El Realismo de Geuss
El Realismo de Geuss
El Realismo de Geuss
The three persons struggling to keep afloat illustrate for Geuss the real world
of politics, a world of ineliminable conflict, value disagreement and imbal-
ances of power. Any political theory that ignores these features is worthless,
a repository of illusions and fairy-dust rather than a genuine contribution to
political understanding. Geuss believes that most contemporary political
theory – modern academic liberal political theory, in particular – suffers
from this failing. Liberal political theorists assume that their core values are
coherent; and that these values can be instantiated in the world that we
inhabit. For Geuss, neither assumption is warranted. The basic elements of
liberalism are themselves hopelessly confused; and any attempt to make the
world conform to these values will founder on the rocks of ineliminable con-
flict. Rather than confront this tension between how the world irremediably
is and how it ought to be, liberal political theorists resort, so Geuss believes,
to fantasy:
One can, of course, say and imagine various things about a ‘common’ or ‘public’ good . . . This is
a bit like saying of the three people clinging to the plank that the public good would require that
they be in a lifeboat or that each of them have a flotation vest; true enough, and if each were a
fish, they could all swim happily away (PG, p. 100).
This is the voice of a realist: someone who understands the centrality of con-
flict, disagreement and power to the real world of politics; someone who has
learned the lessons taught by Hobbes, Marx, Nietzsche, Weber and Foucault.
Yet if the real world of politics is as Geuss describes it, then one might ask
why anyone would even bother with normative political theory. Geuss’s
recent writings suggest three different answers to this query.1 First, norma-
tive political theories play an important role in constituting our world.
Underpinning this view is the assumption – rejected by some realists but not
by Geuss himself – that normative beliefs have an important impact on politi-
cal action (PG, p. 55). To act successfully in the real world, it thus becomes
important that we understand the causal properties of even the false politi-
cal beliefs of others. Secondly, in so far as normative political theories
contain falsehoods and illusions – as is demonstrably the case, so Geuss main-
tains, with liberalism – then these theories act as ideologies that prevent a
clear understanding of the world. The assumption here is that we will act
more successfully in the world only if we can resist embracing normative
political theories that are ideological in nature. Thirdly, a normative politi-
cal theory might identify the conditions for flourishing in a fallen world of
conflict, disagreement, and power. Here the central contribution of any
worthwhile normative political theory is to underscore the importance of
acquiring and maintaining power.
These three different approaches to normative political theory might all
be described as forms of realism: respectively, ideational realism (at least some
normative political theories possess socially significant causal properties);
anti-ideological realism (at least some normative political theories are merely
ideological); and ethical realism (values must be affirmed in the face of
conflict). Where precisely Geuss stands with respect to each of these three
different forms of realism is far from obvious. Nonetheless, these three forms
of realism provide useful perspectives from which to review Geuss’s highly
original and deeply unsettling contributions to our understanding of
politics.
1
In addition to the two books under review, these recent writings include:
Raymond Geuss, ‘Liberalism and Its Discontents’, Political Theory, 30 (2002), pp.
320–38; ‘Neither History nor Praxis’, European Journal, 11 (2003), pp. 281–92; see also
Geuss’s contributions to Quentin Skinner et al., ‘Political Philosophy: The View from
Cambridge’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 10 (2002), pp. 1–19; and his earlier collec-
tion of essays, Morality, Culture, and History, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
1999. Geuss’s writings have attracted far less critical attention than they deserve. The
most useful discussions of his work – from which I have learned a great deal – include
Colin Bird, ‘Book Review: “History and Illusion in Politics” ’, Ethics, 113 (2003),
pp. 879–82; and Leif Wenar, ‘Book Review, “Public Goods and Private Goods” ’, Ethics,
112 (2002), pp. 149–54.
IDEATIONAL REALISM
2
For examples of realist approaches to international relations, see Hans
Morgenthau, Politics among Nations, New York, Knopf, 1948; Kenneth N. Waltz, Theory
of International Politics, New York, Wiley, 1979; and John J. Mearsheimer, The Tragedy
of Great Power Politics, New York, Norton, 2001.
3
Ian Shapiro, Political Criticism, Berkeley and Los Angeles, University of California
Press, 1990, p. 235. Rather than employing the term ‘ideational realism’, Shapiro
prefers ‘critical realism’.
When I use ‘undemocratic’ as a reproach, part of the reason I do so is that I have been subject
to a barrage of speech and writing about ‘democracy’ and its virtues during all my conscious
life. . . . [I]f I had lived two hundred years ago, I would almost certainly have followed the
then virtually universal use of ‘democratic’ as a term of reproach (History and Illusion in Politics –
HIP – p. 2).
Given this account of our ‘practical situation’, the history of political thought
assumes an especially important place. Social actors are thrown into a world
where certain values and institutional forms possess a powerful normative
force. Just how much scope social actors have in resisting this normative
force remains an unanswered (and perhaps unanswerable) question. But it
remains an important intellectual task to inquire into the historical origin
and trajectory of the concepts that social actors can and must employ to
further their social and political projects.
In his efforts to contribute to our understanding of our own ‘historical
existing language’, Geuss makes interesting use of a version of Nietzsche’s
and Foucault’s genealogical approaches. In earlier work, Geuss has written
with great insight about these two theorists.4 For Geuss, a genealogical
approach – best exemplified by Nietzsche’s Genealogy of Morals – involves an
historical account of some commonly held assumption, practice, or institu-
tion that ‘presents itself as unitary and coherent . . . [and] as having a clear
unitary rationale’ (PG, pp. 8–9). The aim of a genealogical approach is to
show, through a tracing of a complex historical process, how this assump-
tion, practice, or institution lacks its claimed coherence or has achieved what
passes for coherence through distortion or violence. Ideally, a genealogical
approach to some of our political concepts and practices might help free us
from certain illusions about the real world. In doing so, this type of histori-
cal approach might help us to act more successfully and even ‘change our
political practice for the better’ (HIP, p. 9).
