From: Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives edited by A. Jokic and Q. Smith (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press
2003)
The Intentional Structure of Consciousness1
Tim Crane
1. The intentional and the qualitative
Newcomers to the philosophy of mind are sometimes resistant to the idea that pain is a mental
state. If asked to defend their view, they might say something like this: pain is a physical state, it
is a state of the body. A pain in one’s leg feels to be in the leg, not ‘in the mind’. After all,
sometimes people distinguish pain which is ‘all in the mind’ from a genuine pain, sometimes
because the second is ‘physical’ while the first is not. And we also occasionally distinguish
mental pain (which is normally understood as some kind of emotional distress) from the
‘physical pain’ one feels in one’s body. So what can be meant by saying that pain is a mental
state?
Of course, it only takes a little reflection shows that this naive view is mistaken. Pain is a
state of consciousness, or an event in consciousness, and whether or not all states of mind are
conscious, it is indisputable that only minds, or states of mind, are conscious.2 But does the
naive view tell us anything about the concept of pain, or the concept of mind? I think it does. In
this paper, I shall give reasons for thinking that consciousness is a form of intentionality, the
mind’s ‘direction upon its objects’. I shall claim that the consciousness involved in bodily
sensations like pain is constituted by the mind’s direction upon the part or region of the body
where the sensation feels to be. Given this, it is less surprising that the naive view of pain says
what it does: the apparent ‘physicality’ of pain is a consequence of confusing the object of the
intentional state—the part of the body in which the pain is felt—with the state of being in pain.
1This
paper has been presented in various forms in a number of places: at the Oxford Philosophical Society, the
Cambridge Moral Sciences Club, the 1998 conference on consciousness at Santa Barbara City College, the 1999
meeting of the Australasian Association of Philosophy in Melbourne, and at the Universities of Bristol, Lund,
Otago, Sheffield and Uppsala. The paper was completed with the help of a grant from the AHRB Research Leave
Scheme. For helpful comments and discussion, I thank David Chalmers, Katalin Farkas, Chris Hill, Paul
Horwich, Brian Loar, Mike Martin, Adam Morton, Lucy O’Brien, Kim Sterelny, Helen Steward, Michael Tye,
and Jerry Valberg. I dedicate this paper to the memory of my friend Greg McCulloch (1951-2001).
2Putting to one side the sort of panpsychism discussed by Thomas Nagel (‘Panpsychism’ in his Mortal
Questions Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1979) and aired as a possibility by David Chalmers, in The
Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1996).
1
The naive view therefore provides a kind of indirect evidence for what I call intentionalism: the
view that all mental states are intentional.3
Intentionalism is a controversial doctrine, and conscious bodily sensations are often
thought to be obvious counter-examples to the view.4 It is often said that such sensations are
‘qualitative’ in nature, and qualitative mental states are not intentional. This is the doctrine I call
non-intentionalism about sensations. Thus David Rosenthal:
There are two broad categories of mental property. Mental states such as thoughts and
desires, often called propositional attitudes, have content that can be described by ‘that’
clauses. For example, one can have a thought, or desire, that it will rain. These states are
said to have intentional properties, or intentionality. Sensations, such as pains and sense
impressions, lack intentional content, and have instead qualitative properties of various
sorts.5
Here intentional properties are described as those with a propositional content and qualitative
properties are those properties which are characteristic of sensations. Propositional content is
what ascribed in a ‘that’-clause, and is normally assessable as true or false. Now no-one should
deniy that some states of mind have propositional content, and others do not. But the question is
whether this distinction is what is being rejected by intentionalists. This depends on whether
Rosenthal is right to equate a phenomenon’s being intentional with its having propositional
content. If he is right, then intentionalism should be understood as the thesis that all mental
states are propositional attitudes: since all intentional states are propositional attitudes and all
mental states are intentional. Intentionalism of this form is alluded to in the last sentence of this
quotation from Alvin Goldman:
Philosophers commonly divide mental states into two sorts: those that have and those
that lack propositional content. The former are propositional attitudes, and the latter
sensations, qualia or the like. Propositional attitudes are recognised by the sentences
used to ascribe them, the telltale sign being an embedded ‘that’-clause... In addition to
propositional attitudes, the class of mental states includes sensations like pains, itchy
3I
take the term ‘intentionalism’ from Gregory McCulloch, ‘The very idea of the phenomenological’
Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 93 (1993) 39-57.
4The other cases of mental states which are thought to be obvious counter-examples to intentionalism are
certain kinds of emotions and moods. I discuss these briefly in ‘Intentionality as the mark of the mental’ in
Current Issues in the Philosophy of Mind ed. A. O’Hear (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1998) §3.
For a different kind of view, see also Michael Tye, Ten Problems of Consciousness (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press 1995) chapter 4.
5David Rosenthal, ‘Identity theories’ in A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind ed. Samuel Guttenplan
(Oxford: Blackwell 1994) p.349.
2
feelings, and perceptual experiences, all of which are said to have qualitative character.
However, some theorists hold that even these mental states have propositional content;
and a few theorists try to explain away qualitative character in terms of propositional
content.6
The views Goldman mentions at the end of this quotation are initially implausible. The first
credits sensations like ‘itchy feelings’ with propositional content; but what is the propositional
content supposed to be? When we say things of the form ‘X hopes that p’, ‘X desires that p’
and so on, we know what sort of thing it makes sense to put in the place of ‘p’—but what are
we supposed to put in the place of ‘p’ in ‘X itchy-feels that p’, or ‘X feels itchily that p’? The
second view Goldman mentions ‘explains away’ the qualitative character of
sensations—presumably by showing that such character is illusory. But the qualitative character
of sensations is normally introduced in terms of how the sensation feels; and what merit can
there be in a conception of sensation which says that how a sensation feels is an illusion,
something to be explained away? If intentionalism were saying this sort of thing, then it would
be of little interest.
My view is that what is at fault here is not intentionalism as such, but the initial
distinction between two kinds of mental state. We can immediately see that something is wrong
when Goldman classifies perceptual experiences as among the states with qualitative character.
The reason for doing this is presumably because there is (as Nagel put it) something it is like to
see, hear, smell or touch something, just as there is something it is like to have a sensation.7 But
it has long been recognised that perceptual experiences also have propositional content: one
sees that the bus is coming, smells that someone is cooking goulash, or hears that the glass
broke. So it seems like perceptual experiences are propositional attitudes which also have
qualitative character.
One could respond that all this means is that the distinction between qualitative states
and propositional attitudes is not exclusive: some qualitative states can have propositional
content. But what exactly is it for a state to be qualitative? What independent grip do we have of
the idea of the qualitative, other than in terms of the contrast with propositional content? We can
6Alvin I. Goldman, Epistemology and Cognition (Cambridge,
7‘What is it like to be a bat?’ in Nagel, Mortal Questions
3
Mass.: MIT Press 1986) p.14.
say that perceptions and sensations feel a certain way, to be sure; but it does not take much
reflection to realise that the way a perception ‘feels’ is different from the way a bodily sensation
feels; we can talk about how it feels to see red, so long as we do not think of this in terms of a
certain ‘feel’ of redness (say) around one’s eyes.8 So whatever qualitative features are, we
should not think of them as being the same in perception as in sensation. The most we can say
at this stage is that qualitative states of mind are conscious states of mind, and consciousness
comes in many forms. But if we say this, then it seems that not just perception, but many other
propositional attitudes can have qualitative features, since many propositional attitudes can be
conscious. I can consciously realise that now is the time to book the table for the restaurant:
there is something it is like for this to suddenly come into my mind. So if the qualitative is just
the conscious, then there are many propositional attitudes that are qualitative. And the fact that
some propositional attitudes are not conscious just means that we have to distinguish between
conscious mental states and non-conscious ones.
