Causality and Calculative Thinking An Av
Causality and Calculative Thinking An Av
Causality and Calculative Thinking An Av
Selami Varlık*
Abstract : Heidegger contrasts meditative thinking, which allows detachment from beings, with calcu-
lative thinking, which maintains an instrumental and interested relationship with them. In his view,
the principle of reason is the main tool for dominating available things. He also embeds the Medie-
val essence-existence duality within this framework of causality geared towards manipulating beings,
judging that the religious notion of creation failed to distance this duality from Greek essentialism.
Now, by appropriating the Islamic notion of creation ex nihilo, Avicenna places an ontological indi-
gence at the heart of the created world. He believes that a being necessary by something other than
itself remains contingent in itself, even after being caused. Thus, knowledge of the cause doesn’t grant
dominance over the thing but fosters detachment from contingent being, recognizing its dependence
on an upstream otherness. Moreover, Meister Eckhart, who according to Heidegger perfectly illustrates
meditative thought, is indebted precisely to this ontological poverty established by Avicenna. In ad-
dition to describing this possible objection from Avicenna to Heidegger, the more general aim of this
study is to explore the possibility of an ethical and disinterested use of the principle of reason.
Key words: Avicenna, Heidegger, Causality, Calculative Thinking, Creation, Contingency, Meister
Eckhart.
DOI dx.doi.org/10.12658/Nazariyat.10.1.M0232en Atıf© Varlık, Selami. “Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian
https://orcid.org/0000-0002-7160-9281 Response to Heidegger”, Nazariyat 10/1 (April 2024): 1-35.
Received: 23 December 2023 Accepted: 25 March 2024
NAZARİYAT
Introduction
In his book Penser au Moyen Age Alain de Libera asserts that the medieval issue of
the relationship between philosophy and religion found its initial expression in Is-
lamic philosophy. This thought, which should not be excluded from “our heritage,” he
says, had a twofold consequence for the medieval world.1 First, through the harmo-
nization of Greek philosophy and revelation, Muslim philosophers gave impetus to
the idea of intellectual universality, within which the pursuit of truth could be collec-
tive and cumulative. The quest for knowledge responded to an intellectual curiosity
surpassing borders and languages. Secondly, Avicenna in particular enabled medi-
eval thought to develop a “spirituality of intellectual work,” which anticipated the
beatific vision.2 He established a link between strictly intellectual labor and spiritual
contemplation, making the exercise of thought itself an ascetic practice. In this way,
Avicenna “not only introduced the West to reason, to its profane use, in a word to sci-
ence, he also introduced it to religious rationality, to a very strict rationality placed,
for the first time and rigorously, at the service of a monotheistic religion.”3 Islamic
philosophy thus contributed to a certain de-professionalization of contemplation,
a secularization of the philosophical ideal that marked the birth of the figure of the
intellectual. This new conception had repercussions up to Dante and Meister Eck-
hart, who popularized it and encouraged its spread. De Libera explains that not only
does Eckhart’s thought, which is sometimes considered to be exclusively mystical,
in no way represents the “twilight of Medieval rationalism,”4 but that he was also in
line with the philosophical contemplation of the Muslim philosophers.5 It is also in
this sense that his notion of Gelassenheit, or releasement, represented the end of an
instrumental conception of thought.
This defense of meditative thought is also found in Heidegger, who draws upon
Meister Eckhart to illustrate his critique of calculative thinking, aiming to extend the
subject’s domination over available beings. In The Basic Problems of Phenomenology,
written well before his influential text on technique, Heidegger uses the term “Vorhand-
enheit” to designate the product as available, ready to be instrumentalised by the sub-
2
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
ject. The thing is then “apprehended as something that, qua finished, is available at
any time for use.”6 Being is therefore what is available, at hand (vorhandenes Verfüg-
bares). Furthermore, Heidegger extends this critique to the principle of reason, more
generally targeting causality, with an emphasis on the instrumentalization of things,
reduced to an available fund (Bestand). Now, this causality is at the heart of Avicenna’s
metaphysics, which de Libera places at the beginning of the influence that extends to
Heidegger. We can thus see the framework of the problem that will interest us here:
the releasement that Heidegger praises against medieval ontology and its conception
of causality is perfectly embodied by Meister Eckhart who, precisely, is fully dependent
on the Avicennian duality between essence and existence. Indeed, according to Avi-
cenna, a thing that does not fully possess its existence deserves no attachment.
Our study consists of two parts—ontological and epistemological—each ad-
dressing Heidegger’s position in the first subsection and responding to it with Av-
icenna in the second. In the first subsection, I will explore how Heidegger reduces
the medieval duality between essence and existence to the paradigm of available
being characteristic of the Greek essentialist view, arguing that the religious notion
of creation conforms to this model of producing a being readily available for use.
The second subsection will respond to this position by showing how Avicenna places
ontological indigence at the heart of being, considering that a necessary being by
another remains fundamentally contingent in itself. I will thus emphasize the way
in which Avicenna’s appropriation of the Islamic notion of creation ex nihilo enables
him to dissociate himself from the total independence of being. The third subsection
will examine the consequences for Heidegger of this medieval ontology, which, for
him, prefigures the principle of reason through which the subject reduces being to
serve as an instrument for its ends. Heidegger contrasts this calculative thinking with
meditative reasoning, evoking Meister Eckhart’s Gelassenheit. Our fourth subsec-
tion will be dedicated to deconstructing this critique by showing how, in Avicenna’s
framework, certain knowledge of the cause does not allow us to dominate the thing
but to develop a detachment towards contingent being by becoming fully aware of
its ontological poverty. Understanding the cause of something means understanding
how much its existence relies on something else upstream.
6 Martin Heidegger, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, trans. Albert Hofstadter (Bloomington
and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1982), 114. The term Vorhandenheit is thereby distinct
from the use Heidegger makes of it in Being and Time, where it is distinguished from Zuhandenheit.
3
NAZARİYAT
Our study ultimately aims to consider the conditions for a more ethical and dis-
interested use of rationality, challenging the view of reason solely as a tool for domi-
nation. Thus, I argue that Heidegger’s meditative thinking can coexist with the prin-
ciple of reason. It is thus a question of contributing to studies on the subject of the
complex relationships between Heidegger and medieval philosophy, rehabilitating
the latter philosophy from Heidegger’s criticisms.7 But this contribution is intended
to be original on two points. First, unlike the majority of these studies, it does not
seek to rehabilitate Saint Thomas but rather Avicenna, as a figure belonging to this
philosophical tradition without being reduced to it, given his Islamic presupposi-
tions.8 Second, this study is located less on a strictly ontological level to say that Avi-
cenna is not concerned by the Heideggerian critique of metaphysical understanding
of being than on an epistemological level in order to proceed with a rehabilitation of
the principle of reason as a properly metaphysical mode of thought.9 Supporting this
7 Numerous studies have been devoted to a comparison between Heidegger and Saint Thomas,
sometimes defending the latter faced with criticism from the former, notably through the no-
tion of actus essendi preventing any essentialisation of being. See Caitlin Smith Gilson, The Met-
aphysical Presuppositions of Being-in-the-World: A Confrontation Between St. Thomas Aquinas and
Martin Heidegger (New York: Continuum, 2010); Johannes B. Lotz, Martin Heidegger und Thomas
von Aquin (Pfullingen: Neske, 1975); Etienne Gilson, “Appendices : Réponses à quelques ques-
tions,” L’être et l’essence, Paris: Vrin, 1962), 350-378; Jean-François Courtine, “Heidegger et Thomas
d’Aquin,” Quaestio 1, n° 1 (2001): 213-234; John D. Caputo, Heidegger and Aquinas: An Essay On
Overcoming Metaphysics (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982). The latter explains that Avi-
cenna is fully in line with the Heideggerian critique, since he presents existence as an accident of
essence (p. 109).
