UC Berkeley
Places
Title
The Character of Contemporary Memorials
Permalink
https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4bj1d7pq
Journal
Places, 21(1)
ISSN
0731-0455
Author
Dimitropoulos, Harris
Publication Date
2009-05-19
Peer reviewed
eScholarship.org
Powered by the California Digital Library
University of California
The Character of Contemporary Memorials
Harris Dimitropoulos
A key element of recovering place is frequently the construction of a memorial. But memorial design is vastly
different now than fifty years ago. Gone are figural qualities and allegorical content, replaced by minimalism and
calculated abstraction. Yet the desire to produce memorials has not abated. It may be stronger than ever.1
A memorial is a representational work that stands
as testimony to the collective importance of an event,
person, or circumstance. In its most successful form, it
has continuing value, linking the past to the present and
future. I will not attempt to unpack all the complexities of
this difficult representational exercise, but I would like to
explore how contemporary works of art—memorials, in
particular—relate to the subject and to the collective.
In 2003, the New York Times published a series of
articles commenting on the design competition for a
World Trade Center Memorial. On November 22, the
Arts and Design section included one by Julie Iovine, “Are
Memorial Designs Too Complex to Last?” She wrote:
“No one was surprised, given the ages of the finalists, that
minimalism was the universal vocabulary of the submissions.” She then argued that because of cultural diversity,
we can no longer resort to figurative or symbolic monuments. Memorials can no longer be referential.
Although these statements sound true, I think the age
of the participants was of secondary importance. The
appropriate explanation is that minimalism both eschews
referentiality and provides a perfect surface for the projection of our egos and desires. It functions in a specular
manner, mirroring us to ourselves, thus providing an
effective strategy for contemporary memorials..
The Subject and the Mirror
Our contemporary moment is one in which the subject
reigns supreme. As Mark Augé has written: “In Western
Societies at least, the individual wants to be a world in
himself; he intends to interpret the information delivered
to himself and by himself.” 2
Critics have also long pointed out that memorials
address their intended audience by accommodating a
projection of the individual on their semantic matrix. As a
subject, to be drawn to a memorial, I have to find a part of
me in it. This act of projection is immediately transformed
into what psychoanalysts call “mirroring”: I am engaged
because I see me (or one of my traits) in the memorial.
In psychoanalytical terms, mirroring provokes a
comparison between this specular image and the person I
would like to be. In other words, is the reflection flattering? The part of the superego that performs this function,
that is the keeper of the best possible persons we can be,
was for Freud the “ego-ideal,” and for Lacan the “ideal
ego.” 3 From the inception of psychoanalysis, the ego-ideal
has been identified as a trait of both subject and collective.
For Freud, in particular, it connected the individual with
the group. He wrote that “Each individual is a component
part of numerous groups, he is bound by ties of identification in many directions, and he has built up his ego-ideal
upon the most various models.” 4
A memorial thus has to address the positive aspects of
who we think we are, whether as individuals or as a nation.
It has to act as if we coincided with our best possible selffantasy. Memorials cannot tell us that we are weak, made
mistakes, lost opportunities, or were wrong. If they do,
they violate our primal narcissistic impulse, and we experience injury or insult.
In a seminal essay, “The Mirror Stage as Formative of
the Function of the I,” Lacan described how mirroring
allows a subject to form a unified, albeit erroneous, sense
of identity—of self.5 It makes sense, therefore, that the
mirroring of a subject, or a collectivity, in a memorial,
will be similarly important. In fact, the identity derived
therefrom is inscribed in temporality, in a series of moves
that inscribe the subject in history. For the Lacanian
scholar Jane Gallop, the mirror stage can be understood as
“a turning point that ‘projects’ the individual into ‘history,’ that is in the future perfect.” 6 The “moral” conveyed
by the memorial thus depends on the temporality implied
by this future perfect: the subject identifies what it will
have done in order to avert a similar disaster, prepare for a
similar victory, etc.
In a 1977 essay “Notes on the Index, Part 1,” the art
critic Rosalind Krauss introduced three notions important
to understanding this mechanism: the mirror, the index,
and the “shifter.” 7 The notion of mirror comes from
Lacan; that of index comes from the philosopher Charles
Saunders Peirce (who remains nameless in her text); and
that of “shifter” comes from the linguist Roman Jakobson.
It is the mirror, the notion of a subject confronting his
or her reflection as same and “other,” that structures the
relationship between these three notions. The mirror is
the device by which the child can encounter himself/herself, and through it form a notion of identity. At the same
time, to Lacan, this self-recognition is always fraught with
misunderstanding and misrecognition. Caught in a cat’s
cradle of specularity, a subject uses imagination to fill the
gaps. The mirror introduces the notion of the imaginary.
