Jump to content

Consequentia mirabilis

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Consequentia mirabilis (Latin for "admirable consequence"), also known as Clavius's Law, is used in traditional and classical logic to establish the truth of a proposition from the inconsistency of its negation.[1] It is thus related to reductio ad absurdum, but it can prove a proposition using just its own negation and the concept of consistency. For a more concrete formulation, it states that if a proposition is a consequence of its negation, then it is true, for consistency. In formal notation:

.

Weaker variants of the principle are provable in minimal logic, but the full principle itself is not provable even in intuitionistic logic.

History

[edit]

Consequentia mirabilis was a pattern of argument popular in 17th-century Europe that first appeared in a fragment of Aristotle's Protrepticus: "If we ought to philosophise, then we ought to philosophise; and if we ought not to philosophise, then we ought to philosophise (i.e. in order to justify this view); in any case, therefore, we ought to philosophise."[2]

Barnes claims in passing that the term consequentia mirabilis refers only to the inference of the proposition from the inconsistency of its negation, and that the term Lex Clavia (or Clavius' Law) refers to the inference of the proposition's negation from the inconsistency of the proposition.[3]

Derivations

[edit]

Minimal logic

[edit]

The following shows what weak forms of the law still holds in minimal logic, which lacks both excluded middle and the principle of explosion.

Weaker variants

[edit]

Frege's theorem states

For this is a form of negation introduction, and then for and using the law of identity, it reduces to

Now for , it follows that . By implication introduction, this is indeed an equivalence,

In minimal logic, the first double-negation in the original implication can optionally also be removed, weakening the forward direction statement to . Here, consequentia mirabilis thus holds whenever . Of course, when adopting the double-negation elimination principle for all propositions, consequentia mirabilis also follows simply because the latter brings minimal logic back to full classical logic.

This shows that already minimal logic validates that a proposition cannot be rejected exactly if this is implied by its negation, and that holds exactly when it is implied by both and .

The weak form can also be seen to be equivalent to the principle of non-contradiction . To this end, first note that using modus ponens and implication introduction, the principle is equivalent to . The claim now follows from , i.e. the fact that there are equivalent characterizations of two propositions being mutually exclusive.

Equivalence to excluded middle

[edit]

The negation of any excluded middle disjunction in particular implies , and thus the weaker disjunction itself. From the above weak form, it thus follows that any double-negated excluded middle statement is valid, in minimal logic. Likewise, this argument shows how the full consequentia mirabilis implies excluded middle.

The following argument shows that the converse also holds. A principle related to case analysis may be formulated as such: If both and each imply , and either of them must hold, then follows. Formally,

For and , the principle of identity now entails

Whenever the second conjunct of the antecedent, , is true, then so is the instance of the principle.

Intuitionistic logic

[edit]

One has that implies . By conjunction elimination, this is in fact an equivalence. In particular, one has

The right hand of this also implies , which gives another demonstration of how double-negation elimination implies consequentia mirabilis, in minimal logic.

In intuitionistical logic, the principle of explosion itself may be formulated as , and therefore . So here,

Classical logic

[edit]

It was established how consequentia mirabilis follows from double-negation elimination in minimal logic, and how it is equivalent to excluded middle. Two more classical arguments follow.

When excluded middle holds for , one contraposition gives , the propositional form of the reverse disjunctive syllogism. The law is now obtained with and one double-negation elimination.

Related to the last intuitionistic derivation given above, consequentia mirabilis also follow as the special case of Pierce's law

for . That article can be consulted for more, related equivalences.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Sainsbury, Richard. Paradoxes. Cambridge University Press, 2009, p. 128.
  2. ^ Kneale, William (1957). "Aristotle and the Consequentia Mirabilis". The Journal of Hellenic Studies. 77 (1): 62–66. doi:10.2307/628635. JSTOR 628635. S2CID 163283107.
  3. ^ Barnes, Jonathan. The Pre-Socratic Philosophers: The Arguments of the Philosophers. Routledge, 1982, p. 217 (p 277 in 1979 edition).
pFad - Phonifier reborn

Pfad - The Proxy pFad of © 2024 Garber Painting. All rights reserved.

Note: This service is not intended for secure transactions such as banking, social media, email, or purchasing. Use at your own risk. We assume no liability whatsoever for broken pages.


Alternative Proxies:

Alternative Proxy

pFad Proxy

pFad v3 Proxy

pFad v4 Proxy