8 Many studies have responded to Caputo’s accusation by attempting to show the extent to which
Avicenna’s metaphysics escapes the essentialisation of being. In this respect, the works of Nader
el-Bizri is particularly noteworthy: Nader el-Bizri, The Phenomenological Quest: Between Avicenna
and Heidegger (New York: SUNY Press, 2000); Nader El-Bizri, “Avicenna and Essentialism”, The
Review of Metaphysics 54, No. 4 (Jun. 2001): 753-778. More generally, on Heidegger and Islamic
thought, see Alparslan Açikgenç, Being and Existence in Ṣadrā and Heidegger: A Comparative On-
tology (Kuala Lumpur: International Institute of Islamic Thought and Civilization, 1993); Muham-
mad Kamal, From Essence to Being: The Philosophy of Mulla Sadra & Martin Heidegger (London:
ICAS Press, 2010). While these books focus on specific authors and concepts, less numerous works
offer an overview, particularly through the reception of Heidegger’s philosophy. See Mouchir Ba-
sile Aoun, Heidegger et la pensée arabe (Paris: L’Harmattan, 2011); Kata Moser, Urs Gösken and
Josh Hayes (eds.), Heidegger in the Islamicate World (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield International,
2019). Let’s also mention a more general work that explores the intersection between philosoph-
ical hermeneutics and Islamic thought: Sylvain Camilleri, Selami Varlik (eds.), Philosophical Her-
meneutics and Islamic Thought (Cham: Springer, 2022).
9 In a footnote, Peter S. Dillard questions Heidegger’s critique of the principle of reason, in the more
general context of his critique of Thomistic metaphysics: “in merely rejecting Aquinas’s meta-
4
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
physics of causation, Heidegger still has not provided a satisfactory, noncausal account of appro-
priation as the “sending” of being/time.” Peter S. Dillard, Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology:
A Neo-Scholastic Critique (New York: Continuum, 2008), 140. Jean Grondin makes the connection
between hermeneutics as an effort to understand the meaning of things and metaphysics as an
effort to know the reasons for the world (Jean Grondin, “La métaphysique du sens des choses,” Phi-
losophiques 41, n° 2 (fall 2014): 353-357). Metaphysics is thus defined as a “vigilant effort of human
thought to understand something about being as a whole and its reasons.” (Jean Grondin, La beau-
té de la métaphysique: Essai sur ses piliers herméneutiques (Paris: Les Éditions du Cerf, 2019), 180.
10 Jocelyn Benoist, “Dépassements de la métaphysique,” Revue Philosophique de la France et de
l’Etranger, 129, n° 2 (2004), 174.
11 Heidegger, The Basic Problems, 85.
5
NAZARİYAT
tably through the figure of ousia. Essence, das Wesen, thus designates what each being
already was. So, the thing was already what it currently is, though not yet fully existent.
On the other hand, existentia designates the actual existence of the being, what the
Scholastics call actualitas (Wirklichkeit), derived from the Greek concept of energeia.
In a broader sense, existentia means being actualized, and correlatively, ability to act.
Actualitas also refers to the idea of action (Handeln), where the hand (Hand) is already
present. Something truly exists when it is in act, in virtue of an agere, an action. But
then, like essentia, existentia also refers to the idea of permanence of Being-at-hand,
rendering essence fully available through effective existence.12 This concept of availa-
ble presence is captured by the German term Vorhandenheit, which refers to the dual
idea of the full presence of a substance and its availability. The adjective vorhanden
can denote both the present and the available, depending on the context. Moreover,
vor refers to being “before,” and hand to the “hand.” The terms ousia and Vorhanden-
heit are therefore closely related: both refer to permanent presencing (ständige An-
wesenheit). Temporal degradation, which for St. Thomas represents the mark of the
contingency of a thing, is only an accidental change of a substance, which itself does
not change. Just as the transition from essence to existence in no way affects its per-
manence, since it always remains unchanged, so the material becoming of the thing
does not affect this permanence either. In Heidegger’s view, the temporal becoming
of things does not question the reign of presence. The same form remains unchanged
despite the degradation of the matter.
Aristotelian time, crucial to medieval metaphysics, is based on an understand-
ing of being as being-extant. When he wrote The Basic Problems of Phenomenology,
Heidegger was particularly attentive to how Aristotle addresses the question of time,
to which he devotes the end of the work. Time in Aristotle is part of a play of anteri-
ority and posteriority that fundamentally remains dependent on the now, since “ever
different nows are, as different, nevertheless always exactly the same, namely, now.”13
Thus, the essence of time always lies in the now, even though it always tends towards
another moment. The later now is a not-yet-now and the earlier now is a no-longer-
now. Every remembered and anticipated moment can only be understood in terms of
a present, whether past or future. Therefore, the representation of time as a continu-
ous line is deceptive since each now, as a new present, renders the others irrelevant.
6
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
7
NAZARİYAT
creatio ex nihilo. The eidos governing the production of things in Greek philosophy
becomes, for scholastics, the forma through which things are created. Heidegger ex-
amines Aristotle’s four causes, with particular attention to the material cause, which
he perceives as problematic given that, unlike the pre-existing matter of the artisan,
creation ex nihilo is supposed to occur from nothing. However, Heidegger contends
that there is indeed a matter in this production: it is the nihil, conceived as sort of
pre-existing substance, representing the material for this creation. It is in this sense
that creation is made from (ex) nothing (nihilo). The pre-existing thing cannot be
pure nothingness since the very being of this nothingness in Christian theology pos-
es a problem: “if God creates out of nothing precisely He must be able to relate Him
self to the nothing. But if God is God he cannot know the nothing, assuming that the
‘Absolute’ excludes all nothingness.”18 The nihil preceding creation is therefore not
true nothingness.
The effectiveness of the divine act enables the production of an inherently con-
sistent object, something that exists autonomously and is, therefore, available for
use. The thing created then “stands for itself, detached from causation and the caus-
es.”19 This argument of the autonomization of the fully existing thing is central to
the way in which it becomes available. Certainly, Thomas emphasizes the radical
dependence of the being on the divine act. But Heidegger sees no reason to challenge
this overall autonomization, because the actualized being “nevertheless exists abso-
lutely for itself, is something that is for itself.”20 This self-sufficiency of being is analyz-
ed in § 20 of Being and Time which dates from the same period and where Heidegger
explains how, even though fully created, substance gains autonomy in Descartes. The
being of a “substance,” writes Heidegger, is “characterized by not needing anything.”21
Certainly this being is then qualified as ens perfectissimum and corresponds to God,
whose assistance remains necessary for the conservation of the being. However, both
the created and the creator are termed beings. Heidegger observes an inconsistency
within the metaphysics of creation, as it establishes an infinite distance between
creator and creature while simultaneously granting both the status of being. Des-
18 Martin Heidegger, “What is Metaphysics,” Basic writings: from Being and Time (1927) to the Task of
Thinking (1964), ed. David Farrell Krell (New York: Harper & Row, 1977), 107-108.
19 Heidegger, The Basic Problems, 87.
20 Heidegger, The Basic Problems, 103.
21 Heidegger, Being and Time, 125.
8
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
cartes calling the created being substance exemplifies this shift, allowing the created
being some autonomy by not needing another being, despite requiring God for its
preservation.22 The heart of the problem therefore lies in the question of the analogy
of being. While the expressions “God is” and “the world is” don’t have the same mean-
ing, in both cases “being” is still the term used. Heidegger is therefore not convinced
by the medieval analogy which had precisely the function of resolving the problem
since it represents a third way between univocity and homonymic equivocity.
In Heidegger’s view, if the Christian doctrine of creation ex nihilo has failed to
impart genuine vulnerability to the created world by dissociating itself from the
Greek ousia, it is because it was situated within the realm of faith, completely dis-
tancing itself from philosophical discourse. Heidegger dismisses the biblical notion
of creation, deeming it religious rather than philosophical. Thus, this vision could
not ask the question of the meaning of being, since “through the truth of revelation,
promulgated in church doctrine as absolutely binding, the question of what the be-
ing is has become superfluous.”23 The being of beings was reduced to the fact of being
created by God: “Omne ens est ens creatum.” Consequently, we cannot address the
question “Why is there something rather than nothing?” that Heidegger explores in
his Introduction to Metaphysics. It is in the name of a denunciation of philosophy
considered as madness by Saint Paul, that Heidegger justifies this incapacity to an-
swer the question of the origin of being.24 In contemporary philosophy Karl Barth,
who influenced Heidegger on the question, represents one of the main figures of
the reduction of creation to the field of revelation, therefore excluding reason: “Ni-
hil observation de contingenta mundi nisi ex revelatione.” The statement may seem
somewhat problematic since, while Heidegger criticizes Christianity for excluding
any philosophical engagement with the concept of creation, he himself reduces the
biblical notion of creation to the language of Greek essentialism. In truth, his ar-
gument is coherent: because Christianity presented a solely religious conception of
creation, it could not provide a philosophical counterpoint to the Greek model based
on the enduring nature of substance.
