Module Ethics
Module Ethics
Nicole I. Revesencio
Instructor
Introduction
It seems that people don't like rules as they represent a kind of restrictions, but in fact life can't be organized without
rules. People always need rules and laws to be able to live and deal together. Can you imagine even a game without rules;
of course it will be a kind of mess. When they are playing a game, they must follow its rules or it will be unfair. Also,
everything in our life should be restricted with rules or it becomes a mess and unfair. If there are no rules and everyone is
free to do whatever they want, most people will probably behave selfishly. We need rules to help us get a long together and
show respect to each other.
All the rules and laws have the same purpose. They organized the relations between individuals and the society to
make it clear what is right and wrong and what happens if someone breaks the rules. They are designed to ensure fairness,
safety and respect for other people's right.
Rules and Its Importance
Rules refer to a set of guidelines which have been put in place in different countries and communities and have
been accepted by all. Rules are useful tools in guiding and monitoring the interactions of humans in the society. A rule is a
prescribed guide for conduct or action. Rules help guide actions toward desired results. When used appropriately, rules
provide a sense of predictability and Consistency for people, thereby promoting physical, moral, social, and emotional
safety. At the heart of ethics is a concern about something or someone other than selves and our own desires and self-
interest.
Ethics is concerned with other people's interests, with the interests of society, with God's interests, with "ultimate
goods", and so on. So, when a person thinks ethically' they are giving at least some thought to something beyond themselves.
Rules are specific sets of norms of behavior, regulations, and laws established on purpose to regulate the life in the
community. These norms secure the order and allow avoiding total chaos. The sets of rules available nowadays have
undergone a long formation process. There were many variations and transformations applied. Due to that, nowadays we
have a well-established social, governmental and educational mechanisms that work as a clock accurately, simultaneously
and in an organized way. The availability of rules is a crucial criterion allowing to call nowadays society civilized and well
developed.
Rules are important because they tend to protect the weaker class if the society as they might be in a disadvantageous
position if rules are broken. When rules are used in the right way. They provide a stable environment and human co-existence
in a society which leads to peace and development. The process of setting rules aims to craft rules in line with some desired
results. For example, rules in schools and other institutions promote trust, fairness and discipline in a bid to establish
desirable relationship among students and people. Besides, rules are vital in one's life because peace and order are
maintained, an important ingredient for society's development. As a way of maintaining these rules, many societies have
adopted and changed them into law. These assure that no rules will be broken. If one violates the rule, a corresponding
punishment is imposed. Most of us are basically honest, and knowing the rules means that we usually try to follow them.
One reason we do is to avoid punishment, but the strongest argument for following the rules is to make the world peaceful
and fair.
Why Do We Have Rules?
Rules help people in many aspects of life. They enable people to organize all the processes correctly, starting from
house chores and ending with more complicated issues as the functioning of as whole country. Rules are specific modes of
behavior that secure a regulated flow of all processes.
A well-developed system of rules help humanity to avoid chaos and many problems that may be caused by the lack
of regulations. Laws dictate what is proper and what is wrong. In many spheres of life, we have guidelines to follow. Norms
enable people to interact, to work together and contribute to the global development. Moral rules assist people in the
establishment of shared values and norms in accordance to which an honorable member of society can be identified.
The Subject: Ethics
Ethics, or moral philosophy, may be defined in a provisional way, as the scientific study of moral judgments. Ethics
is the discipline concerned with what is morally good and bad, right and wrong. The term is also applied to any system or
theory of moral values or principles.
The subject of Ethics consists of the fundamental issues of practical decision making, and its major concerns include
the nature of ultimate value and the standards by which human actions can be judged right or wrong. At its simplest, ethics
is a system of moral principles. They affect how people make decisions and lead their lives. Ethics is concerned with what
is good for individuals and society and is also described as moral philosophy.
The term is derived from the Greek word ethos which can mean custom, habit, character or disposition. Our concepts
of ethics have been derived from religions, philosophies and cultures. They infuse debates on topics like abortion, human
rights and professional conduct. Ethics is not only about the morality of particular courses of action, but it's also about the
goodness of individuals and what it means to live a good life. Virtue Ethics is particularly concerned with the moral character
of human beings.
Branches of Ethics
One way to try and define morality is through ethics, the philosophical study of morality. In the field of ethics,
morality is often defined in one of two ways. First is normative, in which actions are judged by their merits, allowing
societies to develop codes of conduct for behavior. The Golden Rule, do unto others as you would have them do unto you,
is a classic example of normative ethics, since you are determining morality through your actions. Other examples Could
include helping someone who is lost, or finding a wallet and turning it in to the lost and found. If your actions to another
person align with how you want to be treated, they are moral. The other side of this is descriptive ethics. If normative ethics
try and define how people should act, descriptive ethics ask what do people think is moral? This branch of ethics does not
actually claim that things are right or wrong, but simply studies how individuals or societies define their morals. What
makes something right or wrong in a specific culture?
While normative ethics actually defines what is right and wrong, descriptive ethics defines morals in terms of their
cultural or personal significance. Morals are seen as part of a greater system that is not objective or unbiased but is created
by a culture, like language. So, while in normative ethics we may say that it is moral to tun in a lost wallet, in descriptive
ethics, we simply define that a certain society this as moral. We don't actually judge it as right or wrong. These two branches
of ethics are just a few of the ways we try and define morality. While there are many more, most of them can be broken into
the same divisions as these two. Some theories define what is right and wrong as objective truth, others see morals as entirely
subjective, only definable through their respective societies.
Morality
Morality can be defined as the standards that an individual or a group has about what is right and wrong, or good
and evil. Morality is not imposed from outside, but innate and can even be unconscious. We have a fundamental urge to
connect. Ultimately, it's our moral qualities that force us to live in harmony with the unconscious; doing so is the highest
form of morality. Morality is an informal public system applying to all rational persons, governing behavior that affects
others, and has the lessening of evil or harm as its goal. Morality is a complex of concepts and philosophical beliefs by
which an individual determines whether his or her actions are right or wrong. Often, these concepts and beliefs are
generalized and codified in a culture or group, and thus serve to regulate the behavior of its members. Conformity to such
codification is called morality, and the group may depend on widespread conformity to such codes for its continued
existence. A "moral" may refer to a particular principle, usually as informal and general summary of a moral principle, as
applied in a given human situation (Darwall, 2005). There does not seem to be much reason to think that a single definition
d morality will be applicable to all moral discussions. One reason for this js hot "morality" seems to be used in two distinct
broad senses: a descriptive sense and a normative sense. More particularly, the term "morality" can be used either
1. descriptively to refer to certain codes of conduct put forward by a society or a group (such as a religion), or accepted by
an individual for his/her own behavior, or
2. normatively to refer to a code of conduct that, given specified conditions, would be put forward by all rational persons.
Moral Dilemmas
A moral dilemma is a conflict in which you have to choose between two or more actions and have moral reasons
for choosing each action. What is common to the two well-known cases is conflict. In each case, an agent regards herself
as having moral reasons to do each of two0 actions, but doing both actions is not possible, Ethicists have called situations
like these moral dilemmas. The crucial features of a moral dilemma are these: the agent is required to do each of wo or more
actions; the agent can do each of the actions; but the agent cannot do both or all of the actions. The agent thus seems
condemned to moral failure: no matter what she does, she will do something wrong (or tail to do something that she ought
to do). (Lemmons, 1987).
A moral dilemma is a situation where:
1. You are presented with two or more actions, all of which you have the ability to perform.
2. There are moral reasons for you to choose each of the actions.
3. You cannot perform all of the actions and have to choose which action, or actions when there are three or more choices,
to perform.
Since there are moral reasons for you to choose each action, and you cannot choose them all, it follows that no matter what
choice you make, you will be failing to follow your morals. In other words, someone or something will suffer no matter
what choice you make, for example, your friend will suffer if you tell the truth, and you will likely lose your friendship. But
you don't tell the truth, you will be a iar and possibly a lawbreaker, and your friend will get arrested for a crime she did not
commit.
What is Culture?
Culture is derived from the Latin word “cultura” or “cultus” which means care or cultivation. Culture as
cultivation implies that every human being is a potential member of his own social group. He is endowed with certain innate
qualities to make use. However, he cannot develop these inborn talents without the other people. He/she needs other people
who can provide him/her with the needed opportunities so he/she can translate these potentialities into realities called
achievements. These accomplishments not only help him achieve self-actualization but also make him/her a contributing
member of his society.
Anthropologist Edward B. Tylor, an Englishman, developed one of the classic definitions of culture. He said,
"Culture is that complex whole which includes knowledge, belief, law, art, moral, custom, and other capabilities and habits
acquired as a member of society." In other words, culture refers to the totality e the humanly created world, from material
culture and cultivated landscapes, via social institutions (political, religious, economic etc.), to knowledge and meaning
something that human has created and learned in a society. His theory defines culture in descriptive terms as the "complex
whole" that makes up social ideas and institutions.
In Tylor's view, culture includes all aspects of human activity, from the fine arts to popular entertainment, from
everyday behavior to the development of sophisticated technology. It contains the plan, rules, techniques, designs and
policies for living. On the other hand, sociologists defined culture as the entire way of life followed by people, and
everything learned and shared by people in society. (Hunt, et. al, 1994). According to Landis (1992), culture is a complex
set of learned and shared beliefs, customs, skills, habits, traditions, and knowledge common to members of society.
Cultural Relativism
Cultural relativism is the ability to understand a culture on its own terms and not to make judgments using the
standards of one's Own culture. The goal of this is promote understanding of cultural practices that are not typically part of
one's own culture. Using the perspective of cultural relativism leads to the view that no one culture is superior than another
culture when compared to systems a concept that cultural norms and values derive of morality, law, politics, etc. It is a
concept that cultural norms and values derive their meaning within a specific social context. This is also based on the idea
that there is no absolute standard of good or evil, therefore every decision and of what is right and wrong is individually
decided in each society. The judgment concept of cultural relativism also means that any opinion on ethics is subject to the
perspective of each person within their particular culture. Overall, there is no right or wrong ethical system. In a holistic
understanding of the term cultural relativism, it tries to promote the understanding of cultural practices that are unfamiliar
to other cultures such as eating insects or genital cutting (Leano, 1995).
Cultural relativism is considered to be more constructive and p conception as compared to ethnocentrism. It permits
to see an individual's habits values and morals in the context of his or her cultural relevance not by comparing it to one's
own cultural values and by deeming these the most superior and greater of all.
Cultural relativism is a method or procedure for explaining sand interpreting other people's culture. It offers
anthropologists a means of investigating other societies without imposing ethnocentric assumptions (Scupin, 2000).
Cultural relativism is widely accepted in modern anthropology. Cultural relativists believe that all cultures are
worthy in their own right and are of equal value. Diversity of cultures, even those with conflicting moral beliefs, is not to
be considered in terms of right and wrong or good and bad. Today's anthropologists consider all cultures to be equally
legitimate expressions of human existence, to be studied from a purely neutral perspective. Cultural relativism is closely
related to ethical relativism, which views truth as variable and not absolute. What constitutes right and wrong is determined
solely by the individual or by society. Since truth is not objective, there can be no objective standard which applies to all
cultures. No one can say if someone else is right or wrong; it is a matter of personal opinion, and no society can pass
judgment on another society (Ladd, 1973).
