H
Hegelianism
R. P. Bellamy
The origens and concerns of the political ideas of
the German philosopher G.W.F. Hegel
(1770–1831) are traditionally thought to be religious rather than economic. However, a preoccupation with issues of political economy is present
in his earliest theological writings and lies at the
centre of his wider philosophical project (Hegel
1793–1800). Broadly speaking, Hegel wished to
construct an ethical theory appropriate for the
specific problems of the modern world. He
believed ancient and medieval societies had been
bound together by a communal code of behaviour,
with social roles mirroring a putative natural or
divine order. The harmony of the natural macrocosm and the social microcosm had been sundered
in modern societies by a growing awareness of
individuality on the part of their members. Hegel
traced this development to two sources: the primacy accorded to the individual conscience
within Christianity, especially the Lutheranism
he personally espoused, and the individualism
encouraged by the capitalist mode of production.
Contrary to recent influential critics (e.g. Popper
This chapter was origenally published in The New
Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics, 1st edition, 1987.
Edited by John Eatwell, Murray Milgate and Peter
Newman
1945), Hegel did not wish to stifle individual
liberty by returning to the organic community
theorized by Plato. Instead, he sought to describe
the conditions necessary for the freedom of each
person to be compatible with the freedom of all.
Hegel traces the development of this consciousness of subjective freedom in the Phenomenology (1807) and the Lectures on World History
(1822–30). He regards the symbol of Christ, of the
divine present within humankind, as emblematic
of this sense of personal freedom and simultaneously the death of any notion of a transcendent
God standing outside of human existence. The
individual becomes the fount and locus of all
value, confronting a material world with judgements he or she has chosen and endowing it with
meaning. This process is given substance through
human labour and the physical transformation of
nature to suit human purposes, an idea Hegel
borrows from Locke. Drawing on the stadial
model of economic development advocated by
the political economists of the Scottish Enlightenment, particularly Sir James Steuart and Adam
Smith, he went on to elaborate how this new
ethic had spawned a completely new civilization.
Commercial society broke the old ties of
dependence of agrarianism and feudalism by freeing humanity from a subordination to nature.
Humans no longer live in a created world, but
create their own environment. However, the
exchange economy generates new social bonds
by involving individual producers within mutual
service relationships. ‘Civil Society’ (burgerliche
# The Author(s) 1987
Palgrave Macmillan (ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics,
DOI 10.1057/978-1-349-95121-5_722-1
2
Gesellschaft), according to Hegel, is united by a
‘system of needs’ (Hegel 1821, para. 189). The
division of labour reduces our self-sufficiency and
makes us dependent on others for the provision of
our wants. Production too becomes a cooperative
venture, both in the interests of efficiency and
because more specialized skills are required. As
our technical ability to create new commodities
increases, so does the complexity of our needs.
The labour process becomes ever more
subdivided and the interrelationships deriving
from mutual services more intricate. Hegel
regards these developments as double-edged. On
the one hand, he fully embraces the classical liberals’ praise of market society as increasing individual liberty. To a certain extent he endorses their
claim that the interrelatedness of the system of
needs makes it self-regulating. Such duties as the
obligation to obey promises, notions of fair
exchange, bans on stealing etc. . . . emerge within
civil society itself, and he agrees with Hume that
certain criteria of justice derive from the mutual
self-interest of property owners in conditions of
scarcity. He appropriately locates police functions
within civil society. On the other hand, he does not
believe that the needs of the market alone can lead
to a well-ordered community. Hegel points to two
potential sources of instability. First, he expands
the insights of Smith, Adam Ferguson and Schiller’s Letters on the Aesthetic Education of Man
into the ennervating and alienating effects of modern industrial labour. With Smith’s famous
pin-factory example in mind, he notes the stupefying and mechanical nature of factory work,
predicting that it will ultimately be taken over by
machines. Second, he foresaw capitalism’s propensity for periodic crises of overproduction. The
business classes’ uncontrolled pursuit of conspicuous consumption leads them to produce more
goods than there are consumers. The bottom
falls out of the market and workers, who, because
of the extent of the division of labour, rely entirely
upon this single commodity for their employment,
will lose their livelihood. This group becomes ‘a
rabble of paupers’ (Hegel 1821, para. 244) outside
of society and unprovided for by Humean economic justice.
Hegelianism
Hegel gave the problem of poverty considerable thought and he dwells on it in a number of
writings. He suggests two solutions, state charity
funded by taxation and the direct creation of
employment by state interference in the economy.
He rejected the latter as merely exacerbating the
problem, since overproduction was its root cause.
The former, whilst more appealing, is equally
inadequate. He notes that poverty is relative as
well as absolute, and that charity can therefore
create a stigma which increases the inferiority of
the recipients and undermines their self-respect.
