short research article
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
approval date 01 09 2014
UDK BROJEVI: 72.01:111.852 72.071.1:929 Ајзенман П.
COBISS.SR-ID 213406988
PETER EISENMAN, OR HOW TO
ELIMINATE WHAT ONE BECOMES
A B S T R A C T
Peter Eisenman is the Icarus of post-avant-garde architecture
and has numerous highly regarded, controversial built structures
to his name – such as the Memorial to the Murdered Jews of
Europe in Berlin and the Ciudad de la Cultura de Galicia in
Santiago de Compostela. How to eliminate what one becomes –
this is one way of summarizing one of the most decisive features
of Eisenman’s architectural praxis: the disappearance of the
author. Displaying his disdain for individual style in the arts,
Eisenman regularly threw Michel Foucault’s question “what is
an author?” into debates on architecture. However, the death
of the author – “la mort de l’auteur”1 first proposed by Roland
Barthes – was not an end in itself for Eisenman. For it is only the
follow-up question “what is critique?“2 that illuminates the role
of the elimination of the author in the negativity aesthetics of
Eisenman’s architectural praxis: it is the dialectics of the critique
of reason and epistemology. In that sense, Eisenman’s theory of
architecture constitutes an important – if not uncontroversial –
contribution to critical architectural philosophy.
228
Jörg H. Gleiter
Key words
Institute of Architecture, TU Berlin
peter eisenman
philosophy of architecture
critical theory
authorship
deconstruction
design
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
No-one has more ruthlessly opposed the cult of the author’s name and the
belief in individual styles as Eisenman; yet, at the same time, he has sought
in countless publications to establish the very identity whose demise he had
previously encouraged with his freely fluctuating significants. “Why Peter
Eisenman Writes Such Good Books”3 was Jacques Derrida’s title for his
enquiry into the author without handwriting, the stylist without a style. It was
not by chance that Derrida made a connection between Eisenman and another
author who claimed to have a “twofold provenance, as it were from the top and
bottom rungs on the ladder of life, both décadent and beginning.”4 That author
was Friedrich Nietzsche, who ended his game of identity and difference with a
willful, intellectual short circuit. He preceded his autobiographical book Ecce
Homo with the words “How to become What You Are.” At around the same
time, during his last autumn, Nietzsche also claimed to have twice attended his
own funeral “as lightly clad as possible.”5 One funeral was that of the Italian
General di Robilant, the other was that of the architect Alessandro Antonelli,
who had designed the most audacious building in Italy at the time, the Mole
Antonelliana, and, as such, served as an alter ego for Nietzsche.
“The End of the Classical: The End of the Beginning, the End of the End”6 is
the title of one of the various texts in which Eisenman shows that he was not
only always willing to embark on escalation and excess, but just as willing to
use Nietzschean double negatives: “I’m not interested in beauty. I’m interested
in terror,”7 as he once put it in the fashion magazine, Vanity Fair, in the days
when terror was still acceptable as an aesthetic principle.
Eisenman’s paradigmatic elimination of the author is established in a number of
dwelling houses he designed in the 1970s and 1980s which—with their radical
conceptualism and immense aesthetic impact—aroused keen interest amongst
architects, which even the classicists were barely able to conceal behind their
public outrage. Despite their relatively modest dimensions, it is impossible not
to now see Eisenman’s residential house designs as icons of post-avant-garde
architecture, starting with House I (1967–68) and continuing by way of House
11a (1978) right through to the Guardiola House (1988)—with pride of place
going to House VI (1975).
