Paradigma 5
Paradigma 5
Paradigma 5
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03097-5
Received: 28 July 2020 / Accepted: 20 February 2021 / Published online: 11 March 2021
© The Author(s) 2021
Abstract
An influential view in (philosophy of) cognitive science is that computation in cogni-
tive systems is semantic, conceptually depending on representation: to compute is to
manipulate representations. I argue that accepting the non-semantic teleomechanistic
view of computation lays the ground for a promising alternative strategy, in which
computation helps to explain and naturalise representation, rather than the other way
around. I show that this computation-based approach to representation presents six
decisive advantages over the semantic view. I claim that it can improve the two most
influential current theories of representation, teleosemantics and structural representa-
tion, by providing them with precious tools to tackle some of their main shortcomings.
In addition, the computation-based approach opens up interesting new theoretical paths
for the project of naturalising representation, in which teleology plays a role in indi-
viduating computations, but not representations.
1 Introduction
123
6876 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
1 I will often talk of representation simpliciter in what follows, even though by this I refer only to cognitive
representation.
2 Some are less exercised by this worry, holding that the scientific fruitfulness of representation and com-
putation are sufficient to assure us of their scientific respectability (Burge 2010; Rescorla 2013). Although
these are indeed good evidential grounds for their respectability, the history of science is rich in examples of
similarly explanatorily useful notions that turned out to be misguided. Trying to get additional guarantees
is thus a commendable pursuit.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6877
that alternatives to the semantic view tend to be very liberal in bestowing computational
nature on physical systems—making them of little explanatory use.
I suggest that abandoning the influential semantic view of computation in favour of
a robust teleology-based view is a promising strategy for theories of representation.
The best such theory currently on offer is the teleomechanistic view, which reserves an
important role for teleology in accounting for computation (Piccinini 2015; Milkowski
2013; Coelho Mollo 2018). Appealing to teleology in making sense of computation
within a theory of representation, I argue, has much to recommend it, insofar as it makes
theories of representation more solid, whilst doing justice to the currently widespread
belief that teleology is, in some way or another, important for representation. I sug-
gest that instead of explaining computation by means of representation, as per the
semantic view, we should do exactly the opposite: explaining representation by means
of computation—a theoretical path adumbrated by computational mechanists such as
Piccinini and Milkowski. Instead of Fodor’s, we should endorse Milkowski’s (2013,
p. 166) dictum: ‘there is no representation without computation’.
In this paper, I will lay out in detail some of the crucial advantages that a
computation-based account offers for shedding light on cognitive representation, espe-
cially once we subscribe to the teleomechanistic view of computation. My aim here
is not to offer a full-fledged computation-based theory of representation, but rather to
outline the shape that such accounts may take. Some accounts are best seen as improve-
ments over extant theories of representation, but the computation-based approach also
opens the way to novel strategies for naturalising representation. In this paper, I will
remain neutral on the best way to go between these two options: my aim is to show why
we should go for a computation-based approach to representation in general, upending
the received picture, rather than argue for one specific account of representation.
Here is how I will proceed in what follows. In Sect. 2 I briefly review the motivations
and main shortcomings of the currently most influential approaches to representation:
teleosemantics, and structural representation. In Sect. 3, I propose that theories of
representation should abandon the semantic view of computation and rather endorse a
teleo-based view, such as the teleomechanistic account. In Sect. 4, I argue that placing
a robust, teleo-based theory of computation at the basis of theories of representa-
tion presents six distinctive advantages, yielding accounts of cognitive representation
more capable of confronting some of the weighty hurdles that lie in the path of the
naturalisation project.
123
6878 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6879
4 Famous cases of divergent content ascriptions include (toy versions of) magnetotactic bacteria, so-called
bug-detectors in toads, and imaginary cases such as Pietroski’s (1992) kimus.
5 This is largely a toy example. See Neander (2017) for a more biologically precise one, although analogous
in its consequences.
123
6880 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
only.6 At any rate, challenges in the same spirit, that is, that cast doubt on whether
appeal to selection processes are appropriate to helping account for representation
(and computation) are worth keeping in mind, and keeping at bay (see Sect. 4.4).