Cultural relativism sees nothing inherently wrong (and nothing, inherently good) with any cultural expression. So,
the ancient Mayan practices of self-mutilation and human sacrifice are neither good nor bad; they are simply cultural
distinctive, akin to the American custom of shooting fireworks on the fourth of July. Human sacrifice and fireworks – both
are simply different products of separate socialization. Marriage practices of Muslims should not be judged based on the
culture of the Roman Catholics is one example. The celebration of fiesta in the Philippines should not look into by other
nation as too much religiosity.
3. Courtship – We Filipinos are very romantic when it comes to heart affairs. Serenading or harana in Tagalog is one of
the most popular forms of courtship to show that a man is very serious with his intentions to a woman. A serenade would
require the young man to sing a love song in front of the young lady's house. Normally, he is accompanied by his male
friends who act as back-up singers. The man himself or his friend played the instrument, usually a guitar, which provides
the background music to his song. They would have to wait until the young lady opened a window to listen. It would be up
to her if she wanted to invite them in for some refreshment and to chat after the song. Even if they had been asked to come
in, the suitor would not expect that he could have the chance of a private moment with his object of affection. It was highly
likely that the parents would also be there to entertain the man and his friends.
4. Religion – The Philippines is one of two predominantly Roman Catholic nations in Asia-Pacific. Their habit of going to
church and often praying reflects that Filipinos have a deep faith and belief when it comes to religion. They are very devoted
to religions that sometimes many take the risk of their lives just to touch the Black Nazarene (in Quiapo, Manila). For many,
it is just a choice between their faith and fears. Filipinos believe that having a strong devotion may lead to a better life and
their guidance to face everyday life.
5. Superstition – In the Philippines, superstitious beliefs have grown throughout the country. These beliefs have come from
the different sayings and beliefs of our ancestors that aim to prevent danger from happening or to make a person refrain
from doing something in particular. These beliefs are part of our culture, for one derives his/her beliefs from the influences
of what his/her customs, traditions, and culture have dictated to explain certain phenomena or to scare people. Some are
practiced primarily because Filipinos believe that there is nothing to lose if they will comply with these beliefs.
6. Mariage and Wedding Customs – In the country, marriage is a sacred union of man and woman after a period of
courtship and engagement. It is a sacrament between two people who love each other. For many Filipinos, the eternal quality
of dedication to God pervades a truly sacred marriage. A sacred marriage is a covenant between two who love each other
in God and with God, whose joining becomes an expression of the desire of each to love and serve God together.
7. Death – Death in the Philippines is one of the most important occasions in family life. For many Filipinos, a death of a
relative is an opportunity to strengthen ties in the family. To pay respect and honor the relationship to the deceased, long
lost relatives, friends, and even relatives working abroad are reunited. The Philippines is the home of some unique death
rituals that are partly religious and mostly superstitious. The mourning and the weeping are still present, but a happy and
welcoming atmosphere would usually envelop the place to help the deceased on his/her journey to the afterlife. After the
death of a person, a nine-day period of having a novena of prayers and masses offered up to the deceased is held, although
the beginning of the “siyam na araw” varies, but usually ends the week after the death. Another period follows after death,
the 40-day mourning period. Family members indicate their state of bereavement by wearing a small, black rectangular
plastic pin on their left breast or breast pocket area. A ceremonial mass is held at the end of this 40-day period. Common
belief states that the soul goes to Heaven after these 40 days, following the belief that Jesus Christ ascended to Heaven after
the said period of days.
8. Society – The primary ancestors of Filipinos are Malays who came from southeastern Asian country. 1he Philippines is
á combined society. Bos singular and plural in form, It ts singular as one nation, but plural in that is fragmented
geographically and culturally. The nation is divided between Christians, Muslims, and other religious-ethno-linguistic
groups; between urban and rural people; between upland and lowland people; and between the rich and the poor. Although
different in numerous Ways, the Filipinos are very hospitable and give appropriate respect to everybody regardless of race,
culture and belief.
9. Christmas in the Philippines is considered as one of the biggest holidays in the archipelago. We earned the distinction
of celebrating the world's longest Christmas season with Christmas carols heard as early as September and lasting until
Epiphany, the feast of the Black Nazarene on January 9 or the Feast of the Santo Niño de Cebu on the third Sunday of
January. In one article, Archbishop Cruz told in his Christmas message that "the essence of Christmas is God made flesh,
God who has come among us" in an act of love "that joins humankind to the Living God through our Lord Jesus Christ."
For many Filipinos, the true essence of Christmas is not gift giving but sharing this special holy day with family.
10. Fiestas – Every town and city in the Philippines has a fiesta of its own; whatever time of the year it is, there's sure to be
a fiesta going on somewhere. Fiestas in the Philippines are held to celebrate a patron saint. It is part and parcel of Filipino
culture through good times and bad times, it must go on. The biggest and most elaborate festival of all is Christmas, a season
celebrated with all the pomp and pageantry where the whole country breaks out in celebrations that can begin long before
December.
For individual Filipinos, fiestas can be a way of supplicating the heavens or to make amends for past wrongs. It is
a way to celebrate their blessings, commemorate their past and observe solemn religious rituals. Celebrations may take the
form of music, dancing, feasting, beauty contests, balls, processions, sports challenges or a host of other events. Spanish
influence is evident in the elaborate masks, makeup, headdresses and costumes worn by the revelers; outfits which often
take months of preparation.
11. Living with Parents – Filipinos highly value the presence of family more than anything. Adult children living with
their parents are another Filipino traditional that make them exceptional. Unlike in the United States where children leave
the home after finishing high school or college, many Filipinos continue living with parents until they get married. (Abundo,
2015)
Introduction
Human basics can be seen as a first universally designed and coherent philosophy of most basic knowledge for any
human, wherever on the world and regardless of culture, religion, education or status. It consists of generally recognized
and established knowledge, generally verifiable observation, and some basic theories and conclusions, and combined with
a number of basic theses it makes up a universal philosophy of human basics. This philosophy of most basic knowledge is
in the first place about an understanding and awareness of our human nature, and our most basic universal human values. It
contains a concise basic information about social, psychological, cultural and moral human qualities and basic universal
human values in relation to political, economic, ecological, religious, judicial and educational issues in all societies. By its
nature this basic knowledge tends to create a basic understanding and more agreement between people and cultures.
However, by its basic and realistic nature, some of this information can also be experienced as confronting.
Human beings are endowed with spiritual capacities. This is a fact testified to by the founders of all the world
religions as well as by sages and philosophers throughout history. An understanding of these positive virtues and values
gives individuals and societies the moral accountability that is the basis of human integrity. Mere knowledge of ideals and
principles is not enough. There is always the need to translate the ideals into action. The development of civilization has
occurred in a spiral pattern with seasons of enlightenment and periods of darkness, but with constant advancement.
Confidence in the advent of human maturity and global community provides the foundation for world peace.
Kohlberg identified three levels of moral reasoning: pre-conventional, conventional, and post-conventional: Each level is
associated with increasingly complex stages of moral development.
CHAPTER 4: THE ACT
Lesson 1: Ethical Requirements
Objectives:
At the end of the chapter, the students will be able to:
1. Recall immediate responses to moral dilemmas;
2. Differentiate responses based on reason and those based in feelings;
3. Compare reasonable and emotional responses;
4. Check real life cases against moral reasoning model;
5. Differentiate reason from will; and
6. Explain the role of mental frames in moral experience.
Introduction
During the last thirty years R. M. Hare has developed and defended a metaethical view about the meaning of moral
language which he calls "universal prescriptivism" (Potter, et.al, 1985). During this time Hare has also professed allegiance
to a normative theory which constitutes a version of preference utilitarianism. What has never been made entirely clear,
however, is his conception of the relationship between those two theories. In his earlier writings Hare maintained that:
Ethical theory provides only a clarification of the conceptual framework within which moral reasoning takes place; it is,
therefore, in the required sense, neutral as between different moral opinions. On my view, there is absolutely no content for
a moral prescription that is ruled out by logic or by the definition of terms. Fortunately, Hare's most recent writings shed
considerable light on these issues. In his important paper, "Ethical Theory and Utilitarianism", and in his recent book, Moral
Thinking, Hare appears to have modified his theory in at least one very important respect. He now holds that universal
prescriptivism is not only not normatively neutral but in fact entails preference.
Based on Hare's view, to prescribe acting in accordance with a universal moral principle from which, in conjunction
with statements specifying one's beliefs concerning the relevant facts, the judgment can be derived. To in turn determine
whether one can prescribe acting in accordance with a universal principle is to determine whether one would actually choose
to perform that action if one knew that one would have to play, in a series of possible worlds otherwise identical to the
actual world, the role of each person (including oneself) who would be affected. Moreover, it is not enough that one simply
imagines oneself, with one's own interests, in the place of those other persons – rather, one must imagine oneself as being
in their place while having, in turn, their interests and desires.
What is Reason?
Reason is the capacity for consciously making sense of things, establishing and verifying facts, applying logic, and
changing or justifying practices, institutions, and beliefs based on new or existing information (Kompridis, 2000). It is
closely associated with such characteristically human activities as philosophy, science, language, mathematics, and art and
is normally considered to be a distinguishing ability possessed by humans. Reason, or an aspect of it, is sometimes referred
to as rationality.
Reasoning is associated with thinking, cognition, and intellect. The philosophical field of logic studies ways in
which humans reason formally through argument (Hintikka, 2013). Reason is a declaration made to explain or justify action,
decision, or conviction.
The proper role of ethical reasoning is to highlight acts of two kinds: those which enhance the well-being of others-
that warrant our praise- and those that harm or diminish the well-being of others-- and thus warrant our criticism. Developing
one's ethical reasoning abilities is crucial because there is in human nature a strong tendency toward egotism, prejudice,
self-justification, and self-deception. These tendencies are exacerbated by powerful sociocentric cultural influences that
shape our lives- not least of which is the mass media. These tendencies can be actively opposed only through the systematic
cultivation of fair-mindedness, honesty, integrity, self-knowledge, and deep concern for the welfare of others. We can never
eliminate our egocentric tendencies absolutely and finally. But we can actively fight them as we learn to develop as ethical
persons.
Reasons have everything to do with ethics: if you have no good reasons for an act or a belief, then you can't have
thought it through very well and maybe you shouldn't be doing it or believing it at all. It's quite scary to think that there are
people out there who are voting, protesting, financing causes, or running campaigns without any clear idea of why they are
doing it. Each and every one of us should be clear about our reasons for our values, beliefs, and behaviors, and we should
each be able to give a reasoned account of them to others.
If someone asks you why you believe or act as you do, don't just say, “Because I believe (or act) that way.” Give
them a reason why but before you give a reason why, ask yourself why-and keep on asking yourself why. Only then will
your life become meaningful to you. Giving reasons for our actions is important socially, too. It either connects us to others
or divides us from them. So much of our social life depends on a shared understanding of what’s true, right, and appropriate.
When this understanding breaks down, the only way to restore it is by asking the reason why we disagree with one another.