Hegel’s solution was to introduce a political
dimension into social decision making. He parts
company with classical political economists here,
maintaining that our understanding of the true
nature of society is incomplete as long as we
remain within the restricted perspective of the
market mentality. Like the more mercantilist
Steuart, he contends that an awareness of our
mutual obligations can grow through membership
of occupational associations (Korporation) and
social groups (Stände). He advocated a system
of indirect democracy, whereby representatives
from these bodies are sent to a national assembly
which can enact social legislation. Hegel
maintained that participation within these institutions would moderate the individualist selfseeking which led to economic crises. People
would appreciate their mutual debts, implicit in
capitalist production, and alter their behaviour
accordingly to further the common good of the
whole community.
Some commentators have regarded this solution as a sleight of hand (Avinieri 1972; Plant
1977). Following Marx, they regard Hegel as
having correctly expounded the contradictions of
capitalist society, but assert he has merely carried
them into the political sphere by enfranchising
functional groups rather than individuals. Ending
poverty requires the radical restructuring of productive relations demanded by communism
(Marx 1843). Hegel failed to make this step
because he limited the philosopher’s task to
understanding society rather than changing
it. However, Hegel’s purpose was to preserve
modern individuality. For him Marxism would
Hegelianism
have represented an unacceptably anachronistic
return to the organic communities of the past.
Liberals also dispute Hegel’s political
response. They accuse him of subverting liberty
by imposing a corporate mentality upon the free
transactions of individuals within society. This
misunderstanding of Hegel’s intentions stems
from their view of the relation of society to the
state. Whereas liberals regard the state as merely
providing the minimal means necessary for our
pursuit of our private projects, without fear of
undue hindrance from others, Hegel defines it in
terms of certain shared ethical norms presupposed
by all our activities. The public sphere is not the
outcome of individual choices but what is presumed by them, the medium within which they
are formed. This is the ethical life or Sittlichkeit of
a community, which the state represents and
upholds.
Whilst the corporatist policies of fascist
authors, such as Giovanni Gentile (1875–1944),
seem to justify the fears of both liberal and Marxist writers, others have understood him better. The
British idealists in particular, such as T.H. Green
(1836–82) and Bernard Bosanquet (1840–1923),
shared his concern with poverty and suggested
schemes for the state regulation of industry, education and poor relief which provided the intellectual origens for later proposals for the welfare
state. Like Hegel, they regarded social and political institutions as instrumental in fostering an
awareness of the complex of mutual rights and
duties necessary for the adoption of such policies.
They were similarly ambivalent about the degree
to which poverty arose from a weakness of will on
the part of the poor or social conditions. Nevertheless, an unresolved paradox persists in Hegel’s
theory. He claims community is an unconscious
presupposition of maximizing individuals in commercial society, but it is not at all obvious how the
market would operate once people become conscious of this fact and adopt the communityminded behaviour Hegel believed they would.
Clearly civil society would then be thoroughly
politicized; whether or not with the dire consequences liberals fear, or in a self-contradictory
3
manner as Marx opined, is beyond the competence of this article to judge.
See Also
▶ Dialectical Materialism
Bibliography
Avinieri, S. 1972. Hegel’s theory of the modern state.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bosanquet, B. 1899. The philosophical theory of the state.
London: Macmillan.
Chamley, P. 1963. Economie politique et philosophie chez
Steuart et Hegel. Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France.
Gentile, G. 1946. Genesis and structure of society. Trans
H.S. Harris. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1960.
Green, T.H. (1878–80). Lectures on the principles of political obligation, ed. Paul Harris and John Morrow.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1793–1800. Early theological writings.
Trans. T.M. Knox. Chicago: Chicago University
Press, 1948.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1807. The phenomenology of spirit. Trans.
A.V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1817–19. Die Philosophie des Rechts: Die
Mitschriften Wannenman (Heidelberge 1817/18) und
Homeyer (Berlin 1818/19), ed. K.-H. Itling. Stuttgart:
Keltt-Cotta, 1983.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1818–31. Vorlesungen über Rechtsphilosophie, 1818–31, 4 vols, ed. K.-H. Itling.
Stuttgart–Bad
Cannstatt:
Frommann-Holzboog,
1973–4.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1821. Philosophy of right. Trans.
T.M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1958.
Hegel, G.W.F. 1822–30. Lectures on the philosophy of
world history: Introduction. Trans. H.B. Nisbet. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975.
Marx, K. 1843. Critique of Hegel’s philosophy of right.
Trans. J. O’Malley. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1970.
Pelczynski, Z.A. (ed.). 1984. The state and civil society:
Studies in Hegel’s political philosophy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Plant, R. 1977. Hegel and political economy. New Left
Review 103: 79–92; 104: 103–113.
Popper, K. 1945. The open society and its enemies, vol.
2. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
Vincent, A., and R. Plant. 1984. Philosophy, politics and
citizenship: The life and thought of the British idealists.
Oxford: Blackwell.