Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality 12
Tiziana Andina
Petar Bojanić Editors
Institutions
in Action
The Nature and the Role of Institutions
in the Real World
tiziana.andina@unito.it
Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality
Volume 12
Series Editor
Raul Hakli, Dept of Political & Economic Studies, University of Helsinki, Helsinki,
Finland
Managing Editors
Hans Bernhard Schmid, University of Basel, Basel, Switzerland
Jennifer Hudin, University of California, Berkeley, USA
Advisory Editors
Robert Audi, Department of Philosophy, Notre Dame University, Notre Dame, USA
Michael Bratman, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University, Stanford, USA
Cristiano Castelfranchi, Cognitive Science, University of Siena, Siena, Italy
David Copp, University of California, Davis, Davis, USA
Ann Cudd, University of Kentucky, Lexington, USA
John Davis, Marquette University, Milwaukee, USA
Wolfgang Detel, Department of Philosophy, University of Frankfurt, Frankfurt, Germany
Andreas Herzig, Computer Science, University of Toulouse, Toulouse, France
Ingvar Johansson, Philosophy, Umeå University, Umeå, Sweden
Byron Kaldis, Department of Philosophy, University of Athens, Athens, Greece
Martin Kusch, Department of Philosophy, University of Vienna, Wien, Austria
Christopher Kutz, Law, University of California, Berkeley, USA
Eerik Lagerspetz, Department of Philosophy, University of Turku, Turku, Finland
Pierre Livet, Department of Philosophy, Universite de Provence, Marseille, France
Tony Lawson, Faculty of Economics, University of Cambridge, Cambridge, UK
Kirk Ludwig, Department of Philosophy, University of Florida, Gainesville, USA
Kay Mathiessen, Information Science and Philosophy, University of Arizona, Tucson,
USA
Larry May, Philosophy Department, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, USA
Georg Meggle, Institute of Philosophy, University of Leipzig, Leipzig, Germany
Anthonie Meijers, Department of Philosophy, University of Eindhoven, Eindhoven, The
Netherlands
Seumas Miller, Philosophy, Australian National University and Charles Sturt University,
Canberra, Australia
Uskali Mäki, Academy of Finland, Helsinki, Finland
Elisabeth Pacherie, Cognitive Science, Jean Nicod Institute, Paris, France
Henry Richardson, Department of Philosophy, Georgetown University, Washington
D.C., USA
Michael Quante, Department of Philosophy, University of Münster, Münster, Germany
John Searle, Department of Philosophy, University of California, Berkeley, USA
Michael Tomasello, Department of Developmental Psychology, Max Planck Institute,
Leipzig, Germany
tiziana.andina@unito.it
First book series in Philosophy of the Social Sciences that specifically focuses on
Philosophy of Sociality and Social Ontology.
Covers a new and rapidly developing field that has become one of the key topics
of the international philosophical world.
Aims at an interdisciplinary approach that will bring new perspectives to the
study of such topics as communication, unintended consequences of action as well
as social structures and institutions.
This book series publishes research devoted to the basic structures of the social
world. The phenomena it focuses on range from small scale everyday interactions to
encompassing social institutions, from unintended consequences to institutional
design. The unifying element is its focus on the basic constitution of these
phenomena, and its aim to provide philosophical understanding on the foundations
of sociality. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality covers the part of philosophy of
the social sciences which deals with questions of social ontology, collective
intentionality (e.g. collective knowledge, joint and collective action, joint mental
states) and related philosophical topics. The series will include monographs and
edited collections on philosophical and conceptual questions concerning social
existence as well as conceptual and theoretical analyses of social notions and
collective epistemology.
In principle, all phenomena dealing with sociality are covered as long as they are
approached from a philosophical point of view, broadly understood. Accordingly,
the works to be published in the series would in general be philosophical—without
regard to philosophical schools and viewpoints—and they would meet the highest
academic and intellectual standards are met. However, the series is interdisciplinary
not only in an intra-philosophical sense but also in the sense of encouraging highlevel work from other disciplines to be submitted to the series. Others who are
active in the field are political scientists, economists, sociologists, psychologists,
linguists, neuroscientists, evolutionary biologists, and researchers of artificial
intelligence.