22 Clavier considers that Heidegger exaggerates what is merely a “linguistic convention”, a conven-
ience. For fundamentally, in Descartes, substance remains that which only needs the ordinary
assistance of God to subsist. Claver, “L’épuisement,” 738.
23 Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche. Volumes. III and IV, ed. David Farrell Krell (New York: Harper, 1991), 88.
24 Martin Heidegger, Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Gregory Fried and Richard Polt (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 2000), 8.
9
NAZARİYAT
25 Michael Marmura, “The Metaphysics of Efficient Causality in Avicenna (Ibn Sina),” in Islamic
Theology and Philosophy: Studies in Honor of George F. Hourani, ed. Michael Marmura (New York:
SUNY Press, 1984), 181.
26 Parviz Morewedge, The Metaphysics of Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā) (New York: Columbia University Press,
1973), 272.
27 Louis Gardet, M.-M. Anawati, Introduction à la Théologie musulmane. Essai de théologie comparée
(Paris: Vrin, 1948), 320.
28 Ibn Sīnā, al-Mabda’ wa al-ma‘ād, ed. Abdullah Nūrānī (Tehran: Institute of Islamic Studies, 1984), 77.
29 For a response to Beatrice Zedler’s denial of creation in Avicenna, see cf. Olga Lucia Lizzini, “A
Mysterious Order of Possibles: Some remarks on Essentialism and on Beatrice Zedler’s Interpre-
tation of Avicenna and Aquinas on Creation,” American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 88, no 2
(2014): 237-270. Likewise, McGinnis judges that “Avicenna’s notion of atemporal creation is one of
genuine creation ex nihilo, and so is unlike Aristotle’s notion of generation, which required preex-
isting forms and matter.” Jon McGinnis, Avicenna (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 182.
10
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
that which, by essence, does not exist.30 By continuously providing existence, crea-
tion eliminates the continuous non-being. Except for the Necessary Being, which is
necessary in itself, everything else is necessary through another and possible in itself.
Consequently, every created entity is subject to the duality of essence and existence
and the secondarity of the latter.
Avicenna provides a more explicit definition in the Shifā, where ibdā‘ is defined
as “giving of existence to a thing after absolute nonexistence (ba‘d lays mutlaq).”31
Likewise, in the Book of Definitions, ibdā‘ designates first “the founding of something
not from another thing” and second the fact “that absolute existence comes to a thing
from a cause without intermediary,” so that what was preventing the essence from
existing is removed.32 The act of bringing into existence withdraws the thing from
non-existence, given that its essence does not imply its existence. Avicenna leaves
no room for the idea of an eternal uncreated matter, as in Aristotle’s philosophy. Cre-
ation excludes any mediation, be it through matter (mādda), instrument (āla), or
any other thing or intention (ma‘nā). Therefore, creation also excludes time because
any time preceding the creative act would become an intermediary between God
and the world. This is why ibdāʿ occurs without any intermediary such as matter,
nor instrument, nor time. The duality between essence and existence, as well as the
concomitant duality between possible being and necessary being, is the product of
an encounter between the Greek model of emanation and the Qur’anic conception
of creation ex nihilo as appropriated by Avicenna. Avicenna’s religious model, where
the intellectual dimension takes primacy, differs very clearly from the Pauline rejec-
tion of rational thought as madness. Avicenna aligns with the centrality of reasoning
in the Islamic pursuit of one God, who contains no mystery.
Therefore, Heidegger’s critique of essentialism does not really apply to Avicenna
given that the issue is not to assert that essence precedes existence in the sense that
30 Rahim Acar, “Creation: Avicenna’s metaphysical account,” Creation and the God of Abraham, ed.
David Burrell, Carlo Cogliati, Janet M. Soskice, William R. Stoeger (Cambridge & New York: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2010), 78.
31 Avicenna, The Metaphysics of The Healing, trans. Michael E. Marmura (Provo: Brigham Young Uni-
versity Press, 2005), 203. For an analysis of the different terms Avicenna uses to express creation,
cf. Jules Janssens, “Creation and Emanation in Ibn Sînâ,” Documenti e Studi Sulla Tradizione Filo-
sofica Medievale, no 8 (1997), 468 sq.
32 Ibn Sina, “Book of Definition,” in Books of Definition in Islamic Philosophy - The limits of words, Kiki
Kennedy-Day (London: Routledge Curzon, 2003), 114.
11
NAZARİYAT
33 Seyyed Hossein Nasr, Islamic Philosophy from its Origin to the Present: Philosophy in the Land of
Prophecy (Albany: SUNY Press, 2006), 69.
34 Avicenna, The Metaphysics, 276-277.
12
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
through another and false in itself.”35 In the duality between contingency in itself and
necessity through something other than itself, the latter has naturally gained prom-
inence in the reception of Avicenna. To the extent that the state of possibility could
be entirely obscured, as is the case with A. M. Goichon, for whom the thing exists ef-
fectively only as necessary.36 Yet what Avicenna fundamentally preserves by opposing
temporal creation is the permanence of contingency within what now necessarily
exists. Because even as necessary by something other than itself, the thing remains
contingent in itself.37 The state of possible non-being is then located in the present; it
is neither relegated to a bygone past nor projected into an inevitable future. Ontolog-
ical contingency is distinct from any future material perishability, the inadequacy of
which Heidegger had pointed out in his critique of the notion of existentia.
Avicenna defines the possible as that which can exist or not exist, being neither
necessary nor impossible. This dissociation of the modal and the temporal is crucial
because it allows the maintenance of contingency, opposing any constant presence
and availability of things. The temporal conception of creation is opposed to this
concomitance, since we move from absolute non-being to absolute being without
any element of non-being. However, according to Avicenna, the created thing, if not
for the constant support of the Necessary Being itself, would return to non-existence
at every moment and, in this sense, maintain its poverty. Poverty means being de-
pendent on another in order to exist.38 Thus, by rejecting a temporal view of creation,
Avicenna avoids a similar view of destruction. This is how one should understand
the verses “Everything will perish except His face (28:88)” or “Every being on earth is
bound to perish (55:26).”39 Avicenna comments on this verse in the Shifā: considered
independently of the Necessary Being, things only deserve nonexistence.40 A literal
reading suggests everything is not just destined to disappear someday, but rather is
constantly disappearing in the present.
13
NAZARİYAT
Unlike Avicenna, St. Thomas, who is aligned with Aristotle on this point, sees
contingency as an effect of the potentiality of matter, as he explains it in his argu-
ment of the third way to prove the existence of God: “Quod possibile est non esse,
quandoque non est (Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I,2,3c);” that is, for some-
thing that may not be/exist, there is time when it is not/it does not exist. To be con-
tingent is not to be eternal, to be subject to time, to the cycle of birth and death. In
Thomas’s view, contingency is based on the finitude inherent in temporality. The ar-
gument of the third way precisely relies on this indexing of ontological contingency
to temporality: if everything is brought into being and passes away, there must have
been a time when nothing existed. It is not, as in Avicenna, the need for a cause that
determines contingency, i.e. the possibility of not being, but the fact of being com-
posed of matter that is corruptible.
