Hamiduddin - CH 11-16
Hamiduddin - CH 11-16
Hamiduddin - CH 11-16
--12
CHAPTER XII
OWNERSHIP
87. D efinition of Ownership
Ownership is a general right over a particular thing. It has
been defined by Austin as "a right over a determinate thing,
indefinite in point of user, unrestricted in point of duration".
Prof. Salmond defines ownership in its most general and
comprehensive sense as a relation between a person and any right
that is vested in him. That which a man owns in this sense is in all
cases a right, that is, the subject-matter of ownership in this sense
extends to all classes of rights, whether proprietary or personal,
right in rem or in personam, in re-propria or in re-aliena, and it
applies not only to right in the strict sense, but also to liberties,
power and immunities. Thus, I own a debt, a mortgage, a right of
way over neighbours land, a patent, a copyright, a power of
appointment, as well as a house, in other words, ownership consists
of a bundle of rights. The sum total of all rights vested in a person
includes all those things, which are owned by any particular
individual—whether animate or inanimate. That which a man owns
is in all cases a right, and every right is owned. Thus, to own a
piece of land means in truth to own a particular kind of right,
namely, the right to exclusive use and enjoyment of that land.
In this generic sense, ownership is opposed to two other
possible relations between a person and a right i. e. possession and
encumbrance.
Possession
(1) A man may possess a right without owning it as where a
wrongful occupant of a land makes use of a right of way or
other easement appurtenant to it.
(2) A man may own a right without possessing it as where a
man has let out his house on rent to appurtenant.
(3) Finally, ownership and possession may be united in one
and the same person, as where the owner is himself in
possession of his house, the de jure and de facto relations
being co-existent and coincident.
In the second place, the ownership of a right is opposed to the
eiicutnbrance of it. The ownership of a right may be limited or
subject to an advrse righ t vested in different owner, which is
called encumbrance. A may be the owner of a property, B the
lessee of it, C the sub-lessee, D the first mortgagee of it, and E the
Ownership 163
second mortgagee, and so on. Although encumbrance is opposed to
ownership, every encumbrance is nevertheless himself the owner of
the encumbrance. In the above cases, B is the owner of the lease, C
is the owner of the sub-lease and D is the owner of the mortgage
and so on.
88. Corporeal and Incorporeal Ownership
The distinction between corporeal and incorporeal ownership is
the outcome of the distinction between corporeal and incorporeal
things. The term thing—Res--however, is used in three distinct
senses by legal writers:
(1) In its first and simplest application, it means merely a
material object, regarded as the subject-matter of a right, e.
g. land, house, book, coins, etc. which may be perceived
by the senses.
(2) In the second and wider sense, the term thing includes
every subject-matter of a right, whether material or not. In
this sense, things are either material or immaterial, e. g.
land and chattels as well as man's life, reputation, health
and liberty.
(3) In the third application, the term thing means whatever a
man owns as a part of his estate or property i. e an
easement right. Things, therefore, as objects of ownership
are of two kinds—Corporeal and Incorporeal.
A corporeal thing is a material thing and a subject-matter of
corporeal ownership and an incorporeal thing is the subject-matter
of incorporeal ownership, or rather it is any proprietary right except
the right of full dominion over a material object which is regarded
as corporeal ownership.
Therefore, corporeal ownership means ownership over things
which can be perceived by the external organs of senses, e. g. the
owner of a house owns a corporeal thing. Incorporeal things are
those that cannot be perceived by the sense, e. g. a debt, a patent
and so on, e. g. the owner of a patent owns an incorporeal thing.
But this distinction between corporeal and incorporeal ownership is
only the mode of expressing ownership, because in all cases,
ownership is a right and not an objed. We usually speak of
acquiring and transferring land, but strictly speaking, it is an
acquisition and transfer of the rights in land. We nevertheless speak
of ownership of a material object as corporeal ownership and that of
an immaterial or incorporeal thing as incorporeal ownership in a
narrow sense.
164 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
But the use of the word corporeal ownership in its corporeal
sense is not always possible. I may own material coins i.e. money in
my pocket, but as to the money which is due to me, I own not the
money but the right to it. In such a case, it is difficult to draw any
accurate line of demarcation between corporeal and incorporeal
ownership. So, in order not to create confusion, Salmond says that
the ownership of a material thing means the jus in re-propria in
respect of that thing. On the other hand, a right in respect of others
land i. e. a right of way, is called jus in re-aliena, which is always
incorpreal even though the object of the right is a corporeal thing.
In its full and normal compass, corporeal ownership is the
absolute right in its entirety of the lawful uses of a corporeal thing
which may, however, be limited or eaten up by the dominant right
vested in the encumbrances who are owner of their respective
encumbrances, such as, leases, mortgages, servitude, etc, which
form an example of duplicate ownership. We find such duplicate
ownership, in co-ownership and in trust and beneficial ownership.
89. Sole Ownership and Co-ownership
Sole Ownership—Sole ownership means ownership of one
person only. When a right is owned by one person only at a time, it
is called sole ownership.
C'o-ownership----li may often happen that z right is vested in
more than one person at one and the same time. This is called co-
ownership. For example, partners of a1Tthe properties which
constitute the partnership assets. The right owned by co-owners is
not divided between them, each owning a separate part. The right
is undivided unity, which is vested at the same time in more than
one person. If two partners have at their bank a credit balance of
Taka 100, there is one debt of Taka 100 owing by the bank to them
at once and not two separate debts of Taka 50 due to each of them
individually. Each partner is entitled to the whole sum, just as each
would owe to the bank the whole of ti-e banks overdraft. As soon
as each of the two co-owners begins to .wn a part instead of the
whole, the co-ownership is dissolved into sole ownership by the
process known as partition. So. co-ownership arises when the same
right is owned by two or more persons at the same time. Each is the
owner of the whole of the right and not of part of it as partners,.
Thus, the right owned by co-owners is an undivided unity.
Co-ownership assumes two different forms distinguished as—
(a) ownership in common and (b) joint ownership. The most
important difference between the two relates to the effect of death of
one of the co-owners.
Ownership 165
Ownership in common—In this case the right of a deceased cc-
owner passes to his heirs or administrators and not to the surviving
CO-owners.
Joint ownership—The most important incident of joint
ownership is survivorship. If a joint owner dies, his interest passes
to the surviving owners and not to his heirs or legal
representatives.
90. Trust and beneficial ownership
Trust property is that which is owned by two persons at the
same time. It is created when a property is held' oñè person not
for his own benefit but for the benefit of someone else. The owner of
the property is under an obligation and is bound to hold it or use
his ownership for the benefit of the other.The former in whom the
property is vested is called the trustee and his ownership is called
the trust ownership, the latter for whose benefit the trust is created
is called the beneficiary and his ownership is called the beneficial
ownership.iAlthough, in law, the trustee is the legal owner, but he
has no right to make use of his ownership for his own benefit and
his right is nominal rather than real. Thus, a trust is a curious
instance of duplicate ownership, the trustee being the legal or
nominal while the beneficiary being the beneficial owner of the
property.
As between the trustee and the beneficiary the property
belongs to the latter, but as between the trustee and the third
persons, the fiction prevails and the trustee is regarded as the
owner.
Trust ownership and beneficial ownership are independent of
each other. Either of them may be transferred, while the other
remains unaffected Similarly, either kind of ownership may be
independently encumbered.