Predicting Consequences
Moral reasoning involves predicting the consequences of an action before we act. There are always consequences
when we take the action, we think is right, and when we try to be good persons, and usually these include unintended as
well as intended outcomes. When the likely beneficial outcomes of acting on an ethical presumption seem to outweigh the
likely adverse outcomes, then predicting consequences confirms our presumption. But when we predict that the adverse
consequences will outweigh the beneficial consequences, even when we are obeying an ethical rule or following an inspiring
story, then we should consider whether to make an exception to the rule or to look to a different story for guidance. We
must remember, however, that before we act, we can never know for certain what the consequences will be. Therefore, we
should take care in predicting what will result from acting on an ethical presumption. In doing ethics, we look at rules (about
duty and rights) and at stories (about character and relationships) to construct a presumption, and then test this presumption
by predicting what we do know (and don't know) about the likely consequences of acting on it.
Impartiality
Impartiality also called evenhandedness or fair-mindedness is a principle of justice holding that decisions should
be based on objective criteria, rather than on the basis of bias, prejudice, or preferring the benefit to one person over another
tor improper reasons (Wikipedia). Someone who is impartial is not directly involved in a particular situation, and is,
therefore, able to give a fair opinion or decision about it. We might be impartial because this promotes our desire to be fair
or because it promotes our well-being and self-respect and earns us social approval. Or we might appeal to the social good,
or to the inherent badness of violating impartiality. Impartiality makes no discrimination as to nationality, race, religious
beliefs, class or political opinions. It endeavors to relieve the suffering of individuals, being guided solely by their needs,
and to give priority to the most urgent cases of distress.
Ethics vs Feelings
Many times, there's a conflict between what we naturally feel and what is considered to be ethical. Our subconscious
reaction to a news event might be hatred, jealousy or other negative feelings, but we might not be able to morally argue why
we feel that way. My guess is that the human race developed those subconscious reactions as an evolutionary mechanism
to survive. Our ancestors wouldn't have been able to find and obtain food if they hadn't fought for it. Arguing about ethics
would've meant that you’ll have to stay hungry and die. The problem is most of our feelings in today's world are unethical,
politically incorrect or even outright harmful. It takes a great deal of effort to retrospect and self-analyze our feelings to
judge whether they are ethical or not. Let us take a few common examples and see how to tackle those feelings Groupism,
Patriotism, Dunbar's number, Negative feelings to content on Social Networks,
1. Groupism
a. Natural feeling: I am part of a group. I am supposed to help this group become better. I am also supposed to compete
with other groups.
b. Reasoning: Being part of a herd made it easier for us ancestors to survive in the wild. There were so many survival
benefits that belonging to a group brought. Naturally, our ancestors started developing good feelings about belonging to a
group.
c. Ethical viewpoint: Help the group. Help other groups too. There is no compelling reason to compete in today's times of
peace.
2. Patriotism
a. Natural feeling: I was born in a place. I am supposed to help people in the geographical vicinity around me. There are
human-decided borders that define my country. Those outside the border don't deserve that much attention as those inside
the border do.
b. Reasoning: Patriotism is Groupism in a higher scale. Most borders were drawn for political benefits by a small group of
individuals running that country. There have been countless stories of propaganda by governments to motivate people to
join their wars to fight people over borders. We humans tend to justify these efforts as noble.
c. Ethical viewpoint: Wars are always bad. There is no reason to be proud of your country just because you were born in
it. It is okay to be in your country and help your country because you are used to it. But it is also okay to move to other
countries and help those countries.
3. Dunbar’s number
a. Natural feeling: I cannot maintain more than 150 stable relationships.
b. Reasoning: Our brains have limited capacity and it becomes mentally hard to maintain more relationships.
c. Ethical viewpoint: Acceding to the Dunbar's number promotes Groupism. Just as we push ourselves to become better
humans, we should also try to push the Dunbar number limit further. Accepting that all life forms in this world (and outside
the world if life exists) are part of the same group counters the negative effects of Groupism.
4. Negative feelings to content on Social Networks
a. Natural feeling: I hate what’s being posted on Facebook. They are just stupid selfies, people gloating their achievements
or just distracting. unproductive content.
b. Reasoning: Many of us have been taught to compete with others since our childhood. We tend to compare ourselves with
others. We don't like selfies because they are attention-seeking and we look down upon those who seek attention.
Distracting, unproductive content is noise to us and we cannot handle too much noise in our daily life.
C. Ethical viewpoint: We don't have to compete with our friends. We can applaud their life achievements without
comparing our lives with theirs.
We don't have to look down upon those who seek attention. Comedians, actors and other entertainers are attention-seeking.
But we don't look down upon them. 1t1s up to us to filter out noise in our lives. Social networks aren't thrusted into our
face. We can choose to stay away from them if they are noisy. Or even better, adjust the content shown in our feed and tailor
it to our comfort.
Conclusion
It is easy to give in to our feelings. An analogy would be with unhealthy foods. It is easy to choose unhealthy foods
because they are tasty and easy to prepare. But we hit the gym, avoid those foods and exercise because we want to become
better individuals. Similarly, we can take the ethical route, avoid negative feelings and exercise those reactions because we
want to become better individuals.
Moral Theories
Through the ages, there have emerged multiple common moral theories and traditions. We will cover each one
briefly below with explanations and how they differ from other moral theories. Consequentialism. Consequentialist theories,
unlike virtue and deontological theories, hold that only the consequences, or outcomes, of actions matter morally. According
to this view, acts are deemed to be morally right solely on the basis of their consequences. For instance, most people would
agree that lying is wrong. But if telling a lie would help save a person's life, consequentialism says it’s the right thing to do.
Consequentialism is sometimes criticized because it can be difficult, or even impossible, to know what the result of
an action will be ahead of time. Indeed, no one can know the future with certainty. Also, in certain situations,
consequentialism can lead to decisions that are objectionable, even though the consequences are arguably good.
Consequentialism is based on two principles:
1. Whether an act is right or wrong depends only on the results of that act;
2. The better consequences an act produces, the better or more right that act.
It gives us this guidance when faced with a moral dilemma: A person should choose the action that maximizes good
consequences and it gives this general guidance on how to live: People should live so as to maximize good consequences.
Moral Subjectivism. Right and wrong is determined by what you, the subject, just happens to think or ‘feel’ is
right or wrong. In its common form, Moral Subjectivism amounts to the denial of moral principles of any significant kind,
and the possibility of moral criticism and argumentation. In essence, ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ lose their meaning because so long
as someone thinks or feels that some action is right, there are no grounds for criticism. If you are a moral subjectivist, you
cannot object to anyone’s behavior assuming people are in fact acting in accordance with what they think or feel is right.
This shows the key flaw in moral subjectivism probably nearly everyone thinks that it is legitimate to object, on moral
grounds, to at least some peoples' actions. That is, it is possible to disagree about moral issues (Brandt, 1959).
Moral Subjectivism holds that there are no objective moral properties and that ethical statements are in fact arbitrary
because they do not express immutable truths. Instead, moral statements are made true or false by the attitudes and/or
conventions of the observers, and any ethical sentence just implies an attitude, opinion, personal preference or feeling held
by someone. Thus, for a statement to be considered morally right merely means that it is met with approval by the person
of interest. Another way of looking at this is that judgments about human conduct are shaped by, and in many ways limited
to, perception.
There are different types of Moral Subjectivism:
1. Simple Subjectivism: the view that ethical statements reflect sentiments, personal preferences and feelings rather than
objective facts.
2. Individualist Subjectivism: the view originally put forward by Protagoras, that there are as many distinct scales of good
and evil as there are individuals in the world. It is effectively a form of Egoism, which maintains that every human being
ought to pursue what is in his or her self-interest exclusively.
3. Moral Relativism (or Ethical Relativism): the view that for a thing to be morally right is for it to be approved of by
society, leading to the conclusion that different things are right for people in different societies and different periods in
history.
4. ldeal Observer Theory: the view that what is right is determined by the attitudes that a hypothetical ideal observer (a
being who is perfectly rational, imaginative and informed) would have. Adam Smith and David Hume espoused early
versions of the ldeal Observer Theory, and Roderick Firth (1917-1987) is responsible for a more sophisticated modern
version.
5. Ethical Egoism. Right and wrong is determined by what is in your self-interest. Or, it is immoral to act contrary to your
self-interest.
Ethical Egoism is usually based upon Psychological Egoism - that we, by nature, act selfishly. Ethical egoism does
not imply hedonism or that we ought to aim for at least some 'higher' goods example, wisdom, political success, but rather
that we will ideally act so as to maximize our self-interest. This may require that we forego some immediate pleasures for
the sake of achieving some long-term goals. Also, ethical egoism does not exclude helping others However, egoists will
help others only if this will further their own interests. An ethical egoist will claim that the altruist helps others only because
He wants to (perhaps because he/she derives pleasure out of helping others) or because he/she thinks there will be some
personal advantage in doing so. That is, they deny the possibility of genuine altruism (because they think we are all by
nature selfish). This leads us to the key implausibility of Ethical Egoism that the person who helps others at the expense of
his/her self-interest is actually acting immorally. Many think that the ethical egoist has misunderstood the concept of
morality - i.e., morality is the system of practical reasoning through which we are guided to constrain our self-interest, not
further it. Also, that genuine altruism is indeed possible, and relatively commonly exhibited.
6. Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, first popularized by British philosophers Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill in the 19th
century, is a theory that holds that the best way to make a moral decision is to look at the potential consequences of each
available choice, and then pick the option that either does most to increase happiness or does least to increase suffering.
Utilitarianism, also known as consequentialism, is often summed up asa philosophy of "The greatest good for the greatest
number." (NOTE: This is discussed fully in the succeeding chapter)
7. Deontology. Deontology or Deontological Ethics is an approach to Ethics that focuses on the rightness or wrongness of
actions themselves, as opposed to the rightness or wrongness of the consequences of those actions (Consequentialism) or to
the character and habits of the actor (Virtue Ethics). What makes a choice "right" is its conformity with a moral norm: Right
takes priority over Good.
The word ‘deontology’ derives from the Greek words deon for duty and logos for science (or study). In
contemporary moral philosophy, deontology is one of those kinds of normative theories regarding which choices are morally
required, forbidden, or permitted. In other words, deontology falls within the domain of moral theories that guide and assess
our choices of what we ought to do (deontic theories), in contrast to those that guide and assess what kind of person we are
and should be.
Deontology is a duty-based moral theory. Deontology states that society needs rules in order to function, and that a
person can only be called moral to the extent that he abides by those rules. The most famous and eloquent exponent of
deontology is generally agreed to be Immanuel Kant. Kant coined the following maxim, known as the Categorical
Imperative, to help people decide which actions should be governed by rules, "Act only according to that maxim by which
you can also will that it would become a universal law" In other words, people should only do things that they would be
happy to see everyone does. For example, people shouldn't lie, because if everyone lies all the time then society would
collapse.
Deontology is simple to apply. It just requires that people follow the rules and do their duty. This approach tends to
fit well with our natural intuition about what is or isn't ethical. Kant's deontology, sometimes called deontological ethics,
starts by acknowledging that actions and their outcomes are independent things. Basically, there are things you have to do,
even though you know they are wrong, such as shooting that intruder to protect your family. According to deontology, you
need to focus on the act, such as protecting your family, and not the likely death it will mean for the intruder.
