Nova et Vetera, English Edition, Vol. 10, No. 1 (2012): 193–213
193
Thomistic Reflections On The Cosmos,
Man, And Stewardship
S TEVEN A. L ONG
Ave Maria University
Ave Maria, FL
Introduction
T HE FOLLOWING remarks attempt a very formal speculative treatment of cosmos, man, and stewardship, fecundated by the doctrine of St.
Thomas Aquinas.1 In what follows below, I shall first emphasize the speculative principles required to address the character of man’s relation to,
and limited stewardship over, the material cosmos—principles whose
understanding slowly is re-emerging from the tunnel of an anti-realist
eclipse within philosophy, systematic theology, and moral theology. While
their consideration here is as propaedeutic to the contemplation of the
dignity of the lower creation and of man’s stewardship over it, nonetheless there is a strong case that the account of these principles is of greater
value than their application in the ensuing analysis. Indeed, it is the
absence of an appreciation of these principles that haunts contemporary
thought in its relation to revealed truth, metaphysics, cosmology, anthropology, and ethics. Thus almost half of the following remarks regard the
principles that are necessary to address the question in hand. Some of
these are remote and some proximate, and so the treatment of these principles is accordingly divided.
Second, on the basis of these principles I will set forth an account of
man’s relation to the lower creation, to the cosmos as a whole, and to
1
I take this occasion to acknowledge and thank Christopher J. Thompson,
Academic Dean of The Saint Paul School of Divinity, for his invaluable inspiration, example, conversation, and criticism. Whatever may be good in the following work must trace its etiology to his encouragement; whatever falls short of its
promise must redound to myself.
194
Steven Long
God. This account seeks to vindicate the limited but real dignity of the
lower creation and the importance of stewardship precisely on the foundation of the role of the lower creation in the overall order of the cosmos
and in relation to God. Third, I will consider cosmic order in relation to
the good for man, arguing that the dignity of the lower creation, man’s
call to stewardship with respect to it, and the subordination of the lower
creation to the good of man, all flow from the same foundation: the role
of the lower creation in the hierarchic constitution of the cosmos. Fourth,
an argument will be presented against the “boundary hypothesis,” that is,
against the view that the lower creation is demarcated from the zone of
human agency and transformative technology by a mobile boundary that
implies a constant shrinkage for the scope of undiluted nature as opposed
to the growing chrysalis of human technology and technologically transformed nature. I argue that such a view fails to discern the foundation of
the second in the first, and therefore fails to discern that what is in view
is a limited and prudential, rather than an absolute, distinction. Fifth and
finally, a few brief conclusory remarks will be offered regarding the
prudential character of human stewardship of the lower creation.2
The account that follows is Thomistic both in its principles and in its
insistence that any true regard for the lower creation has, finally, a theistic provenance which alike implies hierarchic subordination of lower to
higher, and the dignity of the lower creation precisely with respect to our
attainment of the most important truths.
Itinerary of Principles
General Considerations
There are of course dramatic and profound questions regarding the
nature of human stewardship of the physical world. Yet manifestly, nothing in this consideration can proceed intelligently if knowledge of nature
and being—in particular knowledge of the terrestrial cosmos and its
2
It will be noted that I use the phrase “lower creation” rather than “environment”—this is for two reasons. (1) Man, as a rational creature, does not merely
have an “environment” but a “world” which is indeed the ordered whole of the
cosmos. (2) It is, as a function of metaphysical demonstration, true that all finite
being is created, so that what we are speaking of with respect to the physical
order is quite literally, vis-à-vis creatures endowed with intellect and will, the
“lower creation.” Moderns and postmoderns, having lost the praeambula fidei and
so being deprived of the rigorous character of the metaphysical demonstrations
for the reality of God, naturally tend toward reductionist formulae with respect
to the order of the universe. The language of the Catholic tradition is otherwise,
and should be stressed, just as Catholic authors speak of “procreation” rather than
merely “reproduction.”
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
195
normative relationship to the human good—is impossible. Under the
circumstances, this is the moment when most contemporary environmentalists should be checking out of the discussion: because most of our
contemporaries either do not believe that fixed knowledge of human
nature and of the cosmos—of being and nature—exists; or else, alternately, they believe that our sole knowledge of the cosmos is through
positive science, such that whatever knowledge of the cosmos there may
be is minimal, tentative, provisional, and wholly separate from ethical
wisdom and metaphysics. Those who reduce knowledge and science to
the confines of positive science, and those who deny the adequatio of
human intelligence to the real as such, can found no inference regarding
human stewardship with respect to the lower creation because they can
found no properly metaphysical, cosmological, anthropological, or ethical understanding whatsoever. This, in itself, goes far toward explaining
why it is that reasonable engagement of what are called “environmental
issues” often is lacking.
Thus it is manifest that significant rational deprivations afflict the
effort to understand man’s relation to the lower creation. The first of
these is the denial of the metaphysical adequatio, the conformity of intellect with being and nature. The principle of noncontradiction is widely
today supposed to be a merely logical principle, rather than—as Thomas
noted in question 94, article 2 of the prima secundae of the Summa theologiae—“founded upon the opposition of being and nonbeing.” Although
nonbeing is merely conceptual, being is real. Just as it is eternally true that
the divine nature is not a created nature (and this proposition would be
true even had there never been creatures, such that it is manifest that
divine nature is really distinct from created nature), just so, being is by its
real nature—analogically understood—really distinct from nonbeing.
There is no real relation of being to nonbeing: nonexistent things have no
real relations, and nonbeing is pure negation. But there is a real distinction: the real distinction between being and nonbeing is founded on
being which is itself real.
