Between The Face and The Voice Bakhtin M
Between The Face and The Voice Bakhtin M
Between The Face and The Voice Bakhtin M
Daphna Erdinast-Vulcan
Abstract. The essay draws on a little-known fragment from M.M. Bakhtin's Draft
Exercise Notebooks of 1943 to highlight both the affinities and the divergences of the
respective philosophical projects of Bakhtin and Emmanuel Levinas. The first part of the
discussion follows their parallel itineraries through several points of convergence, from a
living on borderlines, facing the other, irremediably vulnerable and infinitely responsible.
The second part focuses on the "dialogic impasse" and its attempted resolution through
The third part of the discussion, beginning with Bakhtin's and Levinas's different readings
suggests that Bakhtin's discursive conception of subjectivity may point the direction
I. Convergences
Writing on the ruins of a civilization, they share both the sensibilities of survivors in a
temperamental religiosity which persists in the face of that collapse. Indeed, the affinity
between these two philosophers of alterity--far beyond the mere accident of their
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 2
to readers of either thinker.1 Both Bakhtin and Levinas set out on a quest to recover ethics
in the absence or against the silence of God; both can no longer find consolation in the
metaphysics of presence and totality, or resort to the legacy of the absolute; both have
The first point of convergence in the parallel itineraries of these two philosophers
systematization, as it strives to assimilate the other to the Same. The history of Western
embraces the world, leaves nothing other outside of itself, and thus becomes absolute
thought."2
Bakhtin, too, begins his life-long philosophical project with a diagnosis of the
distress which is evident in these passages is the failure of philosophical ethics. Both
thinkers perceive formal, Kantian ethics as dissociated from the lived, concrete
experience of ethical choice and action, entailing the loss of the individual act,
obliterating its specificity, historicity and uniqueness. The "theoretical world," Bakhtin
1
For the most relevant discussions of this affinity, see Ponzio (1987) and Gardiner
(1996).
2
Ethics and Infinity (1982), p. 75. Hereafter abbreviated in the text as EI.
3
Toward a Philosophy of the Act (1919-1921/ 1986), p. 18. Hereafter abbreviated in
writes "is obtained through an essential and fundamental abstraction from the fact of my
unique being and from the moral sense of that fact –‘as if I did not exist.’ ” (PhA, p. 9).
Against the "nostalgia for totality" (EI , p. 76), as Levinas refers to it, or
"fatal theoreticism," as Bakhtin calls it, both thinkers are trying to articulate an
ethics and subjectivity. Rather than normative formal and abstract systems,
propositions and universal laws, they both aim to address the unique, the private
and the concrete. What they offer is "a phenomenology” of ethical subjectivity
experiencing of the world" (PhA, p. 61), of the attitude and the position of the
knowing subject, a dismantling of his or her claims for autonomy and sovereignty.
There are no moral norms that are determinate and valid in themselves as moral
upon him that we have to rely” (PhA, p. 6). To be truly ethical, the encounter with
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 4
the other must not be an assimilation of the other into the Same; it must leave the
alterity of the other untouched, irreducible; above all, it must grant the other's
It is thus that the distinction between knowledge and eros emerges. "Knowledge,"
write Levinas, "has always been interpreted as assimilation. Even the most surprising
discoveries end by being absorbed, comprehended, with all that there is of ‘prehending’
in ‘comprehending." The most audacious and remote knowledge does not put us in
communion with the truly other; it does not take the place of sociality; it is still and
always a solitude" (EI, p.60). Against knowledge, defined as the "suppression of alterity,"
Levinas offers the conception of eros which, he believes, does not reduce the other to the
same. "Alterity and duality do not disappear in the loving relationship. The idea of a love
that would be a confusion between two beings is a false romantic idea. The pathos of the
erotic relationship is the fact of being two, and that the other is absolutely other." (EI, p.