8. Virtue Ethics. A virtue is an excellent trait of character. It is a disposition, well entrenched in its possess or something
that, as we say, goes all the way down, o notice, expect, value, feel, desire, choose, act, and react in certain characteristic
ways. Virtue ethics emphasizes an individual's character as the key element of ethical thinking, rather than rules about the
acts themselves (Deontology) or their consequences (Consequentialism). To possess a virtue is to bea certain sort of person
with a certain complex mindset. A significant aspect of this mindset is the wholehearted acceptance of a distinctive range
of considerations as reasons for action. Virtue ethics states that only good people can make good moral decisions. Therefore,
the best way to be moral is to constantly seek to improve oneself. Virtue ethicists list a number of qualities that they believe
are universal, and are appreciated in all cultures. They include wisdom, prudence, loyalty, honesty, temperance, bravery,
magnanimity, and justice. Virtue ethicists argue that if a person tries his best to embody these traits, then by definition he
will always be in a good position to make moral judgments.
There are three main elements of Virtue Ethics:
1. Eudaimonism. It is the classical formulation of Virtue Ethics. It holds that the proper goal of human life is eudaimonia
(which can be variously translated as "happiness," "well-being" or the "good life"), and that this' goal can be achieved by a
lifetime of practicing "arête" (the virtues) in one's everyday activities, subject to the exercise of "phronesis" (practical
wisdom) to resolve any conflicts or dilemmas which might arise. Indeed, such a virtuous life would in itself constitute
eudaimonia, which should be seen as an objective, not a subjective, state, characterized by the well-lived life, irrespective
of the emotional state of the person experiencing it. A virtue is a habit or quality that allows individuals to succeed at their
purpose. Therefore, Virtue Ethics is only intelligible if it is teleological example, it includes an account of the purpose or
meaning of human life, a matter of some contention among philosophers since the beginning of time. Aristotle, with whom
Virtue Ethics is largely identified, categorized the virtues as moral virtues (including prudence, justice, fortitude and
temperance) and intellectual virtues (including "sophia" or theoretical wisdom), and "phronesis" or practical wisdom.
Aristotle further argued that each of the moral virtues was a golden mean, or desirable middle ground, between two
undesirable extremes. For example, the virtue of courage is a mean between the two vices of cowardice and foolhardiness.
This character-based approach to morality assumes that we acquire virtue through practice. By practicing being honest,
brave, just, generous, and so on, a person develops an honorable and moral character. According to Aristotle, by honing
virtuous habits, people will likely make the right choice when faced with ethical challenges.
2. Ethics of Care was developed mainly by Feminist writers Annette Baier (1987) in the second half of the 20th century,
and was motivated by the idea that men think in masculine terms such as justice and autonomy, whereas women think in
feminine terms such as caring. It calls for a change in how we view morality and the virtues, shifting towards virtues
exemplified by women, such as taking care of others, patience, the ability to nurture, self-sacrifice, etc., which have been
marginalized because society has not adequately valued the contributions of women. It emphasizes the importance of
solidarity, community and relationships rather than universal standards and impartiality. It argues that instead of doing the
right thing even if it requires personal cost or sacrificing the interest of family or community members, as the traditional
consequentialist and deontological approaches suggest, we can, and indeed should, put the interests of those who are close
to us above the interests of complete strangers.
Agent-Based Theories, as developed recently by Michael Slote (1993), give an account of virtue based on our
common-sense intuitions about which character traits are admirable (e.g. benevolence, kindness, compassion, etc.), which
we can identify by looking at the people we admire, our moral exemplars. The evaluation of actions is therefore dependent
on ethical judgments about the inner life of the agents who perform those actions.
The Theory of Natural Rights. Natural rights theorists believe that every person is endowed with certain
inalienable rights, such as the right to life, the right to own property, and the right to liberty. Natural rights theorists argue
that these rights are self-evident, and would exist even if nobody believed in them. The reason that natural rights theorists
hold these rights as self- evident is that they are essential to the flourishing of human happiness and the foundation of civil
society. For example, they argue that without the right to own property, there is no incentive to create property and therefore
there is no mechanism by which society can advance (Pangle, l985).
Locke believed that the most basic human law of nature is the preservation mankind. To serve that purpose. he
reasoned, individuals have both a right a tuty to preserve their own lives. Murderers, however, forfeit their right to life since
they act outside the law of reason.
Locke also argued that individuals should be free to make choices about how to conduct their own lives as long as
they do not interfere with the liberty of others. Locke therefore believed liberty should be far-reaching. By “property,”
Locke meant more than land and goods that could be sold, given away, or even confiscated by the government under certain
circumstances. Property also referred to ownership of one's self, which included a right to personal well-being. Jefferson,
however, substituted the phrase, “pursuit of happiness,” which Locke and others had used to describe freedom of opportunity
as well as the duty to help those in want.
The purpose of government, Locke wrote, is to secure and protect the God-given inalienable natural rights of the
people. For their part, the people must obey the laws of their rulers. Thus, a sort of contract exists between the rulers and
the ruled but, Locke concluded, if a government persecutes its people with “a long train of abuses” over an extended period,
the people have the right to resist that government, alter or abolish it, and create a new political system.
3. Moral Relativism. Moral relativism is a theory which states that no one person's morals are better or worse than any
other. Relativists argue that a person's moral code is shaped by the society in which he is raised, and that no society is
inherently better or worse than any other.
Normative moral relativism is the idea that all societies should accept each other's differing moral values, given that
there are no universal moral principles.
Moral relativism is on the opposite end of the continuum from moral absolutism, which says that there is always
one right answer to any ethical question. Indeed, those who adhere to moral relativism would say, "When in Rome, do as
the Romans do." Relativistic positions may specifically see moral values as applicable only within certain cultural
boundaries (Cultural Relativism) or in the context of individual preferences (Ethical Subjectivism). A related but slightly
different concept is that of Moral Pluralism (or Value Pluralism), the idea that there are several values which may be equally
correct and fundamental, and yet conflict with each other example, the moral life of a nun is incompatible with that of a
mother, yet there is no purely rational measure of which is preferable (Rachels, 1999).
Introduction
Certain early Greeks from lonia (Asia Minor) and southern Italy asked questions about the world around them.
Instead of attributing its creation to anthropomorphic gods, these early philosophers’ broke tradition and sought rational
explanations. Their speculation formed the early basis for science and natural philosophy. After about the 4th or 5th century
A.D., Europe entered the so-called Dark Ages, during which little or no new thought was developed. By the 11th century,
though, there was a renewed flowering of thought, both in Christian Europe and in Muslim and Jewish Middle East. Most
of the philosophers of this time were mainly concerned with proving the existence of God and with reconciling Christianity/
Islam with the classical philosophy of Greece (particularly Aristotelianism). This period also saw the establishment of the
first universities, which was an important factor in the subsequent development of philosophy.
Aristotle on Ethics
The most famous and thorough of Aristotle's ethical works is his Nicomachean Ethics. This work is an inquiry into
the best life for human beings to live. The life of human flourishing or happiness (eudaimonia) is the best life. It is important
to note that what we translate as "happiness" is quite different for Aristotle than it is for us. We often consider happiness to
be a mood or an emotion, but Aristotle considers it to be an activity--a way of living one's life. Thus, it is possible for one
to have an overall happy life, even if that life has its moments of sadness and pain (Barnes, 1984).
Happiness is the practice of virtue or excellence (arete), and so it is important to know the two types of virtue:
character virtue, the discussion of which makes up the bulk of the Ethics, and intellectual virtue. Character excellence comes
about through habit-one habituates oneself to character excellence by knowingly practicing virtues. To be clear, it is possible
to perform an excellent action accidentally or without knowledge, but doing so would not make for an excellent person, just
as accidentally writing in a grammatically correct way does not make for a grammarian. One must be aware that one is
practicing the life of virtue (Broadie, 1991).
Aristotle arrives at the idea that " the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue" is the best life for human beings
through the "human function" argument. If, says Aristotle, human beings have a function or work (ergon) to perform, then
we can know that performing that function well will result in the best sort of life. The work or function of an eve is to see
and to see well. Just as each part of the body has a function, says Aristotle, so too must the human being as a whole have a
function. This is an argument by analogy. The function of the human being is logos or reason, and the more thoroughly one
lives the life of reason, the happier one's life will be (Kraut, 2014).
So, the happiest life is a practice of virtue, and this is practiced under the guidance of reason. Examples of character
virtues would be courage, temperance, liberality, and magnanimity (Rorty, 1984). One must habitually practice these virtues
in order to be courageous, temperate, and so forth. For example, the courageous person knows when to be courageous, and
acts on that knowledge whenever it is appropriate to do. Each activity of any particular character virtue has a related
excessive or deficient action. The excess related to courage, for example, is rashness, and the deficiency is cowardice. Since
excellence is rare, most people will tend more towards an excess or deficiency than towards the excellent action. Aristotle's
advice here is to aim for the opposite of one's typical tendency, and that eventually this will lead one closer to the excellence.
For example, if one tends towards the excess of self-indulgence, it might be best to aim for insensibility, which will
eventually lead the agent closer to temperance.
Friendship is also a necessary part of the happy life. There are three types of friendship, none of which is excusive
of the other: a friendship of excellence, a friendship of pleasure, and a friendship of utility. A friendship of excellence is
based upon virtue, and each friend enjoys and contemplates the excellence of his/ her friend. Since the friend is like another
self, contemplating a friend's virtue will help us in the practice of virtue for ourselves. A mark of good friendship is that
friends "live together," that is that friends spend a substantial amount of time together, since a substantial time apart will
likely weaken the bond of friendship. Also, since the excellent person has been habituated to a life of excellence, his/her
character is generally firm and lasting. Likewise, the friendship of excellence is the least changeable and most lasting form
of friendship.
The friendships of pleasure and use are the most changeable forms of Friendship since the things we find pleasurable
or useful tend to change over a lifetime. For example, if a friendship forms out of a mutual love for beer, but the interest of
one of the friends later turns towards wine, the friendship would likely dissolve, Again, if a friend is merely one of utility,
then that friendship will likely dissolve when it is no longer useful.
Since the best life is a life of virtue or excellence, and since we are closer to excellence the more thoroughly, we
fulfill our function, the best life is the life of theoria or contemplation. This is the most divine life, since one comes closest
to the pure activity of thought. It is the. most self-sufficient life since one can think even when one is alone. What does one
contemplate or theorize about? One contemplates one's knowledge of unchanging things. Some have criticized Aristotle
saying that this sort of life seems uninteresting, since we seem to enjoy, he pursuit of knowledge more than just having
knowledge. For Aristotle, however, the contemplation of unchanging things is an activity full of wonder. Seeking knowledge
might be good, but it is done for the sake of a greater end, namely having knowledge and contemplating what one knows.
For example, Aristotle considered the cosmos to be eternal and unchanging. So, one might have knowledge of astronomy,
but it is the contemplation of what this knowledge is about that is most wonderful. The Greek word theoria is rooted in a
verb for seeing, hence our word "theatre." So, in contemplation or theorizing, one comes face to face with what one knows
(Barnes, 1991).