The purpose of trusteeship is that it is created in order to protect
the rights of those persons who are incapable of protecting their
interests themselves. Such persons are:
(1) Infants, lunatics and disqualified proprietors.
(2) Unborn persons.
(3) Large number of persons commonly interested in a matter.
(4) Persons having conflicting interests in the same property.
91. Legal and equitable ownership
Legal ownership is that which has its origin in the rules of
common law, while equitable ownership is that which proceeds
from the rules of equity, divergent from the common law. The
166 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
distinction between legal and equitable ownership is still
maintained in spite of the fusion of Common Law and Equity by
the Judicature Act of 1873. The distinction between legal and
equitable ownership is not identical with that as existing between
legal and equitable rights mentioned in a previous chapter. The
equitable ownership of a legal right is different from legal
ownership of an equitable right. For example, when a debt is orally
assigned by A to B. A remains the legal owner of it nonetheless,
but B becomes the equitable owner of it. But there is only one debt
s before, though it has now two owners. So a mortgage is a legal
right and the mortgagee owns it legally, but at the same time the
mortgagor owns it equitably, because Equity has made the
mortgagor the owner of the equity of recmption. Hence, the
ownership of the equity of redemption in a legal mortgage is the
equitable ownership of a legal right. Similarly, the ownership of an
equitable mortgage is a different thing from the equitable
ownership of a legal mortgage, because in the former there is only
one owner (i. e. the mortgagor) whereas in the latter there are two
distinct owners, one being the legal and the other equitable owner.
Further, the distinction between legal and equitable ownership
is not equivalent to that between trust and beneficial ownership. It
is true that in a trust and beneficial ownership, all the elements of a
legal and beneficial ownership are present. A trustee is generally
the legal owner and a beneficiary the equitable owner. But this is
not always true. A trustee may be an equitable owner. An
equitable owner (i. e. the beneficiary) might himself be trustee for
another person. Thus, when the equity of redemption in a legal
mortgage is settled upon trust, neither the trustee nor the
beneficiary possesses anything more than equitable ownership. The
legal ownership remains outstanding with the mortgagee.
92. Vested and Contingent ownership
Vested ownership—Ownership is said to have been vested
when the title of the owner with respect to any particular right is
perfect and complete and nothing more is required to be done to
complete the owner's title. The right is absolutely owned by the
owner who has an inimediatc right of present enjoyment or a
present, certain right of future enjoyment. For example, a property
is transferred to A for life and after his death to B. Here B has a
vested ownership in the property during the lifetime of A although
Ownership 167
the enjoyment is postponed till his death i. e. B has present certain
right of future enjoyment on the death of A, and if B dies during
the lifetime of A, the heirs of B will get the property. In technical
language B's interest is vested interest, though not vested in
possession; it becomes vested in possession only on the death of A
Contingent own ership—Ownership is contingent when the
owner's title to any right is yet imperfect and incomplete but is
capable of becoming perfect on the fulfillment of some condition, i.
e. some further event is necessary to complete or make it perfect.
Ownership is contingent when by virtue of a right, which is owned
and vested, a further right will be owned and vested on the
happening of some future event which may or may not occur. For
example, a property is transferred to A for life and after his death to
B if he is then alive, but if B is then dead to C. Here both B and C
have both contingent ownership in the property. Ownership of B is
conditional to his surviving A, while that of C is conditional to the
death of B during the lifetime of A and also to his surviving A.
Similarly, if property is left to A for life, remainder to B if he
attains the age of twenty-one at the time of A's death, B has two
conditions to fulfill before the right is vested in him. Because, here
B should not only have been alive at the time of A's death but also
should have attained the age of twenty one. This is what is called
the rule of 'double possibility'.
It is to be noticed that the contingent ownership of a right is
something more than a simple chance or possibility of becoming the
owner of it. It is more than a mere spes acquisitions. I have no
contingent ownership of a piece of land merely because I may buy
it if I so wish or its owner may leave it to me by his will.
Contingent ownership is based not upon the mere possibility of
future acquisition but upon the present existence of an inchoate or
incomplete title.
The conditions on which contingent ownership depends are
termed conditions precedent to distinguish them from another kind
known as conditions subsequent. A condition precedent is one by
the fulfillment of which an inchoate title is completed. In this case, I
acquire absolutely what I have already acquired conditionally. But
ownership subject to a condition subsequent is not contingent but
vested. Contingent ownership is that which is not yet vested but
may become so in the future; while ownership subject to a condition
168 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
subsequent is already vested, but may be divested or destroyed in
the future for non-fulfillment of the said conditions.
The distinction between the two kinds of ownership is shortly
this
(1) A vested ownership does not depend upon the fulfillment
of any condition; it creates an immediate right (i. e. the
vested interest) though the enjoyment (i. e. the vested in
possession) may be postponed to a future date. But a
contingent ownership is solely dependent upon the
fulfillment of the incumbent condition so that in case of non-
fulfillment of the condition the ownership may fall through.
(2) A vested ownership is transferable as well as heritable. But
a contingent ownership is inalienable and non-transferable.
(3) A vested ownership is not defeated by the death of the
owner before he obtains possession. If the vested owner dies
before actual enjoyment, the ownership with pass on to his
heirs. But a contingent ownership fails if the owner dies
before the happening of the specified event. A contingent
ownership may, however, ripen into a vested ownership on
the fulfillment of the contingency.
CHAPTER XIII
POSSESSION
93. Introduction
Since the time of Roman Lawyers, who brought their usual
acumen to the analysis of the essential nature of possession, the
problem has formed the subject of voluminous literature, for, its
practical importance is not less than its difficulty.
Salmond says that in the whole range of legal theory there is no
conception more difficult to understand than that of possession.
Because, the legal consequences which flow from the acquisition
and loss of possession are many and serious. Possession, for
example, is evidence of ownership; the possessor of a thing is
presumed to be the owner of it, and may put all other claimants to
proof of their title. Long possession is a sufficient title even to
property which originally belonged to another. The transfer of
possession is one of the chief methods of transferring ownership.
The first possession of a thing which as yet belongs to none is a
good title of right. Even is respect of property already owned, the
wrongful possession of it is a good title for the wrongdoer, as
against all the world except the true owner. Possession is also of
such efficacy that a possessor may in many cases confer a good title
on another, even though he has none himself, as when I obtain a
bank note from a thief, or goods from a factor who disposes of them
in fraud of his principal. Moreover, in English law possession is a
good title of right against anyone who cannot show a better. Many
legal systems treat possession as a provisional or temporary title
even against the true owner himself. Even a wrongdoer, who is
deprived of his possession, can recover it from any person
whatever, simply on the ground of his possession. Even the true
owner, who forcibly takes his own, may be forced to restore it to the
wrongdoer and then proceed in due course of law for the recovery
of the thing on the ground of his ownership. These are some of the
results which the law attributes to possession, rightfi1 or wrongful,
which are sufficient to show the importance of the conception of
possession, and the necessity of an adequate analysis of its essential
nature.