66). The complexity of Levinas's conception of love is beyond the scope of the present
discussion, but we should note the persistence of his juxtaposition of love against
possession, power, and knowledge. "The relationship with the face," he writes, "is not an
knowledge that is "the possibility of going unto an object," but its ability "to put itself in
"leads to the Other," to the doubt rather than to the certainty of the cogito. (TI, p. 85).
"Nothing is further from Eros than possession." (TI, p. 265). It is a relationship with
irreducible and uncontainable alterity. 5 It is no wonder, then, that in his quest for another
4
Totality and Infinity (1961/1969), p. 75. Hereafter abbreviated in the text as TI.
5
On the conception of love as opposed to knowledge, see also Emmanuel Levinas,
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 5
way of knowing, Levinas reverses the definition of Philosophy as "the love of wisdom"
Notebooks," when he writes of an ‘element of violence” which characterizes both the act
condition of cognition; subduing the world (converting the world into an object of
overtake the object from the side of the future, to show the object in its
exhaustiveness and thereby to deprive it of the open future, to give it in all its
boundaries, both internal and external, without any exit for it out of this
Time and the Other, pp. 76, 88, 90-91. Hereafter abbreviated in the text as TO. Levinas himself
points to a modification in his conception of love between the writing of Time and the Other and
Entre Nous , where he says that "Agape is neither a derivative nor the extinction of love-Eros."
Whereas the latter seems to be linked with enjoyment, or with concupiscence, the former is
conceived as closer to what Levinas earlier defines as "fecundity" or "paternity" (TI, pp. 267-269),
and later describes "in terms of responsibility for the other" (Entre Nous, p. 113).
6
M. M. Bakhtin, “From Draft Exercise Notebooks” (1943-61. p.154). Hereafter
Russkie Slovari, 1966. However, as they have not yet been published in English
translation and are therefore less accessible or familiar to Western readers, I have
quoted them at some length in this essay. I am very grateful to Victoria Clebanov for
to the end, then it is dead and can be devoured, it is removed out of the
independent participant in the life event, … it has already uttered its last word,
there is no internal open nucleus left in it, nor is there an internal infinity.
Freedom is denied it, the act of cognition wants to surround it completely, cut it
off from incompleteness, [and] therefore, from freedom, from the temporal and
semantic future, from its unresolvedness and from its inward truth. (“Draft,"
pp.153-4)
There is much to be said of this passage to which I will come back at a later point.
For the present, however, we should note that the conflation of cognition and the act of
amply evident in “Author and Hero” of the early 1920’s.7 One might speculate that,
following his own farcical trial in 1929 and his subsequent exile, Bakhtin's view of the
authorial other was somewhat less benign in 1943. Against the authorial consummating
and totalizing gaze, against the presumed power of total cognition and aesthetization,
Bakhtin, like Levinas, offers a concept of love which retains the alterity of the beloved,
and does not seek to assimilate it or to contain its openness into the future.
Only love can see and represent the inner freedom of an object . . . The absolute
leaves it whole and situated outside of itself and side by side with itself (or
behind). Love fondles and caresses borders; borders take on a new significance.
7
"Author and Hero in Aesthetic Activity" (1922-4), hereafter abbreviated in the text
as "AH."
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 7
Love does not speak about an object in its absence [zaochno], but speaks about it
The correlate of unassimilated alterity in Levinas's work is the face of the other.
But rather than a visual phenomenon, an object of the gaze which would enframe, contain
and absorb it, Levinas relates to the face in auditory terms, as that which makes the
One can say that the face is not “seen." It is what cannot become a content, which
that the signification of the face makes it escape from being, as a correlate of a
excellence absorbs being. But the relation to the face is straightaway ethical. . . . .