The way Aristotle sketches the highest good for man as involving both a practical and theoretical side, with the two
sides necessary for each other, is also in the tradition of Socrates and Plato-as opposed to pre-Socratic philosophy. As Burger
(2008) points out "The Ethics does not end at its apparent peak, identifying perfect happiness with the life devoted to theōria;
instead, it goes on to introduce the need for a study of legislation, on the grounds that it is not sufficient only to know about
virtue, but one should try to put that knowledge to use." At the end of the book, according to Burger, the thoughtful reader
is led to understand that "the end we are seeking is what we have been doing" while engaging with the Ethics.
Aristotle also made mention of telos. A telos is derived from the Greek word for “end,” “purpose,” or “goal.” It is
an end or purpose, in a fairly constrained sense used by philosophers such as Aristotle. It is the root of the term "teleology",
roughly the study of purposiveness, or the study of objects with a view to their aims, purposes, or intentions. Teleology
figures centrally in Aristotle's biology and in his theory of causes. It is central to nearly all philosophical theories of history,
such as those of Hegel and Marx. One running debate in modern philosophy of biology is to what extent teleological
language (as in the "purposes" of various organs or life-processes) is unavoidable, or is simply a shorthand for ideas that
can ultimately be spelled out non-teleologically. Philosophy of action also makes essential use of teleological vocabulary:
on Davidson's account, an action is just something an agent does with an intention--that is, looking forward to some end to
be achieved by the action.
Kant on Rights
Immanuel Kant (1724 - 1804) examined the idea of human rights within politics in such a way that it “is only a
legitimate government that guarantees our natural right to freedom, and from this freedom we derive other rights.” From
this basis it can be assumed that Kant looks at the development, creation and implementation of rights as primarily dependent
on the state and how the government within the state functions. Furthermore, Kant stresses that a society can only function
politically in relation to the state if fundamental rights, laws and entitlements are given and enhanced by the state. As Kant
teaches, these righteous laws" are founded upon three rational principles:
1. The liberty of every member of the society as a man
2. The equality of every member of the society with every other, as a subject
3. The independence of every member of the commonwealth as a citizen.
An interesting aspect of these principles is that they are not given by the state, but are fundamental in the creation
and acceptance of a state by the people of the state. In this sense Kant believes that these principles are necessary above all,
not only for the founding of "righteous laws", but for the state to function in the first place. This 1s so because without the
acceptance of the people a state would not exist therefore rights are necessary within states to keep the support of the people
of the state.
The book Metaphysics of Morals has two distinct parts: the “Doctrine of Right” and the “Doctrine of Virtue.”
Kant sought to separate political rights and duties from what we might call morals in the narrow sense. He limits right by
stating three conditions that have to be met for something to be enforceable as right (Byrd, 2010):
1. Right concerns only actions that have influence on other persons, directly or indirectly, meaning duties to the self are
excluded;
2. Right does not concern the wish but only the choice of others, meaning that not mere desires but only decisions which
bring about actions are at stake; and
3. Right does not concern the matter of the other's act but only the form, meaning no particular desires or ends are assumed
on the part of the agents. As an example of the latter, he considers trade, which for right must have the form of being freely
agreed by both parties but can have any matter or purpose the agents want.
These criteria appear to be less rigid than Kant ultimately intends, for the term "influence" is vague enough that it
might include far-reaching minor effects. They would also include under right actions even those imperfect duties that
"influence" others by improving their lot, such as beneficent (humanitarian) acts of charity. While Kant must include
consideration of beneficent action as part of right, he does not conclude that beneficent actions are required by right but
only that most are permitted by right and others violate right. His focus on free individual choice entails that any beneficent
action that interferes with or usurps the recipient's tree choice is wrong, for example, improving the recipient's property
without Permission as opposed to merely donating money to a fund made available to the recipient at the recipient's
discretion (Follesdal et. al, 2014).
In addition to these three conditions for right, Kant also offers direct contrasts between right and virtue, He thinks
both relate to freedom but in different ways right concerns outer freedom and virtue concerns inner freedom being master
of one's own passions. Right concerns act themselves independent of the motive an agent may have for performing them,
virtue concerns the proper motive lor dutiful actions. In another formulation he says that right concerns universality as a
formal condition of freedom while virtue concerns a necessary end beyond the mere formality of universality, thus appearing
to tie the distinction to the first two formulas of the categorical imperative in the Groundwork. In yet another he says that
right concerns narrow duties and virtue wide duties.
In the Feyerabend lectures, Kant notes that right is the subset of morally correct actions that are also coercible These
various alternative formulations of the distinction would exclude imperfect duties not because imperfect duties do not
"influence" others but because. as imperfect they cannot be coerced in particular instances, since imperfect duties always
allow for the moderating role of an individual's inclinations. While these various formulations of the distinction appear to
be quite different, they can in general be summarized by saying that right Concerns outer action corresponding to perfect
duty that affects others regardless of the individual's internal motivations or goals (Ellis, 2012).
Cosmopolitan Rights. Relations among the states of the world, covered above, are not the same as relations among
the peoples (nations, Volk) of the world. Individuals can relate to states of which they are not members and to other
individuals who are members of other states. In this they are considered "citizens of a universal state of human beings" with
corresponding "rights of citizens of the world." Despite these lofty sounding pronouncements, Kant's particular discussion
of cosmopolitan right is restricted to the right of hospitality. Since all peoples share a limited amount of living space due to
the spherical shape of the earth, the totality of which they must be understood to have originally shared în common, they
must be understood to have a right to possible interaction with one another. This cosmopolitan right is limited to a right to
offer to engage in commerce, not a right to actual commerce itself, which must always be voluntary trade. A citizen of one
state may try to establish links with other peoples; no state is allowed to deny foreign citizens a right to travel in its larnd
(Flikschuh, 2014).
Cosmopolitan right is an important component of perpetual peace. Interaction among the peoples of the world, Kant
notes, has increased in recent times. Now "a violation of right on one place of the earth is felt in all" as peoples depend upon
one another and know about one another more and more (8:360). Violations of cosmopolitan right would make more
difficult the trust and cooperation necessary for perpetual peace among states (Hoffe, 2006).
Rights
A right is described as an entitlement or justified claim to a certain kind of positive and negative treatment from
others, to support from others or non- interference from others. n other words, a right is something to which every individual
in the community is morally permitted, and for which that community is entitled to disrespect or compulsorily remove
anything that stands in the way of even a single individual getting it. Rights belong to individuals, and no organization has
any rights not directly derived from those of its members as individuals; and, just as an individual's rights cannot extend to
where they will intrude on another individual's rights, similarly the rights of any organization whatever must yield to those
of a single individual, whether inside or outside the organization. Rights are those important conditions of social life without
which no person can generally realize his best self. These are the essential conditions for health of both the individual and
his society. It is only when people get and enjoy rights that they can develop their personalities and contribute their best
services to the society.
Nature of Rights
Laski's (1935) concepts on the nature of rights are enumerated as follows:
1. Rights are the basic social conditions offered to the individual who is an indispensable member of the society;
2. Rights enable man to fully enhance his personality; to achieve his best self, in the words of Laski they are 'those social
conditions without which no man can seek to be his best self;
3. Rights are inherently social because they are never against social welfare; the rights did not exist before the emergence
of society; they are those fundamental necessities that which are very much social;
4. The state plays the role of recognizing and protecting the rights by providing for the full maintenance and observance of
the rights;
5. Rights are never absolute, the nature and extent for the fulfillment of the rights are relative; as long men endeavor for the
upliftment and betterment of the conditions of life, rights continue to serve as means for the satisfaction and gratification of
individual's needs; so there can be no rights which are absolute in nature because absolute rights are a contradiction in terms;
6. Rights are dynamic in nature because the essence and contents of rights vary according to change in place, time and
conditions.
Kinds of Rights
Hereunder are the different kinds of rights, namely:
1. Natural rights – Many researchers have faith in natural rights. They stated that people inherit several rights from nature.
Before they came to live and state, they used to live in a state of nature. In it, they appreciated certain natural rights, like the
right to life, right to liberty and right to property. Natural rights are parts of human nature and reason. Political theory
maintains that an individual enters into society with certain basic rights and that no government can deny these rights. John
Locke (1632-1704), the most influential political philosophers of the modern period, argued that people have rights, such
as the right to life, liberty, and property that have a foundation independent of the laws of any particular Society. Locke
claimed that men are naturally free and equal as part of the justification for understanding legitimate political government
as the result of a social contract where people in the state of nature conditionally transfer some of their rights to the
government in order to better ensure the stable, comfortable enjoyment of their lives, liberty, and property. Since
governments exist by the consent of the people in order to protect the rights of the people and promote the public good,
governments that fail to do so can be resisted and replaced with new governments.
2. Moral rights – Moral rights are based on human consciousness. They are supported by moral force of human mind.
These are based on human sense of goodness and justice. These are not assisted by the force of law. Sense of goodness and
public opinion are the sanctions behind moral rights. If any person disrupts any moral right, no legal action can be taken
against him. The state does not enforce these rights. Its courts do not recognize these rights. Moral rights include rules of
good conduct, courtesy and of moral behavior. These stand for moral perfection of the people.
3. Legal rights – Legal rights s are those rights which are accepted and enforced by the state. Any defilement of any legal
right is punished by law. Law courts of the state enforce legal rights. These rights can be enforced against individuals and
also against the government. In this way, legal rights are different from al rights. Legal moral rights are equally available to
all the citizens. All citizens follow legal rights without any discrimination. They can go to the courts for getting their legal
rights enforced
Categorical Imperative
The Categorical Imperative was devised by Immanuel Kant to provide a set of requirements a maxim (or
motivation) must pass in order for the action to be considered a moral obligation. When a Categorical Imperative is
established, it becomes one's moral duty to carry out the action under any circumstances. When carrying out this action, the
individual's primary motive should always be duty according to Kant; this is because we can decipher what our duty is by
using our reason. Human's ability to reason is what deciphers us from animals and so, logically, must be part of being a
moral agent. Reason is objective and universal for humanity and so is a reliable and reasonable basis for a moral theory.
Kant characterized the Categorical Imperative as an objective, rationally necessary and unconditional principle that
we must always follow despite any natural desires or inclinations we may have to the contrary. All specific moral
requirements, according to Kant, are justified by this principle, which means that all immoral actions are irrational because
they violate the Categorical Imperative.
Kant argued that conformity to the CI (a non-instrumental principle), and hence to moral requirements themselves,
can nevertheless be shown to be essential to rational agency. This argument was based on his striking doctrine that a rational
will must be regarded as autonomous, or free, in the sense of being the author of the law that binds it. The fundamental
principle of morality the – CI – is none other than the law of an autonomous will (Patton, 1947).
Utilitarianism
Though the first systematic account of utilitarianism was developed by Jeremy Bentham, the core insight motivating
the theory occurred much earlier. That insight is that morally appropriate behavior will not harm others, but instead increase
happiness or utility' What is distinctive about utilitarianism is its approach in taking that insight and developing an account
of moral evaluation and moral direction that expands on it. Early precursors to the Classical Utilitarians include the British
Moralists, Cumberland, Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Gay, and Hume. Of these, Francis Hutcheson (1694-1746) is explicitly
utilitarian when it comes to action choice (Scarre, 1996).
