal (10/9/92: A2). Thomas, Ward and Mark Garrett. 1999. U.S. and California Afrmative Action Policies, Laws, and Programs. Pp. 2558 in Impacts of Afrmative Action. Ed. P. Ong. Walnut Creek, CA: Alta Mira Press. Thornton, Russell. 1998. Who Owns Our Past? Pp. 385415 in Studying Native America. Ed. R. Thornton. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. Trinh, T. Minh-ha. 1989. Woman, Native, Other. Indiana University Press: Bloomington.
References
| 221
. 1991. When the Moon Waxes Red. New York: Routledge. Tucker, Robert C., Ed. 1978. The Marx-Engels Reader. New York: W. W. Norton and Company. Turner, Jonathan H. 1998a. Must Sociological Theory and Sociological Practice Be so Far Apart? Sociological Perspectives 41(2):243258. . 1998b. Response to Commentary: Sociology as an Engineering Discipline. Sociological Perspectives 41(2):27378. Ubelaker, Douglas H. and Lauryn G. Grant. 1989. Human Skeletal Remains: Preservation or Reburial? Yearbook of Physical Anthropology 32:24987. U.S. Bureau of the Census. 1999. Statistical Abstract of the United States: The National Data Book. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Ofce. Published annually. U.S. Department of Interior. 1995. 43 CFR Part 10. RIN 1024-ACO7. Federal Register (60) 232:6213469. U.S. Department of Labor. 1978. 41 CFR 602.11. Required utilization analysis and 41 CFR 602.12. Establishment of goals and timetables. U.S. Bureau of Labor. 2003. Bureau of Labor Statistics. U.S. Department of Interior. 2001. Status of Forbearance Museums. Document on le with Author. . 2004. (National Park Service) National NAGPRA FY 04 Midyear Report for the Period October 1, 2003March 31, 2004. Van Kley, Dale K. 1996. The Religious Origins of the French Revolution. New Haven: Yale University Press. Walton, Beth. 1999. Maintaining Responsibility Through Reason. American Committee for Preservation of Archaeological Collections (ACPAC) Newsletter. March: 56. Ward, Steven. 1997. Being Objective about Objectivity: The Ironies of Standpoint Epistemological Critiques of Science. Sociology 31(4): 77391. Watkins, Joe, Lynne Goldstein, Karen Vitelli, and Leigh Jenkins. 1995. Accountability: Responsibilities of Archaeologists to Other Interest Groups. Pp. 3337 in Ethics in American Archaeology. Eds. M. Lynott and A. Wylie. Weber, Max. 1904/1949. The Methodology of the Social Sciences. New York: Free Press. . 19045/1996. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Los Angeles: Rox bury Publishing Company. Wellman, David 1997. Minstrel Shows, Afrmative Action Talk, and Angry White Men: Marking Racial Otherness in the 1990s in Displacing Whiteness. Ed. Ruth Frankenberg. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Wilson, Pete 1996. Why Racial Preferences Must End. San Francisco Chronicle (1/18/96:A21). Wilson, William J. 1996. When Work Disappears. New York: Vintage Books. Yinger, John. 1993. Access Denied, Access Constrained. Pp. 69112 in Clear and Convincing Evidence: Measurement of Discrimination in America. Eds. M. Fix and R. Struyk. Washington, DC: Urban Institute Press. . 1995. Closed Doors, Opportunities Lost: The Continuing Costs of Housing Discrim ination. New York: Russell Sage.