In Book III of the Will to Power Nietzsche observed that to take this
distinction as a real distinction implies a prior contact of the mind with
reality. Just so: it does. The mind has immediate and direct contactus with
the real—initially and chiefly (and this is not without importance for our
discourse) with the sensible real, sensible being. Likewise pertinent to our
discourse is the datum that this contactus with sensible reality is a function
of the human intellect’s openness to the entire universe of being.
The purely natural but immaterial powers of intellect and will constitute in man the lowest foundational stratum of the imago Dei, the image
196
Steven Long
of God, in man. Were man’s intellect and will not open to the universe
of being, true, and good, then to be made a friend of God through grace
man would need to cease being man and become a different species. But
man’s spiritual powers enable him to receive the divine aid and so to be
uplifted to the divine friendship. This reflects the remarkable uniqueness
of man’s capacity to receive the entire material cosmos not physically but
rather intentionally and spiritually, through knowledge: the universal
openness of the intellect to being and nature. Without such openness, the
very question of man’s relation to the cosmos, and his responsibility with
respect to it, could not arise. Man images God in an essentially nobler
way in grace, and in an even nobler fashion in everlasting glory in beatitude, than is true simply according to the constitution of human nature
in itself. But the nobler aspects of the imago Dei presuppose a natural
substratum in man which is lowest in the order of perfection, but without which the imago Dei in grace and in glory would not be possible.
Even to raise the question of stewardship is implicitly and actually to
acknowledge the distinctive openness to being, true, and good that characterizes the human creature as a function of man’s rational nature. Man
has not merely an environment, but a cosmos, because intellect is not
materially reducible to physical limitations, howsoever much it is in its
exercise correlated with these and dependent upon these. Of course, the
intellect is dependent not with respect to its act as such, which transcends
material limits, but with respect to the prerequisite conditions for attaining the object of its act: as the power of eyesight needs light to see, so the
power of intellect needs its object attained through abstraction from the
sensible phantasm in order to know; but knowledge is not sensation, as
eyesight is not simply light. Were intellection supposed to be reducible
merely to some modification of an intermediating (intermediating as
between knower and known) material substrate—as is for example
proposed in the view that knowledge is merely a function of the modeling of the real by the structure and activity of the brain—the following
question arises. If all one’s “knowledge” is limited to an intermediating
model, and there is no direct knowledge of the real as such, how is it
possible to judge that a model or intermediating medium accurately
reflects the real?
If a photograph is said to be a likeness of my father, this makes sense
only insofar as one may compare it to the original; but if the original
cannot be known as such, one is in no position to say whether the likeness is good or not. To remain momentarily with the language so often
used of our knowledge as a function of a sort of neural “encryption” in
the medium of the brain: if there is no direct knowledge of the real as
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
197
such, how can one know that this “encryption” or this medium and its
structuring are in the least adequate to reality? On the hypothesis of
knowledge as a function of the modeling of the real by the brain, the
brain must be adequate to model the real, and hence adequate to model
itself too—but without direct knowledge of the real we are in no position to know that this is so, and indeed thus in no position even to know
that the brain exists. If, and only if, the intellect has the capacity to
conform in the intentional order to the real—to become intentionally
rather than physically its object—is objectivity possible. If objectivity is
not affirmed, then there is no foundation even for the claim that brain
activity exists. The idea that intellectual intentionality, which is intrinsically immaterial, can be replaced by reductive physical causality (as
opposed to the explication of intentionality and knowledge in relation to
ontological causal analysis in terms of act and potency) is a self-immolative proposition wholly inconsistent with rational objectivity. That brain
activity, and sensory activity in general for that matter, may be a predispository requisite for the mind to obtain its object via abstraction, does
not alter or obviate the intrinsically immaterial nature of the supervening intellective act performed with respect to the object so obtained.
Likewise presupposed to this consideration of cosmos, man, and stewardship are the four causes—material, formal, efficient, and final—and the
real division of being by act and potency, a proposition whose apodicticity is today little understood. These principles are important because they
enter into the articulation of the cosmological order that is participated
by the lower creation. We must largely leave aside a more thorough
examination of the four causes, with the exception of a consideration of
finality in the next section below, where the analysis sustaining unified
normative teleology is discussed.
Yet it would be a mistake not to comment further on the doctrine of
the division of being by act and potency, and to leave unobserved just
how close is the real distinction of potency and act to the principle of
noncontradiction understood as a real metaphysical principle. The division of being by potency and act is a proposition perhaps developed
initially with respect to the physics, but developed in answering the
essentially metaphysical challenge of Parmenidean monism and pregnant
with implicit and actual metaphysical significance.
For it is not enough to see that being is in fact many, limited, and
changing either in order to account for and explain what it is in being that
enables it to be many, limited, and changing, or to reconcile this judgment
with the principle of noncontradiction. It is the discovery of potentia as a
real principle dependent upon act but distinct from and founded upon
198
Steven Long
it—a principle that is a principle of being and not identical with mere
negation—that answers this formal metaphysical interrogatory. As the
capacity for being represented by a certain nature is potentia vis-à-vis its
actual being, or as the sculptability of marble is potentia vis-à-vis its actual
sculpting, so potency is not act, but is founded upon act and limits it.