Some of the earliest utilitarian thinkers were the 'theological’ utilitarians such as Richard Cumberland (1631-1718)
and John Gay (1699-1745). They believed that promoting human happiness was incumbent on us since it was approved by
God.
Gay (1731) held that since God wants the happiness of mankind, and since God's will gives us the criterion of virtue,
"... the happiness of mankind may be said to be the criterion of virtue, but once removed". This view was combined with a
view of human motivation with egoistic elements. A person's individual salvation, her eternal happiness, depended on
conformity to God's will, as did virtue itself. Promoting human happiness and one's own coincided, but, given God's design,
it was not an accidental coincidence.
Gay's influence on later writers, such as Hume, deserves note. It is in Gay's essay that some of the questions that
concerned Hume on the nature of virtue are addressed. For example, Gay was curious about how to explain our practice of
approbation and disapprobation of action and character. When we see an act that is vicious, we disapprove of it. Further,
we associate certain things with their effects, so that we form positive associations and negative associations that also
underwrite our moral judgments.
Anthony Ashley Cooper, the 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury (1671-1713) is generally thought to have been the one of the
earliest 'moral sense' theorists, holding that we possess a kind of "inner eye" that allows us to make moral discriminations.
This seems to have been an innate sense of right and wrong, or moral beauty and deformity.
Like Shaftesbury, Francis Hutcheson was very much interested in virtue evaluation. He also adopted the moral
sense approach. However, in his writings We also see an emphasis on action choice and the importance of moral deliberation
to action choice. Hutcheson, in “An Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil,” fairly explicitly spelled out a utilitarian
principle of action choice. (Hruschka, 1991) notes, however, that it was Leibniz who first spelled out a utilitarian decision
procedure.
The Classical Utilitarians, Bentham and Mill, were concerned with legal and social reform. If anything could be
identified as the fundamental motivation behind the development of Classical Utilitarianism it would be the desire to see
useless, Corrupt laws and social practices changed. Accomplishing this goal required a normative ethical theory employed
as a critical tool. What is the truth about what makes an action or a policy a morally good one, or morally right? But
developing the theory itself was also influenced by strong views about what was Wrong in their society. The conviction
that, for example, some laws are bad resulted in analysis of why they were bad. And, for Jeremy Bentham, what made them
bad Was their lack of utility, their tendency to lead to unhappiness and misery without any compensating happiness, If a
law or an action doesn't do any good, then it isn't any good.
Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) was influenced both by Hobbes account of human nature and Hume's Account of
social utility. He famously held that humans were ruled by two sovereign masters--pleasure and pain. Bentham also
Promulgated the principle of utility as the standard of right action on the part or governments and individuals, Actions are
approved when they are such as to Promote happiness, or pleasure, and disapproved of when they have a tendency to cause
unhappiness, or pain. Bentham viewed liberty and autonomy as good but good instrumentally, not intrinsically. Thus, any
action deemed wrong due to a violation of autonomy is derivatively wrong on instrumental grounds as well.
On Bentham's view the law is not monolithic and immutable. Since effects of a given policy may change, the moral
quality of the policy may change as well. A law that is good at one point in time may be a bad law at some other point in
time. Thus, lawmakers have to be sensitive to changing social circumstances. To be fair to Bentham's critics, of course, they
are free to agree with him that this is the case in many situations, just not all and that there is still a subset of laws that reflect
the fact that some actions just are intrinsically wrong regardless of consequences. Bentham is in the much more difficult
position of arguing that effects are all there are to moral evaluation of action and policy.
John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) was a follower of Bentham, and, through most of his life, greatly admired Bentham's
work even though he disagreed with some of Bentham's claims, particularly on the nature of happiness. To this end, Mill's
hedonism was influenced by perfectionist intuitions. There are some pleasures that are more fitting than others. Intellectual
pleasures are of a higher, better, sort than the ones that are merely sensual, and that we share with animals.
Like Bentham, the good still consists in pleasure, it is still a psychological state. There is certainly that similarity.
Further, the basic structures of the theories are the same (Donner, 1991). While it is true that Mill is more comfortable with
notions like rights', this does not mean that he, in actuality, rejected utilitarianism. The rationale for all the rights he
recognizes is utilitarian.
Mill's version of utilitarianism differed from Bentham's also in that he placed weight on the effectiveness of internal
sanctions-emotions like guilt and remorse which serve to regulate our actions. According to Mill, we are the sorts of being$
that have social feelings, feelings for others, not just ourselves, we care about them, and when we perceive harms to them
this causes painful experiences in us. When one perceives oneself to be the agent of that harm, the negative emotions are
centered on the self. One feels guilt for what one has done, not for what one sees another doing. Like external forms of
punishment, internal sanctions are instrumentally very important to appropriate action.
Mill also held that natural features of human psychology, such as conscience and a sense of justice, underwrite
motivation. The sense of justice, for example, results from very natural impulses. Part of this sense involves a desire to
punish those who have harmed others, and this desire in turnis a spontaneous outgrowth rom two sentiments, both in the
highest degree natural...; the impulse of self-defense, and the feeling of sympathy."
Like Bentham, Mill sought to use utilitarianism to inform law and social policy. The aim of increasing happiness
underlies his arguments for women's suffrage and free speech. We can be said to have certain rights, then but those rights
are underwritten by utility. If one can show that a purported right or duty is harmful, then one has shown that it is not
genuine. In Utilitarianism, Mill argues that virtue not only has instrumental value, but is constitutive of the good life. A
person without virtue is morally lacking, and is not as able to promote the good.
Utilitarian Philosophy
Utilitarianism is a philosophical view or theory about how we should evaluate a wide range of things that involve
choices that people face. Among the things that can be evaluated are actions, laws, policies, character traits, and moral
codes. Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism because it rests on the idea that it is the consequences or results of
actions, laws, policies, etc. that determine whether they are good or bad, right or wrong. In general, whatever is being
evaluated, we ought to choose the one that will produce the best overall results. N the language of utilitarians, we should
choose the option that maximizes utility, i.e. that action or policy that produces the largest amount of good.
Utilitarianism is generally held to be the view that the morally right action is the action that produces the best. There
are many ways to spell out this general claim. One thing to note is that the theory is a form of consequentialism: the right
action is understood entirely in terms of consequences produced.
Utilitarianism is the idea that the moral worth of an action is solely determined by its contribution to overall utility
in maximizing happiness or Pleasure as stummed among all people. It is, then, the total utility of individuals Which is
important here, the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. Utility, after which the doctrine is named, is a
measure in economics of the relative satisfaction from, or desirability of the consumption of goods. Utilitarianism can thus
be described as a quantitative and reductionistic approach to ethics.
Utilitarianism starts from the basis that pleasure and happiness are intrinsically valuable, that pain and suffering are
intrinsically invaluable ana that anything else has value only in its causing happiness or preventing suffering or as means to
an end. This focus on happiness or pleasure as the ultimate end of moral decisions, makes it a type of Hedonism (and it is
sometimes known as Hedonistic Utilitarianism).
Utilitarians support equality by the equal consideration of interests, and they reject any arbitrary distinctions as to
who is worthy of concern and who is not, and any discrimination between individuals. However, it does accept the idea of
declining marginal utility, which recognizes that the same thing furthers the Interests of a well-off individual to a lesser
degree than it would the interests of a less well-off individual.
Utilitarians believe that the purpose of morality is to make life better by increasing the number of good things (such
as pleasure and happiness) in the world and decreasing the number of bad things (such as pain and unhappiness). They reject
moral codes or systems that consist of commands or taboos that are based on customs, traditions, or orders given by leaders
or supernatural beings. Instead, utilitarians think that what makes a morality be true or justifiable is its positive contribution
to human (and perhaps non-human) beings.
Since the early 20th century utilitarianism has undergone a variety of refinements. After the middle of the 20th
century, it has become more common to identify as a ‘Consequentialisť since very few philosophers agree entirely with the
view proposed by the Classical Utilitarians, particularly with respect to the hedonistic value theory. But the influence of the
Classical Utilitarians has been profound- not only within moral philosophy, but within political philosophy and social policy.
The question Bentham asked, "What use is it?" is a cornerstone of policy formation. It is a completely secular, forward-
looking question. The articulation and systematic development of this approach to policy formation is Owed to the Classical
Utilitarians.
CHAPTER 6: FRAMEWORK AND PRINCIPLES
Lesson 1: Righteousness and Equality
Learning Objective:
At the end of the chapter, the students will be able to:
1. Differentiate justice from fairness;
2. Critique justice and fairness;
3. Make use of justice and fairness; and
4. Understand the ethical principles of taxation.
Introduction:
Whatever can be demanded on the ground of Law is a Civil Obligation but, in so far as moral grounds are to be
observed, it is a Duty. The word 'duty' is frequently used of legal relationships. Legal Duties are defined as perfect and
Moral Duties as imperfect because the former must be done, and have an external necessity, while the latter depend on a
subjective will. But one might, with good reason, invert this classification in as much as the Legal Duty as such demands
only an external necessity, in which the disposition is not taken into account, or in which we may even have a bad motive.
On the contrary, for a Moral Duty both are demanded, the right deed as regards its content and, likewise according to form,
the subjective side, the Good Intention.
Law, in general, leaves the disposition out of consideration. Morality, on the other hand, is concerned essentially
with the intention and demands that the deed should be done out of simple regard for Duty. So too the legally right conduct
is moral in so far as its moving principle is the regard for the right.
With legally right conduct the moral aspect should also be essentially connected. It may, however, be the case that
with legally right action there is no sentiment of Law present: nay, more, that an immoral intent may accompany it. The
legally right act, in so far as it is done out of regard for the Law, is, at the same time, also moral. The legally right action,
associated at the same time with a moral disposition, is to be carried out unconditionally before there can be room for the
moral action in which there is no legal command, that is, legal obligation. Men are very ready to act from a merely moral
ground, for example, to give away with an air of generosity rather than pay their honest debts; for in a generous action they
congratulate themselves on account of a special perfection, while, on the contrary, in the performance of just action they
would only perform the completely universal act which makes them equal with all.
Taken in its broader sense, justice is action in accordance with the requirements of some law (Vice, 1997). Some
maintain that justice stems from God's will or command, while others believe that justice is inherent in nature itself. Still
others believe that justice consists of rules common to all humanity that emerge out of some sort of consensus. This sort of
justice is often thought of as something higher than a society's legal system. It is in those cases where an action seems to
violate some universal rule of conduct that we are likely to call it "unjust."
Principles of Justice
The most fundamental principle of justice, one that has been widely accepted since it was first defined by Aristotle
more than two thousand years ago is the principle that "equals should be treated equally and unequal unequally." In its
contemporary form, this principle is sometimes expressed as follows: “Individuals should be treated the same, unless they
differ in ways that are relevant to the situation in which they are involved." For example, if Pedro and Juan both do the same
work, and there are no relevant differences between them or the work they are doing, then in justice they should be paid the
same wages. And if Jack is paid more than jill simply because he is a man, or because he is white, then we have an injustice-
a form of discrimination-because race and sex are not relevant to normal work situations. The principles of justice and
fairness can be thought of as rules of "fair play" for issues of social justice. Whether they turn out to be grounded in universal
laws or ones that are more context-bound, these principles determine the way in which the various types of justice are carried
out. For example, principles of distributive justice determine what counts as a "fair share" of particular good, while
principles of retributive or restorative justice shape our response to activity that violates a society's rules of "fair play."