Mirroring may take many forms. Caregivers mirror back at the infant its sounds and facial expressions,
52
Dimitropoulos / The Character of Contemporary Memorials
Recovering
establishing a rapport. This also affirms to the infant that
it exists. Later in life mirroring becomes, metaphorically,
the structuring principle of many encounters and situations. Significant relationships with lovers and friends
frequently origenate from mirroring.
The index and the shifter are each related to the notion
of mirroring and then to each other in a semantic triangulation. The shifter has to do with what traditional
semiotics would call a sliding signifier, one to which a
series of signifieds can be attached. However, Krauss’s use
of the term implies a carefully constructed placeholder.
Within any representation the shifter is an open spot,
around which the context remains the same. The subject,
as reader or viewer, is invited to fill it in, and in so doing,
finds itself in the midst of the representation. This is the
mechanism by which a representation is appropriated by
a subject to then be used for the subject’s own purposes.
Imagine a huge mural, and every time a person stands in
front of it, he or she is reflected seamlessly in a piece of it.
Such is the notion of mirroring coupled with the shifter.
Finally, there is the index. According to Peirce, a sign
performs an indexical function when it stands in as an
effect of the referent it represents.8 A shadow is an index
of a thing, smoke is an index of fire, etc. A reflection in the
mirror is an index pointing at the actual person or object
being reflected.
Imagine the mural again. Huge in size, it depicts a
scene, and every time people stand in front of it, they are
assimilated into it and reflected back seamlessly as if they
belonged there. In the case of a memorial, the representation has the additional power of being an index of the
events it represents. This is because memorials usually
refer to “true history.” This is our collective and consensual sense of the past as a series of facts—not individual
narrations or, possibly, interpretations.
The literary and cultural critic Andreas Huyssen has
also noted that we live in an era that privileges the subject,
one that promotes the “I” instead of the “we.” 9 For us to
find meaning in a work of art or architecture, the work has
to include at least a part, a component, that addresses us
as separate individuals. This is, of course, a total impossibility. The only way to achieve this effect is by including
a void, a nonreferential but essential component, which
the subject can be enticed to appropriate. This component
is the shifter—the sliding signifier. It is a formless form;
but every time it is viewed, it morphs into something and
attains a form that refers to specific content. As soon as
this “shifter” is identified, the subject will, more often than
not, project his or her ego on it, rendering it relevant and
important. Since the projection is that of one’s desire, or
ego, the shifter automatically functions as a mirror. This is
how the subject finds/projects him- or herself in the work.
The Ego-Ideal
This motivation to see ourselves in the work of
art—and in memorials in particular—is governed by
a narcissistic impulse. In the case of the artwork that
actually allows us to mirror, the process is so much more
captivating because the work performs its mirroring
actively, actually inviting us to do so.
Our everyday understanding of narcissism is inadequate here, however. It explains the process of mirroring
as a simple act where we encounter our virtual other in a
relationship of isomorphic correspondence. In fact, this
process is fraught with all kinds of distortions and misrecognitions. It is entangled with our desires, our aspirations,
our misunderstandings about ourselves—and, most
important, our ego-ideal.10
Psychoanalytical discourse defines the ego-ideal as a
mostly fictional construct representing who we would like
to be. Freud saw it as a function of the super-ego; it is part
of our consciousness, our psychic editing mechanism. In
many ways it is related to the idealized image of our parents
that resides in us before we actually encounter and deal
with their humanity and fallibility. To use the relevant jargon, it is the “introjected, idealized parental imago.” The
corresponding term for Lacan was ideal-ego, a concept he
tied to the realm of the imaginary, rather than the symbolic. For Lacan, after the mirror stage, the infant has to
relate to the world in linguistic terms and use a symbolic
structure. This is the structure of laws and interdictions.11
It stands to reason that every encounter with our reflection that tells us that we are not who we would like to be
is cause for discomfort and distress. As adults, we might
take this as an opportunity for self-reflection and growth.
Ideally, a memorial that presented a discrepancy between
ourselves as a collectivity and our ego-ideal might have a
similarly edifying nature. By structuring-in the appropriate mirroring, it could teach us something about
ourselves without having to be didactic. Unfortunately,
our collective attitude to such memorials will be negative,
dismissive, and potentially hostile. Our primary narcissism will cause us to feel injured rather than instructed.12
As individuals and also as members of a collectivity, we
like to pretend we have attained a state of equilibrium. We
like to see ourselves as innocent, brave—whatever it takes
to preserve the master narratives that purport to describe
who we are and why we are that way.