The challenge of Parmenidean monism—that being is identical with
itself and therefore radically unitary; that nothing exists outside of being
that could limit it, so that being is unlimited; and that being is not nonbeing, cannot be nonbeing, and so cannot change—is answered by the
discovery of potency as a real principle in being that accounts for manyness, limit, and change. Act is not self-limiting—the very denotation of
“act” is of itself not a denotation of real limit—but is limited only by its
relation to potency.3 This foundational discovery of being as divided by
potency and act is at the heart of Thomistic metaphysics, of the real
distinction of essence and existence (which, one recalls, in De ente et essentiae philosophically hinges on the argument that all the ways in which
being is plurifiable presuppose potentia),4 and indeed is the real foundation
for the doctrine of participation (which Thomas always, after his Scriptum
3
4
This of course does not mean that potency temporally antecedes act, nor that an
initially infinite act is somehow contracted by potency (as though the existence
of the frog were infinite but at the last minute limited by the frog nature). Rather
it means that act as such is not self-limiting; when God causes a thing to be, its
actuality is received by and proportioned to a potential principle in relation to
which the limit of act occurs.This is clear when one considers essence as potency
vis-à-vis existence as act. God ordains that a being whose nature represents a
certain capacity for existence comes into being, and potency and act are caused
simultaneously, the potency depending upon the act (as the essence depends
upon existence) and the act (e.g., existence) being limited by the potency of
which it is the act. But the priority of act is natural, not temporal; and although
act as such is not self-limiting, this is not to say that first a created existence was
infinite and then it was limited by potency, because what makes for created existence as finite perfection is precisely its delimitation by potency.Yet act as such, most
formally considered, is not self-limiting: nothing in the real analogical denotation of “act” designates potency as such. Act is limited only in relation to potency.
This analysis seems to rule out the interpretations associated with Rudi A. te
Velde, Participation and Substantiality in Thomas Aquinas (New York: E. J. Brill,
1995), especially 152 and 154. On this matter, it would appear that John F.
Wippel—cf. The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas: From Finite Being to
Uncreated Being (Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press,
2000), 129—is correct regarding Thomas’s teaching.
Text from the Corpus Thomisticum, S.Thomae de Aquino opera omnia, made available
online by the University of Navarre (www.unav.es/filosofia/alarcon/amicis/
ctopera.html#OM), De ente et essentia, Caput 3: “Ergo patet quod esse est aliud ab
essentia vel quiditate, nisi forte sit aliqua res, cuius quiditas sit ipsum suum esse;
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
199
on the Sentences, articulates in terms of the likeness of diverse rationes of act
as limited by potency, which is the evidence upon which the mind rises to
the affirmation of the reality of God). These remote principles are all
bound up with, and indeed, derived from, a knowledge of the absolute
object (universal being), formal object (the true), and proper object (quiddity in corporeal matter) of the human intellect. Not to be aware of the
metaphysical profundity of the knowledge available to man, is in a sense
not to be capable of understanding the dignity of the lower creation and
its place in the hierarchic ordering of the cosmos. The very question of
stewardship over the lower creation itself implies a real relative transcendence with respect to it on the part of man—a relative transcendence that
materialist anthropology cannot in the least explain. Likewise, the metaphysical roots of theism deriving from the analogicity of being as the likeness of diverse rationes of act as limited by potency are required for the
causal analysis reaching to the reality of God, and for the subsequent
account of participation, both of which provide the general context for
contemplation of the role of the lower creation within the cosmic order.
Proximate Considerations
The principles considered above—metaphysical realism; the adequation of
mind to the real; the relation between the first principle of noncontradiction and the real division of being by act and potency as the foundation
for the theistic proofs; the reality of the four causes—are formally necessary but in a certain sense remote. By contrast there are three crucial principles that must here exact from us a greater consideration, because they
are most formally and proximately essential to this analysis. These principles are first, normative unified natural teleology; second, the primacy of
the speculative vis-à-vis the practical reason; and third, the transcendence
of the common good. On these three principles hang not only the correct
approach to the subject of cosmos, man, and stewardship, but a proper
insight into the nature and implications of the natural law.
et haec res non potest esse nisi una et prima, quia impossibile est, ut fiat plurificatio alicuius nisi per additionem alicuius differentiae, sicut multiplicatur natura
generis in species, vel per hoc quod forma recipitur in diversis materiis, sicut
multiplicatur natura speciei in diversis individuis, vel per hoc quod unum est absolutum et aliud in aliquo receptum, sicut si esset quidam calor separatus, esset alius
a calore non separato ex ipsa sua separatione. Si autem ponatur aliqua res, quae sit
esse tantum, ita ut ipsum esse sit subsistens, hoc esse non recipiet additionem
differentiae, quia iam non esset esse tantum, sed esse et praeter hoc forma aliqua;
et multo minus reciperet additionem materiae, quia iam esset esse non subsistens
sed materiale. Unde relinquitur quod talis res, quae sit suum esse, non potest esse
nisi una.”
200
Steven Long
1. The first—normative unified teleology—affirms that agency can
neither be nor be known apart from the end for the sake of which it
exists, and that there is order not only between acts and ends but
among ends.
Normative unified teleology—the co-measuring or commensuration of ends according to their proximity to the proportionate natural, and ultimate supernatural, end—is a metaphysical, cosmological,
and anthropological premise before, and as a condition of being, an
ethical premise. First, no efficient cause can exist apart from teleological finality. As St. Thomas Aquinas reminds us in the Summa contra
Gentiles (III, c. 2), were operations not teleologically ordered, they
would either never begin—because there would be nothing for the
sake of which they would be acting—or else, if per impossibile they
could begin to act without any end, then their action would never
cease, because there would be no end capable of completing, fulfilling, or terminating such an action. Further, no action as such can even
be understood without some minimal understanding of the end
toward which and for the sake of which it moves. If one asks what
snow shoveling is, the answer is “moving snow with a shovel-like
implement” or something to that effect. Even quantum physics identifies the differing probabilities for electron position in terms of the
differing final positions themselves (within a certain time frame)—
something that even the radical Copenhagen school cannot avoid.