Face and discourse are tied. The face speaks. It speaks, it is in this that it renders
possible and begins all discourse. I have just refused the notion of vision to
describe the relationship with the Other. It is Discourse, and, more exactly,
Why, then, does Levinas insist on a metaphor which, being primarily visual,
requires such a degree of modification and qualification? Why does he choose to signify
discourse through the face rather than through the voice? The answer to that may have to
do with the Hebrew root of the word panim (face) which is the same as the verbal root of
"turning." Noting this relation, Susan Handleman (1993) reads the figure of the face as a
"facing relation," a "turning toward the other," which calls into question the separate,
narcissistic ego. Facing, says Handleman, is therefore "a disruption" of the autonomous,
sovereign self-identical Cartesian subject (pp. 50, 61). As we shall presently see,
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 8
however, the problematic signification through the call of the face is symptomatic of a
"image" and "face." The image, for him, is a product of cognition, of aesthetic
consummation and definition from without. It closes off the subject and denies it the gift
of the future: “The image forces [the subject] to become identical to itself, immerses it in
the hopelessness of the finalized and the ready-made. The image takes advantage of all
the privileges of its outsideness. The back of the head, the ears and the back of the object
are in the foreground of the image. All these are limits (“Draft," pp. 154-5). The face, he
says in what sounds like an echo or a pre-figuration of Levinas, is that which should
speak. Becoming an image, accepting a definition from without, away from the
and Bakhtin move from cognition to love: It is the speaking face of the other rather than
his or her reified image which elicits the ethical response and calls for the ‘answerability’
[otvetstvennost ] of the subject. Only in love can the subject retain the mode of being
which Bakhtin calls ‘I-for-myself,' which allows for one’s “inner infinity” ("Draft," p.
155), for alterity and for change. The little note scribbled in the exercise books-- “search
for a new plane of I and Other encounter” ("Draft," p. 155)---seems to offer a concise
Living on its own borderlines, the subject's mode of being is always diachronic, projected
ahead of itself. Time, says Levinas, is "not a simple experience of duration, but a
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 9
dynamism which leads us elsewhere than toward the things we possess. It is as if in time
there were a movement beyond what is equal to us. Time as a relationship to unattainable
alterity and, thus, an interruption of rhythm and its returns" (EI, p. 61). The absolute
alterity which defines the future is the mode of being which is always yet-to-be, never
identical to itself, and always reaches out beyond its presence to itself. "The other is the
future," says Levinas. It is unknowable and impossible to grasp and possess. Time, or
futurity, is the subject's very relationship with the other and with itself (TO, p. 77 and
passim; EI , p. 57).
As we have already seen, Bakhtin conceives the projection of the self into the
condition of ethical freedom: “I need to be open for myself—at least in all the essential
moments constituting my life; I have to be, for myself, someone who is axiologically yet-
to-be, someone who does not coincide with his already existing makeup” ("AH," p. 13).
The ethical subject is never adequate to itself, it is ‘nonunitary in principle” (“AH," pp.
83, 118); “present to itself as a task," “incapable of being given, of being present-on-
hand, of being contemplated” (“AH," pp. 100, 109). This non-coincidence with oneself,
the self projecting itself ahead of itself in time, is translated in Bakhtin's work into the
concept of the "loophole" which is—precisely as in Levinas-- pitted against the concept
the act of self-consciousness—exceed the bounds of this act’s content. . . . a loophole out
of time, out of everything given, everything finitely present on hand. I do not, evidently,
experience the whole of myself in time” ("AH," p. 109). Most explicitly, the connection
is made in the fragment from the "Draft Exercise Notebooks," where the concept of
freedom is synonymous with the unresolved and incomplete perspective of "the temporal
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 10
and semantic future," and the "internal infinity," which is the "inward truth" of the subject
etymological links seem to testify to the wisdom of language itself. But to become what
uniqueness which puts us into an obligatory relationship with the rest of the world. Here,
too, we find an uncanny similarity of idiom and register between Bakhtin and Levinas.
