entropy-26-01004
entropy-26-01004
entropy-26-01004
1 Laboratoire Charles Fabry, Institut d’Optique Graduate School, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique,
Université Paris Saclay, 91127 Palaiseau, France
2 MajuLab International Joint Research Laboratory, Centre for Quantum Technologies, National University of
Singapore, Singapore 117543, Singapore; alexia.auffeves@cnrs.fr
3 Independent Researcher, 38054 Grenoble Cedex, France; naylafarouki@yahoo.fr
4 Thales Alenia Space, 26, Avenue J.-F. Champollion, 31037 Toulouse, France;
mathias.van-den-bossche@thalesaleniaspace.com
5 EPITA Research Laboratory, 14-16 Rue Voltaire, 94270 Le Kremlin-Bicêtre, France; olivier@oezratty.net
* Correspondence: philippe.grangier@cnrs.fr
Abstract: The purpose of this article is to provide a novel approach and justification of the idea
that classical physics and quantum physics can neither function nor even be conceived without the
other—in line with ideas attributed to, e.g., Niels Bohr or Lev Landau. Though this point of view
may contradict current common wisdom, we will show that it perfectly fits with empirical evidence,
and can be maintained without giving up physical realism. In order to place our arguments in a
convenient historical perspective, we will proceed as if we were following the path of a scientific
investigation about the demise, or vanishing, of some valuable properties of the two electrons in the
helium atom. We will start from experimentally based evidence in order to analyze and explain the
physical facts, moving cautiously from a classical to a quantum description, without mixing them
up. The overall picture will be that the physical properties of microscopic systems are quantized, as
initially shown by Planck and Einstein, and that they are also contextual, i.e., they can be given a
physical sense only by embedding a microscopic system within a macroscopic measurement context.
Figure 1. Stern–Gerlach magnets measuring the spin components along Oz (left), along Ox (center),
and along Oz/Ox/Oz (right). In this last case, the results, −h̄/2, are blocked by the dark square
screens. © Manuel Joffre, Ecole Polytechnique.
We can then try to chain several measurements: first along Oz, which gives, let us say,
+h̄/2, then along Ox, then along Oz again. Theory and experiment say that the second
measurement, along Ox, gives a random result ±h̄/2, with probabilities of 1/2. Why not, so
let us assume that we find +h̄/2, and let us go back to the projection component along Oz
that we knew before; but if we make the measurement again along Oz, we find a random
result ±h̄/2, with probabilities of 1/2: everything happens as if measuring along Ox had
erased the previously known result along Oz ! So, already with a single-spin 1/2 particle,
a strange vanishing of some properties can be observed—maybe a hint of what is going on
with the more tricky two-spin situation.
Another very strange fact is this: suppose Alice randomly selects a particle in any one
of the four states, |± x ⟩ or |±z ⟩, and sends it to Bob without any further indication. Bob
is then unable to determine the state of the particle without error! Indeed, if he chooses
(by chance) the same measurement axis as the one selected by Alice, he will find the
right result, the one she has sent, but if he chooses another axis, he will find a random
result, uncorrelated with what Alice sent. This impossibility, which also applies to any
eavesdropper, is at the basis of the technique called quantum cryptography, or, more
precisely, prepare-and-measure quantum key distribution. But then, how it is possible for
Bob to obtain any useful information? This can be performed by Alice and Bob publicly
exchanging their choice of axis after Bob has received the particle, and keeping only the
results where they made the same choice; the revealed information is then useless for a
possible eavesdropper, since the particle is no longer there [16].
The appearance of these random results raises several questions:
- Is it possible to find, in one way or another, situations where a measurement provides
a deterministic result, i.e., one that can be predicted with certainty? This seems
mandatory in order to attribute a physical reality to the objects we consider, and in the
framework of our inquiry, we need actual and objective facts, not ghostly ones.