Such objections are partly responsible for motivating theorists to try and come up
with theories of representation that do not appeal to teleology. Such theories, with few
exceptions, have lost popularity in the past few decades, which have been marked by
a dominance of teleo-based views—as well as of a less optimistic attitude towards
theories of representation in general (Godfrey-Smith 2006). Important examples
of non-teleological theories include causal-informational semantics (Dretske 1981;
Fodor 1987; Usher 2001), structural representation (Cummins 1989; Ramsey 2007;
Isaac 2012), and content pragmatism (Egan 2014; Coelho Mollo 2020b). Content
pragmatism rejects the naturalisation project, and thus I will not discuss it further.
Causal-informational semantics has been largely abandoned, since it has proved to
have serious problems with indeterminacy of content, falling victim to the disjunction
problem ((Fodor 1984); but see Usher (2001) for an improved version of the view). An
additional ground for its decline is the fact that a teleo-based alternative to it, which
keeps much of its spirit, is far superior, namely producer-based teleosemantics. For
these reasons, I will mostly be concerned with the non-teleological theory of represen-
tation that has enjoyed most attention in the past few years: structural representation.
Structural representation is a sophisticated version of resemblance theories of repre-
sentation. It holds that a large factor in determining representational status and content
is that representations and what they represent share relational structure. For instance,
the spatial relations between points on a map are similar to the spatial relations between
locations in the city mapped. Sharing relational structure, or structural resemblance, is
seen as crucial for something to stand in for something else, that is, to play a represen-
tational role. It is because two structures share all or part of their relational structures
that one can be used in the place of the other in reasoning or cognitive processing—as
I can use a map to plan my future movements when visiting a new city. Content is
partly, if not fully, determined by the relevant structural resemblance relation. Several
proposals exist as to how to understand structural resemblance precisely, typically hav-
ing recourse to different kinds of mapping relation, or morphisms, between structures,
such as isomorphism and homomorphism.
The central difficulty for structural representation theories is their liberality. Struc-
tural resemblance relations are notoriously easy to come by, and difficult to constrain
in principled ways (McLendon 1955; Shea 2013). A problematic consequence of lib-
erality is that representational status is bestowed on an enormous amount of vehicles,
watering down the explanatory purchase of appeal to representation. Furthermore,
resemblance relations are reflexive and symmetrical, while representation relations are
not, suggesting that the former are the wrong tools to understand the latter (Goodman
1976). Finally, liberality also infects content determination: since any representa-
tional vehicle stands in structural resemblance relations to a large amount of things
6 I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me on this point.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6881
in the world, its contents, barring further constraining factors, will be wildly non-
unique.7 Explanation of appropriate behaviour in terms of content, and of inappropriate
behaviour in terms of misrepresentation, thus risks losing much of its distinctive value,
since representations will have disjunctive contents that include both task-appropriate
and task-inappropriate contents. This makes appeal to content largely uninteresting,
and moreover picking and choosing the appropriate contents out of the disjunction
begs the questions that accounts of content are meant to answer.
Some authors add further requirements to constrain the preferred morphism and
avoid liberality, including being generated by a causal process originating from what
is represented (Isaac 2012), and being the one relevant for the use that the represen-
tation is put to by the system (Ramsey 2007; Shea 2014). Many teleo-based theories
also make space for structural representation, adding a teleological constraint to the
content-determining structural resemblance relation (Millikan 2004; Neander 2017;
Shea 2018; Gladziejewski and Milkowski 2017).
It is not my aim to assess whether and to what extent these additions to the basic
idea underlying structural representation are successful. I wish only to bring to the
fore a metatheoretical problem in existing attempts at naturalising representation. For
it seems that we either have to appeal to natural teleology in accounting for represen-
tational status and content, thus having trouble with functional indeterminacy; or, if
we reject appeal to teleology, we end up with overly liberal theories of representation,
making appeal to the notion explanatorily uninteresting. In what follows, I wish to sug-
gest one way of moving forward, building on insights by Milkowski (2013); Piccinini
(2015). Namely, that a promising way to go is to appeal to teleology in individuating
computation, in addition to or in alternative to, appealing to teleology in individuating
representation and content.