For Bakhtin,
[it] is not the content of an obligation that obligates me, but my signature below
was not the content of the given performed act or deed. This content could not by
imperative, but "a certain attitude of consciousness" elicited in the "moral subiectum" in a
particular and concrete context, at a specific time and place (PhA, p. 6). The singularity
of the subject, its unique position in time and space at any given moment, is translated
which can be done by me can never be done by anyone else" (PhA, p. 40). The ethical, or
the most concise articulation of this constitutive a-symmetry of the subject and the other
From the ‘objective’ point of view there exist man, personality, etc., but the
difference between I and the other is relative; all and everyone are I, all and
everyone are the other… . and nevertheless I feels itself to be an exception, and
only I in the world (the rest is others) and lives from this juxtaposition. Thereby
the ethical sphere of the absolute inequality of I to all the others, the eternal and
of subjectivity, as if the latter already existed in itself, before the ethical relationship.
Subjectivity is not for itself; it is one again, initially for another. . . .. I say: here I am!’ “
([me voici], (EI, pp. 96-7). It is, of course, significant, that the response to the other
echoes the Biblical form of response to the summons of Divinity (Genesis 22), but rather
than a higher authority of a supreme authorial being, the source of the ethical command
to which the subject is answerable is to be found in the constitution of the subject, in the
same singularity:
matter of saying the very identity of the human I starting from responsibility, that
one can substitute himself for me. Such is my inalienable identity of subject. It is
in this precise sense that Dostoevsky said: “we are all responsible for all men
before all, and I am more than all the others.” (EI , pp. 100-1)
the universal sameness of human beings but on their radical alterity, that ineluctable a-
symmetry which is purely phenomenological, deriving from the fact that we are always
situated, located within a specific and singular context of action, time, and place. When
we recall that the meaning of alibi is "no-elsewhere," Bakhtin's use of this forensic term
becomes much clearer, much closer, in fact, to Levinas's "here I am." The link between
the subject's singularity and his or her ethical responsibility is mediated through the
by inter-subjectivity. For Bakhtin, too, the ethical subject is always already displaced and
place in life” (“Draft," p. 153). This foundational a-topia of subjectivity is the central
paradox of being which hollows out all claims of sovereignty and autonomy. “A person,"
Bakhtin writes, “has no internal territory, he is wholly and always on the boundary"
(1961, pp. 287-8). Being singularly situated, the subject cannot claim an alibi, cannot
evade her involvement or dispose of her own responsibility; living on borderlines, the
and the fundamental "addressivity" of his characters' discourse (PDP, p. 251) are
8
Problems of Dostoevsky's Poetics (1929/1963), p. 49. Hereafter abbreviated in the
text as PDP.
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 13
indeed revolutionary when extrapolated by Bakhtin, who would later come to see the
communication as such:
spoken, the word is at the same time determined by that which has not yet
been said but which is needed and in fact anticipated by the answering word.
lives, as it were, on the boundary between its own context and another, alien, context"
(1961, p. 284)--is most explicit in Bakhtin's later writings10, but its seeds are clearly
Far from a mere rhetorical trope, the concern with borderlines and territorial
enclosures which is much in evidence in the work of both Bakhtin and Levinas is
central to their thinking of ethics. In the epigraph to Otherwise than Being, Levinas
quotes a sentence of Pascal: “This is my place in the sun. That is how the usurpation
9
See also "Discourse in the Novel" (1934-5, pp. 259-422), and "The Problem of
Speech Genres" (1953-4, pp. 60-102), where dialogicity becomes the foundational
10
See "The Problem of Speech Genres" (1952-3, pp. 69, 89, 91, 93); "Notes made in
1970-71" (1970-1, p. 143); and "Toward a Methodology for the Human Sciences,"
of the whole world began." This epigraph, written at the very beginning of God’s
Disappearing Act, remains acutely relevant at turn of the 21st Century: Can one’s
place in the sun be other than a usurpation of another’s? The tentative answer offered
by Bakhtin and Levinas may well be naive, but it is by no means utopian: a move
to the self as a territorial enclosure. Living on borderlines is what we should all do.