- If Bob cannot fully identify the state of the particle (the one known and sent by Alice)
by making measurements of that particle, is it legitimate to say that |ψ⟩ is the ‘complete
state of the particle’?
Usual TBQM attributes a ‘complete quantum state’ to a particle, so its answer to
the second question above is affirmative, but it also says that despite this completeness,
Bob’s measurement result is generally not deterministic. Then, moving on to two particles,
the contradictions accumulate, culminating in the strange situation mentioned at the end of
the previous section. Therefore, unfortunately, one has to conclude that the expert advice
from TBQM did not really help, but rather increased the confusion. So we will now look
for different answers to these questions by saying that the quantum state may not be so
complete after all—and show that we can thereby make one step towards elucidating this
two-spin enigma, in helium and everywhere else.
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 5 of 13
antisymmetric for the spatial part and symmetric for the spin—that is, their spin state does
not change its sign by permutation of the two electrons.
M=2×2 | + +⟩
4 orthonormal spin
first and second spin | + −⟩ basis states
first up and down
context first particle second particle
combinations | − +⟩
spin projection spin projection
= ½ or -½ = ½ or -½ | − −⟩ these contexts share 2
along 0z along 0z identical states
1,1 = | + +⟩ (in blue), which are
S=1 named “extravalent
M=3+1 ! modalities”
triplet 1,0 = "
(| + −⟩ + | − +⟩) = |+⟩
(symmetric
second states)
1, −1 = | − −⟩ another 4 orthonormal
context
triplet singlet S=0 spin basis states
!
states state singlet 0,0 = "
(| + −⟩ − | − +⟩) = |,⟩
(antisymmetric
state) this state is entangled
when viewed using the
total spin first context and it is a
M = system dimension total electron
projection (mS)
spin (S) modality in the second
on the z axis
2 context
S Sz
Figure 2. Various quantum states relevant for two electrons. All |±⟩ mean |±z ⟩. The total spin ⃗S2 is
1
the sum of the squares of the three spin projections (S2x + Sy2 + Sz2 ) and it takes the values S(S + 1)h̄2 .
In this figure, M is the total number of possible, mutually exclusive measurement outcomes—or
modalities—in each context.
Though the inquiry is clearly making progress, we will conclude this part with a new
conundrum by again considering the states/modalities |s⟩ and |r ⟩, perfectly defined for a
measurement of the total spin, and associated with well-defined energy levels of the helium
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 7 of 13
atom. As we have already seen, the question ‘what is the value of the component of the
spin along Oz for only one of the two electrons’ has no answer within the framework of the
formalism of usual QM we have introduced. We can reconcile ourselves with this statement
by saying that of course there is no answer, but this is not really shocking since we are
talking about two electrons within the same atom, very strongly coupled by electrostatic
interaction, so it is not very surprising that they adopt a global behavior. In addition, there
is no clear way to measure each electron’s spin within the helium atom.
Yet the ever-doubting physicist will ask the following question: ok, but can’t we have
the two electrons, or any two spin 1/2 particles, very far apart, and still in the state |s⟩ or in
the state |r ⟩? This can be conducted in suitable experiments, as detailed in the Appendix A.
What, then, is the meaning of the statement that the component of its spin along Oz has
no value, or a completely random value? And what happens if we compare the results
of separate measurements on the two spins? Then, we have to dive into an even deeper
mystery, that of quantum entanglement, Verschränkung in German, with two famous
papers published in 1935: ‘Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be
Considered Complete?’, by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen (EPR) [24], and Schrödinger’s
almost desperate article, though resigned to the quantum weirdness, ‘Die gegenwärtige
Situation in der Quantenmechanik (The present situation in quantum mechanics)’ [25].
The cause of desperation of these great physicists was the following: the spin components
of the two remote electrons, which were supposed to have “no value”, turn out to be
strongly correlated! But how can it be, if their values are undetermined? Did QM fall from
Charybdis to Scylla? It is this new extended enigma that will now have to be solved.
the initial parameters and the laws of dynamics should allow one to predict the result
with certainty.
