Constituionalism of Global South
Constituionalism of Global South
Constituionalism of Global South
CN Introduction
The grammar of modern constitutionalism determines the structure and limits of key
an important part of our legal and political imagination. It determines what questions
we ask about our polities, as well as the range of possible answers to these questions.
This grammar consists of a series of rules and principles about the appropriate use of
concepts like people, self-government, citizen, rights, equality, autonomy, nation, and
popular sovereignty.1 Queries about the normative relationship among state, nation,
and cultural diversity; the criteria that should be used to determine the legitimacy of
the state; the individuals who can be considered members of the polity; the
distinctions and limits between the private and public spheres; and the differences
because they emerge from the rules and principles of modern constitutionalism.
nationalism, among others – compete to control the way these concepts are
understood and put into practice.2 Yet these questions and answers cannot violate the
difficult to accept the relevancy of a question about the relationship between the
2 2
legitimacy of the state and the divine character of the king. It would also be very
difficult to consider valuable the idea that the fundamental rights of citizens should
as well as its egalitarian impulse – would sweep these issues to the margins of the
relatively small group of philosophers.3 Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean Jacques
Rousseau, Charles Montesquieu, Immanuel Kant, and John Stuart Mill, among
others, have contributed to the creation of the basic rules and principles that govern
central political and legal issues of the modern and contemporary polities. Issues like
the relationship between consent and legitimacy, law and politics, will and reason,
the individual and the state, and freedom and diversity cannot be understood without
by these authors are (and have been) continuously interpreted and reinterpreted. For
these norms to provide specific conceptual tools for understanding, evaluating, and
solving contemporary states’ basic challenges, they have to be given more specific
small. Only a few institutions – such as the Supreme Court of the United States, the
European Court of Human Rights, and the German Constitutional Court – are
rules and principles.4 These legal institutions are the ones that determine the
paradigmatic use of modern constitutionalism’s basic norms.5 They are the ones
responsible for defining and solving key contemporary political and legal problems
answers that these institutions give to questions like “What are the limits of judicial
social and economic rights mere political aspirations?,” “How should cultural
rights?,” and “What are the rights of immigrants?” are considered by most legal
become inevitable references for other legal and political institutions around the
world. The jurisprudence of these institutions is widely read and quoted by scholars
Rawls, Robert Nozick, and Charles Taylor, to name only a few, is also considered
modern constitutionalism. Their work brings up to date and sometimes transforms the
ignorance,” for example, have been fundamental to discussions about the foundations
of a modern liberal polity.6 His “overlapping consensus” has been key for thinking
about how to accommodate diversity and make decisions about the norms that should
protecting autonomy has been crucial for imagining the structure that a state should
The history of the modern self offered by Taylor has notoriously contributed to the
understanding of the ways in which we think about the subject in general, and the
legal subject in particular.9 Of course, beneath this first level of authoritative and
publications on political theory and constitutional law is enormous all over the world;
constitutionalism to understand and address key political issues in their polities. Yet
most of them occupy a lower tier position in the dialogue that aims to give content to
and use modern constitutionalism. The politics of constitutional legal and political
In this hierarchy, the scholarship and legal products created by the Global
scholar or a legal institution from the Global South in this dialogue. The
or Western European university that includes a section about the constitutional law of
There are many reasons for this lack. First, the law of the countries of the
Global South, historically, has been considered a secondary component of one of the
major legal traditions of the world.11 The majority of the legal systems of the Global
South, the argument goes, reproduce or derive from continental European or Anglo-
American law.12 Latin America is a weak member of the civil tradition (French,
German, Spanish, and Italian law, in particular);13 Africa is a young and naïve
reproduction of the law of the colonial powers that dominated the region politically.16
Certainly, this official law coexists in many cases with one or more “native” legal
systems. Nevertheless, native law is subordinated to the official law of foreign origin
or else it is of inferior quality. At the same time, the dominant dialogue is colored by
an assumption that the level of effectiveness of the law in the Global South is
generally very low. The law is not a central instrument for social control in this
region of the world, the thinking goes. Other kinds of norms – moral and political, for
example – maintain order and social cohesion. From this perspective, the social,
6 6
It does not seem very useful, therefore, to study this weak academic
production, which reflects on a set of norms that are merely rules on paper and
subproducts of other legal traditions. At most, the law of the Global South – or rather
anthropologists, and law professors interested in issues of social justice and the
reforms needed to achieve it.17 These social scientists, legal academics, and activists
may find an interesting object of study in the social norms that effectively regulate
the lives of those living in the region. Similarly, trying to explain and evaluate the
weakness of the law in the countries of the Global South, as well as proposing and
implementing reforms to solve the problems facing them, can be a fertile field of
research and action for the academia of the Global North. For legal academia in the
North, the attractive object of study in the Global South is not the law itself, or even
the local academic production examining it, but rather the failure of law in the
region.18
Second, the view that Global South countries’ law is merely an iteration of
other legal communities’ legal production has been consolidated by the influence that
U.S. law and the U.S. legal academy have had in the region in recent decades.19 The
impact of U.S. legal rules and scholarship during the past decades has been notable.
Several countries in the region, for example, have imported the U.S. accusatory
criminal system,20 and several others have imported U.S.-inspired neoclassical liberal
7 7
labor laws aimed to increase the flexibility of labor markets.21 Additionally, the U.S.
legal education model has been extremely influential in many Asian, Latin American,
Eastern European, and African countries.22 The work of legal scholars such as Ronald
Dworkin, Lawrence Tribe, and Carl Susstein has become familiar to an important
number of Global South law students and professors.23 The influence of U.S. schools
of thought like law and economics, and law and development is strong in many law
schools in the Global South. As a result, the Global North academy tends to assume
there is little of value in the law of the Global South. To understand and evaluate the
accusatory criminal system or liberal political and legal theory, the thinking goes, it is
not necessary to look to the South. To formulate the normative criteria that should
guide the transformation of law schools, it is not useful to explore the experiences of
law schools in the South. To attain these aims, it is thought necessary only to focus
on the academic production and legal practice of the United States – it is, after all, the
original font of the doctrine and theory that has nourished the changes in the law of
Third, the indifference of the Global North academy toward the law of the
Global South is related to the formalism of the Global South.24 The idea that law is a
closed, complete, coherent, and univocal system has controlled the way in which an
important part of the law in the Global South is thought about and practiced.25 A
significant part of Latin American,26 African,27 Asian,28 and Eastern Europe29 legal
concept of law is certainly not very illuminating or useful. Many academics from the
8 8
Global South have argued so.30 Its descriptive and normative weaknesses are well
known: The mechanical theory of adjudication that it promotes does not describe the
way in which judges really decide cases. In practice, syllogism is only one of the
many tools that judges use to adjudicate. The distance between concepts, norms, and
facts has to be bridged by judges’ wills. There is no natural connection between law’s
concepts and mandates, and social reality. The supposed univocity of most legal
norms defended by legal formalism contrasts with the ambiguity and vagueness that
characterize many of these norms. The supposed coherence of the legal system is in
predominated during the second half of the nineteenth century and first decades of
the twentieth in the United States.31 This is a theoretical view that was radically
debilitated by the attack mounted against it by legal realism.32 For a significant part
of the U.S. legal academy, therefore, the legal systems of the Global South are only
useful to study or illustrate the failure of law.33 The law of the Global South
countries, it is thought, is not a useful object of study if the aim is to understand the
Fourth, the academic communities in the North are more robust than the
academic communities in the South. The quantity and quality of academic products34
are much higher in law schools in the North than in the South. Similarly, the levels of
academic rigor and criticism are much higher in the former than in the latter region of
the world. The number of books and specialized journals produced in the legal
9 9
academia of the North, as well as their richness and complexity, is much greater than
the number produced in the South, for example. Similarly, although the dynamics and
rhythms of production and publication have been established and standardized in the
North, they are just beginning to be structured and disseminated in the South. The
number and type of products generated each academic year, the stability of
specialized journals, and the institutional quality control recognized by the academic
community, among others, are issues that are just beginning to be discussed or
Fifth, the closed and parochial character of the U.S. legal academy, along with
the selective openness of most of Western Europe’s legal academy, discourages any
dialogue with the legal institutions of the Global South.35 Despite the evident
strengths of U.S. law schools, for example, in matters like the quality and number of
that emphasize educating students for the practice of law do not find much value in
comparative law. Young professionals do not need to know foreign legal norms,
doctrine, or theory to practice competently. The more “academic” law schools seem
to believe that the most important objects of study can be found in the U.S. legal