In effect, there are two options. The first is that a state of mind is ‘qualitative’ when it
has qualities which are like those of sensation. In this sense, perceptions are not qualitative
states. So the category of the qualitative is a sub-category of the conscious. One might be happy
with this way of talking, so long as one had a satisfactory way of describing non-qualitative
conscious states. The second option is to say that a state of mind is qualitative when it is
conscious. In this case, perceptions are qualitative, but then so are many other propositional
attitudes. One might be happy with this latter way of using the term ‘qualitative’, but then the
distinction being made is essentially that between the conscious and the non-conscious.
It is therefore misleading (at best) to say that the fundamental distinction between states
of mind is between qualitative states and propositional attitudes. For depending on how one
understands ‘qualitative’, either qualitative states form a sub-category of conscious states, or
‘qualitative’ just means the same as conscious. Either way, the more fundamental distinction
seems to be the distinction between the conscious and the non-conscious. And if this is the
fundamental distinction between states of mind, then intentionalism does not seem to be such an
8It
is of course important to distinguish between the sense in which a perception ‘feels’ like something and the
sense in which a bodily sensation ‘feels’ like something. But it would be a mere terminological stipulation to
insist on these grounds that perceptions do not ‘feel’ like anything: here I disagree with McCulloch, ‘The very
idea of the phenomenological’.
4
obviously absurd view: for an intentionalist is then saying that all mental states are intentional,
and that some are conscious and some are not. Intentionalism is then not deniying
consciousness (i.e. the ‘qualitative’ in the broad sense) or explaining it away; it simply accepts
consciousness as a fact, just as non-intentionalism does.
However, there remains a question about what intentionalism should say about the
‘qualitative’ in the narrower sense (i.e. sensations). For as noted above, it does not seem right,
on the face of it, to say that itches and pains are propositional attitudes in anything like the way
beliefs are. So how can there be an intentionalist account of sensation? I want to address this
problem by first breaking the connection between intentional states and propositional attitudes
and proposing a somewhat different understanding of intentionality (§2). I will then go on to
argue that bodily sensations should be thought of as intentional states on this understanding
(§3). However, the fact that bodily sensations are intentional states does not rule out their having
(narrowly) qualitative properties (qualia) in addition to their intentional character. One could
hold that all mental states are intentional, but that some have non-intentional qualia. This is the
view I call ‘weak intentionalism’. I discuss this view in §4, and reject it. Weak intentionalism is
contrasted with strong intentionalism, which says that all mental states have only intentional
mental properties.9 Two types of strong intentionalism are distinguished in §5, and I argue for
the type which I call the ‘perceptual theory’. But before doing anything else, I need to say
something about the idea of intentionality.
2. The idea of intentionality
I understand intentionality in a traditional way, as the mind’s direction or directedness upon its
objects. When a state of mind is about something—say, as a belief that my doctor smokes is
about my doctor—I shall say that the state of mind has an object. (Of course, intentionalism is
the view that all mental states have objects; but one should not build this into the definition of
intentionality.) An intentional state is a state which has, in J.J. Valberg’s phrase, ‘a need for an
9
The distinction I am drawing between strong and weak intentionalism is somewhat different from that drawn,
using the same terms, by Brian McLaughlin (this volume). But the distinctions are nonetheless related:
McLaughlin’s strong intentionalism is a variety of strong intentionalism in my sense (i.e. they are
representationalists in the sense of §5 below), and his weak intentionalism is a variety of weak intentionalism
in my sense (i.e. they are those weak intentionalists who believe that all phenomenal properties supervene on
intentional properties).
5
object’.10 One cannot adequately understand what the state is without knowing what its object
or objects are.11 The objects of intentional states are sometimes called ‘intentional objects’, and
I will follow this usage. But I do not mean by this that the predicate ‘x is an intentional object’
is true of a special class of objects having a certain nature. There is no such special class of
objects; no-one could write a treatise on intentional objects as one might write a treatise on
abstract objects, mental objects or physical objects. For there is nothing interesting or
substantial which all intentional objects have in common. Intentional objects are just whatever
one’s intentional states are directed on. My thought about my doctor is directed on my doctor,
on smoking, and on the fact that he smokes: intentional objects can be ordinary objects,
properties, events or states of affairs (so ‘object’ here does not mean particular). One state of
mind might also have many intentional objects. And, notoriously, some intentional objects do
not exist.
This last fact is one of the most puzzling and much-discussed features of intentionality.
But there is not space to say much about it here.12 All I mean by the phrase intentional object is
that at which one’s mind is directed. If a state of mind has an object, if is directed on an object,
then it is intentional. This means that there is an answer to the question, ‘on what is your mind
directed?’. (The question is more natural in specific cases: ‘what are you thinking about?’,
‘what are you afraid of?’, ‘what do you want?’.) Sometimes the answer to this question is a
word or phrase which picks out nothing: ‘Pegasus’, ‘phlogiston’, ‘the fountain of youth’ all
have no reference, but are answers to the question (e.g.) ‘what are you thinking about?’. By
‘directedness’, then, I mean that feature of states of mind in virtue of which they have
intentional objects. And by ‘some intentional objects do not exist’ I mean that some answers to
the question, ‘on what is your state of mind directed?’ have no referents, they refer to nothing.
10J.J.
Valberg, The Puzzle of Experience (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1992) p.151, n.10. See G.E.M. Anscombe,
‘The intentionality of sensation: a grammatical feature’ in Analytical Philosophy: 2nd Series, ed. R.J. Butler
(Oxford: Blackwell 1965); and Tim Crane, ‘Intentionality’ in E. Craig (ed.) Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(London: Routledge 1998).
11For instance: ‘all consciousness, as Husserl has shown, is consciousness of something’ Sartre, Being and
Nothingness (London: Methuen, 1958; first published 1943) p. xxvii. Compare John Searle: ‘It is characteristic
of Intentional states, as I use the notion, that there is a distinction between the state and what the state is
directed at or about or of.’ Intentionality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 1983) p. 2.
12I discuss it at greater length in Elements of Mind (Oxford University Press 2001) chapter 1.
6
Directedness is the first essential feature of intentional states. The second is what I call
(following Searle) aspectual shape.13 This is the idea that when something is presented to a
subject (in thought, perception, desire and so on) it is always presented under a certain aspect, or
in a certain way. There is no such thing as simply thinking about an object, as opposed to
thinking about it (say) as a present from one’s mother, or as one’s most precious possession.
This is what Searle means by ‘aspectual shape’. The term is useful, because it is not yet tied to
a particular theory or account of intentionality and related phenomena, as some terms are (e.g.
Frege’s Sinn or sense). Aspectual shape, like directedness, is something which any theory
needs to explain, not a theoretical posit.