Now, without further ado or mathematics, it is clear that the usual quantum state
vector, as introduced in the previous section for describing the spin systems and generically
denoted by |ψ⟩, does not fit in this framework. Specifying everything that may happen
can only be performed once the measurement context has been specified. More precisely,
this measurement context is required, in addition to |ψ⟩, in order to define a standard
probability distribution over a set of mutually exclusive events. In this sense, we can say
that for the spin systems the quantum state alone is predictively incomplete. Specifying
all these possible events (i.e., the possible measurement results) is equivalent to giving the
context, and |ψ⟩ allows one to calculate their respective probabilities of occurring. Since
this is obtained by specifying both |ψ⟩ and the context, we have to acknowledge that what
QM allows are contextual inferences [28].
Though this just tells how quantum mechanics works, it may appear shocking to both
a classical physicist and a (naive) quantum physicist. A classical physicist has a hidden
cause of randomness and correlations (Bell’s LHV) deeply rooted in their mind, so saying
that there are no such variables in quantum physics is hard to accept. On the other hand,
a quantum physicist has deeply rooted in their mind that |ψ⟩ is complete, in the sense that
there is no underlying hidden cause to be sought—as it was taught by Niels Bohr, and as
it is still true. But saying that the quantum state vector |ψ⟩ is incomplete as long as the
context has not been specified, though it is operationally obvious in quantum mechanics,
and does not contradict Bohr’s message, may be quite hard to accept. Why? Because
we would have then to give up the idea that |ψ⟩ fully specifies a physical object, which
is the quantum system under study, and to admit that the actual physical object has to
be the quantum system within a classical context. This appears so shocking that the
quantum physicist may be tempted to consider instead ‘non-local influences’, or other
weird explanations, in order to violate Bell’s inequalities; but this leads to the contradictory
points of views presented before, and it is actually not needed if predictive incompleteness
is acknowledged [28].
4.2. Mutual Consistency of the Classical and Quantum Descriptions of the Physical World
The idea that context is needed to obtain a complete description of what can be ob-
served on a quantum system has often been confused with statements about the subjectivity
of the quantum state, or about the role of the consciousness of the observer [15]. There is
no need for that either, and a physical object remains perfectly objective, but it is still a
system within a context. This requires one, however, to recognize that there is no such thing
as absolute objectivity of predictions about the system alone; this departs from the usual,
classical, apprehension of the universe, taken as a whole, with all its logical and ontological
necessity as Newton and Einstein conceived it. The quantum requirement for a contextual
description of physical objects is related to many issues in quantum physics, and it has
been spelled out initially in the article ‘Contextual objectivity: a realistic interpretation of
quantum mechanics’ (2001) [29], which may provide us with a more suitable, non-classical
view about the world we live in [30].
There is clearly a price to pay for the idea that there are well-defined systems and
contexts: if this is the case, there must be a physical separation between them, usually
known as the “Heisenberg cut”, where the applicable laws change from quantum to
classical. This creates a dualist view of the physical world that does not seem satisfactory,
and there have been many attempts to find ways by which the classical world should
‘emerge’ from the quantum one—if any. This was also the content of Max Born’s initial
request, to build up ‘the new mechanics on its own foundations, without any connection
with classical theory’. But it can also be said, as Bohr and Landau did, that there is no
way to formulate quantum mechanics without referring to classical concepts. For instance,
Landau and Lifshitz [1] write “It is clear that, for a system composed only of quantum objects, it
would be entirely impossible to construct any logically independent mechanics (. . . ) Thus quantum
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 9 of 13
mechanics occupies a very unusual place among physical theories: it contains classical mechanics as
a limiting case, yet at the same time it requires this limiting case for its own formulation”.