These houses owe their appearance to quasi-automatic, formal design
processes. Without exception, all these houses basically stem from the same,
only marginally varied cuboid form, which is subjected to the simplest formal
strategies of decomposition, that is to say, sections, divisions, subtractions and
Jörg H. Gleiter _ Peter Eisenman, or how to eliminate what one becomes
AMOR INTELLECTUALIS DIABOLI
229
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
other modes of transformation. It must have come as a shock to many that the
demise of the author in architecture also meant that nothing could be taken for
granted any longer. And with the onset of serialization and processualization,
architecture appeared to have succumbed to a soulless automatism. These
designs were accompanied not only by pages of tedious protocols,8 but also by
seemingly endless sequences of diagrams that were solely intended to prove
the logical rigor of the processes whereby the architectural design—untainted
by individual sensibilities—was exclusively beholden to its own syntax, that is
to say, a grammar of signs and, hence, pure textuality.
However, it would be to misconstrue Eisenman’s intentions if the disappearance
of the author were to be understood merely as an ironic, intellectual game
between author and work or as a superficial flirtation with travesty or
camouflage. On the contrary, the disappearance of the author is one of the
main cornerstones of Eisenman’s specific dialectics of critique of reason and
epistemology, or in other words, of Eisenman’s amor intellectualis diaboli.
According to Theodor W. Adorno and Max Horkheimer this includes “the
joy of defeating civilization with its own weapons.”9 It is only his critique of
reason and his praxis of epistemology that localize Eisenman in the cultural
history of the twentieth century, equidistant from the Modernist avant-garde,
Postmodernism, and Deconstructivism, but above all Jacques Derrida’s
aesthetics of supplementarity. Eisenman’s experimental aesthetics are neither
a utopian-avant-garde triumph over dominant reason, nor are they—in a
Poststructuralist sense—a subversive degradation of reason: they are “an
instance of a critique of reason founded in experience.”10
CRITIQUE AND ECSTASY
230
Eisenman’s freemasonry of intelligence first culminated in his “Notes on
Conceptual Architecture” of 1970. These consist of four pages with no text as
such but just fifteen footnotes. With characteristic intellectual vigor Eisenman
has reduced his authorship to a set of references to newspaper articles and
books on the subject of aesthetic minimalism and conceptual art. However, the
very attempt to do away with the irrationalism that is inherent in all authorship
and the concomitant close ties between a work and its author, turned—due
to the pure indexicality of the signs—into a new hermeticism. By choosing
not to make any form of aesthetic impact, it seemed that right at the outset
of his career Eisenman might be maneuvering himself into the cul-de-sac of
autonomous conceptual art. The enacted nihilism of the “Notes on Conceptual
Architecture” revealed all too clearly Eisenman’s idealistic longings; an
aesthetic fundamentalism shone through in the terror of theory.
From the outset—and not entirely incomprehensibly—Eisenman’s
intellectualism was met with a deep-seated mistrust. This was mainly
directed at Eisenman’s determination to reduce the design process to a pure
logic of relations. Some critics saw this as an acceleration of the processes
of objectification and reification in the spirit of a positivist-mechanistic
concept of Modernism, whereas others believed that Eisenman’s formalized
desemanticization and syntacticization were still imbued with hidden residues
of iconography and inadvertent semantics. However, both groups, who were
either in thrall to the categorizations of a Neo-Marxist critique of Modernism
or to the critics who had signed up to the Postmodern linguistic turn, may be
countered with the fact that—paradoxically but logically enough—precisely
where Eisenman favors a syntactic-formal rather than a semantic-expressive
approach, his own amor intellectualis diaboli comes to light less in his
intellectualism than in the ecstatic aspects of his work.
Specifically, this is about the moment when Eisenman’s design process
turns from linear, rigorously logical procedures toward the labyrinthine and
figurative-grotesque. With their linearistic process of evolution Eisenman’s
series of dwelling houses embody the real watershed in his work. The basis
of this is the performative, linear design process wherein every step arises
logically from the previous step but also questions that previous step and is
negated as a normative force by every subsequent step. In terms of the logic
of its specific evolution, each step is simultaneously a source of constructive
affirmation and a source of critical negation. By excluding any subjective
influence of his own, Eisenman takes this process to an extreme, to the point
where each subsequent step leads to the collapse of the established order, where
reason has escalated to its own limits and switches into self-negation, and
linearity and processuality mutate into a synoptic simultaneity of forms, that
is to say, into an indecipherable concentration of intersecting and interlinking
lines, planes, and volumes. At the point of excess the processuality that had
been following a rigorous, abstract logic suddenly turns into a Babylonianlabyrinthine confusion of forms.