94. Possession if Fact and in Law
The law is the theory of things, as received and acted upon
within the Courts of justice, and this theory may or may not
conform to the reality of things outside. The eye of law does not
infallibly see things as they are. Partly by deliberate designs and
170 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
partly by the errors and accidents of historical developments, law
and fact, legal theory and the truth of things, may fail in complete
coincidence. With regard to possession also there is the possibility of
more or less serious divergences between legal principles and the
truth of things and between the law and the fact of possession,
partly intentional and avowed, partly accidental and unavowed. So,
not everything which is recognised as possession by the law needs
be such in truth , and in fact. And conversely, the law, by reasons,
good or bad, may be moved to exclude from the limits of the
conception facts which rightly fall within them. There are three
possible cases in this respect. First, possession may and usually does
exist both in fact and i n law. The law recognises as possession all
that is so in fact and nothing that is not so in fact unless there is
some special reason to the contrary. Secondly, possession may exist
in fact but not in law. e. g. possession by a servant of his master's
property, is for some purposes not recognises as such by the law
and he is then said to have detention or custody rather than
possession. Thirdly, possession may exist in law but not in fact; that
is to sa y, for some special reasons the law attributes the results of
possession to someone who as a matter of fact does not possess. The
possession thus fictitiously attributed to him is termed as
constructive. The Roman lawyers distinguished possession in fact as
possession naturalis, and possession in law as possessio civilis. In
consequence of this divergence, partly intentional and avowed, and
partly accidental and unavowed, between the law and the fact of
possession, it is impossible to formulate any abstract theory which
might completely harmonise with the detailed rules to be found in
any concrete body of rules and with the different aspects of the
concept of possession.
95. Corporeal and Incorporeal possession
As in the case of ownership so also in the case of possession a
distinction is to be drawn between corporeal and incorporeal
possession.
Corporeal possession is the possession of a material object, e. g.
a house, a farm, a piece of money. It is the continuing exercise of a
claim to the exclusive use of a tangible material object. Thus,
corporeal possession is a continuing relation between a person and a
material object. But incorporeal possession is the possession or
continuing exercise of a claim to anything other than a tangible
material thing, e. g. a way over another mans land, a right to light,
a title of rank, an office of profit, and such like. All these may be
possessed as well as owned. The possessor may or may not be the
Possession 171
owner of them and the owner of them may or may not be in
possession of them, Incorporeal possession includes—
(a) Possession of intellectual or immaterial objects which have
got only notional existence i. e. some interest or advantage
unconnected with the use of material objects. Such as,
goodwill, trade mark, a patent, or an office of profit; or
(b) Possession of encumbrances, i. e. non-exclusive use of
material object, such as right of way, right to light, etc.
Incorporeal possession is usually called or generally known as
the possession of a right. Hence, it may be defined as the
continuing exercise of a right and corporeal possession is
distinguished from it as the possession of thing.
As in the case of corporeal possession, so also in the case of
incorporeal possession, the two elements viz, animus (mental
element i. e. intention to possess a thing), and corpus (physical or
objective element) are necessary, that is, actual continuous use and
enjoyment is essential. In essence, therefore, the two forms of
possession are identical. Hence, possession in its full compass,
including both corporeal and incorporeal, may be defined as the
continuing exercise of any claim or right.
In the case of corporeal possession, the possession of a material
object is essential to constitute possession. In other words, the
possession of a material object is the continuing exercise of a claim to
the conclusive use of it. Actual use of it, however, is not essential. I
may lock my watch in a safe instead of keeping it in my pocket,
and though I do not look at it for twenty years. I remain in
possession of it nonetheless. In the case of incorporeal possession, on
the contrary, actual continuous use and enjoyment of it is essential,
as being the only mode of possession. I can acquire and retain
possession of a right of way only through actual and repeated use of
it. In the case of incorporeal things continuing non-use of it is
inconsistent with possession, though in the case of corporeal things
it is consistent with it.
Some writers are of opinion that genuine possession is always
corporeal, and incorporeal possession is quasi-possession-
something which is less than possession. So, a doubt arises as to
whether incorporeal possession is possession at all. To meet the
difficulty. Salmond uses the term 'possession' in a wider sense as to
include both corporeal and incorporeal possession. He observes.
"The two forms do in truth belong to a single genus. The true idea
of pos session is wider than that of corporeal possession, just as
the idea of ownership is wider than that of corporeal ownership".
172 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
96. Two elements in the conception possession
According to English law, possession involves two distinct
elements, one of which is called the mental or subjective element,
the other is called the physical or objective element. These two
elements were distinguished by Roman lawyers as animus
possidendi U. e. intention to possess) and corpus of possession
(physical power). "Neither of these", says Salmond, "is sufficient by
itself; possession begins only with their union, and lasts only till
one or the other disappears".
First element, namely, animus possidendi—The first conception
of possession, namely, the animus possidendi consists in the
intention of a person to possess or appropriate for himself the
exclusive use of the thing possessed. Mere possession without the
intention to claim possession over it is ineffective. A person does not
possess a field because he is walking over it unless he has the
intention of excluding others from using it. I may be alone in a
room with money lying on the table that does not belong to me. I
have absolute physical power to appropriate it but I have no
possession of it because I have no intention to possess it.
As to the nature of animus possidendi, Salniond makes the
following observations:
(1) The intention to possess a thing need not necessarily be a
claim of right. It may consciously be wrongful. The thief has
possession of it no less than that of the real owner. The
possessor of a thing is not he who has, or believes that he
has, a right to it, but he who intends to act as if he has such
a right.
(2) The claim of the possessor must be exclusive, but this power
of exclusion need not be absolute. Thus, I may possess my
land notwithstanding the fact that some other person, or
even the public at large, possess a right of way over it. I
intend to exclude all alien interference except such as
justified by the limited and special right of easement vested
in others.
(3) The animus possidendi need not amount to a claim or intent
to use it as owner, Thus, a tenant, a borrower or a pledge
may have possession no less real than the owner himself.
(4) The animus possidendi need not be a claim on one's own
behalf. I may possess a thing either on my own account or
on account of another. A servant, a trustee or an agent may
have true possession, though he claims exclusive use of the
thing on behalf of another than himself.
Possession 173
(5) The animus possidendi need not be specific but may be
general. Thus, I possess all the books in my library, though
I may have forgotten the existence of many of them. That is
to say, animus does not necessarily involve the continuous
and present knowledge of the thing possessed.
It might be thought in this connection that when a person is in
possession of a receptacle, such as a box, bag, cabinet or envelope,
his possession of the receptacle automatically gives him possession
of the contents. This is not, however, always so, at any rate for the
purpose of the law of larceny (theft) as inferred from the following
decided English cases
(1) In Merry & Green (7 M & W 623), the plaintiff purchased a
bureau at auction, and subsequently discovered money in it,
hidden in a secret drawer and belonging to the vendor. The
plaintiff, thereupon, appropriated the money; and it was held that
in doing so, he committed theft, as he obtained possession of the
money not when he innocently purchased the bureau, but when he
fraudulently abstracted the contents of it.
(2) In Cartwright v. Green (7 R R 99), a bureau was delivered
for the purposes of repairs to a carpenter, who discovered in a secret
drawer money which he converted to his own use. It was held that
he committed theft by wrongfully taking the money in his
possession.
(3) In R. v. Hudson (1943 K B 448), the prisoner received a letter
that was intended for someone else. He kept it for some days and
then, on opening of it found inside a cheque which he appropriated
to his own use. The Court of Criminal Appeal held that he was
guilty of theft.
Second element, namely, corpus of possession—To constitute
possession, the animus i. e the intention to possess is not in itself
sufficient, it must be accompanied by the physical ability to obtain
and retain possession, which is called corpus of possession. Corpus
involves the realisation of two things:
(a) In relation to the other persons there should exist the
present exclusion of all alien interference, and
(b) In relation to the thing possessed there should exist some
sort of security that no one will interfere with my enjoyment
of thing possessed.