This leads to the idea that classical and quantum descriptions are both required
from the beginning and are simultaneously needed for mutual consistency [31]. Actually,
classical descriptions without quantum descriptions are unable to explain the structure of
atoms, as seen above, but quantum descriptions without classical descriptions are unable
to say clearly what a quantum state describes, and when extrapolated to the macroscopic
world they become lost in bizarre predictions that clash with empirical evidence.
An apparent difficulty for unifying classical and quantum physics is that their mathe-
matical frameworks seem incompatible – but this is not correct, and a unified formalism,
using operator algebras, is actually possible and was already suggested by John von Neu-
mann in 1939. Though this extension of the standard quantum formalism is mathematically
nontrivial, it definitively deserves a closer look by quantum physicists—after being placed
into the appropriate ontological framework introduced above. This has been discussed in
several recent articles [32].
5. Epilogue
Since the purpose of this paper is to illustrate and discuss quantum ideas using two-
spin 1/2 particles, we did not reconstruct the full quantum formalism yet, and explanations
of basic tools like unitary transforms and Born’s rule are still missing. But there is not much
choice left, because the framework defined above fits with the hypotheses of powerful math-
ematical theorems, establishing the need for unitary transformations (Gerhard Uhlhorn’s
theorem [36]) and for Born’s rule (Andrew Gleason’s theorem [37]). These arguments have
been published elsewhere [34] and will not be reproduced here. Also, systems and contexts
should be part of a unified mathematical formalism, going beyond standard textbook
QM. Operator algebra, introduced by Murray and von Neumann [38,39] and considerably
developed since then, can provide such a formalism and give a mathematical status to the
Heisenberg cut, as has been shown in [32].
So finally, what should we say to the layman to bring our investigation to a successful
conclusion and to replace misleading statements such as “a quantum superposition is like
being in two states at the same time”, or “quantum entanglement is like an instantaneous
action at a distance”? It could be the following:
The physical properties of microscopic systems are quantized, as initially shown by Planck
and Einstein, and they are also contextual; this means that they can be given a physical
sense only by embedding a microscopic system within a macroscopic context that specifies
how the system is observed, as proposed by Bohr. Such a behavior is quite remote from
the non-quantized and non-contextual perspective of classical physics, and it requires
developing a specific contextual probabilistic theory, which is basically what quantum
mechanics has been doing.
To conclude, let us emphasize that QM follows from the conjunction of quantization
and contextuality; these two properties taken separately may have some classical analogue,
and therefore they do not have the same constraining power when being combined.
Author Contributions: Writing—original draft, P.G.; Writing—review & editing, A.A., N.F., M.V.D.B.
and O.E. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript.
Funding: This research received no external funding.
Institutional Review Board Statement: Not applicable.
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 11 of 13
Data Availability Statement: This is theoretical research, so no new data were created.
Acknowledgments: P.G. thanks Franck Laloë, Roger Balian, and Karl Svozil for many interesting and
useful discussions, and Manuel Joffre for permission to use Figure 1 from his Quantum Mechanics
course at Ecole Polytechnique. MvdB thanks the Thales engineers for their candid but actually
extremely relevant questions. The authors thank Michel Kurek and Camilia Ben Messaouda for
proofreading and comments on the paper.
Conflicts of Interest: Author Mathias Van Den Bossche is employed by the company Thales Ale-
nia Space. The remaining authors declare that the research was conducted in the absence of any
commercial or financial relationships that could be construed as a potential conflict of interest.
1 0√ 0√ 0
0 1/ 2
√ −1/√ 2 0
G=
0 1/ 2
1/ 2 0
0 0 0 1
which can be implemented by a sequence of quantum gates, as shown in Figure A1. This
shows explicitly that, as written in the text, two qubits can be set or measured in the state
|s⟩ or in the state |r ⟩ outside the helium atom.