Despite some differences, Avicenna remains quite close to the Aristotelian un-
derstanding of time; but it is rather his way of dissociating contingency from tem-
porality that enables him to distinguish himself from Heidegger’s accusation of ex-
tantness. To better understand the difference with Thomas and Aristotle, we need
to examine this feature more closely. Ontological contingency is distinct from any
temporal perishability, so that it is now that the thing retains its status of contin-
gency, preventing its autonomous existence. Avicenna therefore rejects a complete
identification between, on the one hand, the necessary, the possible, and the impos-
sible, and on the other hand, always, sometimes, and never.41 If everything perishable
is possible, the reverse is not necessarily true. The duality between necessary in itself
and necessary through something other than itself adapts more easily to the caused/
uncaused couple than to the permanent/impermanent couple. According to Wis-
novsky, the reasons for this shift are theological. The existence of caused but eternal
divine attributes requires a distinction between caused eternal things and eternal
things without a cause. In Avicenna, the focus is less on the attributes of God than on
celestial bodies, but the problem is the same.
The possible is not that which will cease to be or was not previously. This dissoci-
ation of the modal and the temporal is essential for our purpose, since it reveals that
contingency does not concern a future non-existence, but the permanent possibility
of not being now. It is precisely because creation did not take place in time, with a
41 Robert Wisnovsky, Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context (New York: Cornell University Press), 248.
See Kaya, Varlık ve İmkân, 208 sq.
14
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
before and an after, that the essential contingency it causes is not located in time,
does not belong to a future where the thing will no longer be. It is here and now that
the thing might not exist, since even when it is caused, it remains a possibility of
nothingness in itself. Therefore, according to the verse cited above, not everything is
destined to disappear one day but is actually disappearing now. Avicenna emphasiz-
es this permanence of indigence after quoting the verse where Abraham–after the
disappearance of various celestial stars–declares that he dislikes what disappears.42
The verb in verse 6:76 (al-āfilīn) is a present participle, which must be understood as
literally meaning what is disappearing here and now.
For Heidegger, the alternative to the common understanding of time must be
sought in early Christian experience. Saint Paul and Augustine proposes a vision in
which the now is constantly projected ecstatically towards a future in the mode of
care.43 For the Day of the Lord will come “like a thief in the night.”44 The original
conception of time is therefore largely inspired by a Christian facticity that experi-
ences eschatological time, because every moment carries the uncertainty of the end
of time. This insecurity is not found in Muslim thought which does not recognize the
notions of Incarnation and original sin. Avicenna does not seem to fit into Heideg-
ger’s duality between chronological time and kairological time because, as we will
see in the final part, the knowledge of the cause precisely aims to allow the soul to be
fully aware of the ontological indicengy of the created world.
It is a similar idea of an ontological contingency which lies at the heart of being
that we find in Meister Eckhart. The confrontation between Heidegger and Avicenna
on their divergence concerning the relationship between creation and essentialism
is all the more instructive because Heidegger relies on an interpretation of Meister
Eckhart that aligns with the ontology of Avicenna. I will return to Heidegger’s re-
course to Meister Eckhart but let me here recall the latter’s proximity to Avicenna on
the duality between essence and existence. Heidegger does not dispute the debt of
his German predecessor to medieval ontology.45 Medieval mystical theology, he says,
42 Shams Inati, Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics: An Analysis and Anno-
tated Translation (New York: Columbia University Press, 2014), 140.
43 See Jonathan O’Rourke, “Reading in Phenomenology: Heidegger’s Approach to Religious Experi-
ence in St. Paul and St. Augustine,” Open Theology 6, no. 1 (2020): 221-233. https://doi.org/10.1515/
opth-2020-0019 (18 feb. 2024)
44 1Th 5, 1-3.
45 Heidegger, The Basic Problems, 83.
15
NAZARİYAT
and especially the philosophy of Meister Eckhart, is not understandable without this
famous distinction.46 The latter in fact allows for an explanation of judgments that
might otherwise seem excessive or paradoxical.47 Eckhart’s statement regarding the
creature being nothing was condemned by the 26th condemnation bull of 1329 be-
cause what God created could not be pure nothingness. However, this proposition
only means that everything created by itself is nothing (creatum omne ex se nihil est)
that is, there is nothing in it that owes its reality to anything other than God. So much
so that “if God withdrew from the creatures for just one moment, they would disap-
pear to nothing.”48 As with Avicenna, the ontological indigence of the thing is based
on its created status. The counterpart of the nothingness of the creature in itself is
the declaration that being is God. If the creature is nothing in itself, it is precisely
because fundamentally its very being, its origin, goes back to God. Thus, these two
propositions rely on the very difference between essence and existence.
The same applies to the assertion that God is entirely outside and entirely inside.
This position of Eckhart is particularly important as it aligns perfectly with his early
appropriation by the young Heidegger. References, explicit or implicit, to Meister
Eckhart are numerous in Heidegger’s works, spanning from his early works in 1915
to writings in the 1950s. This is why his influence cannot be underestimated. He sees
Eckhart as one of the few great thinkers of the premodern West, even referring to
him as a “Master of thinking.”49 Heidegger wrote in 1948, “Since 1910, the master of
letters and life, Eckehardt, has accompanied me.”50 In his dedicated work on the
subject, Ian Alexander Moore specifies that Heidegger cites his predecessor nearly
a hundred times.51 The first explicit mention is in the exergue of the lesson given
in 1915 (“The Concept of Time in Historical Science”). He cites the Sermon Consid-
eravit semitas domus et panem, which states that “an ancient meister” says that the
16
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
soul is placed between “one” and “two”. Now, this ancient meister, of whom Echkart
speaks, is none other than Avicenna. The aim is to underline the difference but also
the proximity between God and the human soul. Another explicit mention is found
in the concluding chapter of the habilitation dissertation, probably written during
the year 1916. Heidegger cites his predecessor in a footnote regarding the correlation
between subject and object, that is, between the soul and God.52 Eckhart has man-
aged to inscribe within existence the principled correlativity between transcendence
and immanence. Thus, “transcendence does not mean a radical, vanishing removal
from the subject: rather, there is a living relation based on correlativity.”53 We find
here, in the young Heidegger inspired by Meister Eckhart, the beginnings of the idea
of a self-transcendence of existence.54 Now what Eckhart says here is that God is
present within the creature without mixing with it, in the very fact that he maintains
it in existence.
Eckhart places the possibility of nothingness at the heart of the existent, but he
does not consider this existent as purely non-existent either. We cannot consider the
created world as totally illusory, as defended by Della Volpe;55 it does exist, but not by
itself. It exists only to the extent that it is continuously supported by the divine being.
How can a thing both exist and retain a form of nothingness within it? The dual Av-
icennian assertion that God is the necessary Being by Himself and that the creature
is a necessary being by something other than itself helps us to better understand this
tension. For the same thing is nothing-in-itself but fully existing through something
other than itself. The reality of the thing is not denied, it is only the claim of total
autonomy of its existence that is called into question.
This proximity is not fortuitous since Avicenna’s metaphysics is one of Eckhart’s
main sources of inspiration, notably through the idea that Esse est Deus, which goes
back to the figure of God as Necessary Being. God has no quiddity other than His
existence. This is precisely how Eckhart reads the Ego sum qui sum. Eckhart explic-
itly refers to Avicenna’s Metaphysics VIII.4 when speaking of God, “whose what-ness
52 Martin Heidegger, Duns Scotus’s Doctrine of Categories and Meaning, trans. Joydeep Bagchee and
Jeffrey D. Gower (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 2022), 158.
53 Martin Heidegger, Duns Scotus’s Doctrine, 163.
54 Emilio Brito comments that “what God is to the soul in Eckhart, Being is to Dasein in Heidegger.”
This does not imply that being is identified with God, but that there is a similarity of relationship.
Cf. Emilio Brito, Heidegger et l’hymne du sacré (Leuven-Louvain: Leuven University Press, 1999), 450.
55 G. Della Volpe, Eckhart o della filosofia mistica (Roma: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, Roma, 1952), 179.
17
NAZARİYAT
(anitas) is his that-ness (quiditas), as Avicenna says.”56 It is primarily with the ex-
pression “in omni creato aliud est esse et ab alio, aliud essentia et non ab alio” that
Eckhart expresses the compound of possible essence and existence in each creature.