Efficiency is defined by telos, defined by the end. Agency or efficiency
can neither be, nor be known, apart from reference to the end in relation to which it is constituted. As Aristotle reminds us, an ordered
series of efficient causes implies an ordered series of final causes or
ends, rising to the Final End, which is demonstrably identical with the
First Efficient Cause, namely, God. An ordered series of efficient and final
causes comprises, not a multiverse but a cosmos: an ordered whole.5 The purely
speculative necessity of teleology is ineluctable.
Some have supposed that evolutionary theory proves decisively
that there is no such unified natural teleology.Yet all that such theory
achieves is the affirmation of teleology extending even to the consti5
Of course God could cause some such physical system without ordering it to us:
and, were this so, it would exist and we would not know of it. But then, too, it
would be linked to us indirectly, by virtue of being linked to the First Cause of
all finite being, which is alike our First Cause. If deriving from the same ultimate
cause places effects in a proportionate analogical unity, then by definition all
possible universes participate one divine order.
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
201
tution of the genetic order.6 The seeming absence of teleology from
the vast expanse of inert physical creation is an illusion that can be
maintained only by the twofold loss of (1) the perception of hierarchy, which makes clear the ordering of the lowest common denominator of the physical to the biological and spiritual, and finally to
God; and, what is closely related to the first, (2) the causal subjection
of subordinate to superordinate realities.
2. These judgments point to the second of the three principles I wish
to address: namely, the primacy of the speculative with respect to the
practical. The realm of practical reason is the realm of reasoning with
respect to doing and making. But such reasoning presupposes the
prior existence of appetite for something that is served by doing or
making. However, appetite—the motion of the will toward some
end—itself requires prior knowledge. Without prior intellectual
specification, without some degree of knowledge, there is no inclinational motion, the will is not moved. But as prior knowledge
precedes the motion of the will, it precedes appetition; and inasmuch
as appetition precedes practical reasoning, such knowledge is prior to
practical knowledge as such. Because practical reasoning presupposes
the prior inclination of the will toward some end, the knowledge
required for this inclination to occur stands as a presupposed principle to the entire practical order. As St. Thomas puts the matter in
Summa theologiae I–II, q. 19, a. 3, ad 2. (Leonine ed.): “Now in regard
to the means, the rectitude of the reason depends on its conformity
with the desire of a due end: nevertheless the very desire of the due
end presupposes on the part of reason a right apprehension of the
end.”7Accordingly, the speculative is absolutely prior to the practical, and
6
7
If one alters the genes that control the eyes of the fly, one gets flies with no eyes,
or many eyes, or flies with funky eyes; if one alters the genes that control the wings,
one gets flies with many wings, or no wings, or wings connected to the head. But
if at the genetic level there were no order of agency to telos or end—if it were
truly random—then one might alter the part of the genotype that concerns the
wings of the fly, and get, say, Barbara Streisand, or a toilet seat, or Mark Twain’s
Huckleberry Finn. In fact, genetic biology vindicates teleology. Granted that
random events—understood as events wherein causes interact in a novel way that
we cannot initially predict—occur, everything about such events is teleologically
intelligible in terms of the composite of operative accidental causes.
St. Thomas Aquinas, ST I–II, q. 19, a. 3, ad 2. (Leonine ed.): “Now in regard to
the means, the rectitude of the reason depends on its conformity with the desire
of a due end: nevertheless the very desire of the due end presupposes on the part
of reason a right apprehension of the end.”—”In his autem quae sunt ad finem,
rectitudo rationis consistit in conformitate ad appetitum finis debiti. Sed tamen
202
Steven Long
every practical reasoning includes what one might call a speculum: a purely
speculative knowledge constituting the intellective contact with real or possible
being lying at the source of the ignition of appetite and designating the character of the end.8 The speculative knowledge of the order of the cosmos is critical in the development of our appreciation of the lower creation.
3. Third and finally, there is a decisive principle for the present consideration, best articulated in the work of St. Thomas Aquinas, and given
masterful exposition by the late Charles de Konick:9 namely, the
principle of the transcendence of the common good. We are familiar
with purely technical and instrumental conceptions of the common
good—the view that the common good is merely a collection of
private goods or is constituted by what is good for the greater number
of individuals. Such instrumentalist conceptions have their uses. But
they cannot substitute for a realist metaphysical account: the speculative intelligence discovers the common good to be substantive rather
than purely instrumental. The common good is an end that is by its
very nature more communicable to many, more irradiantly diffusive in
8
9
et ipse appetitus finis debiti praesupponit rectam apprehensionem de fine, quae
est per rationem.”
ST I, q. 79, a. 11, resp.: “Now, to a thing apprehended by the intellect, it is accidental whether it be directed to operation or not, and according to this the speculative and practical intellects differ. For it is the speculative intellect which
directs what it apprehends, not to operation, but solely to the consideration of
truth; while the practical intellect is that which directs what it apprehends to
operation.” —“Accidit autem alicui apprehenso per intellectum, quod ordinetur
ad opus, vel non ordinetur. Secundum hoc autem differunt intellectus speculativus et practicus. Nam intellectus speculativus est, qui quod apprehendit, non
ordinat ad opus, sed ad solam veritatis considerationem: practicus vero intellectus dicitur, qui hoc quod apprehendit, ordinat ad opus.”
Ibid., q. 79, a. 11, ad 2: “The object of the practical intellect is good directed
to operation, and under the aspect of truth. For the practical intellect knows
truth, just as the speculative, but it directs the known truth to operation.”—“ita
obiectum intellectus practici est bonum ordinabile ad opus, sub ratione veri.
Intellectus enim practicus veritatem cognoscit sicut speculativus; sed veritatem
cognitam ordinat ad opus.”
ST I–II, q. 9, a. 1: “Now the first formal principle is universal ‘being’ and
‘truth,’ which is the object of the intellect. And therefore by this kind of motion
the intellect moves the will, as presenting its object to it.”—“Primum autem
principium formale est ens et verum universale, quod est obiectum intellectus.