𝐻 𝐻
Figure A1. Sequence of one- and two-qubit quantum gates and their matrix unitaries acting on
two qubits, to move between the coupled and uncoupled basis. The first and last gates are Hadamard
gates, the second and forth Controlled-NOT gates, and the middle ones are specific non-Clifford
one-qubit gates.
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 12 of 13
An arbitrary quantum state can thus be measured in either the computational √ basis
{|1, 1⟩, √
|1, 0⟩, |0, 1⟩, |0, 0⟩} or in the coupled basis {|1, 1⟩, (|1, 0⟩ + |0, 1⟩)/ 2, (−|1, 0⟩ +
|0, 1⟩)/ 2, |0, 0⟩}. More precisely, the nontrivial measurement in the coupled basis can
be realized by applying G † to the two qubits, carrying out a QND measurement in the
uncoupled (computational) basis, which is in principle easy, and then applying G to recover
the measured state in the coupled basis. Therefore, such a given sequence of gates, building
up a unitary transformation, implements a controlled change of context, since not only one
but a whole set of mutually orthogonal states are mapped onto another set of mutually
orthogonal states. This has the advantage that modalities can be defined up to a unitary
transform, in the case where the appropriate context cannot be implemented. Though not so
easy to implement in practice, this two-way procedure (G † /QND/G) is useful in quantum
computing and shows that thinking about physical modalities, associated with a context,
may be more enlightening than just thinking about mathematical state vectors, which
represent extravalence classes of modalities occurring in different contexts.
References
1. Landau, L.D.; Lifshitz, E.M. Quantum Mechanics. 1965. Available online: https://archive.org/details/ost-physics-landaulifshitz-
quantummechanics (accessed on 12 May 2023).
2. Conan Doyle, A. The Case-Book of Sherlock Holmes; John Murray: London, UK, 1927.
3. Born, M. The Mechanics of the Atom; G. Bell and Sons: London, UK, 1927.
4. Feynman, R. The Feynman Lectures on Physics, Volume III: Quantum Mechanics. 1963. Available online: https://www.
feynmanlectures.caltech.edu/ (accessed on 12 May 2023).
5. Cohen-Tannoudji, C.; Diu, B.; Laloë, F. Quantum Mechanics; 3 Volumes; John Wiley & Sons: Hoboken, NJ, USA, 2019.
6. Faye, J. Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-copenhagen/
(accessed on 12 May 2023).
7. Bacciagaluppi, G. The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics. 2020. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
qm-decoherence/ (accessed on 12 May 2023).
8. Goldstein, S. Bohmian Mechanics. 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-bohm/ (accessed on 12 May
2023).
9. Ghirardi, G.; Bassi, A. Collapse Theories. 2020. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-collapse/ (accessed on
12 May 2023).
10. Barrett, J. Everettian Quantum Mechanics. 2023. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-everett/ (accessed on
12 May 2023).
11. Vaidman, L. Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-
manyworlds/ (accessed on 12 May 2023).
12. Lombardi, O.; Dieks, D. Modal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics. 2021. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
qm-modal/ (accessed on 12 May 2023).
13. Laudisa, F.; Rovelli, C. Relational Quantum Mechanics. 2019. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/qm-relational/
(accessed on 12 May 2023).
14. Healey, R. Quantum-Bayesian & Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory. 2022. Available online: https://plato.stanford.edu/
entries/quantum-bayesian/ (accessed on 12 May 2023).
15. Laloë, F. Do We Really Understand Quantum Mechanics? Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, UK, 2012.
16. Bennett, C.H.; Brassard, G. Quantum cryptography: Public key distribution and coin tossing. In Proceedings of the IEEE
International Conference on Computers, Systems and Signal Processing, Bangalore, India, 9–12 December1984; Volume 175, p. 8.
17. Braginsky, V.B.; Khalili, F.Y. Quantum nondemolition measurements: The route from toys to tools. Rev. Mod. Phys. 1996, 68, 1.