These two elements of the corpus of possession are stated by
Salmond under two headings:
(1) Relation of the possessor to other persons, and
(2) The relation of the possessor to the thing possessed.
174 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
97. Relation of Possessor to rther persons
In order to constitute possessior over tangible object, the
relation of the possessor to other perso is must he such as to warrant
a security for their non-interference. 1 am in possession of a thing
when the facts of the case are such as to create a probable
expectation that I will not be interfered with. Absolute security is
not needed. Any measure of security is sufficient which reasonably
satisfies the intention to possess. All that is necessary is that I may
count on the continuous enjoyment of the things without
interruption. Such a measure of security may be derived from the
following sources:
W Physical strength of the possessor—This includes the
power to exclude all alien interference, if need be, by
physical force. Thus, if I own a purse of money and lock it
up in my safe. I certainly have possession of it. This
physical power constitutes an effective guarantee of
enjoyment.
(ii) Personal presence of the possessor—The physical power of
the possessor may, in many cases, be absent, but still the
very presence of the possessor is sufficient to constitute
possession. Thus, a little child has no physical power as
against a strong man, yet it possesses the money in its
hand. A dying man may acquire or retain possession by
his personal presence, but certainly not by any physical
power left in him.
(iii) Secrecy—If a person wants to keep a thing safe from
interference by others, he may hide it. He will thereby
gain reasonable guarantee of enjoyment and possession of
the thing and lust as effectually as the strong man fully
arrned.
(iv) Custom—Usage or custoili secures a guarantee against
interference, because the habit or tendency of mankind is
to observe or acquiesce in the established usage, e, g.
previous occupation of land, if not proved to be disturbed,
is the evidence of present possession.
(v) Respect for r4g1tfil claim—People posses greeer regard
for rightful claims than wro ngful ones. Hence a general
belief in the rightfulness of possession will hicrease Its
security.
(vi) Manifestation of intention to possess (aninu18 dominO—If
the intention to possess is mae clear, the security is
greatly increased. This consists pf not only manifesting an
Possession 175
intention of possession, but also the manifestation of
ownership over the thing possessed.
(Vii) The protection afforded by the possession of other thing—
Thus, the possession of a house may confer the possession
of all the things inside the house. The possession of a box
or packet may bring with it the possession of its contents.
98. Relation of possessor to the thing possessed
The second element of the corpus of pcssession is the relation of
the possessor to the thing possessed namely, that the claim must not
only be recognised by other persons, but also the claim must be
realised by the possession of the thing itself. There must be no
barrier between the person who claims possession and the thing
possessed to prevent his claim to the use of it, e. g. if I desire to
catch fish, I have no possession of them till I have them securely in
my net or my line. Again possession once gained may be lost by
the loss of my power to use that thing, e. g. when the bird in my
cage has flown away or when I have dropped my jewel box in the
sea. But so long as my expectation of its enjoyment is reasonable, It
amounts to present possession. Thus, my cow or my dog may have
lost its way, but it will probably return. I may have mislaid a book
in the house, but if I search hard for it, it will be found. These
things, therefore, I still possess though I cannot Jay my hand on
them at will.
99. Nature of possession
According to the English law, animus (intention) and corpus
(physical power) are the two elements which constitute possession.
Actual physical detention of the thing is unnecessary, e. g. when a
person goes out for a walk, he does not cease to possess the
furniture in his house. Neither need the power of exclusion be
actual; a child has no actual power of excluding an adult from
seizing the doll in her hand, but this does not prevent her from
possessing it. We must say that the nature of possession is not
strictly a question of fact, nor one of law, but a question of wired
law and fact. We propose to give here extracts of some of the
English cases on the point.
(1) In Bridges v. Ha wkes worth (21 Q 13 75), a parcel of bank
notes was dropped on the floor of the defendants shop,
where they were found by the plaintiff, a customer. Itws
held that the plaintiff had a good title to them as against the
defendant. For, it was the plaintiff and not the defendant,
who wa s the first to acquire possession of them. The
176 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
defendant has not the animus, for he did not know of their
existence. There the question decided was one of law.
(2) In T. V. Moor (1861 L & C 0, a bank note was dropped in
the shop of the prisoner, who on discovering it, picked it up
and converted it to his own use, well knowing that the
owner could be found. It was held that he was rightly
convicted of larceny (theft), from which it follows that he
was not in possession of the note until he actually
discovered it.
(3) In Elwis v, Brigg Gas Co. (33 Ch. D 562), the defendant-
Company took a lease of land from the plaintiff for erecting
gas work, and in the process of excavation found a
prehistoric boat six feet below the surface. It was held that
the boat belonged to the landlord and not to the tenant who
discovered it. According to the opinion of the Chatty, J,. it
was immaterial that the landlord wat, not aware of the
existence of the boat, all the same he was the first to possess
it.
(4) Similarly, in South Staffordshire Water Co. V. Sharmen, the
defendant was employed by the plaintiff-Company to clear
a pond upon their land and in doing so he found certain
gold rings at the bottom of it. It was held that the Company
was in possession of these things and that the defendant,
therefore, acquired no right to them.
Thus, whether the possession of one thing will bring with it the
possession of another that is thus connected with it, depend s , upon
the circumstances of the particular case. A chattel may be upon my
land, yet I have no possession of it unless the animus and corpus
both exist. I may have no animus as when by neighbours sheep,
with or without my knowledge, stray into my 'and. There may be
no corpus, as when I lose a jewel in my garden, an4 tannot find it
3gan. There may neither be corpus nor animus as when unknown
to me there is a jar of coins buried somewhere upon my estate.
100. Concur re nt possession
It is often expressed that two persons cannot be in possession of
the same thing at the same time. As a general rule, this is true
because exclusiveness is the essence of true possession, an d two
hostile claimants cannot both have possession at once. t is a
fundamental principle of possession that only one person can be in
possession of the samething at the same time. But claims which are
not adverse to each other may co-exist. Thus, concurrent or
Possession 177
duplicate possession is possible when the claims are not adverse, e.
g. owners in common may both be in possession of the same thing.
Iollowing are the cases of duplicate or concurrent possession:
Mediate and immediate possession—Mediate and immediate
possession co-exist in respect of the same thing; e. g. a landlord by
letting a house to a tenant may retain mediate possession While the
immediate possession is vested in the tenant. One person may
possess a thing for and on account of another. In such cases, the
former is in possession of the thing on anothers behalf. The
possession thus held by one man through a tenant, servant,
licensee, etc. is called mediate, while that is acquired or retained
directly and personally may be distinguished as direct or
immediate possession. If! myself go and purchase a book, I acquire
immediate possession of it; but if I send my servant to buy it for
me, I acquire a mediate possession of it through him until the book
is in my hand when it becomes immediate.
Joint possession—Two or more persons may possess the same
thing in common, as they may own it in common, e. g. possession
by the owners in common of the undivided joint family property.
Corporeal and Incorporeal possession—Corporeal or incorporeal
possession may co-exist in respect of the same thing. Thus, A may
possess the land while B may possess a right of way over it at the
same time.
101. Acquisition of Possession
The component elements necessary to constitute possession are
animus times corpus. Possession is acquired when these two
elements come into co-existence and the right of possession ceases
with the loss of either of the elements. There are two modes of
acquisition of corporeal possession namely, (1) Taking and (2)
Delivery.