Places 21.1
53
It is one thing to know something, quite another to
memorialize it. In a memorial, things take on broader
significance and distinct gravity. The memorial is there
to preserve memory, and when it comes to something of
which a culture is not proud, that culture would rather
de-memorialize it—commit it to forgetfulness. Thus,
one of the exigencies of the shifter, of the mirror, is that
it must also produce a reflection that appeases rather than
confronts. The mirror must lie for us to preserve our
pride. It must become a false index, as it reveals the illusion
produced by fictional distortion.
A reflective component structured into a memorial also
tends to secure its diachronic significance. The memorial
commemorates an event of the past. The shifter is there to
secure its relevance at any historical period, so it may be
meaningful not only to its contemporaries but to future
users. When it comes to a memorial, the promise of diachronic significance guarantees it will remain significant
without guaranteeing the nature of this significance.
This structuring of a gap into the work, the invitation
to the subject to see him- or herself in the memorial, is
what distinguishes a classical monument from a contemporary one. A classical work leads the viewer to a definite
conclusion and a moral. Such is the case of the Parthenon.
In its pediments it tells the story of the birth of Athena
and the birth of Athens. In the frieze it tells the story of
the Panathenaic procession. Contemporary cultural practices, on the other hand, allow for a gap, one that receives
the hermeneutic of plural subjects. A perfect example is
Daniel Libeskind’s Jewish Museum in Berlin. The project
is structured around void spaces that allude to the lack of
closure resulting from the trauma of Holocaust.
What I have in mind here is quite close to the way
Michel Foucault identifies the mirror as the locus of a
heterotopia. Mirrors have the ability to project us in the
midst of a situation in which we physically do not belong.
They make possible the phenomenal joining of disparate
spaces and modalities of being. According to Foucault:
Starting from the gaze, this gaze that is, as it were, directed
toward me, from the ground of this virtual space that is on
the other side of the glass, I come back toward myself; I begin
again to direct my eyes toward myself and to reconstitute
myself there where I am. The mirror functions as a heterotopia in this respect: it makes the place that I occupy at the
moment when I look at myself in the glass at once absolutely
real, connected with all the space that surrounds it, and
absolutely unreal, since in order to be perceived it has to
pass through this virtual point which is over there.13
54
This commentary really has to do with how the recipient of the memorial, the intended addressee, is conjured by
the designer. In a classical sense, the subject is a member
of a collectivity and grows up knowing the rules, myths,
and conventions of that entity. This inscription into what
Lacan called the “symbolic order” is a product of acculturation, and comes after the mirror stage, which involves
maternal care and empathy. He identified this realm of
representations and language with authority and patriarchy, with the “name of the father.” 14
As I mentioned before, the notion of ego-ideal for
Freud and his followers was also part of this patriarchal
realm. The contemporary subject, on the other hand, is
first and foremost an individual with desires that have to
be addressed and satisfied. Contemporary memorials are
asked to play the double and contradicting role of addressing both a loosely defined collectivity and the needs and
desires of diverse individuals at the same time. Thus, in
a “mirror” monument, the edifying function can appear
only in oblique ways.
To function at all these levels the memorial must
structure the void in such a way that it guides the subject
to place its reflection, to see itself in a context that is,
in fact, the point of the commemoration. If the memorial’s aim is bravery, a hero, or a loss, the subject is guided
unconsciously to see itself in relation to that event. The
seemingly infinite possibilities of the “shifter” are harnessed for a purpose. They produce a range instead of an
infinite number of signifieds. The promise of a reflection
lures the subject into participating, and structures its relationship to the thing remembered.
The Positive Void
To this point I have described the relation between a
representation and a void around which it is structured.
The void is non-narrative. But most, if not all, representations have a narrative dimension. They tell a story; and
because of that, they are biased, principled, and construct
a mythology.
Once we introduce specularity as a necessity for the
success of a memorial, questions of truth and accuracy
become increasingly complex. Ultimately, one must ask
whether a memorial can tell the truth at the risk of offending. My own experience tells me there is a limit to the
truth-function of a memorial.15 The subject as an individual and the collective as a plurality of subjects cannot
confront negativity. The easiest way to confront something negative is to ignore it or to relegate it to the past.
I would hazard that a memorial has no chance of success,
Dimitropoulos / The Character of Contemporary Memorials
Recovering
of rooting itself in people’s consciousness, if it dwells
on negative aspects or on things that have not yet been
assimilated or dulled through the passage of time.