Thus, dependence on the necessary being by itself is permanent. The phrase ab alio,
equivalent to Avicenna’s bi-gayrihī, perfectly expresses the relationship of constant
dependence on an otherness. As Palazzo states, “it is highly likely, though not sup-
ported by explicit meister quotations, that Eckhart’s very controversial teaching on
the nothingness of creatures is also dependent on Avicenna’s view that all the enti-
ties brought to existence by the Necessary Being are in themselves false.”57
56 Meister Eckhart, Die Lateinischen Werke, zweiter Band: Expositio libri Exodi 14-15 (Stuttgart: W.
Kohlhammer Verlag, 1992), 20-21.
57 Alessandro Palazzo, “Eckhart’s Islamic and Jewish Sources: Avicenna, Avicebron, and Averroes,” A
Companion to Meister Eckhart, ed. Jeremiah Hackett (Leiden, Boston: Brill, 2012), 267.
58 Heidegger, The Basic Problems, 92.
18
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
thinking, which he also calls “calculative thinking” (das rechnende Denken) in his text
Gelassenheit, the title of which refers to Meister Eckhart. The cause that produces
an effect is, above all, a means toward an end, which moreover appears among Aris-
totle’s four causes: “Where ends are sought and means used, where instrumentality
is sovereign, there dominates causality.” The four causes that in 1927 described the
process of divine creation as the production of a ready-to-hand being for human use
now describe how the causality exercised by humans renders everything, such as a
cup, available. Consequently, God becomes the God of philosophers and is reduced
to obeying this causality and thus loses all sublime and mysterious dimensions.59
This model of availability aligns with the essence paradigm that has been in play
since the beginning of the metaphysical tradition because Socrates and Plato already
think of the essence (Wesen) of something as what is (als das Wesende) in the sense
of what endures. These are the causes which characterize the presence of a present
thing (das Anwesen eines Anwesenden). However, this instrumentality should not be
understood merely in a practical sense. Causality concerns more fundamentally the
very coming of the thing into appearance. The common sense of causing something
is secondary and derivative to the very essence of causation. Heidegger has new re-
course in this text to the notion of production, because it is through it that what is not
yet present arrives in presence. Production through the four causes is therefore essen-
tially what a thing passes from the hidden state to the unhidden state. Now the idea
of the presence of a thing at our disposal is precisely what qualifies today, in the era of
modern technology, the nature of a “standing-reserve (Bestand)”.60 But it is no longer
a question of a simple poiesis, of a production, but of “a challenging (Herausfordern),
which puts to nature the unreasonable demand that it supply energy that can be ex-
tracted and stored as such.”61 The notion of accumulation is central here because it ex-
tends the very idea that what comes into existence through causality becomes an ob-
ject of storage because it exists autonomously. Gestell, translated as Enframing, is the
term Heidegger uses for this provocative call by which nature is revealed as an avail-
able and exploitable stock. From then on, causality goes beyond the stage of instru-
mentality and puts itself at the service of the enframing given that, notably through
modern physics, nature is reduced to a calculable and predictable set of forces.
59 Martin Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology,” in The Question Concerning Technology
and Other Essays, trans. William Lovitt (New York–London: Garland Publishing, 1977), 26.
60 Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology,” 17.
61 Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology,” 14.
19
NAZARİYAT
With causality, the thing fully gains its autonomy and becomes ready to use since
a thing, a simple possible, is posited outside its causes. What is actualised in actu-
alitas then stands “for itself, detached from causation and the causes.”62 Even if, in
the religious conception, it is God who accomplishes the effectuation of being, this
act grants an autonomy to a thing that now exists independently of the causes that
necessarily accompanied its creation. Heidegger is referring here to the medieval for-
mula, rei extra causas et nihilum sistentia, or the idea of the institution of the thing
outside its causes and outside nothingness. This means that not only can creation
ex nihilo not be an obstacle to this autonomization, it is even a condition of it, since
something that was not now fully exists. With existentia an essence, a simple possi-
bility is instituted outside its causes as something emerging from nothingness. It is
the exteriority of the effect to the cause that ensures the independence of the object
produced.
In fact, Heidegger follows Suárez whose approach is “the one most appropriate
for working out the phenomenological exposition of the problem.”63 It is mainly from
the theses and texts of Suárez that Heideger describes the scholastic conception of
being. Existentia is located in nature, whereas essence is found in the understanding.
But how do we get from the understanding that thinks about the essence of a thing to
the nature in which it unfolds? Existence is effective precisely when this thing emerg-
es from its causes into the world. Existence is marked by the complete fulfilment of
the causal process that produced the thing. For Suárez, only exists that which is in
nature and which now stands outside its causes after having passed through them.
The content of the Suárezian model is that the rational distinction between essentia
and existentia takes precedence over the real distinction that Heidegger attributes to
St. Thomas.
In Suárez the multiplicity of the four causes can be fundamentally reduced to
the efficient cause, which alone truly deserves the title of cause, whereas the other
three are only analogical. Only the efficient cause is a true cause, because only it fully
satisfies the privilege that Suárez grants to the extrinsic character of the cause. Thus,
it is because the efficient cause, the only true cause, is fundamentally extrinsic to
the thing that the thing exists “outside its causes (extra causas suas).”64 The material,
20
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
formal and final causes being intrinsic to the being, it is not outside of them that
the thing can exist, since in fact they remain there. On the other hand, the efficient
cause being external to the thing, it produces an object external to itself. This is why,
Heidegger emphasises how the four causes are reduced to the efficient cause because
it is fundamentally the efficient cause that acts instrumentally, with a view to an
extrinsic result.
The text The Principle of Reason approaches the relationship between causality
and calculation in the other direction, moving from the effect to the cause, in line
with the principle of reason that states that nothing happens without reason or more
commonly, “nothing happens without a cause.”65 Nihil fit sine causa recalls that the
being and its knowledge always have a cause. As a principle of reason to be rendered,
the principle of reason primarily concerns scientific demonstration. Since some-
thing exists only to the extent that it obeys the principle of reason, this call to pro-
vide the reason is characteristic of representative modern thought, to which modern
sciences adhere. This injunction that leads to the certain knowledge of the reason
for things allows extending human dominance over them. If the demanded reason
must be sufficient, it must above all suffice to ensure the consistency (Ständigkeit) of
the caused object.66 The knowledge of the cause thus makes things available insofar
as they are assured. This is why knowledge of the cause obeys calculating thought
which can use things as it wishes.
In contrast to the desire for calculation through knowledge of causality, Heideg-
ger writes two texts on the notion of Gelassenheit: a discussion between a research-
er (Forscher), a scholar (Gelehrter), and a Meister (Lehrer) dating from 1944-1945,
and the text of his lecture titled Gelassenheit (1955) and in which he makes the fa-
mous distinction between meditative thinking and calculative thinking. Calculating
thought, which is in truth an escape from thought, proceeds through plans aiming
at a determined end. This thinking resorts to the principle of reason, operating by
calculation even if not dealing with numbers, as it employs instruments for a prede-
termined purpose. The essence of calculative thinking is to act towards a premed-
itated end, resembling the functioning of causality where the cause is a means to
achieve the effect. In contrast, meditative thinking denotes a “releasement toward
65 Martin Heidegger, The Principle of Reason, trans. Reginald Lilly (Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1991), 22.
66 Martin Heidegger, The Principle of Reason, 33.
21
NAZARİYAT
things (die Gelassenheit zu den Dingen),”67 allowing for an equal soul in the presence
of things that opposes any instrumentalization of reality. Gelassenheit, maintaining
a completely disinterested relationship with the world, requires a “letting-be” (sich
lassen), accompanied by a letting-happen. This soul equality does not require a re-
fusal of things or even technical tools but rather necessitates an indifference, making
it possible to use them while maintaining a certain distance. As with Eckhart – and
Avicenna – the thing does indeed exist but it is only important not to get attached
to it. Therefore, Gelassenheit implies simultaneously saying yes and no to technical
objects and to things in general. Meditative thinking, says Heidegger, is the only way
out in an environment where science has become uncontrollable.
From the first period of Eckhart’s reception at the beginning of the century the
notion of detachment (Abgeschiedenheit) plays a central role in this influence, as evi-
denced by a note from Heidegger’s lecture course in the winter semester of 1915-1916.68
Detachment, for Eckhart, does not mean a refusal of using things, which would still
rhyme with a form of attachment to non-possession, but rather an indifference to
the presence or absence of things. Therefore, detachment implies being unshakable
in the face of anything positive or negative that may happen to the person: “true de-
tachment is nothing else than for the spirit to stand as immovable against whatever
may chance to it of joy and sorrow, honor, shame and disgrace, as a mountain of lead
stands before a little breath of wind.”69 In this, the person ends up resembling God
Himself since to be empty of all created things is to be full of God.