Taking—Taking is the acquisition of possession without the
consent of the previous owner and the thing taken may or may not
have been in possession of the previous owner. Taking may be of
two kinds:
(1) Rightful—When there is no previous possessor of a thing,
taking possession of it is wrongful.
(IL) !'Vrig1ul—When there is a previous possessor of a thing,
hking possession of it (without consent) is wrongful.
Deivery—Delivery, on the other hand, is the acquisition of
possession with the consent of the previous owner. It is of two kinds
being distinguished as (i) actual and (ii) constructive delivery.
—13
178 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
Actual
Actual delivery is the transfer of immediate possession. It is of
two kinds:
(a) Where mediate possession is not retained by the transferor i.
e. both mediate and immediate possession are delivered to th
transferee, e. g. sale.
(b) Where mediate possession is retained by the transferor only
the immediate possession is delivered to the transferee, e. g. loan of
a furniture.
Constructive
Constructive delivery, on the other hand, is all that which is not
actual. It arises in those cases where the law construes that there has
been a delivery of possession though there is no actual delivery. It
is of three kinds
(a) The first form of constructive possession is that which the
Roman lawyers termed as traditio brev manu; for which
Salmond finds no English equivalent. It consists of the
surrender of mediate possession of a thing to one who is
already in immediate possession of the same, e. g. A lends
a watch to B and afterwards (while B still retains it) sells the
same to B. No fresh delivery is necessary.
(b) The second form of constructive delivery is that which s
called constitum possessorium (i.e. an agreement touching
possession). This is converse of traditio brevi manu. It is the
transfer of mediate possession while the immediate
possession is still in the hand of the transferor, e. g. A
purchases goods from B and there is an agreement betwe*n
them that B shall hold the goods on behalf of A. The goods
are construed as delivered to A.
(c) The third form of constructive delivery is that which is
known as attornrnent. This is the transfer of mediate
possession while the immediate possession is in the hands
of third person, e. g. X has kept his goods in the warehouse
of Y and then sells them to B. Thereafter. Y agrees to hold
the goods on behalf of B and not for X. Y retains the
immediate possession while the mediate possession has
been transferred to B.
102. Relation between possession and ownership
"Possession", says Ihering, "is the objective realisation of
ownership". Possession is in fact what ownership is in right.
J-iistor1cI1y the conception of possession is anterior to that of
ownership.
Possession 179
Possession is the de facto exercise of a claim, ownership is the de
jure recognition of it. A thing is owned by one when his claim is
maintained by the will of the State as expressed in the law, it is
possessed by him when his claim is maintained by his own self-
assertive will. Ownership is the guarantee of law, possession is the
guarantee of facts. Possession, therefore, is thee facto counterpart
of ownership.
Possession is the external form in which rightful claims
normally manifest themselves. Ownership tries to realise itself in
possession and possession endeavours to justify itself as ownership
The law of prescription determines the process by which, through
the influence of time, possession without title ripens into ownership,
and ownership without possession withers away and dies. The two
things tend mutually to coincide. The separation of these two
conceptions is an exceptional incident, due to accident, wrong or the
special nature of claims in question.
Generally, ownership and possession have the same subject-
matter. Whatever may by owned may also be possessed, and
whatever may be possessed may also be owned. To this general
statement there are two exceptions:
(1) There are certain claims which may be realised and
exercised in fact without receiving any recognition or
protection from law, there being no right vested either in
the claimant or anyone else. For example, men might
possess copyright, trade marks and other forms of
monopoly, even though the law erfuses to defend those
interests as legal rights. Claims to them may only be
realised de facto.
(2) Conversely, there are many rights which can be owned but
are not capable of being possessed. These rights are
transitory which do not admit of continuing exercise nor of
possession either. A creditor, for example, does not possess
the debt that is due to him, but he owns the right to the
debt which is transitory, because this right, when exercised,
is wholly fulfilled or destroyed. It is for this reason that
personal rights do not admit of possession. There are,
however, certain obligations which admit of possession
provided that they are of such a nature as to involve a
series of repeated acts of performance. Thus, I may possess a
right of way throu gh repeated acts of use just as I may
180 Jurisprud 'nce & Comparative Legal Theory
possess a right of light or support through continuous
enjoyment. Thus, repeated exercise of right in this respect is
equivalent to continued exercise.
103. Possessory Remedies
Possessory remedies are those legal remedies which are
available for the protection of possession even against ownership,
while those available for the protection of ownership itself may be
distinguished as proprietary.
In English law, possession is a good title of right against any
one who cannot show a better. A wrongful possessor has the right of
an owner with respect to all persons except the earlier possessor or
the true owner himself. Even a wrongdoer, who is deprived of his
possession, can recover it from any other person whatever, simply
on the ground of his possession. Even the true owner, who takes his
own, may be forced to restore it to the wrongdoer. He must first
give up possession and then proceed on due course of law for the
recovery of the thing on the ground of his ownership. The intention
of the law is that every possessor shall be entitled to retain and
recover his possession, until deprived of it by a judgment according
to law. In old times, possession was generally, guarded against by
means of violent self-help. But the tendency of the modern time is
to attain this end by a much more satisfactory and reasonable way.
It adjusts the burden of proof of ownership with perfect equity,
without recourse to any such anomaly as the protection of the
possessor against the owner. This it does by the operation of the
three following rules
(1) Prior possession is prima facie proof of title. Even in the
ordinary proprietary action a claimant need do nothing
more than prove that he had an older possession than that
of the defendant, for the law will presume from the prior
possession a better title. The maxim is, qui prior est
tempore potior est jure (where two rights are in conflict, the
earlier one prevails).
(2) A defendani is always at liberty to rebut this presumption
by proving that the better title is in himself,
(3) A defendant will not be permitted to set ep the defence jus
tertii, as it is called, that is to say, he W ill not be heard to
allege as against the plaintiff's claim, that neither the
plaintiff nor he himself but some third person is We true
owner.
CHAPTER XIV
PERSONS
104. Nature of personality
So far as legal theory is concerned, a person is any being whom
the law regards as capable or rights or duties. Any person that is so
capable is a person, whether a human being or not, and no being
that is not so capable is a person, even though he be a man. Persons
are the substances of which rights and duties are the attributes. It is
only in this respect that persons possess juridical significance and
this is the exclusive point of view from which personality receives
legal recognitions.
Salmond says that personality is a wider and vaguer term than
humanity. In the law, there may be men who are not persons
slaves, for example, are destitute of legal personality in any system
which regards them as incapable of rights or liabilities. Like cattle
they are things and the objects of rights; not persons and the
subjects of rights. Conversely, there are , in the law, persons who
are not men. A joint stock company or a municipal corporation is a
person in legal contemplation. So, also, in Hindu Law, idols are
legal persons which has been recognised by the Privy Council in
the case of Pramatha Nath Mullick v. Pradyumno Kumar Mullick
(1925) L R 52 IA 245. It is true that they are only fictitious, not real
persons but they are not men at all, either fictitious or real.
Hence in legal theory, whatever is capable of rights and duties
is a person. Persons so defined are of two kinds, distinguishable as
(1) natural and (2) legal.
Natural person—A natural person is a living human being who
is recognised by the state as capable of rights or duties, that is to
say, a person who has got a Status. A natural person must be (1) a
living human being and (2) he must be recognised by the State as a
person, that is to say, he must not be a slave or must not have
suffered civil death.