index
Abouali, Diana, 192 Abraham, and Isaac, 5657, 61, 67, 69, 75 Adarand Constructors v. Secretary of Transportation Pena, 158, 163, 177 Advancement of Learning (Bacon), 43 Alexander, Jeffrey C., 8385, 8789, 92 Almaguer, Tomas, 175 American Sociological Association (ASA), 50, 79, 188; Sociological Theory, 79, 83, 85 Ancient One, 11618, 121, 207n5 Antonio, Robert J., 8590, 92 Aristotle, 22, 41, 200 Arriola, Kimberly R. Jacob, 151 Augustine, Saint, 3940 Bacon, Sir Francis, Advancement of Learning, 43; 4448, 51, 186, 200, 204n5 Barbara Grutter v. Lee Bollinger, et al, 163, 209n12, 210n20 Barker, Joanne, 206n13 Baudrillard, Jean, 13, 85, 94, 100 Berger, Peter, 4750, 52, 54, 104, 144 Berman, Morris, 203n5 Bhabha, Homi K., 2, 13, 84, 205n1 Bieder, Robert, 126, 127 Blumer, Herbert, 205n4 Boas, Franz, 13031, 136, 172. 209n15 Bologh, Rosalyn W., 3 Bonnichsen, Robson v. United States of America, 12122, 207n5 Bordo, Susan, 207n16 Bray, Tamara L., 118, 133, 138 Brown, Richard H., 7980 Brown v. Board of Education, 153 Brinton, Daniel G., 128, 130, 139 Butler, Judith, 2, 13, 11011, 143, 203n3 (chap.1) Cartesian faculty, 2, 2325, 28, 31, 33 Charon, Joel M., 4748 Chatters, James, 11617 Christian Aristotelians, 23, 43, 45, 103, 204n5 City of Richmond v. Cronson, 158, 162 Clough, Patricia T., 79, 95, 1036; The End(s) of Ethnography, 106 Code of Federal Regulations, The (CFR), 122, 15657 Cole, Douglas, 112, 130, 136, Cole, Elizabeth R., 151 color blindness, 186, 189 Colish, Marcia L., 40 Cornford, F.M., 35, 37, 41, 203n2 (chap. 2) Collins, Randall, 4 Connerly, Ward, 149, 18990 Copernicus, 23 Creator, 4143 Cross, Harry, 165 Darwin, Charles, Origin of a Species, 126 Davis, James, 17576 DSouza, Dinesh, 17274, 209n15, 209n16 Daston, Lorraine, 204n6, 204n8 Deductive reasoning, 23, 43 Degler, Carl, 177 Deloria, Vine, 138 Denzin, Norman K., 79, 93103, 203n2 (chap. 1), 206n11, 206n12, 2067n15
224 | Index
Derrida, Jacques, 23, 17, 25, 5457, 67, 69, 70, 76, 7879, 84, 88, 9094, 97, 1057, 111112, 142, 180, 199, 205n6, 206n9, 2067n15; on Abraham and Isaac, 57; on the birth of postructuralism, 3; on the concept of centered structure, 12, 2931; diffrance, 6265, 67; the logic of the supplement and, 55; Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourse of Human Sciences, 90 Derridean deconstruction, 52, 7880, 84, 86, 92, 94, 97, 100, 205n3 Descartes, Rene, 2227, 2930, 38, 42, 43 44, 200; inuence by Plato, 23; impact on modern, Western knowledge forms, 2325; Meditations on First Philosophy, 23 dialectic, 29, 32537, 41, 83, 92, 206n6, 206n10 diffrance, 6268, 7071, 93, 105, 111, 172, 180 Dodds, E.R., 33 Dorsey, George A., 13536 Douglass, John, 157 Dumont, Clayton, 192, 206n7, 206n13, 207n7 Durkheim, Emile, and theory, 13, 32; Rules of Sociological Method, 201 Duster, Troy, 149, 192, 208n5, 208n6 Dye, Thomas, 153 Echo-Hawk, Roger, 207n4 Echo-Hawk, Walter, 112 Eisaguirre, Lynne, 150, 154, 157, 208n6 epistemology, 4, 22, 31, 42, 7879, 81, 86, 87, 8990, 9293, 9799, 102103, 180, 200, 209n17 eschatology, 4041, 43; meaning of, 40; metaphysics of, 46, 48; and pledge of, 60; time and, 65 Espiritu, Yen Le, 175 Executive Order 10925, creation of Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC), 153 Executive Order 11246, strengthening equal employment opportunity, 154 Faia, Michael, 4, 9, 12 Feagin, Joe, 150, 174, 187 