Logic Final
Logic Final
• Contradiction:
A and E propositions are contradictories. If one is true, the other must be false.
For example, "All cats are mammals" (A) and "No cats are mammals" (E) cannot both be true
simultaneously.
• Contrary:
A and E propositions are contraries. Both cannot be true, but they can both be false. For
example, "All cats are mammals" (A) and "No cats are mammals" (E) cannot both be true, but they can
both be false.
• Subcontrary:
I and O propositions are subcontraries. Both cannot be false, but they can both be true.
For example, "Some dogs are brown" (I) and "Some dogs are not brown" (O) cannot both be false, but
they can both be true.
• Subalternation:
The traditional square of opposition provides a framework for analyzing the logical relationships
between categorical propositions and is an important tool in traditional Aristotelian logic.
When the middle term is distributed, it allows for a valid inference to be made between the two other
terms (the major term and the minor term). If the middle term is not distributed, it can lead to a fallacy
called the fallacy of the undistributed middle.
Premise 1: All mammals are animals. Premise 2: Some dogs are mammals. Conclusion: Therefore, some
dogs are animals.
In this example, the middle term "mammals" is not distributed in either of the premises. Therefore, the
conclusion that "some dogs are animals" is invalid.
distributed in a premise.
This rule ensures that when a term is distributed in the conclusion (referring to all members of its
category), it must have proper support or distribution in at least one of the premises to maintain the
validity of the syllogism.
Premise 1: All cats are mammals. Premise 2: Some mammals are not dogs. Conclusion: Therefore, some
cats are not dogs.
In this example, the term "mammals" is distributed in the conclusion ("some mammals"), indicating that
it refers to all members of the category. The same term "mammals" is also distributed in the first
premise ("All cats are mammals"). Therefore, it adheres to Rule 2 because the distributed term appears
in one of the premises, supporting its distribution in the conclusion.
By following Rule 2, the syllogism maintains its validity, as the distribution of the term "mammals" is
consistent between the conclusion and the premise.
This syllogism may be seen to be invalid because it has true premises and a false
conclusion. The defect is attributable to the fact that it has two negative premises.
Upon reflection, Rule 3 should be fairly obvious. Let ‘‘S,’’ ‘‘P,’’ and ‘‘M’’ once again
designate the minor, major, and middle terms. Now, if the P class and the M class are
separate either wholly or partially, and the S class and the M class are separate either
wholly or partially, nothing is said about the relation between the S class and the P
class. These two classes may be either distinct or identical in whole or in part. Venn
diagrams may be used effectively to illustrate the fact that no conclusion can be validly
premise.
or
These arguments may be seen to be invalid because each has true premises and a false
conclusion. The first draws an affirmative conclusion from a negative premise, and
An alternate formulation of Rule 4 is: Any syllogism having exactly one negative
negative while the other premise and the conclusion are affirmative, the syllogism is
invalid.
particular.
If a categorical syllogism breaks only Rule 5, it is valid from the Aristotelian standpoint
but not from the Boolean standpoint. The nine syllogistic forms that fall into this
category are those that are included in the ‘‘conditionally valid’’ list in Section 5.1. For
each of these forms, the list specifies one term that must denote existing things before
the syllogism will be valid. In the first example above, the critical term is ‘‘unicorns.’’
If unicorns existed, the syllogism would be valid from the Aristotelian standpoint; but
since they do not exist, it is invalid. It commits the existential fallacy. In the second
example, the critical term is ‘‘tigers.’’ Since tigers exist, the argument is valid from the
3. Clear Communication: Logic helps in constructing clear and coherent arguments, avoiding
fallacies, and expressing thoughts and ideas in a structured and systematic manner. It enhances effective
communication and facilitates understanding between individuals.
4. Evaluation of Arguments: Logic allows individuals to evaluate the validity and soundness of
arguments by assessing the logical consistency and coherence of the premises and conclusions. It aids in
identifying faulty reasoning and distinguishing between strong and weak arguments.
3. Database Management: Logic is used in database systems for query languages, such as SQL,
where logical predicates are employed to retrieve specific data from databases based on given
conditions.
4. Artificial Intelligence: Logic is essential in the field of artificial intelligence (AI). Logical reasoning,
rule-based systems, and formal logic languages like Prolog are used in AI for knowledge representation,
expert systems, automated reasoning, and problem-solving.
5. Circuit Design and Digital Systems: Logic gates and Boolean algebra form the basis of digital
circuits and electronic systems. Logical operators like AND, OR, and NOT are used to design and analyze
digital circuits, ensuring proper functioning and logical operations.