Legal or artifical or juristic person—An artificial or legal
person is such a group of human beings or a mass of property, as is,
in the eye of law, capable of rights and duties. A legal person is
any subject-matter or beings, real or imaginary, other than a
human being to which the law attributes personality by was of
fiction.
The distinction between natural and artificial person is shortly
this-
182 jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
(1) The existence of artificial person is dependent on law, while
the existence of natural person is independent of law.
(2) The duration of existence of artificial person is often much
longer than the natural period of human life.
(3) Natural person acts for himself; while artificial person can act
only through authorised agent.
<a.105 Legal person : its creation and extinction's.
A legal person is any subject-matter other than a human being
to which the law attributes personality. Therefore, legal persons are
creatures of the law owing their very existence to the law alone. The
law, in creating legal persons, always does so by personifying some
real thing. Such a perspn has to this extent a real existence, and it is
his personality alone that is fictitious. The thing personified may be
termed the corpus or the body of legal person so created, it is the
body into which the law infuses the animus of a fictitious
personality.
Although every legal personality involves personification the
converse is not true. In popular language, for the sake of simplicity
of thought and speech, a subject matter is sometimes described as a
person even though the law will not treat it as a legal person. We
speak, for instance, of the estate of a deceased person as if it were
itself a person. We say that it owes debts or hs debts owing to it.
Similarly, we speak of a firm, a club, a jury, a Bench of judges, a
public meeting, etc. as distinct persons. The law, however,
recognises no legal personality in such cases. Legal personality is
not reached until the law itself invests a particular fictitious being
with legal right.
Creation—An artificial person is created by the law giving to a
group of persons or mass of property the character of a legal person.
The legal character is conferred when the said gro1p or mass
satisfies certain legal provisions. Hence, they are created (1) by
charter granted by the executive authority, and/or (2) by special
law.
Extinction—An artificial person comes to an end—
(1)by failure of its component part;
(2) by judicial proceedings leading up to the winding up of a
company;
(3) by forfeiture, and
(4) by surrender of privileges.
Persons 183
106. Classes of juristic persons
Legal persons, being arbitrary creations of the law, may be of
as many kinds as the law pleases. English law recognises only three
classes of legal persons—(1) Corporations, (2) Trade Unions and (3)
Friendly Societies
(1) Corporations—A corporation is a group or series of persons
which by a legal fiction is regarded and treated as a real
person. The creation and extinction of a corporation is
determined by law.
(2) Trade Union—A Trade Union is an association of workmen
or employers for the purpose, among other things, of
collective bargaining; in England, it has been accorded
legal personality by judicial decision.
(3) A friendly society—It is a voluntary association formed for
the purpose of raising, by the subscription of the members,
funds out of which advances may be made for the natural
relief and the maintenance of the members and their
families in sickness, infancy, old age, or infirmity.
But in pther systems of Jurisprudence their are several distinct
varieties of legal persons of which three may be selected for special
mention
(1) Corporations—The first class of legal persons consists of
Corporations as already defined, namely, those which are
constituted by the personification of groups or series of
individuals. The individuals forming the corpus of the legal
person are called its members. We shall consider this form
of legal personality more particularly in the sequel.
(2) Institutions—The second class is that in which the law
attributes fictitious personality not to the group or series of
persons connected with it but to the institution itself, such as
Hospital, Library, College, Church, University and regards
them as persons. But in English law, the legal personality is
attributed to the group of persons connected with it,
namely, the Chancellor, Vice-Chancellor, Fellows and
Graduates, etc.
(3) Funds—The third kind of legal person is that in which the
law attributes fictitious personality to some fund or property
devoted to special use, such as, a trust estate, a charitable
fund, the property of a dead man or of bankrupt. But in
English law, the legal personality is attributed not to the
fund or the estate but to the body of persons who
administer it, namely, the receiver, board of trustees, etc
184 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
107. CorpostIons
A corporation is a group or series of persons which is invested
by law with a personality, that is, by a legal fiction the group or
series of persons is regarded and treated as a real person. The
creation and extinction of corporation Is deteruined by law. The
individuals who thus form the corpus of the legal person are called
its members.
Out it should be noted that a mere association of human beings
does not form a corporation, because a corporation is not merely the
sum total of its component members—i. e. the shareholders, but
something superseded to them—viz, the fictitious or legal
personality. Legal personality is not reached until the law
recognises the fictitious being which represents the associated
individuals. A corporation comes into existence by the
personification of group or series of individuals i. e. when the law
attributes fictitious personality of the group or series of persons. The
fictitious personality is attached to the group collectively but not to
the persons individually. Hence, the personality of a corporation
differs from that of a natural person.
According to English system, corporations are of two kinds,
distinguished as corporations aggregate and corporations sole. A
corporation aggregate is an incorporated group of existing persons
which has several members at a time, e. g. a registered company
consisting of all the shareholders, a municipal corporation consisting
of all the inhabitants of the place, such a corporation is, in law,
something different from its members. The property of the
company is not the property of the shareholders. A shareholder
may enter into a contract with the company, for the two persons are
entirely distinct from each other. Therefore, it is perfectly possible
that a corporation may survive its last member and can exist
Without any member.
A corporation sole is a series of successive-persons, e. g.
Sovereigns, the Solicitor-General, the Posttnaster-General The
element of legal fiction involved here is that the law assumes that in
addition to the natural person who actually occupies that particular
official position, there is a mythical being who is, in law, the real
occupant of the office, and who never dies or. retires. The living
official is merely the agent or representative through whom the
legal person performs his function. The living officials come and go,
but this offspring of the law remains the same for ever. Property
owned by a person as a corporation sole is distinct from that which
he owns in his private capacity and will pass on his death, not to his
Persons 185
estate but to his successors-in-office. One important result of this is
that it enables gifts to be made to the successive holders of an office
which has been incorporated. Without such incorporation such a gift
would fail for remoteness, Corporations sole are not a peculiarity of
English law. The distinction between
between the two forms of incorporation
is also well known to foreign jurists.
In all these respects a corporation is essentia l ly different from an
unincorporated Partnership Firm. A firm is not a person in the eye
of law. It is nothing else than the sum of the individual members.
There is no legal entity, standing over against the partners, as a
company stands over against its shareholders. The property and
debts of the firm are nothing else 4an those of the existing
partners. There can be no firm which consists of one partner only,
but a company may consist of one member, that is, who manages,
the whole show, and the others in name only.
108. The Agents, Beneficiaries and Members of a
corporation
A corporation, having neither soul nor body, cannot act save
through the agency of some representative in the world of real
men. For the same reason, it can have no interest, save those which
are attributed to it as a trustee for or otherwise on behalf of actual
human beings. Whatever a company is reputed to do, in law, is
done, in fact by the directors or the shareholders as its agents and
representatives, Whatever interests, rights or property it possesses
in law are, in fact, those of its shareholders and are held by it for
their benefit. Every legal person, therefore, has corresponding to it,
in the world of natural persons, certain agents or representatives by
whom it acts and certain beneficiaries on whose behalf it exists and
fulfills its functions. Its representatives may or may not he different
persons from its beneficiaries, for these two capacities may or may
not be united in the same individuals. The shareholders of a
company are not merely the persons for whose benefit it exists; they
are also those by whom it acts. In the case of corporation established
for charitable purposes, it is otherwise, for the beneficiaries may
have no share whatever in the management of its affairs. The
relation between a corporation and its beneficiaries may or may not
amount to a trust in the proper sense of the term. A share in a
company is not the beneficial ownership of any portion of the
company's property, but the benefit of a contract made by the
shareholder with the company, under which he is entitled to be
paid a share of the profits made by the company, and of the surplus
assets on its dissolution. A share in a company is a chose in action
186 Jurisprudence & Comparative-Legal Theory
(in English Law)—an obligation between the company and the
shareholder.