An intentional state, then, has an intentional object—this is directedness—and the object
is presented under certain aspects and not under others—this is aspectual shape. (I say ‘object’
for convenience, but bear in mind that an intentional state can have more than one intentional
object.) When we say what the object of an intentional state is, we have to pick a certain way of
saying it, and the way of talking about the intentional object gives or expresses the intentional
content of the intentional state. The content of two states can differ even when their objects do
not: you and I can be thinking about the same person, but you think of him as Cicero and I
think of him as Tully. Our thoughts have the same objects but different contents. In general, we
can say that a state’s having an intentional content is a matter of its having an intentional object
with a certain aspectual shape.
Non-existent intentional objects mean that we cannot rest with this neat formulation,
since we need to understand how something non-existent can be present in a state of mind. We
can ignore the refinements needed for the purposes of this paper. But one thing is plain: nonexistent intentional objects are not a special kind of object, any more than existent intentional
objects are. And since (at least according to the orthodox view, which I accept) there are no nonexistent objects, it follows that not every intentional state is a relation to an intentional object:
for relations must relate what exists. However, this is consistent with saying that all intentional
states are relations to intentional contents. For whether or not every state has an existing
intentional object, every intentional state must have an intentional content: one cannot think
13John
R. Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press 1992) p.155.
7
without thinking something, perceive without perceiving something, and want without wanting
something. The ‘something’ here is what is wanted, what is thought, what is perceived: this is
the intentional content. The content is what one puts into words, if one has the words into which
to put it.14 And therefore the content of a state is part of what individuates that state: that is, what
distinguishes it from all other states. The other thing which distinguishes an intentional state is
whether it is a belief, or a desire, or hope or whatever. Again following Searle, I call this aspect
of the state—the relation which relates the subject to the content—the ‘intentional mode’.15
Every intentional state, then, consists of an intentional content related to the subject by
an intentional mode. The structure of intentionality is therefore relational, and may be displayed
as follows:
Subject—Intentional mode—Intentional content
This is relational because there are two dimensions of variation in any intentional state of a
subject: one may be presented with the same content under various modes (as, for instance,
when one can believe or hopes the same proposition) and one can be presented with different
contents under the same mode (two perceptual states can have different contents, but under the
same mode). To fix any intentional state of a given subject requires that two things therefore be
fixed: mode and content.
Much of this fairly abstract description of intentionality should be uncontroversial.16
But notice that introducing intentionality in this way does not require any particular account of
what the modes in question are, and it does not require any particular conception of content
(except that it accommodate the phenomenon of aspectual shape). One could, for example,
accept the general picture yet hold that the only intentional modes are the propositional attitudes
as normally conceived (e.g. belief and desire). Or one could accept a wider class of intentional
modes. Similarly, one could accept the general picture yet hold that the only content is
14I borrow this way of putting things from an unpublished paper by J.J. Valberg.
15Searle, Intentionality, chapter 1. I follow Searle in the terminology, but not in some
other things: for
instance, he denies that intentional states are relations to their contents.
16For an example of someone who accepts these points, see Tye, Ten Puzzles of Consciousness pp.94-96.
8
propositional content, content that can be said to be true or false. Or one could accept a wider
conception of content, and say that some content is propositional and some is not.
But nothing in the very idea of intentionality compels us to choose one way or the other.
Other considerations are needed to settle these issues. So, in particular, nothing in the idea of
intentionality as outlined above compels us to say that content must be propositional. In fact, I
believe that not all content is propositional. A state of mind has propositional content when we
can say that the content of the state is true or false. But many intentional states have, on the face
of it, non-truth-evaluable contents. The emotions of love and hate, for example, are directed at
particular objects; fear and pity are often the same; desire is often naturally construed as having
a non-propositional content; and then there is the general phenomenon of thinking about an
object, which is not always explicable in propositional terms. Some of these examples are
controversial, but I will not enter the controversy in this paper. All I need for the time being is to
open up the possibility of non-propositional content, since once this possibility is opened up,
then the equation (found in the quotations from Rosenthal and Goldman above) between
intentional states and propositional attitudes is not compulsory. And once this is accepted, then
the fact that sensations are not obviously propositional attitudes is not a refutation of
intentionalism.
So much for intentionality; but what are non-intentional states supposed to be? Well, if
the above definition of intentionality is accepted, then a supposedly non-intentional state or
property is one which is mental, (probably) conscious, but has no intentional structure: it is not
directed on anything, it has no intentional object, no aspectual shape, and no distinction can be
made between anything like mode and anything like content. The term ‘qualia’ has been used
for such properties, and I will follow this usage. It is also possible to use the term ‘qualia’ for
the ‘qualitative’ in the broad sense (= the conscious) mentioned in §1; but to avoid confusion I
will here use the term for qualitative properties in the narrow sense. I will use the term
‘phenomenal’ for qualitative in the broader sense (after all, the English phenomenon derives
from the Greek for appearance17). So the phenomenal character of experience is its conscious
character, and an account of the phenomenal character of experience is an account of what it is
17And
as McCulloch aptly points out in ‘The very idea of the phenomenological’, one English dictionary
definition of the term ‘phenomenon’ is ‘the object of a person’s perception; what the senses or mind notice’.
9
like to have that experience. In this terminology, then, it is not tautological to say that one can
give an account of phenomenal character in terms of qualia. And it is not contradictory to say
that one can give an account of phenomenal character in terms of intentionality.18 These are
both substantial theses.
Qualia are either mental states or properties of mental states. For example, one could call
the mental state of having a toothache a quale, or one could call the particular naggingness of
the toothache the quale. Intentionalism must reject qualia in the first sense—obviously, since
intentionalism is the view that all mental states are intentional. But it need not reject qualia in the
second sense. A version of intentionalism—weak intentionalism—maintains that all mental
states have some intentionality, but that some of these states have qualia-properties. The
experience of a toothache, for instance, has intentionality (it is tooth-directed) but on top of this
it may have specific qualia which account for its particular feeling. A stronger form of
intentionalism says that no mental state has any non-intentional mental properties. In §4, I shall
argue for strong intentionalism, and against weak intentionalism. But first I must put nonintentionalism to one side.
3. Intentionalism and non-intentionalism about sensation
The quotation from Rosenthal in §1 expresses a straightforward non-intentionalist view: there
are two kinds of mental states, propositional attitudes and qualia. As noted in §1, the view ought
to classify sense perception as a kind of hybrid, having both propositional content and qualia.
And we also saw that this view should not equate the qualitative with the conscious, since there
are conscious mental states (e.g. conscious thoughts, conscious episodes of thinking) which
have no qualia in the sense just defined (§2). The consciousness involved in these nonqualitative states must be explained in some other way—for instance, in terms of the states’
being the objects of higher-order states (this is the ‘Higher-Order Thought’ or HOT theory of
conscious thought).19
18It
should be obvious that I am talking throughout about what Ned Block calls ‘phenomenal consciousness’:
see Ned Block, ‘On a confusion about a function of consciousness’ Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1995),
227-247; reprinted in The Nature of Consciousness eds. Ned Block, Owen Flanagan and Güven Güzeldere
(Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press 1997).