response still falls short of an alternative conception of ethics, and the deposition of the
sovereign self-identical Cartesian subject still leaves us with some fundamental questions
unanswered: How does the subject—needy and responsive as it may be—bridge the gap
between the "is" and the "ought"? What is that power which guarantees an ethical
signposts which may point the way towards the good in the absence of Kantian
universals? On what ground--given the subject's response to the call of the other-- can
one make a choice between multiple others? The transition from the dialogic encounter,
the private dyadic and intimate relationship which Levinas and Bakhtin call love, to an
alternative conception of ethics is a difficult one, for it is precisely in the absence of this
relationship, that is, in our dealings with the stranger, unloved but equally deserving of
justice, that the need for signposts will arise most powerfully. It is in the absence of a
personal bond or subjective addressivity that we seem to need is precisely that regulative
The impasse of a purely dyadic conception of subjectivity leads both Levinas and
“third” (tiers), which intrudes into the dyadic intimate relation between the subject and
How is it that there is justice? I answer that it is the fact of the multiplicity of men
and the presence of someone else next to the Other, which condition the laws and
establish justice. If I am alone with the Other, I owe him everything; but there is
someone else….The interpersonal relation I establish with the Other, I must also
establish with other men; there is thus a necessity to moderate this privilege of the
Time and again, Levinas goes back to the concept of the third to account for the
triangulation is as far as he goes. And, as we will soon see, it is not far enough.12
creeps into the later writings. After decades of work on a dialogic conception of the
human subject, a conception which went through several permutations, but has always
11
See also the section on "The Other and the Others" in Totality and Infinity (1961/
1969, pp. 212-14); Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence (1974, pp. 157-162;
158, 160); and Time and the Other ( 1947; 2nd edn.1977/1986, p. 106).
12
For good discussions of the Third and the question of justice in Levinas's thought
"superaddressee" as a third element, which seems to hollow out or at least complicate the
An utterance always has an addressee (of various sorts, with varying degrees of
the author of the speech work seeks and surpasses. This is the second party…. But
in addition to this addressee (the second party), the author of the utterance, with a
and with various understandings of the world, this superaddressee and his ideally
absolute truth, the course of dispassionate human conscience, the people, the court
of history, science, and so forth). . . . Each dialogue takes place as if against the
13
We should note that this new turn comes about at a time of relative relaxation in
state censorship in the Soviet Union, when Bakhtin himself was finally, at the end of
his life, going through a phase of rehabilitation and recognition. It may well be the
case that Bakhtin felt he could now introduce this new factor which would act as a
centripetal ballast and counter the centrifugal, potentially relativistic pull of his earlier
work.
14
"The Problem of the Text" (1959-1961, p.126). Hereafter abbreviated in the text as
"PT."
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 17
immediately adds that the Superaddressee, who is "a constitutive aspect of the whole
understanding of the world, he can be expressed as such)" ("PT," p.126). This disclaimer
notwithstanding, this new participant seems to be positioned above the interlocutors, like
anything but the "supreme-author" or "ultimate Other" who stages his comeback through
the back door, offering the consolation of metaphysical grounding which seems to hollow
out the very concept of the dialogue. Indeed, as many of Bakhtin's readers have felt, there
15
In one of the earliest responses to this issue, Iris M. Zavala argues for a Bakhtinian
subjects, where the listener or the "third" has a regulatory role which affects meaning
Augustine's "third I," who is "the intended moral effect of a closing down of the
enunciatory gap; the complete individual (collective to Bakthin), which will be called
upon to hold in place the circuit of guarantees between subject and knowledge. See
"Bakhtin and the Third: Communication as Response" (1989, pp. 51, 57). Caryl
Emerson and Gary Saul Morson relate to the superaddressee (nadadresat) as "a
principle of hope," which is constitutive in every utterance, a perfect listener who "is
not an ideaological but a metalinguistic fact," and conclude that "God may be dead,