It is therefore evident that, unlike architectural Deconstructivism, Eisenman’s
architectural praxis is about taking rationalism to its own extremes and not,
on the face of things, about subverting it. At its highpoint, the terror of theory
finds itself transformed into the unfathomably grotesque and labyrinthine,
such that the clarity of linear, steadily advancing processuality switches into
a bewildering simultaneity of forms, and heightened intellectualism turns into
physiological psychology.
Jörg H. Gleiter _ Peter Eisenman, or how to eliminate what one becomes
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
231
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
EXCESSIVE RATIONALITY
Eisenman, as a proponent of the death of the author, only partially takes up
Barthes’ suggested transformation of the modern author into a Postmodern
scriptor, that is to say, that architecture as composition should become
architecture as text. In fact Eisenman’s architectural theory, with its negativityaesthetics, is peculiarly at odds with Poststructuralist aesthetics. In open
opposition to Derrida’s aesthetics of supplementarity, which is posited on free,
associative ideas that subversively undermine the system, Eisenman loves
systems and consequences. For his technique of the ecstasy of rationality
does not stop at the transition from individual composition to self-writing
textuality. Eisenman is certainly not one of Foucault’s founders of discursivity.
In contrast to Derrida’s free associations, which seem to be in keeping with
an ideal of human creativity, Eisenman rates the impartiality of the intellect
higher than intuition and he intensifies the intellectualistic, scientistic principle
to the point of annihilation. That is to say, he drives logical process forward to
the point where strictly logical seriality tips over into labyrinthine-grotesque,
spatial figures. As the system collapses, the conceptual becomes figurative and
figurative-labyrinthine structures turn into psychologism.
It is precisely at this juncture that Eisenman’s notion of the end of the author
also marks the end of the hermeneutic phantom and, consequently, the end of
the work as intentional material imbued with a symbolic charge by the author.
The work is no longer an expression or a likeness of the ideality invested in the
material, but is solely determined by the supra-personal process of writing as a
performative act, during the course of which architecture turns into textuality
and textuality becomes “grotext.”
232
By engaging with the notion of the grotesque, Eisenman has tapped conceptually
into one of the most intriguing forms of aesthetic articulation. Following the
discovery of the domus aurea in Rome in the late fifteenth century, the grotesque
wall paintings found there were admired not for their specific expressivity,
but for their depictions of “monstrosities . . . botched together from a variety
of limbs,”11 which are not likenesses in the usual sense, nor identifiable as
anything else. They can be described as instances of varietá e stravaganza or
of terribilitá e capriccio, that is to say, variety and extravagance or awfulness
and caprice. Giorgio Vasari described them as “a kind of free and humorous
picture.”12 Grotesqueries may also be unconstrained in their libertinaggio,
which could be translated here as salaciousness, and as such have roots in
repressed human drives, that is to say, in our psychological make-up. This lack
of constraint is less evident in the sheer force of their images, which breaks
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
The enthusiasm for grotesqueries during the High Renaissance can be
explained by the structural changes that were under way in aesthetics. In face
of the rationalization of cultural life, repressed drives bubble in a Freudian
manner to the surface in the free figurations of grotesqueries. As opposed
to Derrida’s Deconstructivism, it is here that the basis of the negativityaesthetics of Eisenman’s architectural praxis looms into view. In Modernity
aesthetic praxis is specifically not a subversion of rationalism, but an ecstatic
transgression. Its aim is not destruction, but cognition. And it is here, in the
shape of the grotesque, that Eisenman’s epistemological approach culminates
in the aesthetic duality of a critique of reason and epistemology.