community. Foreign legal systems and doctrine produced in other polities are not
very attractive to U.S. law professors. Western Europe’s legal academy might be
viewed as more open to comparative law. Even there, however, the legal systems
North America. Global South scholars or legal systems are seldom invited to the
These five arguments not only explain the marginal position that Global
South scholars and legal institutions occupy in the interpretation, use, and
unstated background assumptions that govern the production, circulation, and use of
legal knowledge. Generally, these assumptions remain implicit: They are not often
discussed openly among legal scholars and other legal operators like judges or
practitioners. However, they firmly govern the relationship between the legal
communities in the Global North and South. They determine, among other things, the
constitutionalism. The first assumption that these five arguments generate is what I
would like to call the argument of the “production well.” This states that the only
context for the production of knowledge is the legal academia in the North. The
the same. It is argued that while legal academia and institutions in the North create
original academic products, legal academia and institutions in the South only
articulate products derived from other sources. Although the former opens up new
descriptive, critical, and normative paths, the latter follows the routes already opened
Second, the arguments presented above generate what I call the assumption of
the North is worthy of respect and recognition per se, given the context from which it
emerges. Even before it has been read or evaluated, the mere origin of the academic
even before being read. Legal knowledge generated in the South is only legitimate
when academics from the North have given it their approval. Legal products from the
South are marked (negatively) by their origin. This seal can only be lifted when
representatives from the production well of legitimate legal knowledge believe that it
should be. The positive qualification of an academic product from the South on the
part of Southern academics is, at best, an indication of its quality. Professors from the
Third, the five arguments outlined above produce what I call the specific
indicates that academics and legal institutions from the North are much better trained
to make effective and legitimate use of legal knowledge than are academics and legal
institutions from the South. The use of academic products, in this view, has ethical
consequences. To ignore or violate the rules guiding the use of legal knowledge
12 12
questions the moral values that the academic community shares, may adversely affect
third parties, and threatens the legitimacy of intellectual products. To illustrate this
projects have an explicit political role, in that they usually involve and directly affect
vulnerable groups. Thus, the improper use of legal knowledge will have negative
consequences for clients of these clinics, as well as for the legitimacy of the projects
themselves. Clinical professors in the North have the academic know-how36 to make
proper use of the academic products created. Similarly, they have access to networks
and spaces of power to make effective use of this knowledge. On the other hand, the
with respect to the use of legal knowledge, it is thought, can lead clinical projects to
ruin. Again, professors from the North must make the key decisions on the use of the
The foregoing factors explain the marginal place the Global South occupies in
the discussion about the content and structure of law and the rules that govern the
exchanges between Global North and Global South legal communities. These factors
have two dimensions: one that illuminates and one that obscures reality. On the one
hand,they describe and properly characterize one part of the reality of legal academic
communities of the Global South and North. It is true, for example, that many sectors
of the Global South legal academy have tended to reproduce and not to create legal
knowledge.37 Many of the legal norms that are issued, the doctrines that interpret
13 13
them, and the theories that substantiate, evaluate, or contextualize them are a local
that legal formalism has controlled part of the Global South’s legal conscience and
that this is a poor concept of law. Many Global South legal scholars have argued so.38
Finally, it is also correct to say that a good part of the Global North legal academy is
centered on itself and is not very interested in what happens beyond its borders,
particularly if crossing these borders takes it to a legal system of the Global South.39
However, on the other hand, these arguments are questionable both from a
descriptive point of view and from a normative standpoint. These arguments, along
with the three assumptions they generate, homogenize a reality that is full of shades
and hues. Thus, first, these general arguments ignore the heterogeneity of legal
academic communities. There is no doubt that, overall, the law schools of the Global
North, in North America particularly, have built stronger academic communities than
those in the Global South. Nevertheless, there are internal weaknesses in both
contexts, as well as nuances and exceptions to the rules noted in each. Legal
academia in the North offers a wide range of schools, with varying levels of quality.
For example, a law school located at the top of the various rankings that exist in the
United States, Canada, or United Kingdom is not the same thing as a school in the
middle of such rankings, or one at the bottom.40 The differences are even more
important when comparing the strengths and weaknesses of schools in the top tier
with those in the second and third tiers of the hierarchy in the United States. The
contrasts in the quality of the academic products generated, as well as the financial
14 14
resources available, are notable in many cases. The strength of journals published, the
wealth of libraries, the number and quality of exchanges with academics from other
parts of the world, and the conferences offered vary markedly between these schools.
Finally, these arguments and rules obscure the fact that, even in good law schools,
there are professors who are not academically strong or that the quality of the
sum, the arguments of the well of production, protected designation of origin, and
effective operator ignore the differences in the quality of law schools. These
arguments invalidate this diversity and identify “professor” and “quality academic
product” with the law schools of the Global North, and with schools in the United
States in particular.
Colombian, or Chilean “garage”41 law school is not the same thing as the law school
at the University of the Witwatersrand, the law school of the National University of
Taiwan, and the National Law School at the University of India, Bangalore. There are
the economic resources at their disposal. It is true that the role still given to the legal
academic in many parts of the Global South is the systematization of the legal order
and that the production generated by this objective often leaves much to be desired.42
However, within the law schools of the Global South are nodes that meet high
academic standards and that distance themselves radically from the various formalist
15 15
traditions found in the countries where they are located. In Latin America we can
mention, for example, research groups within the law schools of the Fundação
Getulio Vargas and University of São Paulo in Brazil, the University of the Andes
and the National University in Colombia, ITAM and the Autonomous University of
Mexico, and the Catholic University and Diego Portales University in Chile;43 in
Africa, nodes in the law schools at the University of Cape Town and University of
University of Nairobi in Kenya; in Asia, groups of scholars within the law schools at
the National University of Taiwan, the National University of Seoul, and the
University of Delhi; and in Eastern Europe, networks of academics within the law
schools of the University of Eastern Europe and Warsaw University. Similarly, there
are legal intellectuals and individual cases whose production is of the highest quality.
Consider, for example, Carlos Santiago Nino, Albie Sachs, and Upendra Baxi.
research projects and legal publications. They have also explicitly and continuously
criticized legal formalism and the epistemological dependence that weakens many of
the region’s legal communities.44 But these examples, purely declarative, simply
illustrate the general argument. They are not meant to weigh and evaluate the totality
of legal academia in the Global North and South. They are only intended to
demonstrate the weakness of the argument that homogenizes legal academia in the
Global South at a low level and the academia of the Global North at a higher one.
16 16
These factors and rules also ignore the fact that the Global South has indeed
formulated rich and valuable rules, theories, and doctrines. The jurisprudence of the
doctrine of the social function of property,46 and the contributions of Latin American
lawyers like Álvaro Álvarez and Carlos Calvo to the creation of international law47
and Mexican labor law, are just a few examples of complex legal products created in
the region. The jurisprudence of the South African Constitutional Court on the use of
comparative and international law for interpreting the South African Constitution and
the Indian Supreme Court’s Public Interest Litigation movement are two other
examples of innovative legal products created in the Global South. Finally, the
contributions to the history of international law and the law of the sea by R. P. Anand,
the rich and complex Islamic legal tradition of countries like Egypt and Pakistan, the
scholarship on duties and the rights of people written by African legal academics, and
the intersections among Buddhism, Hinduism, and law illustrate the multifaceted and
The foregoing arguments and rules also obscure the fact that legal formalism
has not been the only concept of law present in the many legal communities that exist
in the Global South.48 The concepts of law offered by legal positivism,49 the free
school of law,50 and contemporary sociology of law,51 among others, have also been a
concept of law has been influential.52 In North Africa, the legal imagination has been
shaped, partially, by an Islamic concept of law. Within the Global South academy,
17 17
legal phenomena. Finally, it is important to indicate that, within the Global North
legal academy, there are some sectors interested in the law created by other political
show the interest that already exists in such a field.63 The increasing number of
European comparative and transnational law journals also makes explicit the interest
in some Western European quarters for what happens beyond its borders.64
modern constitutionalism, is still too much centered in the Global North. The number
of participants in this conversation should be increased, the doors of the places where
this dialogue takes place should be opened to more southern interlocutors, and the
default attitude toward the law of the Global South should be changed. Of course, I
am not arguing that the legal products of the legal Global South should be valued
because of their origin. This would promote an inverted application of the production
well and protected geographical indication assumptions that I presented above. This
would also obscure the deficiencies and shortcomings of the law of the Global South.