It is worth notice that somL or all of the members of a
corporation may be corporations themselves. There is nothing to
prevent the shares of a company from being held by other
companies. In this case the idea of incorporation is duplicate and the
law creates a legal person by the personification of a group of
persons who themselves possess a merely legal personality.
109. The acts and liabilities of a corporation
When one person acts through an agent, the authority of the
agent is determined by the will and consent of the principal. But
that is not so in the case of a corporation. It is for the law to
determine not only as to who shall be an agent for a corporation,
but also the law determines within what limits the authority of the
agent should be exercised. A legal person is as incapable of
conferring authority upon an agent to act on its behalf as of doing
the act in person. The authority of the agents and representatives of
a corporation is, therefore, conferred, limited and determined not
by the will of the principal, but either (1) by the wills of some
human beings, who are for this purpose identified in law with the
corporation or (2) by the law itself. A good illustration of (1) is
afforded by companies incorporated under the Companies Act. The
first director may be appointed by or in accordance with the Articles
of Association, drawn up by the promoter of the company, or they
may be appointed at a meeting of the shareholders. But thereafter
the first directors are themselves regarded for many purposes as the
alter ego of the company and their wills are, within the limits of the
rules of law, regarded as the wills of the company.
An important rule in connection with companies incorporated
by special statute and companies incorporated under the general
provisions of the Companies Act is that their powers are restricted
by law in a way that the powers of a human being are not. Thus, a
company incorporated by special statute is limited to the power
conferred by the statute. In case of a company registered under the
Companies Act, the Memorandum of Association must set forth the
purposes for which it is established, and even the unanimous
consent of the whole body of shareholders cannot effectively enable
the company to act beyond the limits so marked out for its activity.
Any act which lies beyond these legally appointed limits will not
be imputed to the corporation, even though it is done is its name
and on its behalf. An act which goes beyond authority so conferred
is called ultra vires of the corporation and such act is null and void.
Persons 187
It is well settled by the law of England that a corporation may
be held liable for wrongful acts and this liability extends even to
those cases in which malice, fraud and other wrongful motive from
the special ingredient. The liability on the part of corporations is
extended to criminal liability too, and is also punished by way of a
fine or forfeiture of property as any private individual. That being
so, the question arises, whether it is natural justice to punish a
corporate body for the acts of its agent when the ultimate result of
such punishment is bound to fall on the shoulders of the
beneficiaries. To punish a corporation is nothing more than to
punish the innocent beneficiaries for no fault of theirs. To this
objection Salmond says that although the representatives of a
corporation are, in form and theory, the agents of that fictitious
person, yet, in substance and fact, they are agents of the
beneficiaries. Just as the principal is held liable for the acts of the
agents, so also in the case of a corporation. Thus a company is justly
held liable for the acts of the directors.
A second objection arises from the following considerations. If
the limits of the authority of the agents are determined by the law
itself, can any act done by the agents, which go beyond the
authority conferred upon them, be deemed to be the acts of the
corporation? If illegal, it cannot be the act of a corporation within the
limit of lawful authority; and if not within these limits, it cannot be
the act of a corporation. To this objection, Salmond offers two
different solutions. He says that in the first place, although a
fictitious person cannot do acts which go beyond the scope of his
authority, he certainly can fail to do what he has been authorised to
do, and can be punished for such omissions. And in the second
place, the liability of a corporation for the acts of its agents is a
perfectly logical application of the law as to an employer's liability
for the acts of his servant. It is a rule of law that the master is liable
for all the wrongs committed by his servant in the course of his
employment. A master is liable not only for the acts which the
master has authorised him to do, but also for the way in which the
servant does it. So is the corporation.
110. The uses and purposes of incorporation
Among the various reasons for admitting the fictitious extension
of personality, we may distinguish one as of general and
fundamental importance, namely, the difficulty which the law finds
in dealing with the common interests vested in a large number of
188 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
individuals and with a common action in the management and
protection of such interests. What we are familiar with is individual
ownership. If two persons carry on a partnership or own and
manage property in common, complications arise, with which the
law can deal without calling in the aid of fresh conceptions. But if
there are multitude of such ownership the law finds it impossible to
deal without the aid of fictitious conceptions to overcome these
difficulties, and the law aims to introduce as far as possible some
instrument for the realisation of its purpose of recognising the rights
of all the persons. There are two devices for the purpose, namely,
trusteeship and incorporation.
Trusteeship is generally used as a mode of overcoming the
difficulties created by the incapacity, uncertainty and multiplicity of
the persons to whom the property belongs. In such cases, the
property by law is deemed to be vested not in the virtual owners
(beneficiaries), but in one or more determinate individuals of full
capacity, who hold it for the benefit of those persons for whom it is
meant.
Incorporation is merely a development of the conception of
trusteeship. A trustee, in the case of a corporation, is a fictitious
being, as opposed to a trustee in case of an individual trust, who is
a real person. As between the real and the fictitious trustee, the
latter is preferable, because he never dies.
And secondly, incorporation enables traders to join together and
form one company with a limited liability. As the law stands, if any
one ventures into any particular trade, he has got to bear the whole
loss, it his venture results in any loss. Such risk is avoided by
incorporation. If the business is successful, the gains made by the
company will be held on behalf of the members, and if
unsuccessful, the losses must be borne by the company itself. For,
the debts of a corporation are not the debts of the members
themselves. The only risks run by the members is the amount that
they have contributed towards the share capital. The introduction of
incorporation has been a great boon to commerce and manufactures,
because it has enabled us to undertake big schemes and to venture
upon unthought of adventures.
Thirdly, as the property is vested in the corporation, it is not
necessary that it should he transferred to a new member on his
inclusion in order to give such member the benefit thereof.
It may be said that but for the creation of such artificial persons
the prosperity of the world would not have been possible.
Persons 189
111. The State as a Corporation
Of all forms of artificial persons, the greatest is the State. It owns
wealth and performs many important functions. But according to
the law of England, the State is not a corporation. The State owns no
property, is capable of no acts, and has no rights nor liabilities
imputed to it by the law. The explanation for all this is to be found
in the Monarchial form of Government. The real personality of the
King has rendered any incorporation of the State as superfluous.
Public property in the eye of the law belongs to the King. Whatever
is done by the State is in law done by the King and so on. In
modern times, it has become usual to speak of the Crown rather
than of the King. But this reference to the Crown is only a figure of
peech, because the Crown is not by itself a person in the eye of the
law.
112. The creation and extinction of Corporation
• The birth and death of legal persons are determined not by
nature, but by the law. They come into existence at the will of the
law, and they endure during its good pleasure. In England,
corporations may be established by Royal Charter, by statute, by
immemorial custom, and, in recent years, by agreement of their
members expressed in statutory forms and subject to statutory
provisions and limitations. They are in their own nature capable of
indefinite duration, this being indeed one of their chief virtues as
compared with humanity, but they are not incapable of destruction.