On the fringes of rationalism, as it were at the tipping point into the grotesque,
it may be said that, for Eisenman, his own radically liberating critique of
reason is only possible through his logical pursuit of reason. And this is at the
heart of the affinity of Eisenman’s thinking with Adorno’s aesthetic theory.
For, in Adorno’s view, “modern art is questionable not when it goes too far . .
. but when it does not go far enough.”13 Aesthetic praxis in modern art is only
ever productive when it goes to extremes, not when it merely communicates.
“L’eccesso è sempre portatore di conoscenze”14 —Excess is the vehicle of
cognition: with this insight, Manfredo Tafuri summed up the epistemologically
critical components in Eisenman’s apocalyptic-labyrinthine design processes.
THE UNCANNY AND THE EXALTED
Surely no other contemporary architect has taken a more radical approach to
the myth. For what does the elimination of the author mean if not a reversal
of the classical creator, the demiurge, who—as the archetypal image of an
architect—deploys his almost superhuman will and strength to form the world
from out of primal chaos by separating reason, ethics, and aesthetics from his
Dionysian drives and impulses? But Eisenman’s performativity, as a negative
myth, culminates in the reverse procedure. And this leads to an architecture
that, as a concrete, clearly identifiable object, enters into the realms of the
labyrinthine and grotesque. And this makes it possible to define the aspect that
is crucial to Eisenman’s critical architectural praxis. It consists in the fact that
he not only radicalizes the cognitive processes inherited from Modernism by
taking them to extremes but, in his pursuit of excess, he pushes the rationalism
that is inherent in Modernism beyond its own limits and, at the point where
Jörg H. Gleiter _ Peter Eisenman, or how to eliminate what one becomes
all the formal laws of painting, than in the way that repressed human nature
resurfaces, with all its impulsive vigor.
233
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
its tips into the labyrinthine-grotesque and figurative, drives it back to a point
before its own fixed, rational beginnings. Eisenman’s rational processes are
diabolical, almost apocalyptic, insofar as through them enlightened reason
arrives, in a Nietzschean manner, at a “fundamental sense of the uncanny and
exalted,”15 which in turn sees intellectualism switching into a psychologicalphysiological mode.
In any attempt to locate Eisenman in the architectural history of the twentieth
century, it is essential to recognize that, with his diagrammatic, ultimately
ecstatic design processes, he did away with the dualism of intellectual and
sensory cognition, that legacy of Enlightenment aesthetics that still held sway
over Modernism. At the ecstatic tipping point, sensory experience is placed
after, not before rational processes: it is the result of these processes. Eisenman
thus dissolves the dialectics of senses and reason, which Alexander Gottlieb
Baumgarten first set out in his Aesthetica of 1750. Presenting aesthetics as the
“science of improving sensible cognition,” Baumgarten sought to put sensory
perception on a par with cognitive sciences. Baumgarten described sensory
perception as analogon rationis. In Heinz Paetzold’s view this meant that
the “world- and ego-related modes of experience” that are possible through
the senses now had a rationalism of their own, which corresponded to the
“discursive rationale of ‘pure’ thinking in concepts.”16
234
But Eisenman dismantled the parallelism of senses and reason inherited from
Baumgarten. In ornamental, labyrinthine-grotesqueries, the Dionysian is no
longer pitted against the Apollonian, nor is cognitive comprehension pitted
against sensory experience any more, for, by dint of the processes he developed,
one thing arises from the last and always relates in a critically-reflective manner
to its own origens. Sensory experience thus no longer comes about without
critical reference to the rational processuality that preceded it. With criticalperformative reservations, we could say, as Nelson Goodman has put it, that
“in aesthetic experience the emotions function cognitively”17 in that the former
have already informed the latter. While there have hitherto been reasons to see
art as a counterpart to the technological universe, since Eisenman’s critical
performativity there are now good reasons to not separate the two any longer.
