Review Essay - Good Faith in Public International Law
Review Essay - Good Faith in Public International Law
Review Essay - Good Faith in Public International Law
Citations:
Please note: citations are provided as a general guideline. Users should consult their preferred
citation format's style manual for proper citation formatting.
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
NOTES AND COMMENTS
precise criteria (like the rules of interpretation in Articles 31-33 of the Vienna
Convention, or the concept of reasonableness) in order to ascertain concretely
what good faith actually prescribes, but it is good faith that determines the
goal to be attained.
Last, good faith protects those who trust, reasonably, the appearances cre-
ated by the behavior of other international legal actors (who have confidence
in the good faith of those actors), or who have truly fallen into error: the
innocent victims, in all good faith, of appearances.
Thus, good faith presents itself as an absolutely necessary ingredient to the
operation of the whole international legal order, namely, to the creation and
performance of law. Moreover, this quality is very well shown in the various
chapters of Zoller's book. She herself describes it evocatively when she says
that good faith is like "oil in the engine." In my view, oil, in this case, would
mean gasoline.
Ultimately, the difference between Zoller's position and the thesis that I
am advocating could be said to belong to the realm of philosophy rather than
to legal science. I could agree, perhaps, if it is understood as legal philosophy,
but I would be happier with legal epistemology, even if this phrase has a
pronounced touch of pedantry. The real question is whether we consider law
in isolation from all the social factors (including ideological and ethical ones)
that have an effect on its functioning (beginning with its making)-Kelsen's
celebrated first precept for a pure science of law-or whether we admit that
these factors have to be taken into consideration in order to discover the
foundations of the rules, usually buried under their overt meaning, but es-
sential to understanding their very bearing in difficult cases.
From the standpoint of Kelsen's criteria, Zoller's conclusions would prob-
ably be right. If, on the contrary, we take the broader view, I think that we
cannot escape recognizing that good faith is really a principle of international
law, and that all the actors in the international legal order are subjected to
it and must endure its consequences, since good faith will serve to determine
both the legal effects of their declarations and behavior and the extent of
their duties. It is not a simple ethical principle, when applied to law, even
though it is also an ethical principle and was borrowed by law from the
ethical realm.
On the other hand, it is true that, in practice, this general principle of law
has only marginal value as an autonomous source of rights and duties. On this
point, Zoller's conclusions cannot be faulted. But does this finding imply that
the role of good faith is a minor one? Is the only conceivable test of the legal
nature of a concept that it be an autonomous source of legal rights and duties?
Is that the most suitable one in this case? The point is debatable. Even apart
from its function in helping measure the extent of the obligation undertaken,
which is far from negligible, good faith plays, mutatis mutandis, a role in in-
ternational law comparable to that of a catalyst in a chemical reaction. Alone,
the catalyst is completely passive. It must be added to other elements for a
reaction to occur; without it, nothing will happen, even if all the necessary
components are present in sufficient quantities. It is a bit the same with good
faith. It is never taken into consideration by law in the abstract, as a purely
psychological disposition. It is always related to specific behavior or declara-
134 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW [Vol. 77
tions and it invests them with legal significance and legal effects. Furthermore,
like many general principles of law, good faith is often hidden by the more
precise rules it has generated (e.g., pacta sunt servanda), so that it becomes no
longer necessary to rely upon it expressly for ordinary practical purposes. But
even in such instances, general principles retain their full value as the ratio
legis to which one may profitably turn in difficult cases. Nobody can ignore
them without running the risk of not understanding the real meaning of the
rules. Nobody can ignore that good faith forms part of the foundation of the
whole international legal structure without running the risk of reducing in-
ternational law to a set of hollow legal formulas.
MICHEL VIRALLY*
CORRESPONDENCE
To THE EDITORS-IN-CHIEF:
September 21, 1982
The case note on United States v. Whiting, which appears in the Judicial
Decisions section of your July 1982 issue, reflects a serious misunderstanding
of the law of search and seizure in the armed forces. At the bottom of page
625, the note states that in Whiting the U.S. Court of Military Appeals "did
not consider Whiting's constitutional rights, the application of which might
have led to a contrary result." It then goes on to argue that ithe Fourth
Amendment should apply to searches conducted by military officials abroad.
Your readers should be made aware that searches by military officials have,
in fact, been subject to the Fourth Amendment, including the requirement
for "probable cause," since at least 1959 when United States v. Browrn (10 CMA
482, 28 CMR 48) was decided. The Fourth Amendment requirements have
recently been codified in the Military Rules of Evidence, Executive Order
12198, March 12, 1980, which closely follow the Federal Rules of Evidence
in form and substance.
The search in Whiting was conducted only after the appropriate commander
had determined that probable cause existed; this determination was subject
to judicial review at Sergeant Whiting's trial and on appeal. The only issue
before the Court of Military Appeals was whether the NATO Status of Forces
Agreement granted Whiting any rights in relation to search and seizure beyond
those given him by the Fourth Amendment. This question the court an-
swered, correctly, in the negative.
Judge Fletcher's dissent was not over whether the Fourth Amendment
should apply to overseas searches. Rather, he argued that a search conducted
in violation of the Status of Forces Agreement was, by that fact alone, "un-
reasonable" under the Fourth Amendment. This novel approach goes far
beyond existing Fourth Amendment jurisprudence, and would allow individ-
uals indirectly to gain rights under an international agreement, even if the
contracting parties did not intend to create any individual rights. The majority
rejected Judge Fletcher's approach, again correctly.
BURRUS M. CARNAHAN, Lt. Col., USAF
StaffJudge Advocate
* Professor, University of Law, Economics and Social Sciences, Paris, and Graduate Institute
of International Studies, Geneva.