3 Teleology in computation
According to the semantic view of computation, which until recently was dominant
especially within philosophy of mind and cognitive science, physical computation
presupposes representation: computation essentially involves the transformation of
states with representational content (Sprevak 2010). Including a semantic constraint
in a theory of computation is widely seen as a necessary move in order to curb pan-
computationalism, that is, the claim that everything computes one or more functions
(limited pancomputationalism), or that everything computes any function (unlimited
pancomputationalism). Pancomputationalism, especially of the unlimited sort, jeop-
ardises the explanatory role of computation in the computer and cognitive sciences,
insofar as it makes the notion apply overly liberally, and in ways that are at odds
with scientific practice (Piccinini 2015, chap. 4). Imposing a semantic constraint on
computation is a promising strategy to avoid pancomputationalism. Since plausibly
relatively few systems are representational, the set of computational systems will at
7 Cummins (1996) is a proponent of structural representation who bites this bullet: he claims that content
is non-unique, but tries to save the explanatory power of representation by appeal to a teleological theory
of representational targets.
123
6882 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
most be identical with, but more likely a subset of, the set of representational systems.
Few physical systems will thereby count as computational under the semantic view.
Appealing to semantics in accounting for computation comes with a price. First,
the success of the account depends on the success of an independent theory of repre-
sentation, and one that cannot rely on computation, on pain of circularity (Piccinini
2015, pp. 33–34). 8 Second, the semantic view only succeeds in avoiding pancompu-
tationalism and doing justice to scientific practice, two of its central aims, if the theory
of representation it relies on is not overly liberal in its turn,9 and if it individuates as
computational (and non-computational) those physical systems that the computer and
cognitive sciences take to be such. The latter is particularly troubling for the semantic
view, since arguably many systems considered to be computational by the computer
sciences do not seem to have a semantics, at least not of the externalist kind most
relevant to cognitive representation. Third, the semantic view precludes what can be
a promising avenue to explore in making sense of cognitive representation, namely
basing it on physical computation.10
Until recently, the main alternatives to the semantic view were non-semantic views
based on mappings between abstract computational states and rules, and causal tran-
sitions between physical states and processes (Chalmers 2011). To compute, on this
view, is to have a causal structure onto which an abstract computational description—in
terms of functions from input types to output types—can be mapped. Causal mapping
views admittedly suffer from problems relating to limited pancomputationalism. Since
nearly every physical system has internal causal structure, it follows that nearly all
physical systems compute at least one function, and typically more than one. Pro-
ponents of the view argue that limited pancomputationalism does not endanger the
explanatory power of the notion of computation. I take this strategy to be misguided.
First, by connecting computation too closely to causal structure, causal mapping views
fail to give the notion of computation a distinctive explanatory role over and above that
already granted to the notion of causal structure (Milkowski 2013). Moreover, limited
pancomputationalism is more pernicious than they take it to be, as it flies in the face of
the explanatory practices of the computational and cognitive sciences, which regard
computational systems as a rather small subset of existing systems. Finally, since
causal structures, as such, do not involve any sort of normativity, causal accounts
cannot make space for an objective notion of miscomputation.
In the past years, a more compelling non-semantic view has been proposed: the
teleomechanistic view (Milkowski 2013; Piccinini 2015; Coelho Mollo 2018). The
theory makes use of the influential neo-mechanistic framework of scientific explana-
tion to try and shed light on the nature of physical computation. Importantly, it reserves
a central role for teleology in the individuation of computational systems. In the rest
of this paper, I will argue that endorsing the teleomechanistic view of computation
leads to many valuable advantages for theories of representation. A brief presentation
of the teleomechanistic view will suffice for my purposes.
8 Perhaps more promising are views that see representation and computation as mutually co-defining, such
as Ramsey (2007).