The resulting interdisciplinary approach will give new perspectives to the study
of topics such as social interaction, communication, unintended consequences of
action, social structures and institutions, the evolution of collective intentionality
phenomena, as well as the general ontological architecture of the social world.
The series discourages the submission of manuscripts that contain reprints of
previous published material and/or manuscripts that are below 150 pages / 75,000
words.
For inquiries and submission of proposals authors can contact
christi.lue@springer.com, or contact one of the associate editors.
More information about this series at http://www.springer.com/series/10961
tiziana.andina@unito.it
Tiziana Andina • Petar Bojanić
Editors
Institutions in Action
The Nature and the Role of Institutions
in the Real World
tiziana.andina@unito.it
Editors
Tiziana Andina
Department of Philosophy and Educational
Sciences
University of Turin
Torino, Italy
Petar Bojanić
Institute for Philosophy and Social Theory
University of Belgrade
Belgrade, Serbia
ISSN 2542-9094
ISSN 2542-9108 (electronic)
Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality
ISBN 978-3-030-32617-3
ISBN 978-3-030-32618-0 (eBook)
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-32618-0
© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of
the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation,
broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information
storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology
now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the
editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Springer imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
tiziana.andina@unito.it
Contents
1
Social Corporations as Social Institutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Raimo Tuomela
1
2
Institutions and Functions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Francesco Guala and Frank Hindriks
9
3
Epistemic Virtues of Institutions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Snježana Prijić Samaržija
21
4
What Is an Act of Engagement? Between the Social,
Collegial and Institutional Protocols . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Petar Bojanić
37
5
Play It by Trust: Social Trust, Political Institutions and Leisure . . . .
Nebojša Zelič
51
6
Individual Morality and the Morality of Institutions . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Thomas M. Scanlon
73
7
States and Transgenerational Actions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Tiziana Andina
89
8
From Capital to Documediality . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 107
Maurizio Ferraris
9
The Basis of European Cooperation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 123
Jonathan Wolff
10
Ways of Compromise-Building in a World of Institutions . . . . . . . . . 135
Emmanuel Picavet
Index . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 147
vii
tiziana.andina@unito.it
Chapter 7
States and Transgenerational Actions
Tiziana Andina
Abstract There is a class of actions that, from a metaphysical point of view, has as
its necessary condition some form of cooperation between different generations.
This article aims to analyse the metaphysical structure of this class of actions and to
show that they are a necessary condition for the existence of social reality.
Keywords Transgenerational actions · States · Institutions
What are actions? The extensive literature on the topic has mainly tried (a) to define
the concept of action,1 (b) to distinguish it from the similar concept of event and, (c)
lastly, to organize a taxonomy of actions that explains what and how many types of
actions there are (Danto 1973; Moya 1990). Keeping this framework in mind, I
would like to suggest that, in order to understand the structure of social reality, it is
not enough to consider it as a complex architecture with a certain structure at a time
t1. In fact, it is also important to analyse its basic elements, paying particular attention to its components that undergo changes over time.
I will therefore argue that the common taxonomy of actions should include a
particular type of action that I will define as “transgenerational”. Social reality
needs this type of actions in order to exist and perdure. In other words, there can be
no social reality, organized as we know it, without transgenerational actions.
Furthermore, I will show that the specific structure of these actions presupposes and
requires the existence of particular actors of the social world.
1
Many pioneering studies have been published on this topic: see (1965, 1973).
T. Andina (*)
Department of Philosophy and Educational Sciences, University of Turin, Torino, Italy
e-mail: tiziana.andina@unito.it
© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020
T. Andina, P. Bojanić (eds.), Institutions in Action, Studies in the Philosophy
of Sociality 12, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-32618-0_7
tiziana.andina@unito.it
89
90
7.1
T. Andina
Basic Transgenerationality
I will first define the concept of transgenerationality and then the concept of transgenerational actions. I will defend the thesis that transgenerationality is a primitive
and, as such, shapes our identity as social individuals.Humans, as social and political animals, are naturally prone to creating relationships, often medium or long term
ones. In most cases, these relationships involve individuals who are related neither
by blood nor by kinship. These relationships are defined weak.
The transgenerational relationship – like any other relationship – is mainly a constraint and, in this sense, it implies rights and duties. There are two types of transgenerational relationship. The former is widely considered within social reality and
is protected by the law: the relationship between different generations of the same
family. The transmission of the father’s surname – sometimes the mother’s or, more
rarely, both– is one of the elements that typically identify the generational change.