Et ideo isto modo motionis intellectus movet voluntatem, sicut praesentans ei
obiectum suum.”
Cf. his essays “The Primacy of the Common Good” and “Against the Personalists,” in The Writings of Charles De Koninck, vol. 2, trans. and ed. Ralph McInerny
(Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press: 2009).
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
203
intelligible good, more universal and rational. Thus, truth, mercy,
justice are all by their nature common and not merely individual goods.
An individual or private good is such that if one has it, another
does not—if I eat my lunch, you do not—unless, perchance, you
should happen to eat me. Whereas, truth is not in the least diminished by the number of those who know it, and in fact each person’s
attainment of a truth is enriched by its possession by others, inasmuch as one may see more deeply into it than another and so
augment its appreciation. Likewise, if I do justice in one case, I am
not obliged to do injustice in another, as though justice were a scarce
material object whose supply were running out. The judge never
rightly says: “We ran out of justice two hours ago: would you rather
be lynched or shot?”
The common good, while it is good for man—and it is principally
that in which man’s good consists—is not man’s individual or private
good. It is good for me, but it is not mine. Those who bled the beach
crimson at Normandy in World War II, did so on behalf of a good
that was good for them—the good of justice—but which was not
simply identical with their private good. The common good of society participates the right order of the cosmos toward God in nature
and grace—this is why Bl. John Paul II always spoke of the need for
the political state to do justice to “the whole truth” of man. The
common good of society is constituted by all that defines its actual
ordering toward truth, justice, mercy, friendship, the natural contemplative good, and the supernatural love of God. As such, the common
good of society is a noble end of striving that does not reduce merely
to private good or something reductively instrumental toward
private good, and it is an end worthy of service and sacrifice.10
Howsoever much it remains true that the common good is good for
the individual, it is not merely an individual or private good. Truth is
good for the individual, but the individual does not own it.
In the classical analysis, there is an order of such common goods,
rising to the indwelling good of order constitutive of the cosmos; and
further, rising to the extrinsic common good of the cosmos itself:
namely, God. The ultimate end of man—the beatific vision—is
10
ST II–II, q. 58, a. 7, ad 2: “The common good of the realm and the particular
good of the individual differ not only in respect of the many and the few, but also
under a formal aspect. For the aspect of the common good differs from the aspect
of the individual good, even as the aspect of whole differs from that of part.Wherefore the Philosopher says (Polit. I. 1) that they are wrong who maintain that the state
and the home and the like differ only as many and few and not specifically.”
204
Steven Long
constituted by the most absolutely self-diffusive and communicable
reality: the Triune God Himself. But the indwelling common good
of the cosmos is participated by the lower creation.
I have insisted upon these three points—unified normative teleology, the priority of the speculative, and the transcendence of the
common good—for the following reason: Speculative knowledge of the
teleological ordering constitutive of the indwelling common good of the cosmos
is essential to the question of stewardship. Doubtless the consideration of
these principles may appear to divagate from our object. But without these, our discourse cannot proceed on a firm basis. And it would
be utopian to expect conversation about the nature of man’s stewardship over the lower creation to be able to proceed lacking wellfounded wisdom regarding the saturation of agency in teleological
order, the primacy of the speculative in giving principles to our ethical contemplation, and the transcendence of the common good; or
to think it even possible fruitfully to proceed on foundations other
than realist metaphysics, or sufficiently to address the question of order
in the cosmos in abstraction from the theistic conclusions to which
realist causal analysis leads. Now I must attempt to apply these principles correctly to the question at hand. The first step we must take
is to consider man’s relation to the lower creation, to the cosmos as
a whole, and to God.
Man’s Relation to the Lower Creation, to the Cosmos
as a Whole, and to God
In asking about man’s relation to the lower creation, we have already
assessed the reality of a fixed ontological distance separating minerals,
plants, and nonrational animals from man. Man’s spiritual nature is the
lowest foundational constituent of the imago Dei in man, a purely natural
likeness to God owing to the immateriality of intellect and will. Even on
the plane of the proximate natural order, intellect and will open man to
the universe of being, true, and good.
This fixed difference between man and the lower creation does not,
however, make of man’s private good a good superior to the common
good of the universe, because the entire universe, and not merely its highest part, is ordered to God. Everything in reality is ordered to God, because
the actuality of each and every thing is that in it whereby it is most likened
to God, and the consummate actuation of each creature in attaining the
proportionate natural end to which it is ordered is a specific imitation of
God. Thus, even in precision from supernatural beatitude, man is naturally
ordained to God in a very specific way, through intellect and will.
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
205
But with respect to natural good—and in precision from the infinitely
disproportionate supernatural good—the good of the higher together
with the lower is greater than the good of the higher alone. Man forms
part of the cosmos, a creature individually important because the soul is
a spiritual principle ordered to endure beyond the confines of the physical world, lesser in natural perfection than the multitudinous species of
angels, while nobler than nonrational animals, plants, and minerals. As has
already been intimated with respect to intellectual objectivity, man’s
nobility is in part constituted by the truth that it belongs to human
nature to have, not merely an “environment” but a “world”; and this
“world” is—owing to the very nature of things—not reducible merely to
the lower part of creation. Man is a creature who conceives the immanent ordering of the cosmos—inclusive of the invisible or spiritual
aspects of the cosmos—as flowing from, and ordered toward, the First
Cause. Man is not merely a “part” of the physical order, although he is a
part of this order; but he is a part of the cosmos—part of an ordered
whole that comprises the procession of all creatures from God, and their
return to God. And the lower creation participates the indwelling
common good of right order of the cosmos.