9 Theories that tend toward panrepresentationalism, such as Cummins’ (1996), are therefore of no help.
10 See Piccinini (2015) for further shortcomings of semantic views, and Shagrir (2018) for a recent partial
defence.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6883
123
6884 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
than the other way around. While the teleomechanistic view of computation can plau-
sibly be seen as having recently overthrown semantic accounts as the current ’received
view’, apart from the few exceptions mentioned (i.e., Milkowski 2013; Piccinini 2015)
this development has not been recognised as potentially producing important down-
stream ripples that may considerably affect accounts of cognitive representation. The
rest of this paper is dedicated to examining some of these ripples.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6885
early in the history of philosophy, starting at least with Plato (e.g. in the Theaete-
tus); while recognition of the importance of computation came much later, Hobbes
being a precursor of the explosion in interest that took place in the second half of
the twentieth century, following advances in the theoretical and practical understand-
ing of computational systems. Second, computation is appealed to in helping explain
how representations are transformed in task-appropriate ways, with representation’s
aboutness taken to play the lion’s share of explaining successful behaviour. Third, as
hinted above, the predominant views of computation until recently were extremely
liberal and of little explanatory use if not properly constrained, and representation,
being already a central part of theories of cognition and intelligence, suggested itself
as the natural choice to curb that pernicious liberality.
The teleomechanistic view of computation allows us to do away with this latter
motivation for the semantic view. The former two, on their hand, do not justify the
semantic view, but merely shed light on the mostly historical grounds for its apparent
intuitiveness. They should therefore be weighed against the considerations I brought
to bear above in favour of starting with computation instead, which I take to shift the
balance toward the computation-based approach. Be as it may, the foregoing line of
reasoning is suggestive, but far from decisive. Stronger reasons, I believe, come from
the considerations that follow.
123
6886 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
occurrent.12 Since the teleomechanistic view builds causally inert factors into its con-
ditions of individuation for computation, one may worry that it cannot provide the
desired bridge between representational and causal explanation. In this central respect,
therefore, the foregoing view may seem to be inferior to its competitors.
Such a worry, I believe, trades on a failure to distinguish individuation from imple-
mentation, a distinction that has played an important role in debates about mental
causation. While individuative properties need not be causally efficacious, implemen-
tational properties do.
Computation, under the teleomechanistic view, is a kind that is partly individuated
by historical properties. This makes it so that two physically identical systems—
with identical causal powers—may differ in computational nature if one has the
teleofunction to compute—a historical property—and the other does not. However,
individuation conditions, if they successfully apply to entities in the world, pick out
physical systems that possess causal powers. Computational individuation picks out
those physical systems that implement computations, insofar as they have the appropri-
ate occurrent and historical properties. The implementing systems have causal powers,
and a subset of these causal powers must be such that they fulfil the appropriate parts
of the individuation conditions of computation, namely the systematic transformation
of inputs into outputs.
Therefore, the teleomechanistic view, as other theories of computation, does not
threaten the role of computation in connecting semantic properties with physical,
causally efficacious ones via computational implementation. For the mechanistic view
appeals to teleology in the individuation of computational systems and computational
functions, and not in order to account for computational implementation, which is
purely mechanistic (Coelho Mollo 2018; Tucker 2018).13
The fact that the causal powers of computational systems hinge on their occurrent,
implementational properties, does not make the appeal to teleology idle. For teleology
helps to individuate those physical systems that are computational to start with, and
thereby that implement physical computations by means of some of their causal prop-
erties. Without such a demanding individuation condition, a theory of computation is
forced to embrace pancomputationalism—given the ubiquity of causal relations—with
all the accompanying problems (see Sect. 4.3 below).14
In some cases, such as in structural representation, the causal powers of repre-
sentational states may be more directly explained in terms of representations being
computational structures that stand in structural mapping relations to representational
contents. Here, computational structure captures a central part of what it is for phys-
ical states and processes to represent, helping explain how they generate appropriate
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6887
4.3 Liberality
123
6888 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
It is possible to do justice to the insight that representation is in some way tied to natural
teleology, as per teleo-based views of representation, whilst avoiding having to view
the connection as directly tied to content determination. Instead, teleological consid-
erations may come into play exclusively in the individuation of physical computation,
generating theories that are teleo-based, insofar as they depend on a teleo-based notion
of computation, but that do not use teleology to determine content. This can be helpful
for preserving a role for teleology in accounting for representation, while avoiding
the main lines of objection against teleo-based views. As I show below, appealing to
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6889
16 This is an ontological, not an epistemological point. It may be challenging to discover which input-output
function a computational mechanism has the teleofunction to perform, given the epistemic opacity of past
selection processes, and the complexity of cognitive systems. However, this does not detract from the claim
that, if the foregoing view is correct, there is a fact of the matter about what teleofunctions a computational
system has. At any rate, recent developments in computational neuroscience provide reasons to be hopeful
(Kriegeskorte and Douglas 2018). I thank Rosa Cao for pressing me on this point.