Nor am I arguing in favor of a paternalistic attitude toward the law of the Global
South. I am not arguing that Global South legal scholars and legal products should a
should be evaluated on its own terms to determine its originality and worth.
18 18
However, I do argue that a mindset that closes the door to all Global South legal
Colombian Constitutional Court have been among the most important and creative
courts in the Global South. In Asia, Africa, and Latin America, these courts are
widely seen as activist tribunals that have contributed (or attempted to contribute) to
the structural transformation of the public and private spheres of their countries.65
These courts’ jurisprudence has dealt with problems that are important for and
frequent in all contemporary liberal democracies. Issues about the interpretation and
protection of civil and political rights, for example, have been addressed regularly by
these three courts’ case law.66 Yet these courts’ jurisprudence has also dealt with
problems that are specific to or have special importance in the Global South, and they
have done so through original and imaginative legal theories and political strategies.
Issues related to political violence, poverty, and the consolidation of the rule of law
have been an important part of these Courts’ jurisprudence. These Courts, for
example, have decided cases about the rights of internally displaced people,67 how to
social and economic rights in contexts with high levels of poverty,69 and the limits
that Congress has for amending the Constitution in innovative and appealing ways.70
19 19
supported by modern constitutionalism’s basic rules and principles. These Courts use
with all courts, many of the cases that they decide are doctrinally unimportant – they
constitutionalism, such as the Supreme Court of the United States and the European
least rearrange them in novel ways. The jurisprudence of these three Courts,
of these three Courts. Constitutional law scholars and other participants in this
dialogue would discover, for example, interesting ways of interpreting the principle
of connecting social and economic rights with the principle of human dignity,73 and
This exercise would generate some benefits. On the one hand, interpreters
circumstances, to understand or attempt to solve legal and political issues within their
polities. On the other hand, it might allow interpreters to understand their own
20 20
constitutional systems more clearly or in a new light. In many cases, legal transplants
are not possible. A functionalist approach to comparative law might not be useful in
certain cases:75 There might be substantial differences between legal systems; the
political, economic, and cultural context might be too dissimilar; or the legal
understanding the other, we might be able to better comprehend our own legal and
political community. The “other” can be a mirror in which we can find a more
Colombia, India, and South Africa are very different countries. It might be
argued then that to compare their highest courts would not be useful; the exercise
would not render many profits. The “cases” under examination would run parallel to
culturally, there are important dissimilarities among these countries. For one, they are
located on three different continents. The size and importance of their economies
vary widely. Colombia’s gross domestic product (GDP) in 2010 was nearly
US$288.2 billion,78 India’s was over US$1.7 trillion,79 and South Africa’s was about
and Catholic,82 whereas in India, the majority of the population speaks Hindi and
professes Hinduism.83 In South Africa, Zulu is the most common language spoken at
21 21
home but English is the dominant language in government and the media.84
moreover, belongs to the civil law tradition,86 India’s to the common law tradition,87
and South Africa’s is a mixture of the civil law and common law traditions.88 The
institutional and contextual differences among these three countries are certainly
many.
The three countries, however, have some important similarities. All three are
some of the highest in the world, their history has been marked by political violence,
and their cultural diversity is notable. Likewise, these three countries have legitimate
and activist constitutional or supreme courts that have addressed these political,
economic, and cultural issues in rich and complex ways. In these three countries, the
constitutional courts have played an important role in the protection of the rule of law
The constitutions of Colombia, South Africa, and India are structured around
liberal democratic values.89 The idea that human beings are autonomous and equal
their humanity. Human dignity is a fundamental value in these three countries’ legal
systems.90 These constitutions also contain a wide Bill of Rights that includes civil
and political rights, social and economic rights, and collective rights.91 All these
rights are understood as fundamental tools for the protection of autonomy and
equality. The constitutional frameworks of these three countries also include the
22 22
principle of separation of powers and a system of checks and balances that limit the
constitutions of Colombia, India, and South Africa are committed to democracy, and
therefore to the idea that the government should be held accountable through
multiparty, open, and regularly organized elections. Finally, the constitutions of these
three countries establish that economic relations should be organized in the form of a
market economy.
between leftist guerilla groups and the government, fueled by drug trafficking, has
ravaged the country for more than four decades. In India, the violence between
Hindus and Muslims has weakened the polity since independence. And in South
Africa, the apartheid system and the struggle against its formal and informal rules
economic matters. The promises of economic justice and prosperity for all made by
the 1991 Colombian Constitution, the 1996 South African Constitution, and the 1948
Indian Constitution have not been realized. Colombia’s Gini coefficient is 0.578,
India’s is 0.368, and South Africa’s is 0.65.92 The percentage of the population
currently living under the poverty line in Colombia is 45.5 percent, in India 25
reached 11.2 percent in Colombia, 9.8 percent in India, and 23.9 percent in South
Africa. Poverty and inequality, no doubt, limit the legitimacy and stability of these
countries’ cultural minorities is an aim that has not been achieved. The levels of
discrimination against cultural minorities are still high. The result has been religious
unrest, political violence, and the alienation and marginalization of many individuals
and groups. Cultural minorities’ rights are still very much paper rules in these
countries. Yet the cultural diversity that characterizes Colombia, India, and South
Africa is also one of their great assets. In Colombia, there are eighty-seven
vibrant, culturally diverse black communities on the Atlantic and Pacific coasts, and
the Roma people have a small but strong presence in the country.95 Small European
and Middle Eastern communities enrich (and have historically enriched) Colombia’s
149 million, constitutes the second largest Muslim community in the world. In India,
630 Scheduled Tribes are recognized by the state. Linguistically, India is similarly
rich: 114 languages are spoken by more than 10,000 persons, and more than 1 million
is black, 8.9 percent colored, 2.5 percent Indian or Asian, and 9.6 percent white.98
The black population is divided into four major ethnic groups: Nguni, Sotho,
24 24
communities. Cultural diversity is, surely, a salient component of the past, present,
democracies, political violence, high levels of inequality and poverty, and cultural
diversity – are notable. However, these are characteristics that they share with other
countries of the Global South. What makes these three countries relevant and
attractive for a comparative constitutional law analysis is that they have legitimate,
creative, and regionally prestigious constitutional courts that have addressed the
foregoing common issues. These three Courts have contributed to understanding and
confronting the challenges that these matters create. Surely, the jurisprudence of
these Courts has dealt with many other issues. However, their case law has been
particularly interesting and innovative when dealing with the many dimensions that
compose these key subjects. If this is true, several interesting questions should be
raised and answered: What are the contributions that these Courts have made to the
Colombian Constitutional Court, the Indian Supreme Court, and the Constitutional
Court of South Africa slowly creating a constitutionalism of the Global South? If so,
what are the differences and similarities between this emerging constitutionalism and
South needed?