Federal Glass Ceiling Commission, 164, 208n2 Ferguson, Russel, 205n1 Fix, Michael, 165 free will, 15, 169, 174 Foucault, Michel, 13, 1214, 5960, 69 82, 84, 86, 8889, 91, 100, 105, 111, 145, 165, 167, 179, 195, 167, 179, 195, 199, 206 -7n15; on truth and power, 6970, 75, 89; on verbalization, 49; Foucaultian genealogy, 26, 78, 80, 86, 100, 145, 165, 179 Fuchs, Stephan, 3, 205n3 Galileo, 23, 43, 115, 141 Galster, George, 169 Gamson, William A., 209n18 German Ideology (Marx), 201 Gilroy, Paul, 151 Ginsburg, Ruth, 155, 161, 209n13 Giroux, Henry, 2, 13, 205n1 Gitlin, Todd, 4, 203n2 (chap. 1), 209n18 Goffman, Erving, 32, 209n18 great chain of being, 22, 43 Greenblatt, Stephen, 203n5 Grewal, Inderpal, 205n1 Griggs v. Duke Power Company, 156 Guha, Ranajit, 205n1 Gunnison, Robert, 191 Harding, Nancy, 206n10 Havelock, Eric A., 3337 Hawkinson, Cleone, 116, 141, 14344 Heckman, James J., 17072 Hekman, Susan, 3, 209n17 Heslin, James, 164 Hill-Collins, Patricia, 36, 5254, 59, 144, 206n10 Hirst, Paul, 33, 203n1 (chap. 2) Holzer, Harry, 188 Holy Spirit, 4246, 48, 204n5 Homer, 3337 Hrdlicka, Ales, 120, 13136 Hubert, J., 112 Hulme, Peter, 203n5 identity, 2, 7273, 88, 91, 94, 99, 110, 122, 159160, 162, 173, 176, 195 inductive reasoning, 43, 45, 47, 204n7 Ilter, Tugrul, 52 Jaeger, Werner, 4041 Jefferson, Thomas, 125 Johnson, Lyndon B., 154, 158
Index
Kelly, Erin, 156157 Kennedy, John F., on equal employment opportunity and afrmative action, 15354 Kennewick Man. See Ancient One Kenney, Genevieve, 165 Killion, Thomas W., 118, 133, 138 Kimmel, Michael S., 184 Kinder, D.R., 208n2 Kluegel, James, 150 Kourvetaris, George A., 43 Krupat, Arnold, 130 Kuhn, Thomas, S., 205n3, 209210n18 Landau, Patricia, on opposition to repatriation of Native American human remains 119120, 12426, 128, 136, 145 La Noue, 158, 17778 Leiter, Samuel, 208n7 Leiter, William, 208n7 Lembcke, Jerry L., 4, 12 Lemert, Charles, 79, 9094, 9697, 99, 101, 203n2 (chap. 1); on Derrida, 9293; Postmodernism Is Not What You Think, 90 Levi-Strauss, Claude, 105, 205n6 Lincoln, Yvonna S., 79, 95, 96, 99 Lipsitz, George, 150, 157 logos, 4244, 46, 4849, 58, 60, 65, 69; meaning of, 42 logocentrism, 93 Lorde, Audre, 92, 97 Lovejoy, Arthur O., 41, 203n5 Lukacs, Georg, 206n6 Macmullen, Ramsay, 204n2 Mallouf, Robert, 119, 12930, 136 Mannheim, Karl, 206n6 Marx, Karl, 13, 200; German Ideology, 201; Theses on Feuerbach, 201 Marxism, 20, 2930, 8384, 8788, 94, 102, 2067n15 Massey, Douglas S., 170, 193 Mead, George, 32, 79, 161, 208n10 Meditations on First Philosophy (Descartes), 23 Meighan, Clement W., on opposition to repatriation of Native American human remains, 115, 140, 143 Methodology of the Social Sciences (Weber), 201 metaphysical, meaning of, 18
| 225
metaphysics: impact of classic Greek, 39; of plentitude, 41; of presence, 25, 93, 9798 Mills, C. Wright, 4, 31, 77, 91, 102, 106 7, 199 Mouffe, Chantal, 13, 200, 202, Nagel, Thomas, The View from Nowhere, 203n1 Native American Graves and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA), 6, 8, 108, 118, 120123; 11214 13741, 146, 148; non-federally recognized tribes and, 137 Native American Graves Protection and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA) Review Committee, 110, 113, 116, 117, 123, 207n2 National Museum of the American Indian Museum Act (NMAIA), 112 Nicholson, Linda J., 206n10 