[CrossRef]
18. von Neumann, J. Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik; Springer: Berlin/Heidelberg, Germany, 1932; English translation
Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics; Princeton University Press: Princeton, NJ, USA, 1955.
19. Grangier, P.; Levenson, J.A.; Poizat, J.P. Quantum Non-Demolition Measurements in Optics. Nature 1998, 396, 537. [CrossRef]
20. Haroche, S.; Raimond, J.M. Exploring the Quantum; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006.
21. Hume, D.B.; Rosenband, T.; Wineland, D.J. High-Fidelity Adaptive Qubit Detection through Repetitive Quantum Nondemolition
Measurements. Phys. Rev. Lett. 2007, 99, 120502. [CrossRef] [PubMed]
22. Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Contexts, Systems and Modalities: A new ontology for quantum mechanics. Found. Phys. 2016, 46,
121–137. [CrossRef]
23. Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Extracontextuality and extravalence in quantum mechanics. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. A 2018, 376, 20170311.
[CrossRef]
24. Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete? Phys.
Rev. 1935, 47, 777. [CrossRef]
Entropy 2024, 26, 1004 13 of 13
25. Schrödinger, E.W. Die gegenwärtige Situation in der Quantenmechanik (The present situation in quantum mechanics). Naturwis-
senschaften 1935, 23, 807. [CrossRef]
26. Bell, J.S. On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox. Physics 1964, 1, 195–200. [CrossRef]
27. Aspect, A. Closing the Door on Einstein and Bohr’s Quantum Debate. Physics 2015, 8, 123. Available online: https://physics.aps.
org/articles/v8/123 (accessed on 15 May 2015). [CrossRef]
28. Grangier, P. Contextual inferences, nonlocality, and the incompleteness of quantum mechanics. Entropy 2021, 23, 1660. [CrossRef]
29. Grangier, P. Contextual objectivity: A realistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. Eur. J. Phys. 2002, 23, 331. [CrossRef]
30. Farouki, N.; Grangier, P. The Einstein-Bohr debate: Finding a common ground of understanding? Found. Sci. 2021, 26, 97–101.
[CrossRef]
31. Grangier, P. Completing the quantum formalism in a contextually objective framework. Found. Phys. 2021, 51, 76. [CrossRef]
32. Van Den Bossche, M.; Grangier, P. Postulating the Unicity of the Macroscopic Physical World. Entropy 2023, 25, 1600. [CrossRef]
33. Auffèves, A. and P. Grangier, P. What is quantum in quantum randomness? Phil. Trans. R. Soc. A 2018, 376, 20170322.
34. Auffèves, A.; Grangier, P. Revisiting Born’s rule through Uhlhorn’s and Gleason’s theorems. Entropy 2022, 24, 199. [CrossRef]
35. Bohr, N. Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete? Phys. Rev. 1935, 48, 696. [CrossRef]
36. Uhlhorn, U. Representation of symmetry transformations in quantum mechanics. Arkiv für Fysik 1962, 23, 307–340.
37. Gleason, A.M. Measures on the Closed Subspaces of a Hilbert Space. J. Math. Mech. 1957, 6, 885–893. [CrossRef]
38. Murray, F.J.; von Neumann, J. On Rings of Operators IV. Ann. Math. 1943, 44, 716. [CrossRef]
39. von Neumann, J. On infinite direct products. Compos. Math. 1939, 6, 1–77. Available online: http://www.numdam.org/item?id=
CM_1939__6__1_0 (accessed on 8 September 2019).
40. Fry, E.S.; Walther, T. Fundamental tests of quantum mechanics. Adv. At. Mol. Opt. Phys. 2000, 42, 1.
Disclaimer/Publisher’s Note: The statements, opinions and data contained in all publications are solely those of the individual
author(s) and contributor(s) and not of MDPI and/or the editor(s). MDPI and/or the editor(s) disclaim responsibility for any injury to
people or property resulting from any ideas, methods, instructions or products referred to in the content.