25 25
These questions cannot be answered in this book. They are too broad,
some issues directly related to these questions. The book aims to open the discussion
about the jurisprudence of the Constitutional Court of Colombia, the Indian Supreme
Court, and the South African Constitutional Court. The chapters gathered in this book
explore the jurisprudence of these courts on three matters: social and economic
rights, cultural diversity, and access to justice. These three topics are directly related
to poverty and inequality, political violence, cultural minorities, and the consolidation
of the rule of law – issues that are fundamental in these three countries. The book
also aims to bridge the gap that exists between the Global South and Global North on
constitutional matters. Finally, it aims to make explicit the need to widen the number
and access to justice. These issues have been central to the jurisprudence of the
Colombian Constitutional Court, the Supreme Court of India, and the South African
The first section of the book, “Socioeconomic Rights,” begins with a chapter
justice, social and economic rights, and the Constitutions of South Africa, India, and
Colombia. His line of argumentation can be divided in three parts. First, he argues
that there is an important difference between these three Constitutions and the
Constitutions of the Global North: while the former emphasize social and economic
rights, the latter emphasize liberties. Bilchitz contends that the Constitutions of
Colombia, India, and South Africa are especially committed to substantive equality –
although they also recognize and value autonomy. Second, he analyzes the role that
the Constitutional Court of South Africa, the Supreme Court of India, and the
Constitutional Court of Colombia have had (and should have) in enforcing social and
economic rights, grounding his analysis in the particular political, economic, and
social conditions of each country. Bilchitz indicates that these Courts have played
and should continue to play an important role in protecting the individual’s right to
equality. Without real access to material resources, the distributive justice aims
pursued by the Constitutions of South Africa, India, and Colombia would not be
achieved. These Courts, Bilchitz argues, have stepped up to protect the social and
economic rights of all members of the polity; the work of these Courts is especially
significant given the weaknesses that the legislative and executive branches have in
these three countries. Third, Bilchitz studies the jurisprudence of the Constitutional
Court of South Africa, the Supreme Court of India, and the Constitutional Court of
Colombia on social and economic rights. He examines the legal theories and political
strategies used by these Courts to give content to and, ultimately, to realize these
powers and formulated novel remedies and procedures to enforce social and
economic rights – has not yet created a true constitutionalism of the Global South.
Shylashri Shankar writes the second chapter of this section. In Chapter 2, she
argues that political commentators and scholars argue both that the Supreme Court of
social and economic rights. For some, the fact that the Court has transformed
fundamental rights shows the activist character of the Court. For others, the fact that
the Court has reached agreements with the executive branch to protect the status quo
and has not really enforced social and economic rights provides evidence of the
approaches are wrong; they are based on fuzzy concepts of “activism.” Shankar
argues that a Court can be called “activist” only when it violates the borders of the
legislature’s and executive’s jurisdictions. Shankar also notes that an analysis of the
Court’s jurisprudence on health and education rights between 2006 and 2011 shows
that the Court has been neither strictly activist nor strictly nonactivist. What an
analysis of the Supreme Court of India’s jurisprudence on health and education rights
does show is that it has transformed itself into a negotiator between the state and its
citizens. Shankar argues that the Court has assumed the role of an embedded
the Court’s jurisprudence clarifies the content of the rights – creating no new duties
in the process – and facilitates a dialogue between the state and its citizens
concerning the ways in which social and economic rights should be realized.
The first section of the book ends with the chapter written by Libardo Ariza.
formulated by the Colombian Constitutional Court. This doctrine can be used to stop
blockage. This doctrine, which has been used to address the situation of the millions
of internally displaced people in Colombia (among other things), has been widely
considered as progressive by constitutional law scholars for two reasons. On the one
hand, it has allowed the Court to distance itself from a traditionally functional
interpretation of the principle of separation of powers. The Court, therefore, has been
interpreted as an institution that is willing to cross the borders that determine the
jurisdictions of the executive and legislative branches in order to protect the Bill of
Rights. On the other hand, the USOA doctrine shows the Court’s commitment to the
inequality and poverty. However, Ariza argues that this doctrine has been problematic
when applied to the prison system. Ariza argues that, in this case, the USOA has not
helped to stop the systematic violation of prisoners’ rights and has instead helped the
more prisons and increasing mandatory minimum terms in prison. The slow
implementation of social and economic rights that the USOA doctrine allows by
29 29
sponsoring a traditional interpretation of these rights, Ariza argues, collides with the
inhumane conditions in which inmates are forced to live within the Colombian prison
system.
The second section of the book, “Cultural Diversity,” begins with a chapter by
Cathi Albertyn. In Chapter 4, she explores the tension between customary law and
gender equality that cuts across the South African Constitution, and she also
weaknesses of the Courts’ main argument in the relevant case law: that the concept of
living law and custom should solve the conflicts between cultural diversity and
individual rights. She argues that the Courts’ approach has rightly protected gender
equality, but has not always properly recognized and accommodated cultural
constitution, which would impose liberal values across all cultures. Instead, she
argues for an interpretation that gives priority to deliberation and that balances
cultural diversity, on the one hand, and autonomy and equality, on the other. For
Albertyn, this aim is achievable if we accept that cultures are entities in constant flux
and are susceptible to different interpretations, and that liberal values are open-
textured norms that can reasonably be given different contents. Cultures, she notes,
are contested, flexible, and permeable. Liberalism, she also points out, is not a
are both disputed and capable of change. These arguments, together with a contextual
30 30
approach that takes into account the particular characteristics of each conflict, will
probably attain, Albertyn argues, an adequate balance of the constitutional values that
Grupeet Mahajan, in the second chapter of this section, explores the Indian
the Court has tried to protect religious diversity by balancing the interests of religious
minorities and majorities, as well as the interests of the community and the
individual. The Court, Mahajan states, has not favored an approach that gives priority
to the Hindu religious majority, nor has it valued the individual over religious
congregations. The Court has tried to balance interreligious equality with diversity
and autonomy, while at the same time balancing individual equality with cultural
diversity. Throughout this process of balancing competing values, the Court has taken
into account the particularities of each case, the consequences of its decisions, public
order issues, and religious history and practices. The Court, from Mahajan’s
perspective, has also moved beyond interpreting the law to interpreting sacred texts
among competing religious creeds – Hinduism, Islam, and Christianity – and the
In the last chapter of this second section (Chapter 6), Daniel Bonilla
tension between cultural diversity and cultural unity that structures the Colombian
1991 Constitution. In particular, the relevant case law examines the tension between
cultural minorities’ self-government rights and the principle of political unity. Bonilla
Maldonado divides the jurisprudence of the Court into three stages and critically
examines their philosophical foundations. In the first stage, the Court defines the
characteristics that give structure to the right to prior consultation and formulates the
criteria that should guide its development; in the second stage, the Court determines
the rules that should govern the consultation of legislative and administrative
measures that directly affect cultural minorities; in the last stage, the Court reiterates
the first two stages of its jurisprudence, but rules that the right to prior consultation
includes cultural minorities’ right to veto the decisions made by the state when these
Maldonado argues that the Court’s jurisprudence on the right to prior consultation
questions the first two models and states that the third one offers a better
government rights, and cultural integrity in order to justify and give content to the
Dugard. Chapter 7 is structured around the following question: Has the Constitutional
32 32
Court of South Africa become a voice for the poor? Dugard, assuming what she calls
a pro-poor approach, argues that this has not been the case. The Court, on the one
hand, has not opened a dialogue with the citizenry – particularly with the South
African poor. The Court, Dugard states, has not allowed poor South Africans to gain
direct access to justice, and, when they do arrive before the Court, poor individuals
protection for their rights and interests, such as a weak interpretation of the right to
legal representation. On the other hand, the Court has not been willing, Dugard
problematic, Dugard indicates, given the history of oppression and the structural
legitimacy and becoming an isolated and distrusted institution among poor South
Africans.
Menaka Gurusmany and Bipin Aspatwar are the authors of the second chapter
of this section. In Chapter 8, Gurusmany and Aspatwar explore the Supreme Court of
India’s jurisprudence on access to justice. The authors analyze the celebrated Public
Interest Litigation Movement led by the Indian Supreme Court and examine the
right to access to justice, the authors argue, has opened the Court’s door to many poor
and vulnerable sections of the population, including prisoners, women, and members
of cultural minorities. The so-called epistolary jurisdiction, for example, has allowed
33 33
common citizens to get to the Court and to establish a dialogue with the Supreme
Tribunal. However, the authors also argue that, although the flexible interpretation of
locus standi has been widely applied by the Court in major constitutional cases where
the public interest is clearly at stake, it has not been applied by the Court in ordinary
cases. In these cases, the Court has formulated a more rigid interpretation of standing
rules, with negative consequences for both individual litigants and constitutional
justice in general.