With his automated, ecstatic processuality, Eisenman has done away with the
parallelism of senses and reason that had lingered on since the Enlightenment.
As though performing a double negation, Eisenman has set out “to reverse
through.”18 Here on the margins of reason and in an excess of rationality,
architecture becomes a “vehicle for critical awareness.” All at once Eisenman’s
critique of reason turns into a praxis of epistemology.
Jörg H. Gleiter _ Peter Eisenman, or how to eliminate what one becomes
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
NOTES
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
On this, see Roland Barthes, “La Mort de L’Auteur,” in Essais Critiques IV, Le Bruissement de la
Langue (Paris: 1984), 61–67.
Michel Foucault, “Qu’est-ce que la critique?,” lecture delivered to the Société française de
Philosophie in May 1978; “What is Critique?” trans. Lysa Hochroth, in The Politics of Truth, ed.
Sylvère Lotringer (New York: 1997).
Translated from the German by Fiona Elliott Jacques Derrida, “Why Peter Eisenman Writes Such
Good Books,” A+U (1988):2.
Friedrich Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, trans. Duncan Large (Oxford :2009), 7.
Letter of 6 January 1889 to Jacob Burckhardt in Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche, ed. and
trans. Christopher Middleton (Chicago: 1969), 347.
Peter Eisenman, “The End of the Classical: The End of the Beginning, the End of the End,”
Perpsecta 21 (1984): 154–73.
Peter Eisenman in an interview in Vanity Fair, 1/1991.
On this, see Peter Eisenman, “Transformations, Decompositions, and Critiques: House X,” A+U,
80:01, 25–151.
Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments,
trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford University Press, 2007), 74.
235
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
236
Trans. from Christoph Menke, Die Souveränität der Kunst (Frankfurt am Main: 1991), 10.
Michel de Montaigne, On Friendship, trans. M. A. Screech (London: 2004), 1.
“una spezie di pittura licenziose e ridicole molto”: Giorgio Vasari, Le Vite de’ piú eccellenti pittori
scultori architetti italiani, Introduction, chapter 27: “Come si lavorino le grottesche su lo stucco,”
trans. by Louisa S. Maclehose, in Vasari on Technique (London: 1907), 245.
Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, ed. Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedeman, trans. Robert HullotKentor (London and New York: 1997), 47.
Manfredo Tafuri, “Les Bijoux indiscrets,” in Five architects N.Y., ed. Manfredo Tafuri (Naples:
1981), 10.
Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: 1986),
Aphorism 218, p. 178.
Heinz Paetzold, “Rhetorik-Kritik und Theorie der Künste in der philosophischen Ästhetik von
Baumgarten bis Kant,” in Kritische Theorie des Ornaments, ed. Gérard Raulet and Burghart
Schmidt (Vienna et al., 1993), 30.
Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art. An Approach to a Theory of Symbols (Indianapolis and
Cambridge: 1976), 248.
Friedrich Nietzsche, Nachgelassene Fragmente Frühjahr – Sommer 1888, KSA 13, 16[32], 492;
Available online in English in Nietszche’s Last Notebooks, trans. by Daniel Fidel Ferrer, p. 169, at
http://books.google.co.uk/books?id=8aANUbCezaEC&pg=PA266&lpg=PA266&dq=Nietzsche+
Fragments+1888&source=bl&ots=SsbVASILQ5&sig=3dS28BFiGZ0feVFoT8XurOMbfoU&hl=
en&sa=X&ei=2KwpU4v2Co6jhgf_54G4Bw&ved=0CFUQ6AEwBg#v=snippet&q=experiment
al%20philosophy&f=false
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Barthes, Roland. “La Mort de L’Auteur.” in Essais Critiques IV, Le Bruissement de la Langue.
Paris: 1984.