The last name is thus considered an external and characteristic sign that proves to
preserve “something” in the transition from father to son. This “something”, in its
minimal form, usually coincides with the biological makeup.
In this kind of situations, which are the easiest to identify and define, the living
beings’ biological and therefore constitutive structure is believed to be transmitted.
An important emotional connection makes this transfer possible: if one considers
the situation where x is the father/mother of y, who is therefore the son/daughter of
x, the transmission of the biological makeup corresponds to the transmission of part
of x’s being to y (at least the part linked to her biological makeup), so that x will
maintain a special link with y in the name of natural continuity. The transgenerational biological relationship assumes that something physical and therefore clearly
identifiable and definable is transmitted from one generation to another. Given this
context, the resulting idea is that the transmission of part of the genetic makeup
implies a somehow analogous transmission of the material goods available to the
subject. The parental relationship, therefore, implies the transmission of some of the
biological makeup as well as of some material goods.
Now, this type of transgenerationality, which I call “basic transgenerationality”,
is generally recognized in every culture and is well protected by the law. For example, those systems (such as the Italian one) that protect the transfer of goods from
father to son regardless of the parent’s will are particularly interesting. If, for example, the parent decides to disinherit the son, what is technically called “reserved
share” protects and ensures basic transgenerationality. Therefore, the idea that the
continuity between x and y is an objective factor that must be protected, even by the
law and regardless of the concerned individuals’ will, is generally recognized by
common sense. The paternity acknowledgment – paternity denial must generally
comply very severe constraints – and the material protection of the child’s rights are
some of the tools for the law to protect this kind of transgenerationality. Basic transgenerationality therefore amounts to a well-defined relationship that can be, and in
fact is, well-protected. Thus, basic transgenerationality is essentially a state, a way
of being.
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
91
However, the second type of transgenerationality, which I call “secondary transgenerationality”, is theoretically more interesting. I will try to show that the secondary transgenerationality is a condition of possibility for the existence of a social
reality with a certain degree of complexity and articulation, with the property of
perduring in time. I will now explain what I mean by secondary transgenerationality
and then show why I believe it should be considered a necessary condition for the
existence of social reality.
7.2
Secondary Transgenerationality
Secondary transgenerationality is a transgenerational relationship whose condition
of possibility is neither parenthood nor kinship. Therefore, secondary transgenerationality does not need either of these conditions in order to exist. Given this framework, I will focus on the following questions: what features does secondary
transgenerationality have? How can one support its existence? And why am I introducing a new relationship – the relationship of secondary transgenerationality – as
one of the conditions of possibility of social reality?
To answer these questions, I will try to summarize the issue as Immanuel Kant
foreshadowed it. In his political writings, Kant introduced the idea that the relationship between different generations (not necessarily blood-related) does not only
exist, but is also characterized by a particular structure. We shall see this in detail.
In Idea for a Universal History in a Cosmopolitan Intent, Kant argues for the following theses. First thesis: “all natural predispositions of a creature are determined
sometime to develop themselves completely and purposively”. Second proposition:
“In the human being (as the only rational creature on earth) those predispositions
whose goal is the use of his reason were to develop completely only in the species,
but not in the individual”.
In the first thesis, Kant emphasizes two elements in particular. First, the living
creatures’ natural capacities and predispositions develop– that is, become complete – only over time. That is to say, it takes time for a human being to completely
develop her rational capacities and become fully able to shape and order her energies. Furthermore, and with specific regards to human beings, all natural predispositions whose goal is the use of reason will not develop completely in the individual,
but rather in the species. In this regard, Kant wants to point out that the relationships
within the species are evidently organized with efficiency and completeness only
over time and, particularly, over an indefinitely long period of time. Temporality is
thus a central element: the passing of time, embodied in the individuals’ lives, is
what allows reason to fully develop.
Reason in a creature is a faculty of extending the rules and aims of the use of all its powers
far beyond natural instinct, and it knows no boundaries to its projects. But reason itself does
not operate instinctively, but rather needs attempts, practice and instruction in order gradually to progress from one stage of insight to another. Hence, every human being would have
to live exceedingly long in order to learn how he is to make a complete use of all his natural
tiziana.andina@unito.it
92
T. Andina
predispositions; or, if nature has only set the term of his life as short […], then nature perhaps needs an immense series of generations, each of which transmits its enlightenment to
the next […]. (In Kant’s idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim by Amélie
OksenbergRorty, Cambridge Critical Guides, 2012, p. 11).