Manuel Iturralde, in the third and last chapter of this section (Chapter 9),
particular, Iturralde examines the Court’s flexible interpretation of the tutela legal
action and the actio popularis. The first action has allowed common Colombians to
protect their fundamental rights through a fast, cheap, and uncomplicated legal
process. This legal action can be, in principle, brought before any judge in the
The second action has allowed common citizens to protect the coherence of the legal
system and exercise control over the executive and legislative branches. This legal
action allows any citizen to question the constitutionality of almost any law before
the Constitutional Court. Iturralde also analyzes the ways in which social
organizations and legal clinics have used these legal actions and the Court’s
studies the serious conflicts that the Constitutional Court’s access to justice
34 34
jurisprudence has created with the Supreme Court and the State Council. In this
analysis, Iturralde uses a sociolegal approach that utilizes Bourdieu’s concept of the
legal field.
Acknowledgments
I would like to thank Libardo Ariza for his very useful comments and suggestions.
2011. Sheila Foster and Toni Fine were essential for the organization of this
conference. Without their ideas and support, the event would not have happened. The
conference would also not have been possible without the sponsorship of the Louis
Rakin Foundation. The funds provided by this foundation were fundamental to its
success. The Leitner Center for Human Rights at Fordham Law School also played a
very important role in this conference. I warmly thank its members for their
3 See id. at 42, 59–60, 79–80; Charles Howard McIlwain, CONSTITUTIONALISM ANCIENT AND MODERN 3–24
(Cornell University Press [[AQ? Publisher?]]1940).
4 In 2003, the International Journal of Constitutional Law published a symposium issue on constitutional borrowing.
The articles published in this volume mainly analyze cases about borrowing from Western Courts (U.S., German,
French, for example) or Constitutions. The overwhelming majority of the cases explored are those of non-Western
institutions borrowing from Western institutions. See D. M. Davis, Constitutional Borrowing: The Influence of Legal
Culture and Local History in the Reconstitution of Comparative Influence: The South African Experience, 1 INT’L. J.
CONST. L. 181–95 (2003); Lee Epstein and Jack Knight, Constitutional Borrowing and Nonborrowing, 1 INT’L. J.
CONST. L. 196–223 (2003); Yasuo Hasebe, Constitutional Borrowing and Political Theory, 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 224–
43 (2003); Wiktor Osiatynski, Paradoxes of Constitutional Borrowing, 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 244–68 (2003); Carlos F.
Rosenkrantz, Against Borrowings and Other Nonauthoritative Uses of Foreign Law, 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 269–95
(2003); Kim Lane Scheppele, Aspirational and Aversive Constitutionalism: The Case for Studying Cross-constitutional
Influence through Negative Models, 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 296–324 (2003).
5 See generally 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 181–324 (2003) (analyzing various aspects of constitutional borrowing while
overwhelmingly limiting the analyses to borrowings from Western institutions).
6 See John Rawls, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 15–24 (Harvard University Press rev. ed. [[AQ? Publisher?]]1999).
8 See generally Robert Nozick, ANARCHY, STATE, AND UTOPIA ([Basic Books [AQ? Publisher?]]1974) (arguing in
favor of a minimal state for the best protection of individual rights).
9 See generally Charles Taylor, SOURCES OF THE SELF: THE MAKING OF THE MODERN IDENTITY (Harvard University
Press [[AQ? Publisher?]]1989) (inquiring into the nature of identity and humanity in the modern West).
10 I use the words “Global South” and “Global North” as less pejorative synonyms of the words “developing countries”
and “developed countries,” respectively.
11 See Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Three Metaphors for a New Conception of Law: The Frontier, the Baroque and the
South, 29 L. SOC’Y. REV. 569, 579–82 (1995); Mark van Hoecke and Mark Warrington, Legal Cultures, Legal
Paradigms and Legal Doctrine: Towards a New Model for Comparative Law, 47 INT’L. COMP. L.Q. 495, 498–
99 (1998).
12 See de Sousa Santos, supra note 11, [[AQ? Supra note 11?]]at 579–82; Ugo Mattei, Three Patterns of Law:
Taxonomy and Change in the World’s Legal Systems, 45 AM. J. COMP. L. 5, 10–12 (1997); van Hoecke and Warrington,
supra note 11 at 498–99. [[AQ? Supra note 11?]]
13 See Jorge L. Esquirol, The Fictions of Latin American Law (Part I), 1997 UTAH L. REV. 425, 427–28 (1997); Jorge
L. Esquirol, Continuing Fictions of Latin American Law, 55 FLA. L. REV. 41, 42 (2003); Jorge L. Esquirol, The Failed
Law of Latin America, 56 AM. J. COMP. L. 75, 94–95 (2008).
15 See René David and J. E. Brierley, MAJOR LEGAL SYSTEMS IN THE WORLD TODAY, 222–4 (Simon and Schuster
2nd ed., [[AQ? Publisher?]] 1978).
16This inherited or imported law from the colonial cities coexists with the religious legal traditions in many countries in
the region, Islamic or Buddhist ones in particular. See Lama Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)recognition: Islamic Law
Pedagogy in American Academia, 52 AM. J. COMP. L. 789, 806–8 (2004).
17 See Brian Z. Tamanaha, “The Primacy of Society and the Failures of Law and Development,” p. 6, St. John’s Univ.
Legal Studies Research Paper Series, Paper No. 09–0172 (2009), available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?
abstract_id=1406999; Jorge L. Esquirol, Writing the Law of Latin America, 40 GEO. WASH. INT’L L. REV. 693, 706, 731
(2009). It is interesting to contrast this argument with the fact that, in other fields, such as literature and art, the
production of the South is considered relevant and valuable. Literature and art departments in the United States and
Europe, for example, usually offer courses on Latin American, Asian, or African literature or art. The faculties of these
departments often include professors from the South or those specialized in the artistic production of the South. In the
same way, the work of authors like Gabriel Garcia Marquez, J. M. Coetzee, and Gao Xingjian has contributed to the
creation of the grammar of contemporary literature. It would be important to explore the reasons that explain the
“universality” of southern art and the marginality of southern law.
19 See John Henry Merryman and Rogelio Pérez-Perdomo , THE CIVIL LAW TRADITION : AN INTRODUCTION TO
THE LEGAL SYSTEMS OF EUROPE AND LATIN AMERICA 57, 60 (Stanford University Press [[AQ? Publisher?]]2007); R.
Daniel Kelemen and Eric C. Sibbitt, The Globalization of American Law, 58 INT’L ORGANIZATION 103, 103–36; John
Henry Merryman, Comparative Law and Social Change: On the Origins, Style, Decline, and Revival of the Law and
Development Movement, 25 AM. J. COMP. L. 457, 484–89 (1977); Kerry Ritttich, The Future of Law and Development:
Second-Generation Reforms and the Incorporation of the Social, in THE NEW LAW AND ECONOMIC DEVELOPMENT 203,
203–52 (D. Trubek and A. Santos eds., Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2006).
20 See Pilar Domingo and Rachel Sieder, Rule of Law, in LATIN AMERICA: THE INTERNATIONAL PROMOTION OF
JUDICIAL REFORM 1 (Pilar Domingo and Rachel Sieder eds., Institute of Latin American Studies [[AQ?
Publisher?]]2001) (Eng.); Andrés Torres, “From Inquisitorial to Accusatory: Colombia and Guatemala’s Legal
Transition,” p. 2, Law and Justice in the Americas Working Paper Series, Paper no. 4 (2007), available at
http://lawdigitalcommons.bc.edu/ljawps/4.
21 See María Victoria Murillo, Partisanship Amidst Convergence: The Politics of Labor Reform in Latin America, 37
COMPARATIVE POLITICS 441, 441–3; Graciela Bensusán, “La efectividad de la legislaciónlaboral en América Latina,
Instituto de Estudios Laborales,” pp. 13–22, Organización Internacional del Trabajo (2007), available at
http://www.ilo.org/public/spanish/bureau/inst/download/dp18107.pdf.
22 See Haim Sandberg, Legal Colonialism – Americanization of Legal Education in Israel, 10 (2) GLOBAL JURIST,
(Topics), article 6.
23 See Ugo Mattei, A Theory of Imperial Law: A Study on U.S. Hegemony and the Latin Resistance, 10 IND. J. GLOBAL
LEGAL STUD. 383, 447 (2003); Ugo Mattei, Why the Wind Changed: Intellectual Leadership in Western Law, 42
AM. J. COMP. L. 195 (1994); Wolfgang Wiegand, Americanization of Law: Reception or Convergence?, in LEGAL
CULTURE AND THE LEGAL PROFESSION 137 (Lawrence M. Friedman and Harry N. Scheiber eds., Westview Press[[AQ?