but in some form the Superadddresee is always with us" (1990, pp.135-6); Michael
Holquist writes that "poets who feel misunderstood in their lifetimes, martyrs for lost
political causes, quite ordinary people caught in lives of quiet desperation—all have
been correct to hope that outside the tyranny of the present there is a possible
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 18
Have we come full circle, then? Is this a return of metaphysics through the back
door?16 Not quite. I would suggest that what emerges from the work of both Bakhtin and
Levinas is a shift from a vertical orientation towards the Authorial Other or the proverbial
Auctor Mundi as the source of the ethical command to a lateral relationship wherein
human inter-subjectivity (the opening up to alterity) is extrapolated into the realm of the
divine. Temperamentally religious as both Levinas and Bakhtin are, they can no longer
Post-Stalinist world, where God has finally accomplished his retreat into silence or death,
the source of ethical imperative can no longer be thought to emanate from a divine
Providence or an abstract system, and God can no longer be thematized and postulated as
the supreme Author. What Bakhtin and Levinas offer is a reversal of the onto-theological
paradigm: It is not the human subject who aspires to imitate the infinite goodness of
divinity, as the very concept of divinity (or the infinite, in Levinas's terms) consists in the
with the infinite Other passes through the personal human other: 'l'absolument Autre,
c'est Autrui" (TI , p. 39). The religious dimension of human existence cannot and should
not be eradicated, but it derives from the inter-subjective constitution of the subject and
addressee who will understand them" (1990, p. 38); Craig Brandist links the
perspective into meaningless relativism" (2002, p.169); and Graham Pechey sees the
its relationship with alterity. Ethics precedes metaphysics, but the metaphysical persists
would now turn to the point of their divergence. Both Bakhtin and Levinas enlist
Dostoevsky in their engagement with the relationship of the subject and its other, but
rather than yet another junction of convergence, it is precisely in this invocation that we
can most clearly see the line of their division. Levinas's formulation of "we are all
responsible to all and for all, and I more than all the others," directly and explicitly
borrowed from Dostoevsky, recurs about a dozen times in his work, and becomes the
recurrent motto, indeed the credo of his ethical position.17 What Levinas offers in this
spiritual tradition of the saints' lives, and premised on the subject's "radical humility," its
While this thematic reading is entirely in keeping with Levinas's postulates of the
absolute primacy of the other, the non-reciprocity of the ethical relationship, the
17
Jill Robbins (1999, pp. 147-150). The phrase is first articulated in The Brothers
repeated by Father Zosima in his recounting of his own conversion; and then
Levinas's explicit discursive orientation, his insistence on the primacy of the "saying"
over the "said" and his non-visual conception of the face as that which "speaks."18 As his
self-abdicating saintly subject takes his cue from the explicit imperative of a particular
Dostoevkean character and becomes "more responsible than everyone else," Levinas
subjection to the Other. His perception of the ethical subject remains entirely within the
realm of the "said," a categorical imperative which is absolute, binding, and non-
negotiable. Going back for a moment to the "face" which looms so large in Levinas's
philosophy, we should note here that the Hebrew verbal root of "face" (Panim; Pana)
means not only bodily "turning," as Handleman has pointed out, but also an
"addressing," as in a request or a question. But Levinas does not follow up this rich
allusiveness which seems to have motivated his initial choice of the term. His insistence
on the non-visual, "speaking face" nothwithsanding, it seems that the ocular sense of this
metaphor has taken over, after all, obscuring the discursive, dialogic, and—yes,
reciprocal—nature of the ethical relationship. As Paul Ricoeur (1990) has succinctly put
it: "Levinas's entire philosophy rests on the initiative of the other in the intersubjective
relation. In reality, this initiative establishes no relation at all, to the extent that the other
separation. The other, in this sense, absolves himself of any relation" (pp. 188-9).
The questions proliferate. If the conception of the saintly subject who lays himself
unconditionally (and uncritically) open to the call of the other emerges from a
aren't we all saints? Given the imperative of an a-priori obligation to the other, how can
18
See also Ethics and Infinity (1982, pp. 42, 87-8); and Time and the Other (1947;
nd
2 ed, 1979/1987, p. 103).
