Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.
To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to upgrade your browser.
2013, International Encyclopedia of Ethics
…
6 pages
1 file
Consider a case in which, if some person A1 injures, lies to, kills or in some other way violates another person P1, she will set in motion a chain of events that will prevent two other persons, A2 and A3, from similarly violating two other persons P2 and P3. Intuitively, it is wrong in such a case for A1 to violate P1: A1 has an obligation not to violate others just as A2 and A3 do, and prevention of their violations of P2 and P3 does not justify A1 in violating her obligation to P1. Rights, for example, are commonly understood as generating such obligations not to violate even in certain cases in which such a violation can prevent more such violations from happening.(see RIGHTS) Many moral theories, including deontological theories (see DEONTOLOGY), attempt to provide rationales for such intuitive moral restrictions.
Sats, 2000
According to deontologists, morality includes constraints. These constraints are (in part) intended to cater for our moral intuitions about various cases in which an agent can prevent harm to some by seeing to it that someone (else) is harmed. I briefly argue that neither the Doctrine of Doing and Allowing nor the Doctrine of Double Effect quite match our intuitions about such cases, and suggest that our intuitions are better explained in terms of a psychological mechanism that Peter Unger has called 'projective separating'. Furthermore, I argue that projective separating has no moral merit and that this casts some doubt on the enterprise of defending constraints.
Philosophical Studies, 1995
Philosophical Studies, 2020
Scanlonian contractualism rejects the consequentialist assumptions about morality, value, and rationality in virtue of which deontological constraints appear paradoxical. And yet, Jeffrey Brand-Ballard and Robert Shaver have claimed that it cannot succeed in defending the said restrictions. That is because they see Scanlon’s tie-breaking argument as threatening to justify aggregation in paradox of deontology cases. I argue that this claim rests upon a failure to appreciate contractualism’s relational character. Once we take this feature of the view into account, it becomes clear that the tie-breaking argument is ruled out in cases where the only way for us to prevent several killings would be to commit one ourselves. To show this, I provide a contractualist explanation of why our duty not to harm persons is stricter than our duty to help them when they are threatened with harm. I conclude by distinguishing two ways in which this defense of deontological restrictions might bring contractualism objectionably close to absolutism.
Discussions in basic ethical problems are often framed by the essential differences between consequentialism and deontology -two fundamental theories in normative ethics.
Introduction to Formal Philosophy, 2018
Deontic logic is the logic of normative concepts such as obligation, permission, and prohibition. This non-technical overview of the area has a strong emphasis on the connections between deontic logic and problems discussed in moral philosophy. Major issues treated are the distinction between ought-to-be and oughtto-do, the various meanings of permissive expressions, the logical relations among norms, the paradoxes of deontic logic, and the nature of moral conflicts and moral dilemmas. It is concluded that deontic logic has resources for precise treatment of important issues in moral philosophy, but in order to make full use of these resources, more cooperation between logicians and moral philosophers is needed.
It has sometimes been suggested that, just as there are no atheists in foxholes, there are no deontologists in the field of policy studies. Political philosophers often articulate their normative commitments in terms of "a system of rights" or a set of "principles of justice," the elements of which are each supposed to serve as binding constraints on state action. And yet when one turns to questions of implementation-to figure out how these abstract commitments can be honored in real life-the inevitability of tradeoffs becomes increasingly unavoidable. Just as no military plan survives first contact with the enemy, no theory of justice survives the imposition of a budget constraint. While two principles, x and y, may seem mandatory and essential, if resources are insufficient to achieve complete satisfaction of both, then the question necessarily becomes one of how much satisfaction of x one is willing to sacrifice in order to achieve more of y, and vice versa. Consequentialists, of course, employ a deliberative apparatus that is well-suited to answering such questions. Deontologists generally do not. As a result, many have found that serious engagement with policy questions generates a slow, steady pressure in the direction of consequentialism. Deontological theorists are, however, not without recourse. 1 The centrepiece of their response to this problem has been to introduce a distinction between ideal and non-ideal theory, where principles developed at the level of ideal theory are assessed under the assumption of full compliance, whereas principles developed at the level of non-ideal theory are assessed under the more realistic assumption that not everyone is going to comply all the time with the obligations specified by the first set of principles. 2 For convenience, we may refer to the former as "first-best" principles, the latter as "secondbest" principles. Perhaps the most obvious difference between the two levels will be that second-best principles will typically include a theory of punishment, whereas first-best principles will not (because ideally everyone will always act as they are supposed to). 3 So at the first-best level, one may specify that no one should ever perform actions of type x. The question then arises of what should happen to those who defy the prohibition and do it anyway. The most commonly held view is that they should be punished for the transgression. A set of second-best principles will then be elaborated that constrains the practice of punishment (such as a principle of proportionality, which specifies the severity). It is important to observe, however, that the same basic problem can recur. What happens if people do not respond to the threat of punishment, or even the punishment itself, as expected? This arguably creates an even-less-ideal context, requiring the specification of set of third-best principles. 1 I use the term "deontological" very broadly, to refer to theories that assign priority to "the right" over "the good." For an overview of the key concepts, see Christine Tappolet, "Evaluative vs. Deontic Concepts," in Hugh LaFollette, ed. International Encyclopedia of Ethics (New York: Wiley, 2022): 1791-99. 2 This influential approach was pioneered by John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. edn (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), pp. 212-16. 3 The other major component of second-best theory is that it must contain principles for making tradeoffs between firstbest principles, which may not conflict with one another under the assumption of full compliance, but begin to conflict when people misbehave, or require incentive to comply.
Revue archéologique du centre de la France, 2020
Toplumsal Tarih, 2023
Lean Construction Journal, 2016
Benedikta Yeunifan, 2023
International journal of innovative research and development, 2023
… . International Series of Translation Studies. Prague, …, 1993
Revista Brasileira De Historia, 2003
International Journal of Chemical Reactor Engineering, 2011
Polymer sciences, 2018
Gaelic Ireland (c.600-c.1700) Lordships, Saints and Learning: Essays for the Irish Chiefs’ and Clans’ Prize in History, eds. Luke McInerney and Katharine Simms (Dublin, 2021), 91-96., 2021
Norsk Konferanse For Organisasjoners Bruk Av It, 2014
International Journal of Performance Analysis in Sport, 2019
Coastal Engineering Proceedings, 2018
Canadian Journal of Urban Research, 2010
Matʹ i ditâ v Kuzbasse, 2020
Journal of Physics G: Nuclear and Particle Physics, 2008