Publisher?]]1996).
24 See Carlos Peña González, “Characteristics and Challenges in Latin American Legal Education,” Conference of
International Legal Educators 1, 1–3 (2000), available at http://www.aals.org/2000international/.
25 See Carlos Santiago Nino, INTRODUCCIÓN AL ANÁLISIS DEL DERECHO 36–37 (Astrea[[AQ? Publisher?]]1984)
(Arg.).
26See Merryman and Pérez-Perdomo, supra note 19, at 66. [[AQ? Supra note 19?]]
27 See generally Martin Chanock, THE MAKING OF SOUTH AFRICAN LEGAL CULTURE 1902–1936: FEAR, FAVOUR AND
PREJUDICE (Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2001) (Eng.); Samuel C. Nolutshungu, Constitutionalism in
Africa: Some Conclusions, in CONSTITUTIONALISM AND DEMOCRACY: TRANSITIONS IN THE CONTEMPORARY WORLD
(Douglas Greenberg, Stanley N. Katz, Melanie Beth Oliviero, and Steven C. Wheatley eds., Oxford University
Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]1993) (Eng.).
28 See generally ADMINISTRATIVE LAW AND GOVERNANCE IN ASIA (Tom Ginsburg and Albert H. Y. Chen eds.,
Routledge[[AQ? Publisher?]]2009) (Eng.); Tom Ginsburg, JUDICIAL REVIEW IN NEW DEMOCRACIES:
CONSTITUTIONAL COURTS IN ASIAN CASES 42 (Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2003) (Eng.).
29 See, for example, Marcin Matczak, Judicial Formalism and Judicial Reform: An Example of Central and Eastern
Europe (Jul. 25, 2007) (unpublished paper presented at the annual meeting of The Law and Society Association, Berlin,
Germany) (describing the persistence of formalist-inflected adjudication in Poland).
30 See generally Carlos Santiago Nino, ETICA Y DERECHOS HUMANOS (Astrea[[AQ? Publisher?]]2003) (Arg.);
Eugenio Bulygin, EL POSITIVISMO JURÍDICO (Fontamara[[AQ? Publisher?]]2006) (Mex.); Carlos Alchourrón and
Eugenio Bulygin, INTRODUCCIÓN A LA METODOLOGÍA DE LAS CIENCIAS JURÍDICAS Y SOCIALES (Astrea[[AQ?
Publisher?]]1974) (Arg.); Boaventura de Sousa Santos, TOWARD A NEW LEGAL COMMON SENSE: LAW,
GLOBALIZATION, AND EMANCIPATION (Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2002) (Eng.).
31 See, for example, Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457 (1897) (articulating the
antiformalist bases for which legal realism came to be known).
32 See, for example, John Dewey, Logical Method and the Law, 10 CORNELL L. Q. 17 (1924); Karl Llewellyn, Some
Realism about Realism – Responding to Dean Pound, 44 HARVARD L. REV. 1222 (1931). See also NATURALIZING
JURISPRUDENCE: ESSAYS ON AMERICAN LEGAL REALISM AND NATURALISM IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY (Brian Leiter ed.,
Oxford University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2007); Brian Leiter, Legal Formalism and Legal Realism: What Is the
Issue? 16 LEGAL THEORY 111 (2010).
33 See generally Jorge L. Esquirol, Fictions of Latin American Law (Part 1), 1997 UTAH L. REV. 425 (1997) (exploring
how the failure of law has been used to understand Latin American law and highlighting the antiformalist strains in
Latin American law). It is interesting to note the parallels between the failure of law argument and the birth and early
development of some social sciences, like anthropology. Two arguments are of special importance in this context. On
the one hand, the idea that the only valuable local knowledge is the one that can be translated into the categories of the
“universal” knowledge – that is, the knowledge produced in the center. On the other, the thought that there is a
difference between the space where knowledge is produced – the center – and the space where fieldwork is done – the
periphery.
34 This chapter understands academic products as those created by nonclinical professors, as well as those generated by
legal clinics. There are remarkable differences between an article published in an academic journal and some of the
typical products of the clinics – a lawsuit or report on human rights, for example. However, I simply want to note in this
chapter that both products are the result of intellectual work generated in a law school.
35 See Ugo Mattei, An Opportunity Not to Be Missed: The Future of Comparative Law in The United States, 48 AM. J.
COMP. L. 712 (1998).
36 This academic know-how includes familiarity with and use of the ethical rules that should guide the use of legal
knowledge.
37 See generally DERECHO Y SOCIEDAD EN AMERICA LATINA: UN DEBATE SOBRE LOS ESTUDIOS JURIDICOS CRÍTICOS
(Cesar Rodriguez and Mauricio Garcia, eds.,ILSA [[AQ? Publisher?]]2003) (Colom.).
38 See generally Carlos Santiago Nino, ETICA Y DERECHOS HUMANOS (Astrea[ [AQ? Publisher?]]2003) (Arg.);
Eugenio Bulygin, EL POSITIVISMO JURÍDICO (Astrea[[AQ? Publisher?]]2006) (Mex.); Carlos Alchourrón and
Eugenio Bulygin, INTRODUCCIÓN A LA METODOLOGÍA DE LAS CIENCIAS JURÍDICAS Y SOCIALES (Astrea[[AQ?
Publisher?]]1974) (Arg.); Boaventura de Sousa Santos, TOWARD A NEW LEGAL COMMON SENSE: LAW,
GLOBALIZATION, AND EMANCIPATION ([Cambidge University Press [AQ? Publisher?]]2002) (Eng.).
39 See Ugo Mattei, Three Patterns of Law: Taxonomy and Change in the World’s Legal System, 45 AM. J. COMP. L. 5, 7
(1997).
40The two best-known publications in which law schools in the United States are classified are US News and
Lawschool 100. See Best Law Schools, U.S. NEWS AND WORLD REPORT, available at http://grad-
schools.usnews.rankingsandreviews.com/best-graduate-schools/top-law-schools (last accessed Feb. 2, 2012). For
Canadian law school rankings, see Ranking Canada’s Law Schools, MACLEANS.CA, available at
http://www2.macleans.ca/2009/09/16/ranking-canada%E2%80%99s-law-schools/ (last accessed Feb. 2, 2012). For
rankings of law schools in the United Kingdom, see University Guide 2011: Law, THE GUARDIAN, available at
http://www.guardian.co.uk/education/table/2010/jun/04/university-guide-law (last accessed Feb. 2, 2012). Law schools
have criticized these classifications from various perspectives. Law school administrators and professors argue, for
example, that the criteria used by U.S. News to rank law schools are vague, irrelevant, or incomplete. I agree with these
critiques. However, for the purposes of this essay, they are useful for showing the overall differences within legal
academia in the United States. I would say that many in the U.S. legal community agree in that there are notable
differences between the first fifteen law schools and the last fifteen law schools in the top 100, or between first-tier law
schools and third-tier law schools. Yet even these broad differences are obscured by the arguments of the production
well, protected geographical indication, and effective operator.
41“Garage universities” are those whose primary goal is the profit of their founders and whose standards of quality are
very low. Generally, their infrastructure is very poor.
42A portion of legal academia in Latin America, Africa, Asia, and Eastern Europe, therefore, continues to believe that
the work of an academic should be to define the content of the principles and rules that comprise the legal system, as
well as how to resolve their inconsistencies. Hence, in many of these law schools, the treatise is considered to be the
product par excellence of law professors. In the best of cases, the basic units of the national legal systems of the Global
South are judiciously systematized in this type of academic product. Nevertheless, in most cases, these academic
products are nothing more than glosses to the law. In these texts, the professor of law repeats the content of legal norms
in different wording and makes comments that are more or less marginal to guiding professional practice or morally
evaluating the contents of the law. The weak products of parts of the legal academia in the Global South can be partially
explained by the fact that the professionalization of the legal academy is a very recent event in most of the region.