Now, in Eckhart detachment towards things fundamentally relies on their status
as created things, which do not exist fully in themselves. They cannot deserve any
desire or attention because they are incapable of existing by themselves, given that
being belongs only to God. For Eckhart, this means that one must fully realize how
things are nothing in themselves. Therefore, detachment from created things is thus
an ethical consequence of an ontological realization.
67 Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, trans. John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund (New York:
Harper and Row Publishers, 1966), 55.
68 Martin Heidegger, Die Grundlinien der antiken und scholastischen Philosophie (Wintersemester,
1915/16, Fribourg).
69 Meister Eckhart, “On Detachment,” in Meister Eckhart, The Essential Sermons, Commentaries, Trea-
tises and Defense, trans. Edmund Colledge and Bernard McGinn (Newyork/Ramsey/Toronto: Pau-
list Press, 1981), 288.
22
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
23
NAZARİYAT
the cause of the physical motion that made the structure possible, while the meta-
physical cause that provides existence and is always present ensures the subsistence
of the structure. Thus, all causes contributing to the construction of the building are
simultaneous with the subsistence of the building.74 Unlike true causes (ḥaqīqī), nat-
ural causes are accidental (bi-l-ʿaraḍ) rather than essential; they are auxiliary causes.
Accidental causes precede the effect in time and constantly replace each other in
continuous movement; they only have a preparatory function for the action of true
causes that give being and coexist with their effects. The preparation of matter to
receive the form depends not only on the father or the builder but on a combination
of causes intersecting at a given moment. It is when the entire causal complex exists
in reality that the effect of this causal complex necessarily occurs.
Similarly, Eckhart emphasizes the difference between water heated by fire,
which remains hot even after the fire is removed, and air illuminated by the sun,
which loses its light as soon as the sun disappears.75 As with the duality between
physical causality and metaphysical causality, he proceeds to a distinction between
two types of causality: on the one hand, univocal causality, where the effect belongs
to the same genus as its cause, and on the other, analogical causality, which implies a
difference in nature between the active and the passive.76 The effects of the univocal
cause continue even without the continued presence of that cause, as in the engen-
dering of the son. For the analogical cause, on the other hand, the gift is provisional
because, as pure grace, it lasts only as long as the action of the cause. Now God is the
analogical creative cause of all things, since creation ex nihilo establishes a relation-
ship of analogy. The analogical cause is in no way affected by the subject on which its
action is exerted, and is therefore never weakened.
We have seen how Heidegger uses the argument of the independence of the ef-
fect from its cause to justify its availability to calculating thought. We certainly find
the same idea in Avicenna, for whom the efficient cause designates “the cause which
bestows an existence that is other than itself.”77 The efficient cause is not only a prin-
24
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
25
NAZARİYAT
Being necessary in itself. And knowledge must be certain because the ontological
contingency of the created thing is itself certain and inevitable. In other words, the
certain knowledge of a necessary thing implies certainty in knowing the otherness
of that necessity, i.e., a need for a cause other than itself. In line with the duality and
complementarity between natural efficient causes and the metaphysical cause as a
vector of creation, the necessity of the cause refers to the necessity of the bestowing
of existence. Knowing that a thing is necessary is being sure that it has been necessi-
tated, meaning it necessarily needs a cause.
Heidegger regrets that medieval ontology was unable, any more than its ancient
model, to pose the question of the mode of signification of being. The meaning of
being seemed self-evident and therefore remained unclarified. Yet the plurivocity of
being that Avicenna unfolds through the duality between possible being and nec-
essary being invites us precisely to ask the question of the meaning of being. But
it is then knowledge of the cause that enables us to understand that what seemed
autonomous and available, that is, what seemed to exist necessarily in itself, is in
truth only necessitated by another than itself, and therefore contingent in itself. It
seems to us entirely possible, indeed necessary, to integrate Avicenna into a reflec-
tion on the meaning of being, given that the very effort to understand the reason
for things is a hermeneutical task that serves the question of the meaning of being
as a created being.
We should then cast a different perspective on the scientific knowledge of the
necessary features of the world, in contrast to the skepticism found in Heidegger. As
seen also in Eckhart, the world is both stable and fragile. On the one hand, Avicen-
na’s world is not a completely evanescent being with no real existence. Under the
rule of causality, it rigorously obeys immutable laws, making scientific knowledge
possible and even necessary. On the other hand, this necessity is precisely not in
itself but through another. Thus, the certainty of necessity also becomes the indubi-
table awareness of a form of contingency. While, if the subject is uncertain about the
contingency of the thing, it leaves room for it to be otherwise, for the created thing
to become necessary in itself. The ontological contingency of the existing thing is
not itself contingent; it is certain and inevitable. The challenge is to make room for
epistemological certainty in the subject concerning the ontological uncertainty of
the object. While for Heidegger knowledge of the cause serves the autonomization
of the thing that becomes available to satisfy the calculative thinking, for Avicenna
it is the same knowledge of the cause which allows us to fully realize the impossible
26
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
27
NAZARİYAT
We saw that Heidegger establishes continuity between divine action and human
action, both following a logic of production incapable of calling into question the
primacy of the available being. Avicenna himself extends this analogy but in a spirit
of renunciation of all calculation. One who knows being acts without calculation or
personal interest, just as God creates without calculation or premeditation. Creation
is not prompted by desire or need; it is a gift, a pure a pure generosity generosity
(al-jūd al-maḥḍ), meaning an act with neither intention (qaṣd) nor end beyond the
act itself. Therefore, creation is not temporal, for it would then confirm, for Avicen-
na, the idea of divine calculation for a purpose. We therefore see to what extent the
necessary conception of creation allows him to dissociate himself from the model
criticized by Heidegger and which fundamentally rests on free will. This generosity,
which means wealth and abundance, is opposed to ontological poverty, which is the
mark of the contingent being. God indeed has an intention, but it is nothing other
than His essence itself since there is no duality in Him.82
Avicenna makes a distinction between two kinds of generous acts. In the first
case, the agent receives compensation, which can be a tangible good but also a sim-
ple thank you, gratitude, or a good reputation. This expectation is a sign of imper-
fection. Expecting such compensation is already not being generous because the
wise one recognizes that any action motivated by desire is ultimately self-serving.
Whereas, in the second case, nothing is expected in response to the generous act. For
“generosity is providing a benefit that must be for no compensation.”83 The divine act
is thus an act of pure generosity because it has no purpose beyond generosity itself.
In the generous act, the agent is in no way affected by what he does or by anything
that follows what he does. If Heidegger explains, with Angelius Silesius, inspired by
Eckhart, that “the rose is without why,”84 against the metaphysics of causality, Meister
Eckhart’s “without why” is very close to Avicenna’s position since God gives not only
entirely but also freely, expecting nothing in return. As Eckhart puts it “God acts
without ‘why’ and has no ‘why.’”85 To the point that Eckhart presents, like Avicenna,
this generous gift as necessary.86
82 For the difference between wealth and poverty in Avicenna, see Alper, Varlık ve İnsan, 53.
83 Inati, Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics, 145.
84 Angelus Silesius, Der cherubinische Wandersmann (Basel, 1955), 35.
85 Meister Eckhart, “Speech 41,” 71.
86 Meister Eckhart, Opus sermonum, VI, n. 56.
28
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
Conclusion
In summary, our first two subsections have shown how Avicenna, through his
non-temporal conception of creation ex nihilo, places an ontological indigence at
the core of beings, considering that a necessary being by something other than it-
self remains fundamentally contingent in itself. This stance distances Avicenna from
Heidegger’s reduction of the medieval duality between essence and existence to the
paradigm of available being inherent in Greek essentialism. The following two sub-
sections have examined the implications of this major difference from the perspec-
tive of causality. For Heidegger, this essence-existence duality foreshadows the prin-
ciple of reason, enabling the subject to reduce being to a mere instrument according
to the logic of calculative reason. Now, for Avicenna, knowledge of the cause does
not entail dominating the thing. Rather, it cultivates detachment towards contingent
being by fully acknowledging its ontological poverty. Understanding that a thing is
caused means being aware that its existence does not belong to it inherently and
remains constantly dependent on an otherness.