123
6890 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
for because they contribute, often enough, to behavioural success. It seems extremely
implausible to claim that there can be no biological functions to perform input-output
functions of specific types, since this is arguably what most biological functions,
including non-computational ones, consist in (e.g. taking food as input and generat-
ing energy as output).17 In consequence, worries about a possible mismatch between
computational and behavioural success, in the spirit of Burge’s (2010) objection to
teleosemantics, do not affect teleo-based theories of computation.
17 The medium-independence of computation, however, does pose a challenge. See Coelho Mollo (2019)
for an extended treatment of this problem, and more generally for a defence of the idea that there are
teleofunctions to compute.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6891
123
6892 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
tions that play a distinctive explanatory role: they reveal the typically many-stepped,
richly-branched algorithm that leads from sensory stimulus to motor behaviour.
The difficulties of teleo-based views of representation in doing justice to internal
cognitive complexity are therefore not shared by the teleomechanistic view of compu-
tation. A theory of representation can exploit this feature in order to avoid the problem
of internal complexity, in at least two mutually-exclusive ways.
First, by relying on the teleomechanistic view of computation, a theory of represen-
tation may make use of the non-semantically individuated intermediate computational
states and processes, and the contributions they have the teleofunction to make to over-
all behaviour, to help distribute representational responsibility across the components
of the cognitive system. A theory of representation may be able to pick out a sub-
set of computationally-individuated states and processes that play representational
roles by standing in exploitable (and exploited) relations to salient features of the
environment—such as cognitive maps in entorhinal cortex (Moser et al. 2008).
Alternatively, theories of representation may reject representational ascription
to intermediate states and processes, while keeping allegiance to intermediate
computations and computational teleofunctions. On this view, the units on which rep-
resentations are bestowed are whole organisms, or at least whole brains, as Cao (2012)
suggests, since it is at this level of description that talk of external behaviour is justified,
and thereby appeal to selection processes takes a direct hold. This view is strongly revi-
sionary of mainstream cognitive science, since it rejects subpersonal representational
vehicles, and thereby subpersonal representational explanation. However, by means
of the teleomechanistic view of computation, it is sensitive to subpersonal explana-
tion cashed out in purely computational terms, thus following mainstream cognitive
science at least in its focus on the complex internal goings-on that lead to cognition
and intelligent behaviour.
Since my aim in this paper is to open up paths, rather than to tread them, I remain
neutral on which route is the most promising.
Finally, appealing to natural teleology in accounting for computation allows for a sort
of weak normativity already when it comes to computational workings. This can be
useful for a theory of representation insofar as it makes it possible to distinguish differ-
ent factors that may lead to inappropriate behaviour. In particular, it opens the way for
distinguishing cases in which misrepresentation depends on computational error, from
cases in which misrepresentation takes place despite the fact that the system correctly
follows its computational norms (i.e. fulfils its computational teleofunctions).
Applying this point to teleosemantics does not entail that separate selection
processes need be responsible for the representational and for the computational tele-
ofunctions of the system. It is compatible with the foregoing that the same kinds
of selective pressure led to both the representational and computational organisation
of the system—the former hinging on the latter. However, it does not follow that
there cannot be dissociations, that is, cases in which there is misrepresentation but
no miscomputation, and even, by a fluke, miscomputation without misrepresentation.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6893
For instance, if the environment is not the adequate one for the organism, the rela-
tions between internal states and world that are relevant for representational success
will not obtain, leading to misrepresentation. But this is compatible with the inter-
nal computational processes performing the correct computations, since under the
teleomechanistic view, the latter are non-semantic.