Nietzsche, Friedrich, 13, 18, 21, 2526, 32, 61, 76, 84, 86, 105, 145, 180; on Christianity, 205n5; On the Genealogy of Morals, 205n5; The Will to Power, 70; Twilight of the Idols, 204n9 Nihipali, Kunani, 112 nihilism, 34, 62 Nixon, Richard M., 15556, 158, 16667, 196, 208n5 objectivity, meaning of, 204n10 OConnor, Sandra Day, 15863 On the Genealogy of Morals (Nietzsche), 205n5 Ong, Paul, 157 Origin of Species (Darwin), 126 Owen, David, 206n5 Owsley, Doug, on opposition to repatriation of Native American human remains, 108, 11011, 117, 120 patriotism, 20, 183, 191 Pincus, Fred, 151 Plato, 10, 23, 25, 32, 3445, 4749, 51, 55, 57, 70, 71, 79, 8687, 103, 152, 164, 169, 186, 200, 204n1, 207n17, 209n17 positivist science, 1819, 46 Postmodernism Is Not What You Think (Lemert), 90 postructuralism, and difculties in dening, 13
226 | Index
Preston, Douglas, 112, 133, 137 Puddington, Arch, 174, 183 Pullar, Gordon, 133 Racial identity. See identity racism, 21, 52, 66, 74, 95, 129, 144, 150 54, 161, 166, 169, 174, 176, 185 Radhakrishnan, R., 205n1 Reich, Robert, 174 relativism, 3, 4, 50; cultural, Boas and, 172 Reskin, Barbara, 165, 18788 Riding In, James, 130 Ritzer, George, 4, 5861, 203n2 (chap. 1) Rogers, Mary F., 8283 Root, Deborah, 205n1 Rosenau, Pauline M., 3 Rubenstein, Richard E., 204n5 Rules of Sociological Method (Durkheim), 201 Ryan, William, 154 Schuman, Howard, 208n2 Scalia, Antonin, 160, 163, 164, 168169, 194 Scott, Joan W., 13, 169 scholastics. See Christian Aristotelians Seidman, Steven, 6, 78, 8083, 85, 88, 90 self-disdain, 26, 38, 45, 47, 51, 56 Simon, Bennet, 3435 Skrentny, John, 174 Smith Dorothy, 206n10 Smithsonian Institution, Enola Gay display controversy and, 20; holdings of Native American human remains and, 112, 133, 137, repatriation of Native American human remains and, 114, 133, 145 Snell, Bruno, 3334 Society for American Archaeology (SAA), 12122 Sociological Theory (American Sociological Association), 79, 83, 85 Sowell, Thomas, 172 Spivak, Gayatri, 3, 13, 78, 84, 88, 90, 205n1 Steele, D. Gentry, on opposition to repatriation of Native American human remains 119120, 12426, 128, 136, 145 Stephanopoulos, George, 165 Structure, Sign and Play in the Discourse of the Human Sciences (Derrida), 90 subjectivity, decentering of, 61, 67 Swain, Carol, 150 Symbolic Interactionsim, 80, 99 Symposium on the Social History of Objectivity, 204n10 teleology, 4041, 43, 65, 96, 104, meaning of, 41; metaphysics of, 46, 48; poststructuralist attack on, 96; time and, 65 Texas Historical Commission, 207n5 The End(s) of Ethnography (Clough), 106 Theses on Feuerbach (Marx), 201 Thomas, Clarence, and opposition to afrmative action, 157; on diversity, 210n20; on the Constitution, 209n12 Thomas, David H., 12526 Thomas, Paulette, 164 Thomas, Ward, 208n9 Thornton, Russell, 112, 125, 127 Trinh, T. Minh-ha, 2, 13, 9799, 102, 205n1 Turner, Jonathan H., 5054, 59, 101, 144, 15152 Ubelaker, Douglas H., 120, 12526, 131 32 University of California v. Bakke, 157 Van Kley, Dale K., 46 View from Nowhere, The (Nagel), 203n1 Walton, Beth, 11516, 12830, 136 Ward, Seven, 3, 5254, 205n3 Watkins, Joe, 122 Weber, Max, 9, 18081; The Methodology of the Social Sciences, 201; 204n3 (chap. 3), 206n4, 209n17 Wellman, David, 165, 184, 210n21 Wilson, Pete, and opposition to afrmative action: 182, 185. 191, 193 Yinger, John, 169