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 21
the deposed subject make any truly ethical choices? If the obligation to the other—any
other—is unconditional and infinite, how can one relate to a plurality of conflicting
demands, to the call of the Levinasian "third," and the fourth, and the fifth other? The fact
that the Hebrew word for the single face (panim) has a plural form is, perhaps, more than
little to do with what any of the characters say, their ethical positions, personalities, or
religious convictions. Rather than in any thematic formulation or thesis, the revolutionary
potential of Dostoevsky's work, as Bakthin reads it, lies entirely in the "saying," that is,
the discursive relationship between author and character and among the characters
textual analysis (which Bakhtin does not do) is not as relevant as the fact that the
paradigm shift which Bakhtin ascribes to Dostoevsky is, in fact, a major turnabout in his
own philosophical project. In the earlier essay, "Author and Hero in Aesthetic Activity,"
the author is defined as "a principle of seeing," the sum total of "the transgredient
moments of seeing that are actively referred to the hero and his world" ("AH" pp. 207,
enables him to "enframe" the hero, to "consummate" him, to render him whole, to contain
him within his context, against his background, between the moments of his birth and his
death ("AH," p.148). It is, as we have seen, precisely what Bakhtin will later describe as
the "deadening power of the artistic image," a denial of the internal freedom of the
prerogative: his characters are no longer finalized artistic images, but living voices which
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 22
will not be contained by or subsumed under the authorial word. "Dostoevsky's hero is not
an objectified image but an autonomous discourse, pure voice; we do not see him, we
hear him; everything that we see and know apart from his discourse is nonessential and is
swallowed up by discourse as its raw material" (PDP, p. 53); "The hero [is] not a
It is not about the character" (PDP, p. 63). What we have here is much more than a
literary innovation: it is, in fact, a new cultural paradigm, which ranges far beyond the
realm of aesthetics. The "peculiar 'revolt' of the hero against his literary finalization" is
not only an artistic transition. It entails a deeper ethical meaning, as "a living human
being cannot be turned into the voiceless object of some secondhand, finalizing cognitive
fictional characters: "In Dostoevsky's artistic thinking, the genuine life of the personality
takes place at the point of non-coincidence between a man and himself" (PDP, p. 59).
Dostoevsky's characters, whatever their ideological positions may be, retain the "capacity
to outgrow, as it were, from within and to render untrue any externalizing and finalizing
definition of themselves. As long as a person is alive he lives by the fact that he is not yet
finalized, that he has not yet uttered his ultimate word" (PDP, p.59). The Dostoevskean
revolution is, in fact, a transition from aesthetic containment to the ethical relationship,
from the aesthetic image to the speaking face/voice, which can always say "no" to its
Dostoevsky's novels rather than to any thesis or profession of faith, that the radical move
from the "said" to the "saying" is made, and it is this move which enables a conception of
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 23
the ethical as predicated on the subject's discursive position in relation to the other. While
Levinas might say that "it is only because I acknowledge the other's claim on me that I
subsequently 'speak' to the other" (Crowell, 2003, p. 29), Bakhtin would certainly put
discourse first. This is not a question of rhetoric, but an entirely different conception of
subjection and martyrdom of the self before the demand—any demand-- of the other.19
because the distinction between the "saying" and the "said," or—to use Bakhtin's and
Voloshinov's terms—the "utterance" and the "sentence," remains operative throughout it.