Cosmic Order and the Good for Man
This brings us specifically to the question of the relation between the
order of the cosmos and the good for man. It has already been affirmed
that the good for man consists chiefly in the hierarchy of common goods,
extending to the indwelling common good of the right order of the
universe, and extending further to the extrinsic common good of the
universe, namely God. Because man is created in grace, from the moment
of his creation man is further ordered in and by grace to the friendship
of God and to intrinsically supernatural beatitude. What is the role of the
lower creation in all this? Is the lower creation merely an object of use
for man?
Certainly there is what one might call a “trumping right” of the good
of a person over the subordinated good of any particular lower physical
being or nature. If it comes to the life and well-being of a child versus
the life and well-being of a deer—or even the life and well-being of a
lower species—then, since the soul of the child is ordained to outlive all
merely terrestrial physical species whatsoever and is possessed of rational
dignity, one should have no hesitancy whatsoever in preferring the life of
a child. Nonetheless, the good of the order of the cosmos is a common
good, as all things have their proper natural good in accordance with it—
from the diverse species of angels, to man, to the lower creation. Man is
206
Steven Long
called to know, and to honor, this order. But what can it mean to honor
this order as found within that lower creation that man is in fact called
to use, to subject to human activity, in multiform ways?
Surely subjecting the lower creation to the service of reason and of
God constitutes part of honoring the lower order of creation, which is
dignified in being brought to a higher and more attuned service of God
and man. But it is not alone in our activity directing lower nature to the
human good that we honor the divinely inscribed order of the cosmos
in the lower creation. Before ever we turn to doing and making, there is
natural inclination; and before there is natural inclination, there is knowledge. The chief element in our honoring of the lower creation, then, will
consist in our contemplation of this order as manifestative of the order of
the cosmos as such—as bearing the trace and imprimatur of the divine
wisdom—and so as manifesting the First Cause of all things—and finally
even the vestigial trace of the Trinity.
It is largely from the knowledge of the lower creation that our knowledge of the full reaches of the cosmos, and of the existence of God,
derives. We move from what is less intelligible in itself, and more intelligible to us, to what is more intelligible in itself, but less intelligible to us:
that is, we move from the multifarious world of nature in all its variety,
to the judgment that there is a unitary First Cause, whose perfection lacks
any limit of potency, namely, God. Hence Romans 1:20: “For the invisible things of him, from the creation of the world, are clearly seen, being
understood by the things that are made; his eternal power also, and divinity: so that they are inexcusable.”
It is not simply that the whole edifice of natural science, and philosophy of nature, and even metaphysics, presuppose first the humble beginning of our contemplative contact with the physical universe in sensation
and abstraction. It is that the order defining this lower universe is thus
constituted as a primitive and primordial good for man as such, body and
soul, who relies upon its physical solidity and whose intelligence is fed by
it. Hence, granted also that the application of the positive sciences in
productive arts designed to serve the larger good of man is both valid and
founded upon a certain measure of speculative conformity with the order
of lower nature, that measure of speculative conformity with the order of
lower nature necessary to the productive arts does not exhaust the being,
true, and good even of lower nature.
This is an important judgment. For God is in some way reflected in
anything that is, and so there is a sense in which what man makes of
nature and offers to God is also theophanic. Given the obvious worth and
dignity of the transformative aspect of technology, and of the subjection
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
207
of the lower creation to the service of man, one can imagine someone
thinking that the natural purpose of the lower creation is nothing other
than its transformation into the perfect quasi-technical cocoon for the
germination of human culture. But what is missing from this conception
is precisely the extra-utilitarian dimension of the lower creation as manifesting the divine order of the cosmos, and of sensible nature as constituting the birthplace of human intelligence with respect to the wider
horizons of being and nature.
It might be objected that human transformations of nature exhibit
more rather than less worth because they doubly derive from nature—first
from subrational nature and then from the rational nature. If we accept this
approach to the matter as presenting the entire picture, then even the
ineradicable dependence of applied science, technology, and the productive arts upon the prior ordering of nature will be conceived merely as the
dependence of the chalk upon the blackboard, because then nature stands
to technology as potency to act. In fact, clearly there is a limited sense in
which this is true. What then stands to limit this truth and to place it in
confrontation with something of a different order? That is to say, what is
there, in principle, to constitute a limit to the use of transformative technology with respect to the lower creation? How can the subrational
creation avoid the fate of being endlessly remade at the whimsy of man?
The answer here is that the divine ordering of the cosmos as such extends
into the lower order of creation and is manifest there according to the
natures of the things God has made: the lower creation participates the
common good of the cosmos. It would be saying too much, to say that what
is best or optimal for subrational nature is always a desideratum, because the
lower creation is for the sake of the higher creation, and because man’s harm
or death is not an acceptable price to pay for some essentially lower good.11
Nonetheless, all things being equal, there is a permanent natural desideratum for respecting and preserving the general order of lower nature, not
alone because it serves some human utility of medicine or production or
technology, but for the following reasons. First, the lower creation is the
evidentiary home of our intellectual life and contemplation, the realm in
which our natures and our narratives have been tried and refined. There is
nothing in the intellect that is not first in the senses, and the connatural
11
Further, it is a sinful world, a world in which evil, both physical and more importantly moral, infects the orchestration of the providential symphony. In a world
that is affected in this way by evil, although the perfect is not the enemy of the
good, it may nonetheless be impossible prudently and with integrity simply to
pursue the perfect “as the crow flies” (to use Michael Oakeshott’s phrase).