Social justice requires both that the rules be fair, and also that people play by the rules.
Rawls identified two principles of justice, namely (Wolff, 1977):
1. Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar
system of liberty for all. This principle is mainly concerned with distribution of rights and liberties, the basic liberties of
citizens are the political liberty to vote and run for office, freedom of speech and assembly, liberty of conscience, freedom
of personal property and freedom from arbitrary arrest. However, it is a matter of some debate whether freedom of contract
can be inferred to be included among these basic liberties.
2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged,
consistent with the just savings principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair
equality of opportunity.
These principles are lexically ordered, and Rawls emphasizes the priority of liberty. The first principle is often
called the greatest equal liberty principle. The second, until (a), the difference principle and the final addendum in (b) the
equal opportunity principle.
On the other hand, there are also criteria that we believe are not justifiable grounds for giving people different
treatment. In the world of work, for example, we generally hold that it is unjust to give individuals special treatment on the
basis of age, sex, race, or their religious preferences. If the judge's nephew receives a suspended sentence for armed robbery
when another offender unrelated to the judge goes to jail for the same crime, or the brother of the Director of Public Works
gets the million-peso contract to install a new building adjacent to the municipal hall despite lower bids from other
contractors, we say that it's unfair. We also believe it isn't fair when a person is punished for something over which he or
she had no control, or isn't compensated for a harm he or she suffered. And the people involved in the "brown lung hearings"
felt that it wasn't fair that some diseases were provided with disability compensation, while other similar diseases weren't.
Egalitarian Justice
Egalitarianism is a trend of thought in political philosophy. An egalitarian favors equality of some sort: People
should get the same, or be treated the same, or be treated as equals, in some respect. An alternative view expands on this
last-mentioned option: People should be treated as equals, should treat one another as equals, should relate as equals, or
enjoy an equality of social status of some sort. Egalitarian doctrines tend to rest on a background idea that all human persons
are equal in fundamental worth or moral status. So far as the Western European and Anglo-American philosophical tradition
is concerned, one significant source of this thought is the Christian notion that God loves all human souls equally.
Egalitarianism is a protean doctrine, because there are several different types of equality, or ways in which people might be
treated the same, or might relate as equals, that might be thought desirable. In modern democratic societies, the term
"egalitarian" is often used to refer to a position that favors, for any of a wide array of reasons, a greater degree of equality
of income and wealth across persons than currently exists.
As a view within political philosophy, egalitarianism has to do both with how people are treated and with
distributive justice. Civil rights movements reject certain types of social and political discrimination and demand that people
be treated equally. Distributive justice is another form of egalitarianism that addresses life outcomes and the allocation of
valuable things such as income, wealth, and other goods. To judge two things equal, we must also specify the relevant
qualities they have in common. Therefore, egalitarianism is the belief that all humans share an essence or quality that makes
them equal. Although all egalitarians believe equality, they often differ in their understanding of the qualities all humans
share.
Every form of egalitarianism is cosmopolitan and inclusive. Those who See only the members of their own group
as equal are not egalitarian. Because Egalitarianism is always based on a theory of universal human commonality and
because such universal human qualities are difficult to define, their essence is often unspecified by egalitarian thinkers.
Nonetheless, anyone who believes all humans quality in are equal must also believe all humans have some kind of essence
or common, because without commonality there can be no equality. The term is derived from the French word "égal",
meaning "equal" or "level", and was first used in English in the 1880s, although the equivalent term "equalitarian" dates
from the late 18th century.
Types of Egalitarianism
1. Economic Egalitarianism (or Material Egalitarianism) is where the participants of a society are of equal standing and
have equal access to all the economic resources in terms of economic power, wealth and contribution. It is a founding
principle of various forms of socialism.
2. Moral Egalitarianism is the position that equality is central to justice, that all individuals are entitled to equal respect,
and that all human persons are equal in fundamental worth or moral status.
3. Legal Egalitarianism is the principle under which each individual is subject to the same laws, with no individual or
group or class having special legal privileges, and where the testimony of all persons is counted with the same weight.
4. Political Egalitarianism is where the members of a society are of equal standing in terms of political power or influence.
It is a founding principle of most forms of democracy.
5. Luck Egalitarianism is a view about distributive justice (what is just or right with respect to the allocation of goods in
a society) espoused by a variety of left-wing political philosophers, which seeks to distinguish between outcomes that are
the result of brute luck (e.g. misfortunes in genetic makeup, or being struck by a bolt of lightning) and those that are the
consequence of conscious options (e.g. career choices, or fair gambles).
6. Gender Egalitarianism (or Zygarchy) is a form of society in which power 1s equally shared between men and women,
or a family structure where power is shared equally by both parents.
7. Racial Egalitarianism (or Racial Equality) is the absence of racial segregation (the separation of different racial groups
in daily life, whether mandated by law or through social norms).
8. Opportunity Egalitarianism (or Asset-based Egalitarianism) is the idea that equality is possible by a redistribution of
resources, usually in the form of a capital grant provided at the age of majority, an idea which has been around since Thomas
Paine (1737-1809).
9. Christian Egalitarianism holds that all people are equal before God and in Christ, and specifically teaches gender
equality in Christian church leadership and in marriage.
Socialism (Socialist Justice)
In contrast with libertarians, socialists take equality to be the ultimate political ideal. In the Communist Manifesto
(1848), Karl Marx (1818-1883) and Friedrich Engels (1820-1895) maintain that the abolition of bourgeois property and
bourgeois family structure is a necessary first requirement for building a society that accords with the political ideal of
equality. In the Critique of the Gotha Program (1891), Marx provides a much more positive account of what is required to
build a society based upon the political ideal of equality. Marx claims that the distribution of social goods must conform, at
least initially, to the principle from each according to his/her ability, to each according to his/her contribution. But when the
highest stage of communist society has been reached, Marx adds, distribution will conform to the principle from each
according to his/her ability, to each according to his/her need.
Socialism is a populist economic and political system based on the public Ownership (also known as collective or
common ownership) of the means of production. Those means include the machinery, tools and factories used to produce
goods that aim to directly satisfy human needs.
Socialism’s mantra is "From each according to his ability, to each according to Is contribution." Everyone in the
society receives a share of the production based on how much each has contributed. That motivates them to work long hours
if they want to receive more. Workers receive their share after a percentage has been deducted for the Common good.
Examples are transportation, defense, and education. Some also define the common good as caring for those who can't
directly contribute to Production. Examples include the elderly, children, and their caretakers. Socialism assumes that the
basic nature of people is cooperative. That nature hasn't yet emerged in full because capitalism or feudalism has forced
people to be competitive. Therefore, a basic tenet of socialism is that the economic system must support this basic human
nature for these qualities to emerge.
In a purely socialist system, all legal production and distribution decisions e made by the government, and
individuals rely on the state for everything from food to healthcare. The government determines output and pricing levels
of these goods and services. Socialists contend that shared ownership of resources and central planning provide a more
equal distribution of goods and services, and a more equitable society.
Advantages
1. Workers are no longer exploited, since they own the means of production. All profits are spread equitably among all
workers, according to his or her contribution. The cooperative system realizes that even those who can't work must have
their basic needs met, for the good of the whole.
2. The system eliminates poverty.
3. Everyone has equal access to healthcare and education. No one is discriminated against.
4. Everyone works at what one is best at and what one enjoys. If society needs jobs to be done that no one wants, it offers
higher compensation to make it worthwhile.
5. Natural resources are preserved for the good of the whole.
Disadvantages
1. The biggest disadvantage of socialism is that it relies on the cooperative nature of humans to work. It negates those within
society who are competitive, not cooperative. Competitive people tend to seek ways to overthrow and disrupt society for
their own gain.
2. It doesn't reward people for being entrepreneurial and competitive. As such, it won't be as innovative as a capitalistic
society.
3. The government set up to represent the masses may abuse its position and claim power for itself.
Capitalism
Capitalism is an economic system where private entities own the factors of production. The four factors are
entrepreneurship, capital goods, natural resources, and labor. The owners of capital goods, natural resources, and
entrepreneurship exercise control through companies. The individual owns his or her labor. The only exception is slavery,
where someone else owns a person's labor. Although illegal throughout the entire world, slavery is still widely practiced.
Capitalism, also called free market economy or free enterprise economy, economic system, dominant in the Western world
since the breakup of feudalism, in which most of the means of production are privately owned and production is guided and
income distributed largely through the operation of markets.
Characteristics of Capitalism
1. Two-class system: Historically a capitalist society was characterized by the split between two classes of individuals-the
capitalist class, which owns the means for producing and distributing goods (the owners) and the working class, who sell
their labor to the capitalist class in exchange for wages. The economy is run by the individuals (or corporations) who own
and operate Companies and make decisions as to the use of resources. But there exists a "division of labor" which allows
for specialization, typically occurring through education and training, further breaking down the two class system into sub-
classes (e.g., the middle class).
2. Profit motive: Companies exist to make a profit. The motive for all companion is to make and sell goods and services
only for profits. Companies do not exist solely to satisfy people's needs. Even though some goods or services may satisfy
needs, they will only be available if the people have the resources to pay for them.
3. Minimal government intervention: Capitalist societies believe markets should be left alone to operate without
government intervention. However, a completely government-free capitalist society exists in theory, only. Even in the
United States--the poster child for capitalism, the government regulates certain industries, such as the Dodd-Frank Act for
financial institutions. By contrast, a purely capitalist society would allow the markets to set prices based on demand and
supply for the purpose of making profits.
4. Competition: True capitalism needs a competitive market. Without competition, monopolies exist, and instead of the
market setting the prices, the seller is the price setter, which is against the conditions of capitalism.
5. Willingness to change: The last characteristic of capitalism is the ability to adapt and change. Technology has been a
game changer in every society, and the willingness to allow change and adaptability of societies to improve inefficiencies
within economic structures is a true characteristic.
Advantages
Capitalism results in the best products for the best prices. That's because consumers will pay more for what they
want the most. Businesses provide what customers want at the highest prices they'll pay. Prices are kept low by competition
among businesses. They make their products as efficient as possible to maximize profit. Most important for economic
growth is capitalism's intrinsic reward for innovation. This includes innovation in more efficient production methods. It also
means innovation of new products. As Steve Jobs said, "You can't just ask customers what they want and then try to give
that to them. By the time you get it built, they'll want something new."
Disadvantages
Capitalism doesn't provide for those who lack competitive skills. includes the elderly, children, the developmentally
disabled, and caretakers. 0 keep society functioning, capitalism requires government policies that value the family unit.
Despite the idea of a "level playing field," capitalism does not promote equality of opportunity. Those without the proper
nutrition, support, and education may never make it to the playing field. Society will never benefit from their valuable skills.
In the short term, inequality may seem to be in the best interest of capitalism's winners. They have fewer competitive
threats. They may also use their power to "rig the system" by creating barriers to entry. For example, they will donate to
elected officials who sponsor laws that benefit their industry. They could send their children to private schools while
supporting lower taxes for public schools. In the long term, inequality will limit diversity and the innovation it creates. For
example, a diverse business team is more able to identify market niches. It can understand the needs of society's minorities,
and target products to meet those needs.