Bakhtin's "superaddressee" and Levinas's "third" are both belated escape clauses from the
potential relativity of dialogics, and in both their projects there is at least a residual appeal
to metaphysics. But whereas Levinas's "third" remains at the level of an other to whom
one owes, as the Levinasian ethical subject remains in a state of ineluctable and a-priori
19
For a different evaluation of this fundamental difference between Levinas's and Bakhtin's
conceptions of the relation between the subject and the other see Michael Eskin (2000), who writes
that "while Levinas reiterates the priority of the other, who interpellates me (in the accusative case),
thus enabling me to become an agent, an 'I' (in the nominative case), Bakhtin takes the 'I' as/ the
most fundamental moment in co-existence for granted . . . . In other words, B does not problematize
the initial emergence of the active 'I' by way of the other . . . . the self is always already an actively
am always already an actively experiencing agent." (p. 78, italics at source); Jeffrey T. Nealon
(1998) is even more critical of the Bakhtinian conception of subjectivity which, he suggests, is
ultimately "approporiative" and "voracious" in that it does not allow the same primacy to the other
addressee. There has, above all, to be some commonality which would enable the address
on the non-coincidence of the subject with itself and its radical openness to the other. But
constitutive role of the other, but at least from 1929 onwards, it remains aware of both the
benign and the malevolent aspects of this role. The Bakhtinian ethical subject—modeled
between vulnerability and resistance, navigating between the appeal of the needy other
and the violence of the oppressive other, as we all do in the real world, it is both all-too-
synthesize it above, is perhaps less radical than Levinas's in that it posits a standard of
arbitration "beyond and above" the participants in the dialogue, but it is also more viable
than Levinas's kenotic conception in that it posits that source of authority as implicit in
the structure of discourse rather than in the Other, and allows for subjective agency and
choice. It is thus in Bakhtin's work that the transition from a vertical to a lateral
dialogic relationship, a position of choice. And making choices is what ethics is all about.
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 26
References
Note: in view of the truncated and complex publication history of Bakhtin's work,
and the intervals between the writing and the publication of his essays, I have provided
the dates of completion and/ or publication of the text in Russian in the initial
parentheses, with the publication dates of the English edition following the details of the
translation.
Press, 1993.
1990, 4-256.
------ . (1929; 2nd edn., 1963). Problems of Dostoevsky's Poetics. Ed. and trans. Caryl
1984.
------ . (1934-5) “Discourse in the Novel." First published in the Soviet Union in 1972.
------ . (1952-3), "The Problem of Speech Genres." In in Speech Genres and Other
Late Essays. Eds. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. Trans. Vern E.
------ . (1959-1961). "The Problem of the Text in Linguistics, Philology, and the
Human Sciences." In Speech Genres and other Late Essays. Eds. Caryl
Dostoevsky's Poetics (2nd edn. 1963). Ed. and trans. Caryl Emerson.
------ . (1970-1971) “From Notes Made in 1970-1971”. In Speech Genres and other Late
------ . (1974) “Toward a Methodology for the Human Sciences”, in Speech Genres and Other
Late Essays. Eds. Caryl Emerson and Michael Holquist. Trans.Vern E. McGee.
Brandist, Craig (2002). The Bakhtin Circle: Philosophy, Culture and Politics.
Critchley, Simon (1992). The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida & Levinas. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Derrida, Jacques (1994). Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of
Mourning, and the New International. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New York:
Routledge.
Bakhtin Meets Levinas 28
Emerson, Caryl and Gary Saul Morson (1990). Mikhail Bakhtin: Creation of a
Eskin, Michael (2000). Ethics and Dialogue in the Works of Levinas, Bakhtin,
Handleman, Susan (1993). "Facing the Other: Levinas, Perelman, and Rosenzweig,"
Holquist, Michael (1990). Dialogism: Bakhtin and His World. London: Routledge.
Levinas, Emmanuel (1947; 2nd edn. 1979/ 1987). Time and the Other. Trans. Richard
------ . (1982). Ethics and Infinity: Conversations with Philippe Nemo. Trans. Richard A.
------ . (1982/ 1998). "Philosophy, Justice and Love." Entre Nous: On Thinking-of-the-Other.
Translated Michael B. Smith and Barbara Harshav. London: The Althone Press.
Sublime." Critical Essays on Mikhail Bakhtin. Ed. Caryl Emerson. New York:
Ricoeur, Paul (1990). Oneself as Another. Trans. Katheleen Blamey. Chicago and
Robbins, Jill (1999). Altered Reading: Levinas and Literature. Chicago and London:
Zavala, Iris (1989). "Bakhtin and the Third: Communication as Response." Critical