In his Very Short Introduction to continental philosophy, Simon Critchley high-
lights the major risk faced by continental philosophy of sliding into an anti-scien-
tific obscurantism on the pretext of avoiding the excesses of scientism, which are
also very real. He argues that the debate between Carnap and Heidegger perfectly
illustrates this issue, impacting in a certain manner the very duality between con-
tinental and analytic approaches. Thus, we need an “existential conception of sci-
ence” that would allow us to maintain a concern for lived wisdom without aban-
doning the rigour of scientific discourse.87 It is precisely on this point that the path
we have explored in Avicenna is fundamental. This rehabilitation of causality, with
the reinstatement of the concept of creation ex nihilo, extends beyond the stud-
ied divergence between the two philosophers involved. It allows us to question the
possibility of escaping from what the Heidegger scholar Jean Greisch refers to as a
“wisdom of uncertainty.”88 For it is necessary to overcome the opposition between,
on the one hand, a calculating causality that reduces being to a simple availability
87 Simon Critchley, Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction (New York: Oxford, 2001), 117.
88 Cf. Jean Greich, L’herméneutique comme sagesse de l’incertitude (Paris: Le Cercle Herméneutique
Éditeur, 2015).
29
NAZARİYAT
and, on the other hand, an ethical and disinterested approach that would exclude
any principle of causality, even though this is the basis of both intellectual reason-
ing and scientific progress.89
In the 1950s, Heidegger, aware of the threat of atomic energy, emphasized the
urgent need to know how to manage the problem of a science that had become
uncontrollable. He regretted that man was not ready enough to face up to this tech-
nicisation of the world. But the meditative thinking he proposes as an alternative
to calculating thinking is not the only way forward, contrary to what he suggests.
The real challenge lies precisely in the possibility of a meditative reason that does
not turn its back on the notions of causes, proofs and arguments. This is why I fully
share Jocelyn Benoist’s scepticism about Heidegger’s phenomenological conviction
that metaphysics can be overcome. Failing to take into account the diversity and
complexity of the latter, this vision extends and radicalises the profound enmity
towards causality that accompanied the beginnings of phenomenology. This is why
he is astonished at the lightness with which people speculate about the death of the
principle of reason, “as if one could even imagine a thought that did not in some
way bring it into play.”90 This does not mean that Heidegger’s warnings are not still
relevant, at least as a reminder of a permanent risk, including for the medieval con-
ception of causality.
This divergence with Heidegger is all the more important given the growing body
of work that attempts to bridge his philosophy with Islamic thought. This connection
is built on shared critiques of the modern subject and the idea of knowledge as a way
of being. What is important is to establish a rational dialogue on his philosophy with
its similarities and differences. It is precisely through this dialogue of reason that I
have proceeded in this study on both a synchronic and a diachronic level: on the one
hand, by engaging in a philosophical confrontation between the two authors using
a common ontological and epistemological terminology to express opposing theses;
89 Another way in which Heidegger might encounter the spiritual significance of the principle of
reason could be through the way in which Leibniz conceives it. For him, reason “is never merely
calculation, but always also a mirroring of the universe”. See Renato Cristin, Heidegger and Leibniz:
Reason and the Path (Dordrecht/Boston/ London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1998), 121. See also
on the same theme: Hans Ruin, “Leibniz and Heidegger on Sufficient Reason,” Studia Leibnitiana,
Bd. 30, H. 1 (1998), 49-67.
90 Jocelyn Benoist, “Dépassements de la métaphysique,” Revue Philosophique de la France et de
l’Etranger, 129, n° 2 (2004): 174.
30
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
on the other hand, by confirming the results thus obtained through recourse to the
historical figure of Meister Eckhart, who stands between the two philosophers. This
is why, moreover, I have not resorted to any comparative or intercultural approach
here, because the same Wirkungsgeschichte links the two philosophers here, even if
we cannot, of course, reduce Avicenna to this historical tradition. Thanks to this con-
tinuity, the encounter between medieval and contemporary philosophers can be the
occasion for mutual decentering, because, as de Libera reminds us, we cannot “work
on the Middle Ages without letting the Middle Ages work in us.”91 This is why it is vital
that the encounter between the contemporary and the medieval should be genuinely
reciprocal, so that the former can also be challenged by the latter.
But behind the philosophical divergences lie also the theological differences be-
tween the conceptions of the relationship between faith and reason in the two re-
ligions concerned. For even if we avoid any reductionist essentialisation that would
deny the plurality and complexity of each tradition, dominant features - the study
of which goes beyond the scope of this work - remain on both sides.92 The respective
dualities between, on the one hand, the notions of mysterium and tawhīd on a theo-
logical level and, on the other hand, original sin and fitra on an anthropological level
should not be overlooked. For if Heidegger reproaches the Christian conception of
creation for not being situated in a philosophical level following Pauline mistrust of
reason, he himself remains dependent on this mistrust in the very way he excludes
the principle of reason from the field of releasement. Moreover, de Libera consid-
ers that Tempier’s Christian condemnation of Islamic philosophy was aimed less at
the theory of the double truth than at this model of philosophical contemplation
and earthly beatitude, accessible through intellectual work, and which represented a
danger for Christian life. If many works trace the religious background of Heidegger’s
thought, it seems essential to us to evaluate his religious sources through a confron-
tation with Islamic theology which joins them on certain points but also differs from
them on others which are fundamental.
Avicenna occupies a unique space. In Western philosophy, he embodies both
familiarity – on the philosophical level – and difference – due to his Islamic back-
ground. It is this hybrid status that can be the vector of rich conflicts on a concep-
31
NAZARİYAT
tual level and numerous cross-fertilisations.93 The same can be said of Fārâbī, Aver-
roes, Ibn Tufayl and many others who, on the one hand, are to some extend part of
the history of European philosophy without being reduced to it, but, on the other
hand, are nourished by an Islamic worldview which, if it sometimes comes close
to it, is also very different from the Christian background of certain contemporary
philosophers.
Bibliography
Acar, Rahim, “Creation: Avicenna’s metaphysical account.” Creation and the God of Abraham. Ed. David
Burrell, Carlo Cogliati, Janet M. Soskice, William R. Stoeger, 77-90. Cambridge & New York: Cam-
bridge University Press, 2010.
Acar, Rahim, Talking About God and Talking About Creation: Avicenna’s and Thomas Aquinas’ Positions.
Leiden, Boston: Brill, 2005.
Alper, Ömer Mahir, Varlık ve İnsan: Kemalpaşazâde Bağlamında Bir Tasavvurun Yeniden İnşası. İstanbul:
Klasik Yayınları, 2010.
Açikgenç, Alparslan. Being and Existence in Ṣadrā and Heidegger: A Comparative Ontology. Kuala Lum-
pur: International Institute of Islamic Thought and Civilization, 1993.
Aoun, Mouchir Basile. Heidegger et la pensée arabe. Paris: L’Harmattan, 2011.
Benoist, Jocelyn. “Dépassements de la métaphysique.” Revue philosophique de la France et de l’étranger
129, no. 2 (2004): 167-180.
Biemel, Walter, and Hans Saner, ed. The Heidegger-Jaspers Correspondence (1920–1963). Translated by
Gary E. Aylesworth. Amherst: Humanity Books, 2003.
Brito, Emilio. Heidegger et l’hymne du sacré. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1999.
Brunner, Fernand. “Mysticisme et rationalité chez maître Eckhart.” Dialectica 45, No. 2-3 (1991): 99-115.
Camilleri, Sylvain and Varlik, Selami (eds.). Philosophical Hermeneutics and Islamic Thought. Cham:
Springer, 2022.
Caputo, John D.. Heidegger and Aquinas: An Essay On Overcoming Metaphysics. New York: Fordham Uni-
versity Press, 1982.