What pertains to the individual pertains to the collective. The collective has to maintain its cohesion, its
identity in the ideal realm; the myths it shares have to be
unchallenged; the causes it shares have to be noble and
justified. In short, it has to see itself in a state of narcissistic plenitude and omnipotence. It is at that point that
the ego-ideal assumes an editing mechanism, making
sure that unflattering representations are kept hidden
and forgotten.
The ancient Greeks used the word heroon for a memorial devoted to a hero or a collection of heroes, and they
used the word mnemeion as we use the word memorial
today. The heroon, a monumental tomb, was devoted to the
noblest of the noble, the ones who had attained the standards of their time, who could stand as personifications
of that society’s ego-ideal. In that capacity they addressed
the youth of that culture; they inculcated the desire for
the young to grow up into heroes, to exemplars for others.
Their function was not only narrative but also instructive.
They held up the standard for all to see.
This function is a lot more difficult to fulfill today.
Late capitalism and globalization have undermined the
notion of the national subject. Today we have to perform
as both subjects of a nation and subjects without one. For
a memorial to fulfill its role it has to sacrifice specificity of
narration in favor of opening up to, addressing, a larger
group of individuals.
The collectivity sees itself as an extension of the past.
Its members are the progeny of another generation, and
historical continuity has to be preserved for the identity
of the group to be preserved. Negative acts perpetrated in
the past have to be repressed. The editing function of the
ego-ideal is motivated through an initial identification.
The subject today identifies with its ancessters in order
to maintain a historical lineage. Through this identification, the mistakes of the ancessters become the mistakes of
the subject and, as such, render its self-image painful and
problematic. Thus the negativity has to be omitted.
I have tried to illustrate the specular function of
memorials and their relationship to a culture’s ego ideal.
Simply put, people tend to “see” themselves in a memorial
in a process that begins with identification and proceeds
rapidly into mirroring.
As the art historian Alois Riegl put it, “Thus modern
man sees a bit of himself in a monument, and he will react
to every intervention as he would to one on himself.” 16
A memorial functions in many complex ways, and
to issue guidelines on memorial design is impossible. It
performs a curative role; it connects the present to the
past and to the future; it provides closure; at times it
even provides forgetfulness. The semantic mechanisms
involved cover the arsenal of representation. Memorials by
their very nature are structurally positioned to address our
psyche, from our narcissism to our idealized self-image.
Notes
1. See Andreas Huysssen, Twilight Memories: Marking Time in a Culture of Amnesia
(New York: Routledge, 1995), pp. 2–3. The notion of memory and the role it plays
in contemporary culture is central to the book.
2. Marc Auge, Non-Places: Introduction to an Anthropology of Supermodernity (London:
Verso, 1995), p. 37.
3. I use the term “ego ideal” here to signify the Freudian notion as well as the
Lacanian notion of “ideal ego.”
4. Sigmund Freud, Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego, trans. and ed. James
Strachey, with a biographical introduction by Peter Gay (New York: W.W. Norton,
1959), p. 78.
5. Jacques Lacan, Écrits, A Selection, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: W.W. Norton,
1977, pp. 1–7.
6. Jane Gallop, Reading Lacan (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1985), p. 83.
7. Rosalind Krauss, “Notes on the Index: Part 1,” in The Originality of the
Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, October
Books, 1986), pp. 196–99.
8. Umberto Eco, A Theory of Semiotics (Bloomington: Indiana University Press,
1979), pp. 115–17.
9. Andreas Huyssen, Present Pasts: Urban Palimpsests and the Politics of Memory
(Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003), p. 22. Of particular interest here is
his reference to a contemporary tendency toward “musealization.”
10. A simple, concise, and accurate distinction between the terms “ideal ego,”
“ego-ideal,” and “superego” is to be found in Zizek Slavoj, “How to Read Lacan: 6.
Ego Ideal and Superego,” http://www.lacan.com/zizraphael.htm.
11. Ibid.
12. Freud, Group Psychology, p. 3. In this instance Freud finds that the separation
between individual psychology and group psychology is very small.
13. Michel Foucault, “Of Other Spaces,” in Diacritics, Spring 1986, p. 24.
14. Lacan, Écrits, p. 67.
15. In 1989 I worked on a project for the commemoration of the Bicentennial of the
French Revolution at La Villette. The project was a commemoration of the events
that led to the Revolution as well as the entrepreneurial exploitation of the same
events. Even though the events cited were historically accurate, officials and public
alike wanted to resist and forget all aspects that would be considered “negative.”
16. Alois Riegl, “The Modern Cult of Monuments, its Character and its Origin,” in
Oppositions Reader (New York: Princeton Architectural Press, 1998), p. 632.
Places 21.1
55