208
Steven Long
mode of our cognition in this life is through abstracting from, and adverting to, sensible phantasms. We are ordered to the knowledge of sensible
quiddities, and the variety and diffusiveness of the lower creation condition
our intellectual, imaginative, and aesthetic life. Second, in its mystery and
variety the lower creation represents an essential and primary constituent
of the primordial revelation of God in creation, providing the foundation
for our awareness of the essential analogicity of being and nature, and for
our ascent to God; third, the lower creation participates the indwelling
common good of the order of the cosmos, a common good which
includes the ordering of angel and man as much as it does that of animal,
plant, and mineral.
These interrelated propositions say much the same thing.That the lower
creation, even prior to our placing it at the service of human concerns
through technology, forms the aboriginal context and the source for our
intellectual life, providing us the native images and language of our senses
and the poetry of space and time; that the lower creation ineradicably
constitutes an essential aspect of the primordial revelation occurring from
the moment of creation, pointing to the extrinsic common good Who is
God; and that the lower creation participates the indwelling common good
of the order of the cosmos—all these insights point in the same direction.
It is from the purely speculative contemplation of the lower creation that
the understanding of the causal arguments for the existence of God are
developed, and these highlight and articulate primordial revelation, framing the lower realm of nature whence our speculations have begun as the
effect and gift of God. And the immanent common good of the universe
is defined as a good of right order, and so is chiefly a causal affair—and of
course our knowledge of the causal order of things begins with our knowledge of causes in the lower creation. Without contactus with sensible being,
our ascent to loftier knowledge is impossible, because there is nothing in
the intellect that is not first in the senses, a doctrine of Aristotle and
Aquinas that is defensible today just as when first it was uttered. Our
knowledge is abstractive, and it presupposes sense knowledge without
which we have nothing from which to abstract—the root of the agony of
intellectual creatures when they suffer illnesses of the nervous system such
as Alzheimer’s that cut the dense contactus of man with sensitive memory
or the sensible world and leave man a cognitive orphan.
Does this mean that it is an act of impiety to God, and to the cosmos,
to permit a single species to go extinct? That man’s practical reason is in
material servitude to an over-lush vegetation of lower nature that chains
man’s life to the miasmal swamps of pre-human cosmic history? It would
mean this, were we to infer from it any absolute or normative require-
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
209
ment always to regard the integrity of every particular lower nature as
essential for the human good as such. But it is not merely of some lower
nature that we are speaking, but of the whole order of the lower creation
as such.
The question is, not whether we are bound to undertake heroic exertions to save every threatened species, but whether the whole nexus of
such species does not invite from the cultivated human mind a distinctive regard. Yet what can it mean to have a global predilection for a
certain realm of unsuppressed and unneutered created natures, while also
generally approving the application of science to technology and the
productive arts? How does one generally approbate pristine, untamperedwith-nature, while simultaneously approving the general tendency
toward technological tampering with nature? Is this not a contradiction
in the making? On what principled basis will the seemingly necessary
material boundary judgment be made delineating the acceptable transformative application of natural science for the sake of technological
betterment, from applications which are not acceptable?
The False Alternative of the Boundary Hypothesis
The question which has just been raised arguably involves a false hypothesis: namely, the hypothesis that the realm of lower creation in its splendor
is differentiated from the realm of human agency and transformation by a
clear but mobile boundary, and moreover such a boundary as to imply a
constant shrinkage for the scope of undiluted nature as opposed to the
growing chrysalis of human technology and technologically transformed
nature. But the second always presupposes and depends upon the first—
the laws and ontological density of the first are absolutely required for the
second. Thus, the boundary in question is not an absolute boundary
between two antithetic kingdoms, but rather a boundary of a prudential
type, regarding the precise degree to which a constitutive element of technologically untransformed nature—as a native constituent of the spiritual,
scientific, and aesthetic good of man—ought be preserved. Granted that
something of intrinsic worth for man is bound up with preserving
enclaves of nature which preserve in their integrity multifarious living
things, and the ecologies that support them, there remains the necessary
prudential question of degree, precisely because the lower creation is
ordered to the service of the higher. Accordingly, no subhuman nature can
simply of itself demand the homage of human sacrifice. I have argued here
that the human realm implies a consubstantial ordering to and with the
cosmos, which includes the ordering of the lower creation that is so vital
to our contemplative, affective, and physical lives.
210
Steven Long
It is crucial to see that the same ordering that thus warrants regard for
lower nature, also warrants that the hierarchic ordering of the lower to
the higher be honored.
But does this doom mankind to a Cartesian existence—one part technically driven and transformed, the other primitive but remote, and
preserved but yet in its preserved state largely, for millions of people, thus
inaccessible? No. Because even within the zone of application of science
and technology, the human mind is not wholly encased within techne
but encounters nature and reasons for respecting natural limits.12
While in a certain limited respect the natures of things in the lower
creation appear before technology as matter yet to be formed, in the wider
economy of human life—which is absolutely presupposed to technology—
this nature now and always will constitute not merely matter to be formed
but rather an already formed preamble to human engagement upon which
that engagement cannot but depend. And the presence of an order not of
human devising is most powerfully manifest in the lower creation, however
much it is true that this order extends even within technological products
themselves. Rather than constituting two kingdoms—the kingdom of the
Cartesian Cogito reducing the lower creation to the status of manipulable
object, and the kingdom of subhuman nature—in fact the drama of human
stewardship is played out along a necessary continuum in which prudential
regard for natural order is circumstantially inflected in many different ways.
Since the order of the cosmos permeates the physical creation, it is
literally impossible to escape it—whereas sadly by stark contrast it is
possible to fail to appreciate or honor this order in the physical creation.
It is perhaps principally with respect to this consideration that we may
see that man honors the physical creation most profoundly in the sacred
liturgy, because it is in the sacred liturgy that the whole universe is offered
in prayer in the Holy Spirit, through Christ, to God the Father. The
preservation of enclaves of technologically unaffected wildlife is, by
comparison, a lesser appreciation and honoring of the physical world,
which is sacramentalized by the Incarnation, through and through.