Capitalism ignores external costs, such as pollution and climate change. This makes goods cheaper and more
accessible in the short run. But over time, it depletes natural resources, lowers the quality of life in the affected areas, and
increases costs for everyone. The government should impose Pigouvian taxes to monetize these external costs and improve
the general welfare.
Capitalism and Private Property
Private property rights are very important in capitalism. Most modern concepts of private property stem from John
Locke's theory of homesteading, in which human beings claim ownership through mixing their labor with unclaimed
resources. Once owned, the only legitimate means of transferring property are through trade, gifts, inheritance or wages.
Private property promotes efficiency by giving the owner of resources an incentive to maximize its value. The more valuable
a resource, the more trading power it provides the owner. In a capitalist system, the person who owns property is entitled to
any value associated with the property.
When property is not privately owned, but shared by the public, a market failure can emerge, known as the tragedy
of the commons. The fruit of any labor performed with a public asset does not belong to the laborer, but is diffused among
many people. There is a disconnect between labor and value, creating a disincentive to increase value or production. People
are incentivized to wait for Someone else to do the hard work and then swoop in to reap the benefits without much personal
expense. For individuals or businesses to deploy their capital goods confidently, a system must exist that protects their legal
right to own or transfer private property. lo facilitate and enforce private property rights, capitalist societies tend to rely on
Contracts, fair dealing and tort law.
Lesson 3: Taxation
Introduction
The power of taxation is inherent power of the State. It rests upon necessity, the significance of which stems from
the recognition that since governments have been established to promote and protect the general welfare, it is necessary that
government should be provided with the means by which it could carry out its exercise the power of taxation. Government
financial operations are well-nigh impossible without taxation. Apart from this, taxation can be a powerful means in order
to achieve the goals of social progress and the objectives of economic development. Taxation is very important to maintain
the society we live in. People are always criticizing the government for this but it is very important.
Meaning of Taxation
Taxation is the supreme power of a sovereign state through its law-making body, to impose burdens or charges
upon persons, property or property rights for public purpose. It is the power vested upon the legislature for the purpose of
raising revenues to finance government expenditures and for the general welfare and protection of its citizens. Henceforth,
taxation is a state power that is exercised only through the law-making body of the State or the Legislature. Neither the
President nor the Judiciary has the power to impose taxes. Taxes are levied by Congress by means of laws. Taxation is the
method of apportioning the cost of government among those who, in some measures are privileged to enjoy its benefits and
must therefore, bear its burden. (Cooley, n.d.). Taxation does not confine itself on government expenditures. It also regulates
the flow of income in our economic system. When there is too much money in the system, the government withdraws some
of this money to check inflation.
Introduction
Globalization has been in the air. It has now come to be one of the most frequently used terms in Politics and
Economics. It is being projected as the common objective of the whole humankind.
This current wave of globalization has been driven by policies that have opened economies domestically and
internationally. In the years since the Second World War, and especially during the past two decades, many governments
have adopted free-market economic systems, vastly increased their own productive potential and created myriad new
opportunities for international trade and investment. Governments also have negotiated dramatic reductions in barriers to
commerce and have established international agreements to promote trade in goods, services, and investment. Taking
advantage of new opportunities in foreign markets, corporations have built foreign factories and established production and
marketing arrangements with foreign partners. A defining feature of globalization, therefore, is an international industrial
and financial business structure.
Gen Y, more known as the millennials, has their ups and downs in today's world. The millennials are a generation
that is deserving and commendable sometimes. It's no doubt that they accomplish their goals based on their term and use
the resources that were given to them. They continue to climb up the success ladder and show their hard work and can
change the views on how other generations see them. They need to come together as generations and make sure they teach
the upcoming generations everything they have learned and ultimately continue to grow and push forward towards a better
future.
Globalization implies the continuing expansion and intensification of economic, political, social, cultural and
judicial relations across borders. It is furthered by reductions in transportation and communication costs, the rise of new
information technologies, such as the internet, and liberalizations in the markets for goods, services, labor, capital, and
technology. Although it also occurs within existing legal structures, globalization in many cases involves political decisions
about deregulation, free trade, and the integration of markets. It changes the life styles and living conditions for people
around the world, presenting new opportunities for some, but risks and threats to others. Individuals, firms, governments,
and transnational organizations that are lifted out of the framework of the nation state, like the World Bank, United Nations,
the European Union, and multinational firms all face challenges of how to respond to globalization.
What is Globalization?
Globalization is a process of interaction and integration among the people, companies, and governments of
different nations, a process driven by international trade and investment and aided by information technology. This process
has effects on the environment, on culture, on political systems, on economic development and prosperity, and on human
physical well-being in societies around the world.
Globalization is seen as a conscious and active process of expanding business and trade across the borders of all the
states. It stands for expanding cross-border facilities and economic linkages. This is to be done with a view to secure an
integration of economic interests and activities of the people living in all parts of the world. The objective of making the
world a truly interrelated, inter-dependent, developed global village governs the on-going process of globalization.
Globalization represents the desire to move from national to a global sphere of economic and political activity". It seeks to
transform the existing international economic system into a unified system of global economics. In the existing system,
national economies are the major players. In the new system, the globalized economic and political activity will ensure
sustainable development for the whole world.
Technology has been the other principal driver of globalization. Advances in information technology, in particular,
have dramatically transformed economic life. Information technologies have given all sorts of individual economic actors-
consumers, investors, businesses valuable new tools for identifying and pursuing economic opportunities, including faster
and more informed analyses of economic trends around the world, easy transfers of assets, and collaboration with far-flung
partners.
To find the right balance between benefits and costs associated with globalization, citizens of all nations need to
understand how globalization works and the policy choices facing them and their societies.
“Globalization is both an active process of corporate expansion across borders and a structure of cross border
facilities and economic linkages that have been steadily growing and changing.” – Edward S. Herman
“Globalization is the process whereby social relations acquire relatively distance-less and borderless qualities.” –
Baylis and Smith
Conclusion
What makes the ethics and values in business special relevant and topical in the present-day context in the world is
the fact that we are on the threshold of environmental changes of far-reaching consequences. Business ethics presents
pertinent solutions to the concerns and dilemmas faced by global organizations. Ethical leadership is essential for the long-
term survival and success of any Organization. In the era of globalization, business ethics considerably influences
shareholders, employees, customers, suppliers, competitors, government and civil society. Organizations should focus on
the ethical issues faced by them in various functional areas like marketing, finance, human resources, production, ICT etc.
The commendable work done by global corporations in inculcating and practicing business ethics underscores the
importance of value-based leadership in international business scenario.
Fillennial Morality
Children now love luxury. They have bad manners, contempt for authority, disrespect their elders, and love talking
instead of exercise." These were the words the Greek philosopher Socrates in a tirade against Athenian youth during his
Ene, but many older adults in this modern age would use the very same words when railing against the youth.
Millennials are perceived by their elders as having a rather tenuous grip on morality. While they are more open-
minded with regard to issues regarding sexual identity, pre-marital relations, and the concept of having and raising children
out of wedlock, they are also seen as a little too sensitive when it comes to reacting o socio-civic issues. The use of social
media through which to air their views has been considered by many as a coward's way out: many people air scathing
opinions online instead of in public, protected, as they are, by a sense of virtual anonymity.
According to Jos Ortega, chairman and CEO of digital media agency Havos Media Ortega, the last thing a millennial
wants to hear is to be told that he or she will be unable to do something. "To them, that is violating the very being of what
they stand for," he explained during a discussion on the millennial market with the Philippine Association of National
Advertisers (PANA). "[Life] for millennials is a journey of self-discovery."
But this drive towards self-discovery is not without consequences. Older generations see them as willful and
disrespectful to others; highly interactive online but completely lacking in interpersonal skills in the real world; overly
dependent on technology; narcissistic and overly materialistic; even fatalistic as many millennials do not seem to have a
solid foundation for their future or even a sense of where to go next.
Exposure to other ways of thinking thanks to being connected to the world online has also made many millennials
drift away from traditional religion, with some veering into becoming agnostics and others into all-out atheists. Ironically,
many baby boomers who once shunned organized religion find themselves seeking spiritual solace in the faith they left
behind as they grow older. Even Generation X cynics have found new life, so to speak, in their respective churches: a sort
of refuge and backlash against the wanton behavior they see proliferating among the young.
There are various aspects of the generation gap that can be opened for discussion. Corporate and financial issues,
particularly those involving the balance of power in the workplace or proper investing, are one; changing values are another.
In the end, it is up to all of us to coexist in mutual respect and some modicum of understanding. Perhaps the one question
we need to answer is "Why can't we all just get along?"
Introduction
When academics talk about ethics, they are typically referring to decisions about right and wrong. As noted, the
study of ethical behavior goes back thousands of years to ancient Greece. Ethics is a branch of philosophy that investigates
questions such as "What is good and what is bad?" "Is it just to reward one group with more benefits than another?" "What
action should an individual or organization take if a client mistreats him/her/it?" In practice, ethics is decision-making tools
that try to guide questions of human morality, by defining concepts such as good and bad, right and wrong, virtue and vice,
justice and crime, etc. Often, religion and ethics are treated as the same thing, with various religions making claims about
their belief systems being the best way for people to live, actively proselytizing and trying to convert unbelievers, trying to
legislate public behaviors based around isolated religious passages, etc. Of course, not all religions are the same, some are
more liberal than others and some more conservative, but in general, all religious traditions believe that their faith represents
a path to enlightenment and salvation.
Ethics involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior. A central
aspect of ethics is "the good life'", the life worth living or life that is simply satisfying, which is held by many philosophers
to be more important than traditional moral conduct (Singer, 1993). Most religions have an ethical component, often derived
from purported supernatural revelation or guidance. Some assert that religion is necessary to live ethically. Blackburn states
that there are those who "would say that we can only flourish under the umbrella of a strong social order, cemented by
common adherence to a particular religious tradition.
Internet:
www.sonnenbergonline, retrieved May 21, 2018.
www.liveboldandbloom.com, Character Traits that Impact Happiness, retrieved May 21.
www.britannica.com Kohlberg Stages of Moral Development
www.wikipedia.com
https://www.google.com/url?sa=i&url=https%3A%2F%2Fsteemit.com%2Fhive-131369%2F%40larapambuan%2Ffilipino-tradition-
101-bayanihan-a-spirit-of-cooperation-and-
camaraderie&psig=AOvVaw3WWtiEwcPv3tzpxk_bEbTN&ust=1738426463207000&source=images&cd=vfe&opi=89978449&ved=
0CBcQjhxqFwoTCLictsqtoIsDFQAAAAAdAAAAABAE
https://josephscollege.ac.in/lms/Uploads/pdf/material/IncomeTax1Notes.pdf
https://www.google.com/url?sa=i&url=https%3A%2F%2Fwww.vecteezy.com%2Ffree-vector%2Ftwo-
paths&psig=AOvVaw3HodowGAfZjx6GWfdzQAgb&ust=1738491122517000&source=images&cd=vfe&opi=89978449&ved=0CBc
QjhxqFwoTCJChsLWeoosDFQAAAAAdAAAAABAE
https://www.vecteezy.com/vector-art/15426900-concept-of-choice-between-hard-and-easy-way