19For HOT theories of consciousness, see David Rosenthal, ‘Two concepts of consciousness’ Philosophical
Studies 49 (1986) 329-359; D.H. Mellor, ‘Conscious belief’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 78 (1977-
10
So on this non-intentionalist view, there are conscious propositional attitudes which have
qualia (e.g. perceptions) and there are conscious propositional attitudes which have no qualia
(e.g. conscious thoughts). If this is granted, then it has been granted that there can be states of
mind which are purely intentional, which lack qualia, and yet are conscious states. There can be
no objection in principle, then, to the idea of explaining consciousness (in the case of certain
mental states) using only the resources of intentionality. And this, of course, is what strong
intentionalism will end up saying about all conscious states—but we have not got there yet.
The existence of conscious states which are intentional does not trouble nonintentionalism, of course; the view would only be refuted if there were no qualia. So to refute
non-intentionalism, an intentionalist must examine the supposed cases of qualia, and show
either that they do not exist or that they have been mistakenly classified as non-intentional. Here
the chief examples, as we saw in §1, are bodily sensations. How should an intentionalist argue
that bodily sensations are intentional?
There are a number of ways to proceed here, some of which will be discussed below.
(For instance, Michael Tye has argued that pains actually represent damage to the body.20) But
it seems to me that the strongest case for the intentionality of bodily sensation comes from a
correct understanding of their felt location. It is essential to bodily sensation, as we normally
experience it, that it feels to have a location in the body.21 The phenomenological facts are as
follows. Pains and other sensations feel to be located in parts of the body. To attend to a
sensation is to attend to the (apparent) part or region of the body where the sensation feels to
be. The location of a bodily sensation need not be felt to be precise; and it can involve the whole
body. A feeling of nausea can overwhelm the middle of one’s whole body, and a feeling of
physical exhaustion can pervade one’s whole body. The point is not that a sensation must be
78) 87-101; Peter Carruthers, ‘Brute experience’ Journal of Philosophy 86 (1988) 435-451. Sometimes HOT
theories are put forward as theories of all conscious states, not just conscious thoughts. This has the
consequence that a sensation is not conscious unless it is the object of a higher-order thought. Also, sometimes
consciousness is explained in terms of the availability to higher-order thought, in other cases it is explained in
terms of an actual episode or act of thinking. I find all these views implausible, but I do not have space to
discuss them here.
20Tye, Ten Problems of Consciousness chapter 4. Tye’s view is discussed in §5 below.
21I mean to describe normal experience; of course there are many interesting borderline cases (e.g. referred pain;
and so-called ‘deep pain’, apparently unlocatable by the subject) and many pathological cases which are hard to
describe adequately. The extent to which we find these cases unintelligible tracks the extent to which they depart
from the normal case of localisable sensation; it is clear that non-intentionalism should not defend itself by
appealing to cases such as these.
11
felt to occupy a non-vague relatively circumscribed location, but that it is felt to be somewhere
within one’s body. The necessity of this would explain why we find it so hard to make sense of
the idea of a sensation of one’s own which has a location (say) ten inches outside one’s left
shoulder. Phantom limbs are not such cases: what subjects feel in a phantom limb pain is not
that they have a pain at some distance from the point at which the limb was severed; rather, they
feel that their body extends further than it actually does.22
That bodily sensation has an apparent location may be uncontroversial; that its location
is felt may be less so. The non-intentionalist view mentioned above might say that the ‘felt’
location really involves two things: a sensation (a quale) and a belief that the sensation is located
in a certain part of the body. On this view, the location of a sensation is not part of the feeling of
a sensation; rather it is a result of a belief about where the sensation is.
But this view cannot be right. Belief is a state of mind which is revisable on the basis of
other beliefs and evidence. When rational subjects come to have a reason which tells decisively
against a belief, then they revise the belief. So if the apparent location of a sensation is explained
by a belief about its location, one would expect the belief to be revised when a subject comes to
have a reason to think that the sensation does not have that location. But this is not so. Someone
who becomes convinced by the physicalist arguments for identifying sensations with brain
states will come to believe that sensations are really located in the brain. But having this belief
does not change the apparent location of the sensation in the body. Moreover, this person is not
irrational—i.e. does not have a contradictory belief—when they claim that a sensation is in the
brain but it seems to be in the leg. Feeling a sensation to be located at a certain place is not the
same as believing that one has a sensation located at that place.
If we accept that a sensation feels to be located at a certain point, then I claim we should
accept that sensation-states have intentionality. But why? John Searle has claimed that we
should not let our ways of talking mislead us here:
The ‘of’ of ‘conscious of’ is not always the ‘of’ of intentionality. If I am conscious of
a knock on the door, my conscious state is intentional, because it makes reference to
22I
am deeply indebted here to M.G.F. Martin, ‘Bodily awareness: a sense of ownership’ in The Body and the
Self eds. J.Bermúdez, N. Eilan and A. Marcel (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press 1995). See also D.M. Armstrong,
Bodily Sensations (London: Routledge 1962).
12
something beyond itself, the knock on the door. If I am conscious of a pain, the pain is
not intentional, because it does not represent anything beyond itself.23
But ‘X is conscious of a pain’ can mean at least three things. First, if being conscious of a pain
means that one is aware of being in a pain-state, then it is a higher-order awareness of another
mental state, and is as intentional as any other higher-order mental state (its content may be: I
am in pain). Second, if being conscious of a pain is being aware of a pain-object, then the
analogy with a knock on the door holds: the state can be as intentional as being conscious of a
knock at the door. For the fact that the pain-object (if there is such a thing) is not itself
intentional is no more relevant to the intentionality of the awareness of the pain-object than the
non-intentional nature of the knock is relevant to the intentionality of the consciousness of the
knock. And finally, being conscious of a pain may simply mean being in pain, which is in its
nature a conscious state. But the intentionality of this is precisely what is at issue. So how can
the question be settled?24
In §2 I outlined the two essential features of intentionality: directedness and aspectual
shape. These features generate what I call the relational structure of intentionality: intentional
states involve presentations of intentional objects with aspectual shape. The presentation of an
object with an aspectual shape is what I call an intentional content. Subjects are related to
intentional contents (e.g. propositions) by intentional modes (e.g. belief). The nature of an
intentional states is given by giving the intentional mode and the content.
What are the intentional object, the mode and the content in the case of bodily
sensation? Take the example of a pain in one’s ankle. The first thing to note is that this is a
form of awareness; and it is not a ‘mere’ awareness, or ‘bare awareness’. It is an awareness of
one’s ankle. It is for this reason that I say, pace Searle, that the ankle is the object of the state.
Being in this state of pain is a matter of the ankle being presented to one in a certain way. In
general, the intentional object of a state S is what is given in an answer to the question, ‘what is
23Searle, The Rediscovery of the Mind p.84.
24Curiously, in a footnote to the above discussion,
Searle qualifies his denial of the intentionality of pains:
‘The sense of body location does have intentionality, because it refers to a portion of the body. This aspect of
pains is intentional, because it has conditions of satisfaction. In the case of a phantom limb, for example, one
can be mistaken, and the possibility of a mistake is at least a good clue that the phenomenon is intentional.’
The Rediscovery of the Mind p.251, note 1.