Historically, judges and practitioners have constituted law faculties in most of the Global South. These part-time law
professors, although many times incredibly competent and committed to teaching and writing, can only dedicate a few
hours in the morning or at night to their academic endeavors. Likewise, the weaknesses of legal academia in the Global
South are related to the weaknesses of the university system in many of the region’s countries. The economic resources
received by the public university system have never been very high and have recently declined in many of them.
43 The universities of Sao Pablo, Andes, Católica, and Autónoma are among the ten best universities in Latin America.
See World’s Best Universities: Latin America, U.S. NEWS AND WORLD REPORT, available at
http://www.U.S.news.com/education/worlds-best-universities-rankings/best-universities-in-latin-america (last accessed
Jan. 17, 2012).
44 Of course, the legal products created by these (and other) universities are not formulated in a vacuum. They are
nourished by preexistent legal concepts and practices – many of which were not locally created. Yet this is the case with
the creation of all legal knowledge. The contributions of U.S. legal liberalism, for example, are nourished by the
European liberal tradition. Locke, Mill, and Kant are key figures in the work of authors like John Rawls and Ronald
Dworkin. Equally, many of the contributions of the Critical Legal Studies are based on the oeuvre of European authors
like Marx and Gramsci. New legal knowledge, as with all knowledge, is created only on the edges of the discipline, and
it is based on the preexisting conceptual structure. For understanding the process through which legal knowledge is
produced in the South, it is key to understand the process through which legal academic elites have been created
recently in the region. An important number of the members of these elites have studied in universities in the Global
North and, thus, have knowledge of both the local and global legal academic contexts.
45 See generally Manuel José Cepeda-Espinosa, Judicial Activism in a Violent Context: The Origin, Role, and Impact
of the Colombian Constitutional Court, 3 WASH. U. GLOBAL STUD. L. REV. 539 (2004).
46 See generally Alexandre dos Santos Cunha, The Social Function of Property in Brazilian Law, 80 FORDHAM L. REV.
1171 (2011).
47 See generally Liliana Obregón, Noted for the Dissent: The International Life of Alvaro Alvarez, 19 LEIDEN J. INT’L
L. 983 (2006) (Eng.).
48 See Alexandra Huneeus et al., Introduction in CULTURES OF LEGALITY: JUDICIALIZATION AND POLITICAL ACTIVISM
IN LATIN AMERICA 3, 3–5 (Alexandra Hunee, et al., eds., Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2010).
49 See generally Carlos Santiago Nino, INTRODUCCIÓN AL ANÁLISIS DEL DERECHO (Astrea[[AQ? Publisher?]]1984)
(Arg.); Genaro Carrió, NOTAS SOBRE DERECHO Y LENGUAJE ([[AQ? Publisher?]]1965) (Arg.).
50 See generally Diego López Medina, TEORÍA IMPURA DEL DERECHO (Legis[ [AQ? Publisher?]]2004) (Col.).
51 See Marcelo Gomes Justo and Helena Singer, Sociology of Law in Brazil: A Critical Approach, AM. SOCIOLOGIST,
Summer 2001, at 10–25.
52 See Werner Menski, Comparative Law in Global Context, in THE LEGAL SYSTEMS OF ASIA AND AFRICA 531–34
(Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2006).
53 Hauser Global Law School Program, Institute for International Law and Justice, Center for Human Rights and
Global Justice, Center on Law and Security, Global Public Service Law Project, Jean Monnet Center for International
and Regional Economic Law and Justice, Project on Transitional Justice.
54 China Law Center, Global Constitutionalism Seminar, Center for International Human Rights, Latin America Annual
Seminar, Middle East Legal Studies Seminar, The Honesty and Trust Project (Eastern Europe), and Yale Center for the
Study of Globalization.
55 East Asian Legal Studies Program, European Law Research Center, Human Rights Program, International Center for
Criminal Justice, Islamic Legal Studies Program, Program on International Financial Systems, International Law
Library.
56 Center for Transnational Legal Studies, London Summer Program, Asian Law and Policy Studies, Center for the
Advancement of the Rule of the Law in the Americas (CAROLA), Georgetown Human Rights Institute, Institute of
International Economic Law, Program on International Business and Economic Law.
57 Center for International and Comparative Law, Program in Refugee and Asylum Law, Program for Cambodian Law
and Development, European Legal Studies Program, Chinese Legal Studies, Japanese Legal Studies Program, South
Africa and Geneva Externship Programs.
58 The Berger International Legal Studies Program, The Clarke Center for International and Comparative Legal
Studies, The Clarke Program in East Asian Law and Culture, Mori, Hamada and Matsumoto Faculty Exchange, The
Clarke Middle East Legal Studies Fund.
59 The Global Law Workshop and Center for International and Comparative Law.
60 Center for National Security Law, Center for Oceans Law and Policy, International Human Rights Law Clinic,
Immigration Law Program.
61 Center for Contract and Economic Organization, Center for Chinese Legal Studies, Center for Japanese Legal
Studies, Center for Korean Legal Studies, European Legal Studies Center, The Center for Global Legal Problems,
Human Rights Institute, Parker School for Foreign and Comparative Law, International Moot Court.
62 Immigration Clinic, Transnational Worker Rights Clinic, Center for Human Rights, Institute for Transnational Law,
International Moot Court Competitions, Lozano Long Institute for Latin America Studies.
63 For a general analysis of the best programs in international law, see Denisse Romero, “Top Ten International Law
Schools in the U.S.A,” MACQUIL.COM GLOBAL PORTAL (Oct. 5, 2010), available at
http://www.macquil.com/articles/topintlaw.php.
64 The International and Comparative Law Quarterly, the Electronic Journal of Comparative Law, and the European
Journal of Legal Studies are prime examples of this tendency.
65 See Manuel José Cepeda-Espinosa, Judicial Activism in a Violent Context: The Origin, Role, and Impact of the
Colombian Constitutional Court, 3 WASH. U. GLOBAL STUD. L. REV. 529, 529–75, 649–91 (2004); Lynn Berat, The
Constitutional Court of South Africa and Jurisdictional Questions: In the Interest of Justice?, 3 INT’L J. CONST. L. 39
(2005); Burt Neuborne, The Supreme Court of India, 1 INT’L. J. CONST. L. 476 (2003).
66 See, for example, junio 26, 2009, Sentencia C-417 /09, M. P. Juan Carlos Henao Pérez (Col.) (freedom of speech);
Maneka Gandhi v. Union of India, AIR 1978 S.C. 597 (India) (limits to government’s restrictions to personal liberties);
Minister of Home Affairs and Another v. Fourie and Another, 2005 ZACC 19; 2006 (3) BCLR 355; 2006 (1) SA 524 (S.
Afr.) (gay rights); Lesbian and Gay Equality Project and Others v. Minister of Home Affairs and Others, 2005 ZACC
20; 2006 (3) BCLR 355; 2006 (1) SA 524 (S. Afr.) (gay rights).
67 See Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], enero 22, 2004, Sentencia T-025/04, M. P. Manuel José
Cepeda Espinosa.
68 In the Indian context, see M. H. Quraishi v. State of Bihar, A.I.R. 1958 S.C. 731; Abdul Jalil and Ors. v. State of U.P.
and Ors. on February 14, 1984, A.I.R. 1984 S.C. 882; Commissioner of Police and Ors v. Acharya J. Avadhuta and Anr.
on March 11,
2004, A.I.R. 2004 S.C. 2984. See also Gurpreet Mahajan, Indian Exceptionalism or Indian Model: Negotiating Cultural
Diversity and Minority Rights in a Democratic Nation-State, in MULTICULTURALISM IN ASIA 1–20 (Will Kymlicka and
Baogang He eds., Oxford University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2005).
69
In the South African context, see Soobramoney v. Minister of Health (Kwazulu-Natal) 1997 ZACC 17; 1998 (1) SA
765 (CC); 1997 (12) BCLR 1696 (CC); Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v. Grootboom and
Others 2000 ZACC 19; 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); 2000 (11) BCLR 1169 (CC); Minister of Health and Others v. Treatment
Action Campaign and Others (No 1) 2002 ZACC 16; 2002 (5) SA 703 (CC); 2002 (10) BCLR 1075 (CC); Khosa and
Others v. Minister of Social Development and Others, Mahlaule and Another v. Minister of Social Development 2004
ZACC 11; 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC); 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC).