Nonetheless a lower but genuine mode of this sacramentalization is
served in preserving enclaves of the lower creation outside human techno12
It is one thing to enhance certain natural beings through human technology, and
another to completely transform a species without remainder. To enhance a
nature in certain limited ways for particular human purposes—say, through
genetic alterations to make grain more survivable vis-à-vis common pests—is
not, itself, an act of impiety. But this does not mean that a commonplace regard
for the general natures of things vanishes. What is involved is a certain regard for
the primitive constitution of things, which by their natures can evoke for man
the wider ordering of the cosmos.
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
211
logical space, for by doing so man acknowledges that in creating lower
natures, God has created subjects of being and not mere objects for technical reconstruction. Although these subjects of being are ordered to the common good
of the universe, and not least ordered through supporting the existence of
the rational animal, their primitive signification to the contemplative
intelligence is of even greater value to man than is their vast utilitarian
aid vis-à-vis the transformative arts. For that primitive signification of
non-technized nature places man in contact with a wide, variegated, teleological multiplex, whose character is not of itself the effect of any human
choice, and which manifests most concretely and awesomely the theonomic
character of nature, the mysterious analogicity of being, and the transcendent excellence of its divine principle. Just as there is an order of human
ends that is of ethical significance prior to choice, so there is an intra-cosmic
common good whose integral nature is but dimly comprehended, but yet
which is not only a source of many potential technological benefits but far
more importantly an evidentiary source with respect to the contemplation
of being and God. The contemplative life of man is irreparably in debt to
this lower order, precisely as participating the common good of the whole
cosmos as such, material and immaterial. Further, to the degree that the
lower creation is subjected prudently to transformative technology, there are
questions of fittingness even regarding the proper and fitting manner for
such subjection to occur (for example, at the most obvious: some technologies achieve a necessary end with more environmental destruction than is
either necessary or desirable).Yet the prudential legal objective is not to so
hamper human technical development that it is stifled underneath a dead
mass of particular limitations, but rather to safeguard certain permanent
goods by reasonable generic limitations.To preserve areas for wildlife should
never be tantamount to subordinating or sacrificing human life to the aim
of protecting subrational creatures.
Many virtues have been hidden by divine providence in the earth, and
man’s discovery of nature is not merely the Baconian enterprise of
“putting nature on the rack” to wrest her secrets from her for the benefit of mankind. To the contrary, nature gives her secrets most readily, not
to those who put her on the rack, but to those who read her intelligible
ordering closely and well, which cannot be done simply by subjecting
nature to instrumental reason.
Conclusion: On the Role of Prudence
I would like to conclude by noting that discerning the implications of all
these truths for the workaday world requires prudence (and hence all the
other virtues)—because, however valuable is contemplation, and however
212
Steven Long
necessary it is to honor God’s script in nature, the lower creation is for the
sake of the nobler creation, not only with respect to contemplation, but
also with respect to use. Hence when and insofar as the limits of the
lower creation become, not only invitations to contemplation, but occasions for harm or death or even for the impeding of life-saving or lifeenhancing agency, just so far does man’s reason insist upon transformative
operations within and upon the lower creation. And these discernments,
being discernments of prudence, do not and cannot follow mathematical
formulae or purely axiomatic protocols.
The rational nature does not act under mere rote instruction from the
lower creation, but gazes upon it, seeks its principles and causes, and takes
instruction and refreshment from it in the course of living out its trajectory, which is an inherently rational one that is as distinct from the course
of lower nature as the salt in the ocean is from mere H2O. Indeed, it is
because the lower nature shares in the common good of the order
indwelling the cosmos as such that from the lower creation the rational
animal perceives the normativity of this cosmic ordering, and—following
the telos connatural to the rational soul—honors it. But this honor paid to
the inherent order of the cosmos as participated by lower nature is not a
replacement for the rational nature’s own teleology but rather an essential
instruction and aid for it, for we are not mere physical natures, and nature
is an essentially analogical principle that rises beyond the lower creation.
Thus lower terrestrial nature should be neither opposed to technical
development nor disdained as mere matter before technical form, but
should be regarded, precisely in its participation of cosmic and divine
order, as a good to be preserved. Such preservation will to some degree
occur in enclaves apart from technical civilization, where by reason of its
beauty, its variety, and its manifestation of an order which is not merely
that imposed by techne and which stands in analogical relation to all the
other goods of human nature, it is kept pristine. But the virtualities of
nature are preserved in a different manner when they are to some degree
transformed by human ingenuity in the service of human life and
elevated to a greater analogical participation of the good of human
nature. Those who are called to make the prudential decisions about the
particulars of these decisions will do so better to the degree to which
their minds and imaginations enable them to perceive both cosmological
and metaphysical order, and formal and teleological hierarchy. In short:
those who are wise—and not merely those who enjoy the reasonable
physical utilities afforded by the lower creation—are those best equipped
to undertake a reasonable stewardship and dominion over the lower
creation that gives glory to God and solace to man. And the truth defin-
The Cosmos, Man, and Stewardship
213
ing this stewardship is that the same ordering that warrants regard for
lower nature, also warrants that the hierarchic ordering of the lower to
the higher be honored. That which principally accounts for the dignity
of the lower creation—its participation of the indwelling common good
of the universe—is also that which determines the hierarchic subordination of the lower creation to the good of man, because lower goods are
for the sake of nobler goods. Beyond even its practical contribution to
human betterment, however, the importance of the lower creation for
our contemplative lives in relation to the order of the universe as such
ought not be forgotten. The lower creation is the womb of science, the
home of poetry and beauty, and the primal evidentiary foundation for
the causal ascent of human reasoning to God.
N&V