Clavier, Paul. “L’épuisement de la création – le coup de grâce heideggérien.” Revue philosophique de Lou-
vain 112, no. 4 (2014): 727-749.
Courtine, Jean-François. “Heidegger et Thomas d’Aquin.” Quaestio 1, n° 1 (2001): 213–234.
93 For a more extensive study of this sameness-otherness status, see Selami Varlik, “Application of
Tradition in Gadamer and the Sameness-Otherness of Islamic Philosophy,” in Differences in Identi-
ty in Philosophy and Religion: A Cross-Cultural Approach, ed. Lydia Azadpour, Sarah Flavel, Russell
Re Manning (London: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2020), 69-89.
32
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
Cristin, Renato, Heidegger and Leibniz: Reason and the Path. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Aca-
demic Publishers, 1998.
Critchley, Simon. Continental Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction. New York: Oxford, 2001.
de Libera, Alain. Penser au Moyen Âge. Paris: Seuil, 1991.
Dillard, Peter S.. Heidegger and Philosophical Atheology: A Neo-Scholastic Critique. New York: Continu-
um, 2008.
Eckhart, Meister. Deutsche Werke. Edited by Josef Quint and Georg Steer. Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1936–
2007.
Eckhart, Meister. Die lateinischen Werke, zweiter Band: Expositio libri Exodi 14-15. Stuttgart: W. Kohlham-
mer Verlag, 1992.
Eckhart, Meister. “On Detachment.” In Meister Eckhart, The Essential Sermons, Commentaries, Treatises
and Defense, translated by Edmund Colledge and Bernard McGinn. New York, Ramsey, and Toron-
to: Paulist Press, 1981.
el-Bizri, Nader. “Avicenna and Essentialism.” The Review of Metaphysics 54, n° 4 (Jun. 2001): 753–778.
el-Bizri, Nader. The Phenomenological Quest: Between Avicenna and Heidegger. New York: SUNY Press,
2000.
Gardet, Louis, and Georges Anawati. Introduction à la théologie musulmane: essai de théologie comparée.
Paris: Vrin, 1948.
Gilson, Caitlin Smith. The Metaphysical Presuppositions of Being-in-the-World: A Confrontation Between
St. Thomas Aquinas and Martin Heidegger. New York: Continuum, 2010.
Gilson, Etienne. “Appendices: Réponses à quelques questions.” In L’être et l’essence. 350–378. Paris: Vrin,
1962.
Goichon, Amélie-Marie. La distinction de l’essence et de l’existence d’après Ibn Sīnā (Avicenne). Paris: De-
sclée de Brouwer, 1937.
Grondin, Jean. “La métaphysique du sens des choses.” Philosophiques 41, n° 2 (fall 2014): 351–357.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1962.
Heidegger, Martin. Bremen and Freiburg Lectures - Insight Into That Which Is and Basic Principles of
Thinking. Translated by Andrew J. Mitchell. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2012.
Heidegger, Martin. Discourse on Thinking. Translated by John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund. New
York: Harper and Row, 1966.
Heidegger, Martin. Duns Scotus’s Doctrine of Categories and Meaning. Translated by Joydeep Bagchee
and Jeffrey D. Gower. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2022.
Heidegger, Martin. Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt. New Ha-
ven: Yale University Press, 2000.
Heidegger, Martin. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology. Translated by Albert Hofstadter. Blooming-
ton: Indiana University Press, 1982.
33
NAZARİYAT
Heidegger, Martin. The Principle of Reason. Translated by Reginald Lilly. Bloomington: Indiana Univer-
sity Press, 1991.
Heidegger, Martin. “The Question Concerning Technology.” In The Question Concerning Technology and
Other Essays, translated by William Lovitt, 3-35. New York–London: Garland Publishing, 1977.
Heidegger, Martin. “What is Metaphysics.” In Basic Writings: From Being and Time (1927) to the Task of
Thinking (1964), edited by David Farrell Krell, 89-110. New York: Harper and Row, 1977.
Ibn Sīnā. al-Mabda’ wa al-Ma‘ād. Edited by Abdullah Nūrānī. Tehran: McGill University Institute of Is-
lamic Studies Tehran Branch, 1984.
Ibn Sīnā. The Metaphysics of The Healing. Translated by Michael E. Marmura. Provo: Brigham Young
University Press, 2005.
Inati, Shams. Ibn Sīnā and Mysticism. Remarks and Admonitions: Part Four. Translated by Shams Inati.
London and New York: Kegan Paul International, 1996.
Inati, Shams. Ibn Sina’s Remarks and Admonitions: Physics and Metaphysics: An Analysis and Annotated
Translation. New York: Columbia University Press, 2014.
Janssens, Jules. “Creation and Emanation in Ibn Sînâ.” Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medi-
evale, no. 8 (1997): 455-477.
Kahn, Charles. “Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy.” In Philos-
ophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval, edited by Parviz Morewedge, 7-17. New York: Fordham
University Press, 1982.
Kamal, Muhammad. From Essence to Being: The Philosophy of Mulla Sadra & Martin Heidegger. London:
ICAS Press, 2010.
Kaya, Cüneyt, Varlık ve İmkân: Aristoteles’ten İbn Sînâ’ya İmkânın Tarihi. İstanbul: Klasik, 2011.
Kennedy-Day, Kiki. “Book of Definition.” In Books on Definition in Islamic Philosophy: The Limits of
Words, 85-159. London and New York: RoutledgeCurzon, 2003.
Lizzini, Olga Lucia, “A Mysterious Order of Possibles: Some remarks on Essentialism and on Beatrice
Zedler’s Interpretation of Avicenna and Aquinas on Creation.” American Catholic Philosophical
Quarterly 88, no 2 (2014): 237-270.
Lotz, Johannes B.. Martin Heidegger und Thomas von Aquin. Pfullingen: Neske, 1975.
Marmura, Michael. “The Metaphysics of Efficient Causality in Avicenna (Ibn Sina).” In Islamic Theology
and Philosophy: Studies in Honor of George F. Hourani, edited by Michael Marmura, 172-187. New
York: SUNY Press, 1984.
McGinnis, Jon, Avicenna. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010.
Moore, Ian Alexander. Eckhart, Heidegger, and the Imperative of Releasement. Albany: SUNY Press, 2019.
Morewedge, Parviz. The Metaphysics of Avicenna (Ibn Sīnā). New York: Columbia University Press, 1973.
Moser, Kata, Gösken, Urs and Hayes, Josh (eds.). Heidegger in the Islamicate World. Lanham: Rowman &
Littlefield International, 2019.
Nasr, Seyyed Hossein. Islamic Philosophy from its Origin to the Present: Philosophy in the Land of Prophecy.
Albany: SUNY Press, 2006.
34
Selami Varlık, Causality and Calculative Thinking: An Avicennian Response to Heidegger
Palazzo, Alessandro. “Eckhart’s Islamic and Jewish Sources: Avicenna, Avicebron, and Averroes”. In A
Companion to Meister Eckhart, edited by Jeremiah Hackett, 253–298. Leiden, Boston: Brill, 2012.
Türker, Ömer, İbn Sînâ Felsefesinde Metafizik Bilginin İmkâni Sorunu. İstanbul: İsam Yayınları, 2011.
Varlik, Selami, “Application of Tradition in Gadamer and the Sameness-Otherness of Islamic Philoso-
phy.” In Differences in Identity in Philosophy and Religion: A Cross-Cultural Approach, edited by Lyd-
ia Azadpour, Sarah Flavel and Russell Re Manning, 69–89. London: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2020.
Walzer, Richard. “New Studies on Al-Kindī.” Oriens 10, No. 2 (1957): 203-232.
Wisnovsky, Robert, Avicenna’s Metaphysics in Context. New York: Cornell University Press, 2003.
Zum Brunn, Emilie, and Alain de Libera. Maître Eckhart: métaphysique du verbe et théologie négative.
Paris: Beauchesne, 1994.
O’Rourke, Jonathan. “Reading in Phenomenology: Heidegger’s Approach to Religious Experience in St.
Paul and St. Augustine.” Open Theology 6, no. 1 (2020): 221-233. https://doi.org/10.1515/opth-2020-
0019 (18 feb. 2024)
35