70
See Kesavananda Bharati v. State of Kerala, 4 S.C.C. 225 (India) (1973).
71
The Colombian Constitutional Court, for example, has used the U.S. and European case law and literature on
balancing. See Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], septiembre 26, 1995, Sentencia T-425 /95, M. P.
Eduardo Vargas Muñoz; C.C., mayo 9, 1996, Sentencia T-198/96, M. P. Abelardo Gómez Restrepo; C.C., septiembre
18, 1997, Sentencia C-448/97, M. P. Alejandro Martínez Caballero; C.C., septiembre 25, 1997, Sentencia C-475/97, M.
P. Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C., mayo 20, 1998, Sentencia SU-225/98, M. P. Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C.,
octubre 20, 1998, Sentencia T-588/98, M. P. Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C., diciembre 16, 1998, Sentencia T-801/98,
M. P. Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C., octubre 6, 1999, Sentencia C-741/99, M. P. Fabio Moron Diaz; C.C., febrero 9,
2000, Sentencia C-110/00, M. P. Antonio Barrera Carbonell; C.C., marzo 29, 2000, Sentencia C-371/00, M. P. Carlos
Gaviria Díaz; C.C., abril 25, 2001, Sentencia C-648/01, M. P. Jaime Araujo Renteria; C.C., abril 10, 2004, Sentencia T-
1031/01, M. P. Rodrigo Escobar Gil; C.C., diciembre 5, 2001, Sentencia C-1287/01, Marco Gerardo Monroy Cabra;
C.C., octubre 29, 2002, Sentencia C-916/02, M. P. Manuel José Cepeda Espinosa; C.C., agosto 9, 2005, Sentencia C-
818/05, M. P. Rodrigo Escobar Gil; C.C., agosto 10, 2005, Sentencia C-822/05, M. P. Manuel José Cepeda Espinosa;
C.C., septiembre 7, 2005, Sentencia T-933/05, M. P. Rodrigo Escobar Gil; C.C., mayo 10, 2006, Sentencia C-355/06,
M. P. Jaime Araujo Rentería; C.C., marzo 21, 2007, Sentencia C-210/07, M. P. Marco Gerardo Monroy Cabra.
72
See, for example, the cases in which the Colombian Constitutional Court has used the Unconstitutional State of Affairs
doctrine. See Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], noviembre 20, 1997, Sentencia SU-599/97, M. P.
Jorge Aranga Mejía; C.C., marzo 5, 1998, Sentencia T-068/98, M. P. Alejandro Martinez Caballero; C.C., mayo 26,
1998, Sentencia SU-250/98, M. P. Alejandro Martinez Caballero; C.C., septiembre 23, 1998, Sentencia T-153/98, M. P.
Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C., enero 22, 2004, Sentencia T-025/04, M. P. Manuel José Cepida Espinosa.
73
See, for example, the Colombian Constitutional Court cases about the vital minimum and the principle of dignity. See
Corte Constitucional [C.C.] [Constitutional Court], enero 16, 1995 Sentencia T-005/95, M. P. Eduardo Cifuentes
Muñoz; C.C., enero 23, 1995, Sentencia T-015/95, M. P. Hernando Herrera Vergara; C.C., marzo 30, 1995, Sentencia T-
144/95, M. P. Eduardo Cifuentes Muñoz; C.C., mayo 8, 1995, Sentencia T-198/95, M. P. Alejandro Martínez
Caballero; C.C., octubre 4, 1996, Sentencia T-500/96, M. P. Antonio Barrera Carbonell; C.C., junio 4, 1998, Sentencia
T-284/98, M. P. Fabio Morón; C.C., febrero 4, 1999, Sentencia SU-062/99, M. P. Vladimiro Naranjo Mesa.
74
See, for example, People’s Union for Democratic Rights v. Union of India, 3 S.C.C. 235 (India) (1982). Regarding the
Public Interest Litigation Movement in India, see generally Upendra Baxi, Taking Suffering Seriously: Social Action
Litigation in the Supreme Court of India, 1985 THIRD WORLD LEGAL STUD. 107, 107–122; (1985); K. G. Balakrishnan,
Chief Justice of India, Address on the Growth of Public Interest Litigation in India, Singapore Academy of Law,
Fifteenth Annual Lecture (Oct. 8, 2008) 1–23; R. Sudarshan, Courts and Social Transformation in India, in COURTS
AND SOCIAL TRANSFORMATION IN NEW DEMOCRACIES: AN INSTITUTIONAL VOICE FOR THE POOR 154–67 (Roberto
Gargarella, et. al., eds., Ashgate[[AQ? Publisher?]]2006).
75
See Mark Tushnet, The Possibilities of Comparative Constitutional Law, 108 YALE L. J. 1225 (1999).
76
See James Whitman, The Neo-Romantic Turn, in COMPARATIVE LEGAL STUDIES: TRADITIONS AND TRANSITIONS 312
(Pierre Legrand and Roderick Munday, eds., Cambridge University Press[[AQ? Publisher?]]2003).
77
See Paul Kahn, Judging Judicial Review: Marbury in the Modern Era: Comparative Constitutionalism in a New Key,
101 MICH. L. REV. 2677 (2003).
78
The World Bank, “Data by Country,” available at http://data.worldbank.org/country (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
79
Id.
80
Id.
81
CONSTITUCIÓN POLÍTICA DE COLOMBIA [C.P.] art. 10 (Spanish is the official language of the country).
82
See U.S. Department of State, “2005 Report on International Religious Freedom: Colombia,” available at
http://www.state.gov/j/drl/rls/irf/2005/51632.htm (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
83
Government of India, “Census Data 2001: Religious Composition,” available at
http://censusindia.gov.in/Census_Data_2001/India_at_glance/religion.aspx (last accessed Feb. 12, 2002).
84
Statistics South Africa, “Census in Brief: Census 2001,” available at
http://www.statssa.gov.za/census01/html/C2001CensusBrief.asp at 14 (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012). The South African
Constitution recognizes eleven official languages. S. AFR. CONST. art. 6(1).
85
See U.S. Department of State, “2005 Report on International Religious Freedom: South Africa,” available at
http://www.state.gov/j/drl/rls/irf/2005/51496.htm (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
86
See Merryman and Pérez-Perdomo, supra note 19, at 141. [[AQ? Supra note 19?]]
87
The Law Library of Congress, “Introduction to India’s Legal System,” available at
http://www.loc.gov/law/help/india.php (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
88
http://ox.libguides.com/content.php?pid=167351andsid=1410025
89
See David Bilchitz, Constitutionalism, the Global South, and Economic Justice, Chapter 1, in this volume.
90
See S. AFR. CONST., Act 108 of 1996, S 10; CONSTITUCIÓN POLÍTICA DE COLOMBIA [C.P.] art. 1; INDIA
CONST. art. 21.
91
See CONSTITUCIÓN POLÍTICA DE COLOMBIA [C.P.] Title II; INDIA CONST. Part III-IV; S. AFR. CONST. Chapter II.
92
Central Intelligence Agency. Gini Index, “World Factbook,” available at https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-
world-factbook/fields/2172.html (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
93
Central Intelligence Agency, “Percentage below Poverty Line, World Factbook,” available at
https://www.cia.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook/fields/2046.html (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
94
Departamento Nacional de Estadística, “Colombia: Una Nación Multicultural,” available at
http://www.dane.gov.co/files/censo2005/etnia/sys/colombia_nacion.pdf at 20 (2007) (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).
95
See Daniel Bonilla, Introduction, in LA CONSTITUCIÓN MULTICULTURAL [The Multicultural Constitution] (Siglo del
Hombre-Universidad de los Andes- Instituto Pensar[[AQ? publisher?]]2007) (Col.).
96
See Gurpreet Mahajan, “Negotiating Cultural Diversity and Minority Rights in India,” available at
http://www.idea.int/publications/dchs/upload/dchs_vol2_sec3_4.pdf at 1.
97
See id.
98
Statistics South Africa, “Census in Brief: Census 2001,” available at
http://www.statssa.gov.za/census01/html/C2001CensusBrief.asp at 13 (last accessed Feb. 12, 2012).