The best example of Geuss’s use of a genealogical approach is to be found
in his Public Goods, Private Goods, a small gem of a book that can be recom-
mended to both students and seasoned scholars alike. In this brief, readable
and often very funny book, Geuss takes us on a delightful intellectual journey
from the Greek agora – where we encounter Diogenes masturbating in public
– through to the Roman world – where we encounter both Caesar and
Augustine worrying away at the meaning of res publica – and onwards to
modern liberal conceptions of anti-paternalism. The upshot of Geuss’s inquiry
is to lay bare the errors of those who still think in terms of a single, unitary dis-
tinction between the public and the private. As becomes increasingly clear as
one proceeds through Public Goods, Private Goods, Geuss is not interested in
4
See Geuss, Morality, Culture and History, op. cit., esp. ch. 1.
merely contrasting different historical usages of the terms public and private;
he has a particular axe to grind: modern academic liberalism. In Public Goods,
Private Goods, Geuss confines himself to some hard-hitting remarks about what
he believes to be the naive and incoherent nature of modern academic liber-
alism. Yet, in his History and Illusion in Politics this criticism takes the form of an
attack on the contemporary ‘ideal model’ of politics. This ‘ideal model’ con-
tains, so he argues, five different components – democracy, the state, capital-
ism, liberalism and human rights. Advocates of this ‘ideal model’ – including
modern academic liberals – believe that these elements are, whether con-
strued individually or combined together, minimally consistent and practically
coherent. Geuss spends the bulk of History and Illusion in Politics trying to per-
suade us that these elements are neither. Since this ‘ideal model’ serves to
obscure the real nature of politics and society, Geuss’s critique of this model
might be thought of as a form of anti-ideological realism.
ANTI-IDEOLOGICAL REALISM
5
For versions of this so-called interest theory of rights, see Joseph Raz, The Moral-
ity of Freedom, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1986, ch. 6; and Jeremy Waldron, The
Right of Private Property, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1988, ch. 2.
6
See, for a useful compendium, Jeremy Waldron, Nonsense upon Stilts: Bentham,
Burke, Marx on the Rights of Man, London, Methuen, 1988.
‘historically existing language’. Where this language has taken hold, gov-
ernments must go to great lengths to explain and justify any laws or special
measures that violate the rights of the individual. Far better to live in such
a society than one where arbitrary governmental action is the norm, or
where the interests of some corporate entity (‘the nation’, ‘the people’s
republic’ or whatever) routinely trump those of the individual.7 Geuss’s
second argument against rights applies more specifically to human rights.
He is quite correct to complain that some human rights charters are often
ludicrously over-ambitious. But there is no reason to accept his stronger
claim that the most basic interests of all human beings cannot, due to limi-
tations of natural resources, be guaranteed. The language of human rights
serves, in one of its roles, to register a set of urgent global priorities. Ideally,
the list of human rights should cover only a minimal set of basic human
interests. The language of human rights (if defined in this minimal way)
would then serve to remind (and embarrass) affluent Western governments
about their own public commitment – and, in some cases, founding consti-
tutional commitment – to the universal rights of all. In the absence of a
human rights discourse, the prosperous West, both governments and people,
would likely prove even more stony-hearted to the plight of the impover-
ished. The fact that even the most minimal human rights now go unpro-
tected owes less to the constraints of natural resources than to the constraints
of the West’s imagination and sympathy. Geuss’s final argument against
human rights turns on the alleged incoherence of any set of rights that are
not instantiated in a legal system backed up by a sovereign political author-
ity. Geuss seems to think that anyone committed to human rights is ipso facto
committed to a world state. This argument is clearly false. Even if one were
to allow that human rights will remain ineffectual unless embodied in a sov-
ereign legal system, this does not mean that human rights require a world
state. The proponent of human rights need only think that all legal systems
– whether located in a few or many states – must, at a minimum, protect
basic human rights. Nor does this claim entail (as Geuss further suggests)
that proponents of human rights must be in favour of ‘speedy regular armed
intervention’ (HIP, p. 145) in those states that fail to protect human rights.
Any number of non-military options might be taken in support of human
rights.
Pervading Geuss’s critique of human rights – and his critique of modern
academic liberalism in general – is an assumption of ineliminable moral and
7
In a rather alarming comment (HIP, p. 135), Geuss notes that for thousands of
years China has done ‘very nicely’ without the language of subjective rights. This sug-
gests only that Geuss possesses a very eccentric understanding of what it is for a society
to do ‘very nicely’.
ETHICAL REALISM
8
See, for instance, John Gray, Enlightenment’s Wake, London, Routledge, 1998; and
Stuart Hampshire, Justice as Conflict, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 2000.
9
Thus in contrast to Gray and Hampshire, both of whom attempt to resolve con-
flicts on the basis of a minimal Hobbesian peace, Geuss believes that: ‘To arrive at a
realistic assessment of the modern predicament, one must add to Hobbes’s view a
Nietzschean skepticism about “reason” ’ (PG, p. 102).
10
For a similar comment, see Wenar, ‘Book Review’, op. cit., p. 154. Geuss himself
notes that he contributed a new preface to the paperback edition of PG, partly because
some readers expressed ‘a certain puzzlement about . . . the final implications of the
argument’ (PG, p. i).
11
Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, London, Allen and
Unwin, 1943.