Moreover, attention to the role of (mis)computation in explaining behaviour can
decrease the scope and weight of representational explanation, thereby helping to avoid
overly liberal ascription of representational nature. For explanation of behavioural
inadequacy or error may be cashed out in terms of pure miscomputation in cases
in which the relevant computational states and processes lack representational sta-
tus. This is important to keep in check the temptation to overextend representational
explanation to cases, capacities, or systems for which the notion makes little to no
explanatory contribution—thus risking to make appeal to representation lose its dis-
tinctive explanatory power, and with it, its theoretical justification.19
5 Concluding remarks
In this paper, I have argued that theories of cognitive representation have much to gain
by paying more attention to the roles that computation can play in helping explain
representation. More strongly, I have argued that the influential semantic view of the
conceptual relations between representation and computation should be turned on its
head, in light of recent developments in philosophical accounts of computation in
physical systems: computation helps explain cognitive representation, rather than the
other way around. I have shown that this strategy holds much promise if theories of
representation rely on a robust, non-semantic, teleo-based theory of computation such
as the teleomechanistic account.
I have examined six advantages that theories of representation can reap by adopting
this approach: (a) starting from computation seems more justified, since computation
is arguably simpler or more primitive than representation, and has better naturalisation
prospects; (b) it helps to account for the causal powers of representations; while the
teleomechanistic view more specifically (c) helps to narrow down the states and pro-
cesses that are candidates for representational status, making more tractable problems
with liberality and, to a more limited extent, content indeterminacy; (d) it individuates
non-semantically the complex internal organisation of cognitive systems; and (e) it
makes space for useful distinctions between different sources of (behavioural) error;
all the while (f) avoiding the main lines of objection against appeal to teleology in
theories of representation. While I have not defended here a specific theory of repre-
sentation along these lines, I hope to have shown that it is a promising way to go for
theories of representation in general.
Acknowledgements I am indebted to Rosa Cao, Manolo Martinez, Nicholas Shea, Marc Artiga, Fernando
Martinez Manrique, Margherita Arcangeli, Michael Pauen, two anonymous referees, and audiences at
the EuroCogSci conference, and the workshop ‘Mental Representations in a Mechanical World’, both in
Bochum, Germany, in 2019, for valuable feedback on earlier versions of this material.
19 See Artiga (2016) for a recent defence of radical liberality about representational explanation, and about
representational status more generally.
123
6894 Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895
Funding Open Access funding enabled and organized by Projekt DEAL. This research was funded by
the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research Foundation) under Germany’s Excellence
Strategy—EXC 2002/1 “Science of Intelligence”—Project number 390523135.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which
permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give
appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence,
and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included
in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If
material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted
by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the
copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/.
References
Artiga, M. (2016). Liberal representationalism: A deflationist defense. Dialectica, 70(3), 407–430.
Bielecka, K., & Milkowski, M. (2020). Error detection and representational mechanisms. In J. Smortchkova,
K. Dolega, & T. Schlicht (Eds.), What are mental representations?. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cao, R. (2012). A teleosemantic approach to information in the brain. Biology and Philosophy, 27, 49–71.
Chalmers, D. J. (2011). A computational foundation for the study of cognition. Journal of Cognitive Science,
12(4), 323–357.
Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy,
78, 67–90.
Coelho Mollo, D. (2018). Functional individuation, mechanistic implementation: the proper way of seeing
the mechanistic view of concrete computation. Synthese, 195, 3477–3497.
Coelho Mollo, D. (2019). Are there teleological functions to compute? Philosophy of Science, 86(3), 431–
452.
Coelho Mollo, D. (2020a). Against computational perspectivalism. The British Journal for the Philosophy
of Science. https://doi.org/10.1093/bjps/axz036.
Coelho Mollo, D. (2020b). Content pragmatism defended. Topoi, 39, 103–113.