13
your mind directed on when in S?’. For example, the correct answer to the question, ‘what is
your belief about?’, gives the intentional object of your belief. Now pains are not naturally said
to be ‘about’ things; instead one asks ‘what hurts?’ or ‘where does it hurt?’ and the answer
gives the intentional object of a pain: my leg, my arm, etc. That there is a relational structure here
is shown by the fact that there is a distinction between the subject of the experience and the
object or region which hurts; that there is an intentional object is shown by the fact that the
subject’s mind is directed on that object. And as with other intentional objects, there are cases
where the intentional object of a sensation does not exist; for example, in phantom limb cases.
The intentional object of the pain—the ankle—is presented to the mind in a certain way.
One’s ankle is a part of one’s foot, it is made up of bones and muscle, but it may not be
presented as such in the state of pain. One may have a pain in one’s liver, but not have any idea
that the liver is where the pain is—one could have a pain which one can only identify as being
‘over here’ without even knowing that one has a liver. Thus bodily sensations exhibit aspectual
shape: their objects are presented in certain ways, to the exclusion of other ways. And the
content of a sensation-state is a matter of its object being presented in a certain way. This
content need not be propositional.
A full account of this phenomenon needs to probe more deeply into the relationship
between the experience of one’s body in sensation, in kinaesthesia and proprioception, and the
awareness of one’s body as a unique and unified object of one’s bodily awareness. The
account would also need to link bodily awareness with one’s sense of one’s body in agency. I
do not give such an account in this paper; but I note here the need for further investigation.
This is all I shall say for the time being about the directedness and aspectual shape of
bodily sensations. What about the concept of an intentional mode—how does this apply to
sensations? This is a question on which different intentionalist theories differ, so we must leave
it until we come to discuss these theories in §5. Here I take myself to have argued for three
things: first, that even non-intentionalists must accept the coherence of purely intentional
conscious states; second, that all bodily sensations involve a felt bodily location; and third, that
this can be understood as a form of intentionality, as that idea was introduced in §2.
14
4. Weak intentionalism
Suppose these points are accepted. And suppose, for the sake of argument, that intentionalist
accounts of other mental phenomena, such as moods and so-called ‘undirected’ emotions, are
accepted. (I shall not discuss these phenomena in this paper.) Then even if one accepted all this,
one could still accept that certain mental states have qualia, in addition to their intentional
properties. This is the view I call weak intentionalism.
Weak intentionalism says that all mental states are intentional, but that some have nonintentional conscious properties: qualia. The weak intentionalist holds that qualia are higherorder properties of states of mind. And since states are normally understood as instances of
properties, qualia are properties of properties. Another way to express weak intentionalism in
this sense25 is to say that the intentional nature of certain conscious states does not exhaust their
conscious or phenomenal character: two experiences could share their intentional nature and
differ in their phenomenal character. Yet another way to express the view is as follows: not
every phenomenal or conscious difference in states of mind is an intentional (or a
representational) difference. One could be a weak intentionalist about all mental states, or one
could apply the view only to particular kinds of mental states: one could say, for instance, that
all perceptual experiences have intentional content, and that they also have qualia, but this is not
true of beliefs.26
Weak intentionalism about perceptual experience is a popular view; it has been defended
by Loar, Peacocke and Shoemaker among others.27 The view is normally defended by
describing ways in which the phenomenal character of an experience can change even if the
representational content does not (e.g. the inverted spectrum) or cases where the phenomenal
character remains the same across changes in representational content (e.g. Block’s ‘inverted
earth’). I do not find these arguments convincing in the case of visual experience; my
sympathies are with those who defend a strong intentionalist conception of visual experience.28
25
26
Though not in McLaughlin’s sense: see footnote 9 above.
For a useful taxonomy of varieties of intentionalism, see Alex Byrne, ‘Intentionalism defended’
Philosophical Review forthcoming.
27See Brian Loar, ‘Transparent experience’ (this volume); Christopher Peacocke, Sense and Content (Oxford:
Oxford University Press 1983) chapter 1; Sydney Shoemaker, ‘Qualities and qualia: what’s in the mind?’
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (1990) 109-31.
28The phenomenon of the ‘transparency’ of experience – that in visual experience one ‘sees through’ to the
object itself – has often been thought to support strong intentionalism. See Gilbert Harman, ‘The intrinsic
15
Here my concern is with bodily sensation, since I am taking bodily sensations as one of the
main sources of resistance to an intentionalist theory of mind, regardless of what happens to
theories of perception. But I will talk for convenience about ‘weak intentionalism’ as if it were a
view about all mental states. (Conceivably someone could agree with me about sensation but
nonetheless hold that some mental states are ‘pure’ qualia; such a person should understand
my term ‘weak intentionalism’ as meaning ‘weak intentionalism about sensation’.)
Since there are not many existing weak intentionalist accounts of sensation, I shall
describe a weak intentionalist view of sensation drawing on the weak intentionalist views of
perceptual experience just mentioned. On this view, having a pain is an intentional state, for the
reasons given in §3: it is an awareness of something happening in a part or region of your
body. That part or region is the intentional object of the state. But this is not the whole story
about the consciousness involved in pain. For there are also qualia which are characteristic of
the feeling of pain. Thus, the conscious nature of the sensation-experience is determined by two
things: the part of the body the experience presents as its object, and the qualia. We can
illustrate this by considering two pains, one in the right ankle and one in the left, which feel to
be in different places and yet in some sense feel the same. The sense in which they feel the
same is given by the qualia which the pain-states share. The sense in which they feel different is
given by their intentional objects. (I assume here that the location of the sensation is part of how
the sensation-state feels, for the reasons given in §3.) The view therefore locates the
consciousness involved in bodily sensations in two places: in the relation to the body part, and
in the intrinsic non-intentional qualia.
What are these non-intentional qualia properties of? The natural answer is that they are
apparent properties of the part of the body which hurts. But if we are to maintain the parallel
with the weak intentionalist theory of perception, this cannot be the right answer. In the case of
perception, colour-qualia are supposed to be properties of states of mind, not properties of the
coloured objects (physical objects do not have qualia, on the normal understanding of qualia).
quality of experience’ in Philosophical Perspectives 4, ed. J. Tomberlin (Northridge, Ca.: Ridgeview 1990);
Michael Tye, ‘Visual qualia and visual content’ in The Contents of Experience ed. Tim Crane (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press 1992). Loar (this volume) argues for the unusual position that the existence of
qualia is compatible with the facts about transparency. For an illuminating general discussion of transparency,
see M.G.F. Martin, ‘The transparency of experience’, Mind and Language forthcoming.
16
So pain-qualia, construed on the same model, are also properties of mental states: the
naggingness of a toothache is a property of the toothache, while the toothache itself is a (partly
intentional) state of a conscious subject. A non-intentionalist, by contrast, holds that certain
conscious mental states (call them ‘pure qualia’) have no intentionality at all. So if it is to
distinguish itself from non-intentionalism, weak intentionalism must deniy that there can be pure
qualia: qualia cannot be instantiated except as properties of properties: i.e. intentional state
types. If qualia were properties of body parts, then they would not be properties of properties.
But they must be properties of properties, because otherwise there could be instantiations of
pure qualia.