Its life can be brought to an end by the same authority by whom it
came into being or by the members or by the Court. The extinction
of a body rporate is called its dissolution—the severing of that
legal bond by which its members are knit together into .a unity. It
must be noted that it is perfectly possible for a corporation to
continue to live, although the last of its members is dead. In the
case of a corporation sole the person is merely dormant, and not
extinct, during the ink'rval between two successive occupants of the
office.
113. The legal status of lower animals
The only natural persons are human beings. Beasts are things
and not persons, either natural or legal. They may be objects of
legal rights and duties but never t1 e subjct of them. Beasts, like
men, are capble of acts and possess interests. Yet their acts; are
neither lawful nor unlawful, they are not recognised by the law, as
the appropriate subject-matter either of permission or of prohibition.
No animal can be the owner of property. The rule that a trespassing
190 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
beast may be distrained damage pheasant and kept until its owner
or someone else pays cotnpensation, does not, however, in the
modern law, involve any lgal recognition of the personality of the
animal.
A beast is as incapable of legal rights as of legal duties; for its
interests receive no recognition from the law. The law is made for
men and allows no fellowship or bonds of obligation between them
and the lower animals. A hurt done to the beast may be a wrong to
its owner or to the society of mankind, but it is no wrong to the
beast. No animal can he the owner of any property, even through
the medium of any trustee. If a trust is created for the benefit of a
particular animal, it is a trust of imperfect obligation and casts no
legal duty on the trustee to execute the trust.
There are, however, two cases in which beasts may be said to
possess certain legal rights (1) In the first place, cruelty to animals
is a criminal offence, but that is not so much on account of the love
for the beasts, but on account of the repugnant feelings produced to
the society by such cruelty. (2) Secondly, a trust for the benefit of a
particular class of animals, as opposed to one for an individual
animal (say my favourite dog), is valid and enforceable as a public
and charitable trust, e. g. a provision for the establishment and
maintenance of a home for stray dogs or broken-down horses. Such
trusts correspond not to private trusts but to public rights vested in
the community at large,—for the community is interested in the
well-being even to the deaf and dumb animals—which belong to it.
But these instances form no real exception. For, these duties
towards animals are conceived by the law not as a duty towards the
beasts, but as duties towards society itself. The animals are owned
by the society and hence the society has got an interest for their
protection. Therefore, these duties do not correspond to private
rights vested in the animals, hut to public rights vested in the
whole community.
114. The legal status of dead men
Ordinarily speaking, the personality of a human being may be
said to commence on birth and cease to exist at death, and in
general the law takes the same view. Dead men are no longer
p'rsons in the eye of the law. They have laid down their legal
personality with their lives and are now as destitute of legal rights
as of liabilities. Although the law does not confer rights upon the
dead, it does to some extent recognise and make account of a
person's desires and interests when alive. They are—(1) a mans
body, (2) his reputation and (3) his estate
Persons 191
(1) According to law, a corpse is the property of no one. It
cannot be disposed of by will and no wrongful dealing
with it can amount to theft. Again any testamentary
directions of a person as to the disposal of his body after his
death are destitute of legal effects. Similarly a permanent
trust for the maintenance of his tomb is illegal and void,
However, the criminal law secures decent burial for all
dead men, and the violation or desecration of a grave is an
offence under the Penal Code of India, Pakistan and
Bangladesh as well as of England. Every person dying in
England has a right to Christian burial. "Whether is
ground consecrated or unconsecrated, indignities offered to
huian remains improperly and indecently disinterring
them, are the grounds of an indictment" as decided in an
English case [Foster vs. Dodd (1867), 3 Q B 771.
(2) The reputation of the dead receives some degree of
protection from the criminal law. Under the Bangladesh
Penal Code, it may amoupt to defamation to impute
anything to a deceased person, if the imputation would
harm the reputatiqi of that person, if living, and is
intended to be hurtful to the feelings of his family or other
near relations. According to English law, a libel upon a
dead man will be punished as a misdemeanour but only
when its publication is in truth an attack upon the interests
of living persons. The right so attacked and so defended is
in reality not that of the dead, but that of his living
descendants.
(3) By far the most important matter in which the desires of
dead men are allowed by the law to regulate the actions of
the living is that of testamentary succession. For many
yc'rs after a man is dead his hand may continue to
regulate and determine the disposition and enjoyment of
the property which he owned while living.
115. The legal status of unborn persons
Though the dead possesses no legal personality, it is otherwise
with the unborn, Unlike dead persons, unborn persons do,
according to the law, possesses a personality. There is nothing in
law to prevent a person from owning property before he is born.
His ownership is necessarily contingent, indeed, for he may never
he born at all. But it is nonetheless a real and present ownership.
Thus, a person may settle property upon his wife and the children
192 Jurisprudence & Comparative Legal Theory
that are to be born of her. Or he may die intestate and his unborn
child will inherit his estate. A child in its Mother's Womb is for
many purposes regarded by legal fiction as a1ea4y born. In the
words of Coke: "The law it many cases has consideration of him in
respect of the apparent expectation of te birth". thus, In the law of
property, there is a fiction that a child Is a person in being for the
purposes of (1) acquisition of property by the child itself, or (2)
being a life chosen to form part of the period in the rule against
perpetuities.
To a certain extent unborn persons may possess personal
interests. It has been held that a posthumous child is entitled to
compensation under Lord Campbells Act for the death of its father.
Willful or negligent injury inflicted on a child in the womb, by
reason of which it dies after it was born alive, amounts to murder or
manslaughter. A pregnant woman condemned to death is respited
as of right, until she has been delivered of her child.
The rights of an unborn person, whether proprietary or
personal, are all contingent on his birth as a living human being.
The legal personality attributed to him by way of anticipation falls
away ab initio if he never takes his place among the living.
Abortion and child destruction are crimes, but such acts do not
amount to murder or manslaughter unless the child is born alive. A
posthumous child may inherit, but if he dies in the womb or is still-
born, his inheritance fails to take effect, and no one can claim
through him, though it would be otherwise if he lived for an hour
after his birth. Finally, though the law imputes no rights to persons
not yet even conceived, it may protect their interests. If some of the
beneficiaries of a trust are unborn persons, the trust cannot be
varied without obtaining the Courts consent on their behalf.
116. Double capacity and double personality
Sometimes a single human being may hold two capacities to
possess legal rights. He is one man but two persons. In such a case
the law attributes to him double personality. As for example, a
trustee is two persons in the eye of law. In the right of his
beneficiary he is one person and in his own right he is another.
English law recognises many different capacities in which a
man may act. Often he has the power to act in an official or
representative capacity when he would have no power to do the act
in his private capacity or on his own account. But the niere fact that
a man has two or more capacities does not give him the power to
enter into a legal transaction with himself. For instance, at common
Persons 193
law a man could not sue himself or contract with himself or convey
property to himself; and it made no difference that he was acting on
each side in a different capacity. So, rigorous was the rule that if the
same party appeared on both sides to a contract, even though
accompanied by different parties in each case, the contract was void.
In many cases this rule worked hardship and its consequences had
to be mitigated. For example, where a creditor became his debtors
executor, the rule that he could not sue himself was mitigated by
giving him a right of retainer. Now by statute, where a person
purports to contract with himself and others, the contract is
enforceable as if it had been entered into with the other persons
alone. With such small exceptions the rule that a man cannot enter
into a legal transaction with himself remains unchanged.
—i4
CHAPTER XV
TITLE