Coelho Mollo, D. (forthcoming). Deflationary realism: Representation and idealisation in cognitive science.
Mind & Language.
Cummins, R. C. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Cummins, R. C. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dewhurst, J. (2018). Computing mechanisms without proper functions. Minds & Machines, 28(3), 569–588.
Dewhurst, J. (2018). Individuation without representation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,
69(1), 103–116.
Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining Behavior. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Egan, F. (2014). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170, 115–135.
Elber-Dorozko, L., & Shagrir, O. (2019). Integrating computation into the mechanistic hierarchy in the
cognitive and neural sciences. Synthese.
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1984). Semantics, wisconsin style. Synthese, 59(3), 231–250.
Fodor, J. A. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Fresco, N. & Milkowski, M. (forthcoming). Mechanistic computational individuation without biting the
bullet. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
Garson, J. (2019). What biological functions are and why they matter. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gladziejewski, P., & Milkowski, M. (2017). Structural representations: Causally relevant and different from
detectors. Biology and Philosophy, 32(3), 337–355.
Godfrey-Smith, P. (2006). Mental representation, naturalism, and teleosemantics. In D. Papineau & G.
Macdonald (Eds.), Teleosemantics: New philosophical essays. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
123
Synthese (2021) 199:6875–6895 6895
Goodman, N. (1976). Languages of art: An approach to a theory of symbols. Indianapolis: Hackett Pub-
lishing.
Haugeland, J. (1981). Semantic engines: An introduction to mind design, in ‘Mind Design’. Cambridge:
MIT Press.
Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT
Press.
Illari, P. M., & Williamson, J. (2012). What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences.
European Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 2, 119–135.
Isaac, A. M. C. (2012). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,
91(4), 683–704.
Kriegeskorte, N., & Douglas, P. K. (2018). Cognitive computational neuroscience. Nature Neuroscience,
21, 1148–1160.
McLendon, H. J. (1955). Uses of similarity of structure in contemporary philosophy. Mind, 64(253), 79–95.
Milkowski, M. (2013). Explaining the Computational Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (2004). Varieties of meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod lectures. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Millikan, R. G. (2017). Beyond concepts: Unicepts, language, and natural information. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Moser, E. I., Kropff, E., & Moser, M.-B. (2008). Place cells, grid cells, and the brain’s spatial representation
system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 31, 69–89.
Neander, K. (2017). A mark of the mental: In defense of informational semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.
O’Brien, G. (2015). How does mind matter?–Solving the content causation problem. In T. Metzinger & J.
M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND. MIND Group.
Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation: A mechanistic account. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2013). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive
Science, 34, 453–488.
Pietroski, P. M. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73, 267–282.
Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rescorla, M. (2013). Against structuralist theories of computational implementation. British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science, 64, 681–707.
Schweizer, P. (2016). In what sense does the brain compute? In V. C. Müller (Ed.), Computing and philos-
ophy. Synthese library (Vol. 375, pp. 63–79). Berlin: Springer.
Searle, J. R. (1992). The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Shagrir, O. (2001). Content, computation and externalism. Mind, 438, 369–400.
Shagrir, O. (2018). In defence of the semantic view of computation. Synthese, 197(9), 4083–4108. https://
doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-01921-z.
Shea, N. (2013). Millikan’s isomorphism requirement. In J. Kingsbury, D. Ryder, & K. Williford (Eds.),
Millikan and her critics. Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell.
Shea, N. (2014). Exploited isomorphism and structural representation. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian
society CXIV, Part, 2 (pp. 123–144).
Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sprevak, M. (2010). Computation, individuation, and the received view on representation. Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science, 41, 260–270.
Sprevak, M. (2013). Fictionalism about neural representations. The Monist, 96, 539–560.
Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87, 449–508.
Thompson, E. (2007). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard: Harvard
University Press.
Tucker, C. (2018). How to explain miscomputation. Philosophers’ Imprint, 18(24), 1–17.
Usher, M. (2001). A statistical referential theory of content: Using information theory to account for mis-
representations. Mind & Language, 16(3), 311–34.
Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied Mind: Cognitive science and human experience.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.
123