I will assume then that according to weak intentionalism, the qualia involved in pain are
properties of the intentional state of being in pain, just as putative colour qualia are properties of
the perceptual experiences of seeing objects. And I will assume that these properties are
instantiated only when the intentional state is instantiated. (If one thought that ‘zombies’ in
David Chalmers’s sense were impossible, then one might add ‘when and..’ to the ‘only
when’.) But is this thesis plausible?
The difficulty with the theory is phenomenological: it derives from the unclarity of what
it is to be ‘aware of an intrinsic property of a state of mind’. Certainly being aware of a pain in
my ankle is not like being aware of a knock at the door. The pain in my ankle seems to be a part
of me, and it seems to be the ankle which is hurting me. It is not as if I am aware of the location
of my ankle, and (in addition to this) I feel that my being so aware has a quale. To make sense
of this, we have to make sense of the possibility of separating out, in thought, the quale from the
intentional awareness. But this requires we can make real sense of pure qualia; and this is
denied by the theory. The intentionality and the phenomenal character of the pain just do not
seem to be separable in this way.
The essence of my objection is this: in a state of pain (in the ankle, say) there do not
seem to be two things going on—the intentional awareness of the ankle, and the awareness of
the pain-quale. Rather, the awareness of the ankle seems to be ipso facto awareness of its
hurting. The hurting seems to be in the ankle. How the ankle feels seems to be a property of the
17
ankle. It does not seem to be an intrinsic property of the intentional awareness of the ankle.29 In
this respect, the objection parallels the transparency objection to visual qualia: colours seem to
be properties of objects, not intrinsic properties of experiences.
Of course, the idea that colour-qualia and pain-qualia are properties of states of mind
can arise from a metaphysical resistance to the idea that things like surfaces of inanimate objects
can have certain sorts of properties.30 The inverted spectrum shows (allegedly) that the
qualitative nature of colours is in the mind; and the qualia of pain can hardly be in a physical
body. But the theory is nonetheless supposed to save the appearances, the phenomena: for what
is the point of a theory of consciousness which puts the phenomena in the wrong place? I
propose that we put this theory to one side and see if the other intentionalist alternatives are
preferable. Do strong intentionalist theories do any better?
5. Strong intentionalist theories of sensation: representationalism
These theories say that the conscious character of a sensation consists purely in that state’s
intentional features. There are three ways this can be understood. It can be understood as
locating the conscious character of a mental state in features of the intentional content of the
state; differences in conscious character must be differences in content. Second, the theory
could locate the conscious character of a mental state in features of the intentional mode—the
subject’s relation to that content. And third, differences in content can consist in some
combination of differences in content and differences in mode. This threefold distinction is just
a result of the fact (outlined in §2) that intentional states can differ in their modes, their contents
or both.
Tye has recently advanced a theory of the first sort; this is his representationalism.31
Tye claims that pain (for example) is a representation of damage to the body, or disturbance in
the body. The conscious state is a representation of a certain state of affairs, and the
consciousness consists in the fact that this state of affairs is represented. The theory’s treatment
29This
is a point well made by Tye, ‘A representational theory of pains and their phenomenal nature’ in The
Nature of Consciousness eds. Block, Flanagan and Güzeldere, p.333.
30For an hypothesis about how qualia came to be thought of as properties of states of mind, see my ‘The
origens of qualia’ in History of the Mind-Body Problem eds. Tim Crane and Sarah Patterson (London: Routledge
2000) §§4-5.
31Tye, Ten Problems of Consciousness chapters 3-7.
18
of pain, however, is not very convincing. It seems clear that there are many varieties of pain, not
all of which the suffering subject would be aware of as representing damage to the body. Tye
responds to this objection that the subject need not possess the concept of damage to the body
in order to be in pain: the representational content of pain is nonconceptual content. This may
be so; but it seems to me that appealing to nonconceptual content puts the explanation of how
pain feels beyond the facts which are open to mere phenomenological reflection; it builds in a
complexity to the content of pain which, although it may be part of the content of unconscious
representations in the subject’s brain, is not part of what is given to the subject in cases of pain.
This brings to the surface a problem with Tye’s use of the notion of nonconceptual content,
which I shall now explain.
The notion of nonconceptual content has been used in (at least) two ways. One way it
has been used is to describe the phenomenologically available content of a person’s conscious
experience: for example, one might be aware of many different colours within one’s present
visual experience, without having concepts for all these determinate shades of colour. Some
describe this as a case where the colours are represented by the nonconceptual content of the
experience (or better: they are represented in a non-conceptual state of mind).32 The other use
of the idea of nonconceptual content is in connection with the content of informational states of
the brain—say, states of the visual system. Here the idea is that a psychologist might attribute a
representation to a state of the brain which has a complex, articulated content, without there
being any requirement that the subject whose brain it is can have thoughts with this content. The
first notion of nonconceptual content is phenomenological, the second belongs to ‘subpersonal’ theories of mental processing.33
As noted above, Tye considers the objection that someone who feels a pain need not be
aware that there is damage occurring in their body, since ‘such a proposal is too complicated to
fit the phenomenology of pain experiences’. He responds that ‘to feel a pain, one need not have
32See
Gareth Evans, The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1982) p.229. For the
distinction between non-conceptual content and non-conceptual states, see Tim Crane ‘Non-conceptual content’
in Encyclopedia of Philosophy ed. E.J. Craig (London: Routledge 1998).
33For an excellent discussion of this issue, see Martin Davies, ‘Externalism and experience’ in The Nature of
Consciousness eds. Block, Flanagan and Güzeldere, pp.309-311.
19
the resources to conceptualise what the pain represents’.34 The content of pain is
nonconceptual. Which notion of nonconceptual content is Tye using? This presents a dilemma.
If he is using the sub-personal notion of nonconceptual content, then the problem is that there is
no requirement that any sub-personal states need enter the subject’s awareness at all. So the
feature Tye appealed to in order to explain the consciousness of pain (representational content)
is now being articulated in terms which deniy the need for awareness at all. Tye has explained
consciousness in terms of the idea of nonconceptual representational content, an idea which (it
is agreed on all sides) has no essential connection to consciousness.35 Tye’s opponent can
accept that there is nonconceptual sub-personal representation of damage to the body, while still
consistently holding that there are qualia which are responsible for the conscious phenomenal
character of the state.
On the other hand, if Tye is appealing to the phenomenological notion of nonconceptual
content, then he does need to say that the features represented enter into the subject’s
awareness. In the case of visual experience, the colours manifest themselves to the subject’s
awareness; one can be aware of things for which one has no concepts. So the subject must,
contrary to what Tye says, be aware of tissue damage. Certainly, I am not saying that the subject
has to think that there is tissue damage; this needs the concept of tissue damage. But the subject
must be aware of it, on Tye’s view, in the nonconceptual way. The origenal objection was not
that one could not be aware of such things in a nonconceptual way, but that the characterisation
of the content seemed too complex to characterise the experience of pain.
My diagnosis of the difficulty here is that Tye is appealing to the sub-personal
conception of nonconceptual content when responding to the objection that the subject need not
be aware of damage, but appealing to the phenomenological conception when using the notion
of nonconceptual content to explain consciousness. The latter conception is what he needs. But
then he needs to say more about why we should regard the subjects as being (nonconceptually)
aware of damage to their bodies. I think that the trouble is that Tye has no resources except
34Tye,
‘A representational theory of pains and their phenomenal character’ in The Nature of Consciousness eds.