Foucault, Michel. “What is Critique?” In The Politics of Truth, edited by Sylvère Lotringer,
translated by trans. Lysa Hochroth, New York: 1997.
Derrida, Jacques. “Why Peter Eisenman Writes Such Good Books.” A+U (1988): 2.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Ecce Homo. Translated by Duncan Large. Oxford: 2009.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Selected Letters of Friedrich Nietzsche. Edited and translated by
Christopher Middleton. Chicago: 1969.
Eisenman, Peter. “The End of the Classical: The End of the Beginning, the End of the End.”
Perspecta 21 (1984).
Eisenman, Peter. “Transformations, Decompositions, and Critiques: House X.” A+U, 80:01
Horkheimer, Max and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical
Fragments. Translated by Edmund Jephcott. Stanford University Press: 2007.
Menke, Christoph. Die Souveränität der Kunst. Frankfurt am Main: 1991.
Montaigne, Michel de. On Friendship. Translated by M. A. Screech. London: 2004.
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
Jörg H. Gleiter _ Peter Eisenman, or how to eliminate what one becomes
Vasari, Giorgio. Le Vite de’ piú eccellenti pittori scultori architetti italiani, Introduction, chapter
27: “Come si lavorino le grottesche su lo stucco.” Translated by Louisa S. Maclehose, 245, in
Vasari on Technique. London: 1907.
Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory. Edited by Gretel Adorno and Rolf Tiedeman, translated
by Robert Hullot-Kentor. London and New York: 1997.
Tafuri, Manfredo. “Les Bijoux indiscrets.” In Five architects N.Y., edited by Manfredo Tafuri.
Naples: 1981.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Translated by R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: 1986.
Paetzold, Heinz. “Rhetorik-Kritik und Theorie der Künste in der philosophischen Ästhetik von
Baumgarten bis Kant.” In Kritische Theorie des Ornaments. Edited by Gérard Raulet and
Burghart Schmidt. Vienna et al., 1993.
Goodman, Nelson. Languages of Art. An Approach to a Theory of Symbols. Indianapolis and
Cambridge: 1976.
237
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
PITER AJZENMAN,
Ž
ILI KAKO ELIMINISATI ONO ŠTO COVEK
POSTANE
Jörg H. Gleiter
Piter Ajzenman je Ikar post-avangardne arhitekture koji se može pohvaliti brojnim visoko cenjenim,
kontroverznim objektima – kao što su Spomenik ubijenim Jevrejima Evrope u Berlinu i Ciudad
de la Cultura de Galicia u Santijagu de Kompostela. Kako eliminisati ono što čovek postane-ovo
je jedan od načina da se rezimira jedna od presudnih odlika Ajzenmanove arhitektonske prakse:
nestanak autora. Pokazujući svoj prezir prema individualnom stilu u umetnosti, Ajzenman je u
debatama o arhitekturi redovno potezao pitanje Mišela Fukoa: ,,Šta je pisac?” Međutim, smrt
autora – ,,la mort de l’auteur” koju je prvi put pomenuo Roland Bart – nije bila sama sebi svrha
po Ajzenmanu. Zato što jedino pitanje koje sledi:,,Šta je kritika?”, osvetljava ulogu eliminacije
autora u negativnosti estetike Ajzenmanove arhitektonske prakse: to je dijalektika kritike razuma
i epistemologije. U tom smislu, Ajzenmanova teorija arhitekture predstavlja važan-ako ne
nekontroverzan-doprinos kritičkoj filozofiji arhitekture.
ključne reči: piter ajzenman, filozofija arhitekture, kritička teorija, autorstvo,
deKonstruKcija, projeKtovanje
OPERATIVNE RAZLIKE.
AJZENMAN, TAFURI I LEKCIJA PIRANEZIJA
Gabriele Mastrigli, Alessandro Toti
Piter Ajzenman je arhitekta. Iako povezana sa interesovanjem za razne oblike, oblast njegovog
delovanja obuhvata istraživanje teorijskog osnova arhitektonske discipline. Arhitektura, kao
artefakt i kao projekat, može da se posmatra kao najočiglednija reprezentacija tradicionalne
opozicije zapadne metafizike: odsustva i prisustva. Stoga je zadatak arhitekte, prema Ajzenmanu,
da analitički interveniše u ovom dijalektičkom stanju i učini ga operativnim.
Sa ove tačke gledišta, Ajzenmanov pristup disciplini – kao i čitav njegov, celoživotni arhitektonski
razvojni put – posmatra se u svetlu dela Đovanija Batiste Piranezija. Otišavši dalje od kritike
italijanskog istoričara arhitekture Manfreda Tafurija, Ajzenman je istraživao mogućnost novog
tumačenja dijalektike između pozitivnog i negativnog, izbravši pojam zemljišta kao samog mesta
ove opozicije. Berlinski Spomenik ubijenim Jevrejima Evrope nudi konačnu reprezentaciju ove
dijalektike, čime otvara mogućnost daljeg, neuporedivog rada na njoj.
ključne reči: arhiteKtura, razliKe, analiza, projeKat, dijaleKtiKa, reprezentacija, jeziK,
montaža, trag, zemljište, subjekt.
S A J _ 2014 _ 6 _
DIGITALNO:
OD KOMPLEKSNOSTI DO JEDNOSTAVNOSTI – I NATRAG
Mario Carpo
Na početku digitalnog prevrata u ranim 90-tim godinama, digitalno inteligentna arhitektura je
uopšteno smatrana krivolinijskom, oblom i modernom. Zašto? Računari su izuzetno svestrane
mašine, ali koje ne pokazuju estetičke preferencije. Svakako da Piter Ajzenman, koji je jedan
od izumitelja digitalizovanog pravca i 90-tim, nije imao ovo na umu. I zašto se danas stil/pravac
digitalno inteligentne arhitekture ponovo menja?
Ovo su (neka od) pitanja koja su obrađena u ovom kratkom radu koji ispituje zašto i kako digitalno
kao alat uključuje, ovladava i proizvodi kompleksnost.
ključne reči: digitalno, splajnovi
/ Krive, alat, KompleKsnost, ajzenman
ŠTA JE ARHITEKTONSKO ISTRAŽIVANJE DANAS
I GDE JE OSNOV?
Djordje Stojanović
Zašto graditi velike objekte od gumica sa studentima arhitekture? Na koji način je taj poduhvat
povezan sa arhitektonskim obrazovanjem? I ako objekti od gumica nisu ni zgrade, ni modeli, već
neka vrsta eksperimenata, kakvu vrstu znanja relevantnog za građevinsku industriju i izgrađeno
okruženje oni generišu? Ovo su neka od pitanja koja su postavljena na konferenciji “ISSUES?
Concerning the projects of Peter Eisenman” /PITANJA? U vezi sa projektima Pitera Ajzenmana/
koja je održana u Beogradu, u novembru 2013. Ona su povezana sa nizom projektantskih
istraživačkih projekata koji su nedavno završeni na Arhitektonskom fakultetu, Univerziteta u
Beogradu, i koji su dokumentovani u tematskom izdanju Srpskog arhitektnoskog žurnala pod
naslovom ,,Arhitektonsko obrazovanje u postdigitalnom dobu’’ koje je objavljeno nezavisno
od, ali skoro istovremeno sa održavanjem konferencije. U skladu sa argumentima iznetim u
toj publikaciji, ovaj rad će prikazati neke od relevantnih i opšteprihvaćenih teorija i manifesta
koji se odnose na metodologije projektantskog istraživanja, pružajući osnov za tekući rad na
Arhitektonskom fakultetu, Univerziteta u Beogradu.
ključne reči: arhitektonsko istraživanje, umetničko istraživanje, istraživanje kroz projekat,
istraživanje zasnovano na praksi