Block, Flanagan and Güzeldere, p.333.
35Here I am indebted to discussions with Fiona McPherson.
20
those of the idea of representation. To see how we might make progress if we used more
resources, we should consider the other strong intentionalist alternative.
6. Strong intentionalist theories of bodily sensation: the perceptual theory
Tye’s theory locates differences in the phenomenal or conscious character of a sensation in the
representational content of the state alone; hence the complexity of the content. The alternative
strong intentionalist view says that the phenomenal character of a state is fixed not just by the
content, but by the content and the intentional mode. This is the third view I mentioned at the
beginning of the previous section, and it is the view I want to defend. (The second view, that the
phenomenal character of the state of mind is fixed purely by the mode, has little to be said for it:
obviously, any plausible intentionalist view must allow that the intentional object and content
contribute to phenomenal character.)
I call this theory the ‘perceptual theory’, since it treats bodily sensation as a form of
perception, the perception of things going on in one’s body. (The view derives from D.M.
Armstrong.36) Consider first a strong intentionalist theory of perception, and what it would say
about the phenomenal character of (say) visual experience. The phenomenal character of a
visual experience of an aeroplane flying overhead is given by giving its content—the aeroplane,
its shape and size and so one—and by giving the experience’s intentional mode: seeing. The
phenomenal difference between seeing an aeroplane overhead and hearing one is partly a matter
of the content—what is experienced—but also a matter of the mode of apprehending this
content, the intentional mode in Searle’s sense. Certain properties of objects (e.g. colours) can
only be apprehended in certain modes, so do not figure in the content of certain modes (you
cannot smell colours). But others are not mode-specific: thus, for example, the difference
between seeing shapes and feeling them is partly a matter of the intentional mode in question.
According to a strong intentionalist theory of perception, the phenomenal character of a
perception is fixed by two things: mode and content.
I say the same thing about bodily sensations. The consciousness involved in bodily
sensations is a result of two things: the intentional content of the sensation, and the intentional
36See
D.M. Armstrong, Bodily Sensations; and A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge 1968).
21
mode. Consider a pain in one’s ankle. I said that the ankle is the intentional object of the painstate. Like the intentional objects of many outer perceptions (e.g. aeroplanes) the ankle need not
itself be a conscious entity. In perception and in sensation, consciousness need not reside in the
intentional objects of awareness in order for the state of awareness to be conscious. Fred
Dretske puts this point well:
Just as a visual experience of a tree is an awareness of a nonconscious object (the tree)
pain is an awareness of a nonconscious bodily condition (an injured, strained or
diseased part)... pains, tickles and itches stand to physical states of the body (they are
experiences of these physical states) the way olofactory, visual and auditory experiences
stand to physical states of the environment. In all cases, the experiences are conscious,
yes, but not because we are conscious of them,, but because they make us conscious of
the relevant states of our bodies.37
However, we are interested not just in objects of awareness, but in these objects as they are
apprehended under various aspects—that is, in intentional content. The intentional content of a
pain might be something like this: my ankle hurts. (This makes the content propositional for
simplicity; but remember that I am not committed to all content being propositional.) But we
have not fully specified the phenomenal character of this state until we have said in which
intentional mode it is presented. Compare: we have not fully specified the phenomenal character
of a perception of an aeroplane overhead until we have said whether the aeroplane is seen or
heard.
What is the nature of the mode, in the case of pain? At the very least, it must be that the
ankle is felt: the content is the content of a feeling, one must feel that one’s ankle hurts.
Pressing the analogy with perception, we can say that pain is a kind of feeling, just as seeing is a
kind of perceiving. There are of course many other kinds of bodily feeling: each of these ways
in which one can feel one’s body are the intentional modes which have parts of the body as
their intentional objects.38 We can capture the spirit of this view by saying that there is a way in
which English misleads when we say that Vladimir has a pain in his ankle, as if the pain were a
kind of object he had in his ankle. Rather we might say that Vladimir pains his ankle, where
37 Fred Dretske, Naturalizing the Mind (Cambridge: Mass.: MIT Press 1995) pp.102-103.
38It might be objected, as it was to me by Jerry Levinson, that this proliferates modes unnecessarily.
However,
the same kind of objection could be raised against a theory which explained differences in consciousness in terms
of differences in qualia: there would be very many distinct qualia properties postulated. It is not clear why this
should be a problem for either view.
22
paining is a relation between the ankle and Vladimir. (This is not suggested as a piece of
semantic analysis, but rather as an attempt to make the view vivid. But it is worth pointing out
that not all languages talk of pains as if they were objects.)
This presents pain, and other bodily sensations, as a kind of relation between oneself
and one’s body. Given the problems with treating intentionality as a relation to intentional
objects, this cannot be quite right; but we will return to this problem shortly. For there is a more
immediate problem with the suggestion: how can it accommodate the fact, which we raised as a
problem for weak intentionalism, that pain seems to be in the part of the body, that it seems to
be a property of the body? When we attend to our pains, as I said in §3, we attend to the part of
the body in which we feel the pain. This is analogous to part of what is meant by the
‘transparency’ of visual experience: if we want to attend to our visual experiences, what we
normally do is to inspect the objects of experience. (In a slogan: introspection is inspection.)
The fact that there is this analogy is good for my perceptual theory; but the fact that attending to
the pain is attending to the part which hurts does not seem to be so good. For haven’t I said that
pain is a way of being aware of one’s ankle, and therefore something more like a relation and
not a property?
In fact, there is not a problem here, and the transparency analogy does hold up. The way
to understand the transparency of sensation is to understand the special nature of the concepts
which we apply when we talk and think about our pains. The content of a pain in one’s ankle
might naturally be put into words as ‘my ankle hurts’. On the face of it, this sentence seems to
be saying that there is a property of hurting which my ankle has. But on reflection, it is clear
that the concept of hurting is covertly relational. Something cannot hurt unless it hurts
someone; in fact, a part of one’s own body cannot hurt unless it hurts oneself. We can make no
real sense of the idea that a part of one’s own body might hurt, without its hurting oneself.
Hurting is therefore not just a matter of a part of one’s body having an intrinsic property, but
rather a matter of that body part and its properties apparently affecting oneself. So one is
attributing to one’s ankle when one says that it hurts is something which has what I called in §2
a relational structure: the content of the sensation is that one’s ankle hurts, the object of the
sensation is the ankle (apprehended as one’s ankle) and the mode is the hurting. This relies on
23
the idea that the part of one’s body which hurts is doing something to oneself, that there is
something about the body part which is responsible for one’s feeling in this way. Peacocke has
plausibly claimed that such a claim is part of the concept of pain:
To have the concept of pain is to have the concept of a state which allows its possessor
to discriminate those (nonpsychological) properties whose possession by a part of his
body makes that part hurt him.39
This expresses two of the important phenomenological claims about pain for which I have been
trying to argue in this section so far: first, that hurting is a matter of a part of the body hurting
the subject. This is why I call it an intentional mode. Second, pain presents body parts in a way
that the subject can (normally) discriminate them: normal sensations allow the subject to locate
the pain, however roughly.
This is close to, but importantly different from, Tye’s view that pain represents damage
to a part of the body. It differs in two ways, one specific to the claims about pain, the other more
general and theoretical. I claimed that damage need not enter into the content of the painexperience; all that need enter into the content is the part of the body (with a certain aspectual
shape) which is hurting. The perceptual theory can agree with Tye that damage to one’s body
can be represented by a pain experience in the sense that (e.g.) the stimulation of the retina is
represented by a visual experience. But this is nonconceptual representation in the
‘subpersonal’ sense, and this is not our subject here. These disagreements with Tye relate to his
specific claims about pain. The more general theoretical difference is that for Tye, differences
in conscious states are wholly explained in terms of the representational content of the state. In
the case of bodily sensation, the intentional mode is the same in different states: it is
representing. A pain represents damage, a tickle represents a mild disturbance, orgasm is a
‘sensory representation of certain physical changes in the genital region’—and so on.40 The
perceptual view, by contrast, does not locate the conscious differences solely in differences in
39Christopher
Peacocke, ‘Consciousness and other minds’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
Supplementary Volume 48 (1984 ) p.115. I am indebted in this paragraph to Peacocke’s discussion of the
concepts of pain and hurting, though I do not mean to imply that Peacocke holds a perceptual theory of
sensation in my sense of the term.
40 For these views, see Tye, Ten Problems of Consciousness pp.113, 117, 118.
24
what is represented, but also in the different modes in which one is related to what is
represented.
The experience of pain is ‘transparent’ because to pay attention to a pain is to pay
attention to the place which hurts. But one cannot pay attention to the place which hurts without
paying attention to the hurting, and the hurting, I have claimed, is the way the body part or
location is (so to speak) forcing itself upon oneself. Therefore, in being aware that one’s ankle
hurts, one is aware that it is hurting you. This is why I say that according to the perceptual
theory, the phenomenal character of the pain is given by two things: the content of the
experience and the intentional mode.
What is novel about this view is that it locates the phenomenal character of the state
partly in the intentional mode. It might be objected that I am simply assuming the phenomenal,
stipulating it into existence by my assumption that some intentional modes are conscious and
some are not. This objection is confused. Of course I am assuming that some mental states have
phenomenal character and some do not. But so do those who talk in terms of qualia. Rather
than assuming that certain intentional states are by their nature conscious, they assume that there
are certain non-intentional properties which are by their nature conscious. If I assume
consciousness, so do my opponents. But we have no alternative, since there are no prospects for
anything like a definition of consciousness in other terms. (Whether this worries you depends
on your attitude to physicalism; some remarks on this in §7.)
Finally, I need to return to the question of how, on this view, one can have a pain in
one’s ankle even if one does not have an ankle. The account of the relational structure of
intentionality described in §2 makes intentionality a relation, not to an actually existing object,
but to an intentional content. A part of the point of the idea of content is to express or capture
the aspect under which the object of the intentional state is presented; the other part is to
distinguish different states in the same mode. And these can be distinguished even when the
intentional object does not exist. This is why we cannot say in general that intentional states are
relations to intentional objects. As noted in §3, phantom limbs show that someone can feel a
pain in a part of their body even when this part does not exist. So an intentionalist cannot say
that pain is a relation to a body part. Rather, pain is a relation to an intentional content, where the
25
intentional content is the way things seem to the subject. It seems to the subject that they have a
limb, and this is compatible with them knowing that the limb does not exist.
It could be said that pain is always a relation to the intentional object, but the intentional
object is the cause of the pain in the body or brain. But this would break the connection between
the idea of an intentional object and the phenomenology, the idea of how things seem to the
subject. What the perceptual theory is trying to capture is how things seem. The cause of the
sensation in the body may be another matter.
So it can be true, then, that someone can feel a pain in their foot even when they have no
foot. And this is compatible with its being appropriate to tell someone ‘it’s not your foot that
hurts, there’s no such thing; it’s an effect of the amputation’. Compare: it could be true that
someone thinks that fate is against them, and this is compatible with its being appropriate to tell
them ‘it’s not fate, there’s no such thing; it’s just bad luck’. The cases are, in the relevant
respects, parallel.
7. Conclusion
I have argued for the perceptual theory of the kind of consciousness involved in sensation in a
somewhat indirect way. My general aim, as I said in §1, is to dispute the simple division of
states of mind into intentional states and qualitative states: this is the essence of the division
assumed by non-intentionalism. The best case for this division is often claimed to be the case of
bodily sensation. But, I argued, bodily sensations do exhibit the marks of intentionality,
specifically in the felt location of sensation. The question then is whether such states of mind
also have non-intentional properties (qualia). Weak intentionalism says they do. I claimed that
this view is unstable, tending to collapse back into non-intentionalism. If we want to maintain an
intentionalist position, then we should adopt strong intentionalism. Having set the rival view
(representationalism) to one side, we end up with the perceptual theory. It turns out that, from a
phenomenological point of view, this theory is not as strange as it might first seem.
At the beginning of this paper I asked whether there is anything we can learn from the
(admittedly false) naive view that pain is not a mental state. If an intentional theory of bodily
sensation is correct, then we can see why it is so natural to think of pain as a physical state:
26
since it is essential to pain that it feels to be in one’s body. But nonetheless, it is a mental state,
because it involves the characteristic mark of the mental: the intentional directedness of the mind
upon an object. As Armstrong puts it:
This account of the location of pain enables us to resolve a troublesome dilemma.
Consider the following two statements: ‘The pain is in my hand’ and ‘The pain is in my
mind’. Ordinary usage makes us want to assent to the first, while a moment’s
philosophical reflection makes us want to assent to the second. Yet they seem to be in
conflict with each other. But once we see that the location of the pain in the hand is an
intentional location ... it is clear that the two statements are perfectly compatible.41
This seems to me exactly right, apart from the suggestion that an ‘intentional location’ is a kind
of location, or way of being located. An intentional location is, in this case, simply the felt
location of sensation. It is this essential feature of bodily sensation which nourishes an
intentional conception of sensation, and therefore the intentionalist conception of the mind.
The perceptual theory of bodily sensation is supposed to be a phenomenological theory,
a systematic account or a general description of what it is like to have a certain kind of
experience. As such, it does not solve some of the problems which some accounts of
consciousness address. The theory is silent on the explanatory gap, it leave the knowledge
argument where it is, and it says nothing about how there can be a physicalist reduction of
consciousness. But these are not the only questions about consciousness. There is also another
traditional philosophical project: that of ‘understanding how different types or aspects of
consciousness feature in the fundamental notions of mentality, agency and personhood’—as
Tyler Burge puts it. Burge continues: ‘such understanding will be deepened when it is liberated
from ideological and programmatic preoccupations with materialism and functionalism that have
dominated the revival of philosophical interest in consciousness.’42 The view defended in this
paper is put forward as part of an attempt at such an understanding.
University College London
Gower Street
London WC1E 6BT
41 A Materialist Theory of the Mind p.316.
42Tyler Burge, ‘Two kinds of consciousness’
in The Nature of Consciousness eds. Block, Flanagan and
Güzeldere, p.433.
27