Notoriously, the basic idea is that human nature is deeply flawed: a crooked timber that, as Kant writes in the sixth thesis, can never be straightened completely.
Human beings are in fact governed by two opposing predispositions: the former
leads them to gather together and the latter leads them to isolate themselves. Human
beings are practically torn between the tendency to work together and the tendency
to egoistically and authoritatively impose their will. Kant seems nevertheless convinced of the existence of a relationship between generations that has a constitutive
function for social life. However, he also seems convinced that this relationship is
positive and augmentative – that is, it increases the overall amount of both tangible
and intangible goods.
Basically, the idea is that however imperfect human nature may be, the relationship between generations is intrinsically positive and creates a virtuous circle in
which the work of each generation will somehow benefit the following one.
But it appears to have been no aim at all to nature that he should live well; but only that he
should labor and work himself up so far that he might make himself worthy of well-being
through his conduct of life. Yet here it remains strange that the older generations appear to
carry on their toilsome concerns only for the sake of the later ones, namely so as to prepare
the steps on which the latter may bring up higher the edifice which was nature’s aim, and
that only the latest should have the good fortune to dwell in the building on which a long
series of their ancestors (to be sure, without this being their aim) had labored, without being
able to partake of the good fortune which they prepared. (In Kant’s idea for a universal
history with a cosmopolitan aim by Amélie OksenbergRorty, Cambridge Critical Guides,
2012, p. 12).
Prescinding from Kant’s teleological idea – which clearly reflects a cultural conditioning – of an anthropomorphic nature committed to accomplishing through the
species what could never be achieved by the individual, the basic argument remains
interesting: each generation seems to act so as to favour the next generations or at
least, each generation seems driven by nature’s plan (obscure as it may be obscure)
to reach goals that often remain unknown to humans but that, together, reveal their
meaning as a whole. Each generation builds something that only the next generation
will completely and fully enjoy. What is interesting here is not so much Kant’s thesis – he was being optimistic, as one could easily show that the transgenerational
legacy is not necessarily positive – but rather the fact that Kant considers secondary
transgenerationality an obvious fact. Kant therefore believed that, since nature follows a grand design and makes human history worthwhile, a secondary transgenerationality must exists. Otherwise, men would remain crooked timbers. For this
reason, Kant’s transgenerationality – which is fundamentally augmentative – exists
regardless of the individuals’ will. It is somehow part of a supra-historical dimension in which human beings are acted upon and act a little bit against their will and,
in any case, beyond their awareness. Kant therefore deduces the existence of secondary transgenerationality from what he thinks is nature’s general work. Progress
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
93
exists in human history because nature’s goals transcend the individuals and are
brought about through the dynamics of secondary transgenerationality.
At this point, provided that Kant’s teleological model can be legitimately questioned, one should ask oneself if the concept of secondary transgenerationality falls
with it or if the existence of a secondary transgenerationality can rest on different
foundations.In the following pages, I will try to show that this concept is related to
some actions that constitute social life and are carried out mainly by states, which
also represent their condition of possibility. These actions are those that indeed
identify secondary transgenerationality.
7.3
States
Typically, political philosophy answers the question “what is the state?” by subordinating the metaphysical analysis to the functional one. Essentially, the question
“what is it?” is replaced with “what is it for?” Thomas Hobbes, for example, followed this strategy when he laid the basis for the philosophical reflection on the
modern nation-state. Hobbes’ answer is quite simple and direct. The state’s function
is to defend human beings, whoby nature want to be absolutely free and to prevail
over others. Since this is their nature, one cannot expect them – unlike other animals
that naturally live in a society without coercive forms of power – to be able to live
socially without conflicts and fights, unless they are forced to do so (Hobbes and
Shapiro 2010: chap. XVII). In short, the animals that live a social life agree naturally. Humans, on the contrary, build societies as a result of a conventional agreement derived from a common determination due, mostly, to fear: “Therefore it is no
wonder if there be somewhat else required (besides covenants) to make their
Agreement constant and lasting; which is a Common Power, to keep them in awe
and to direct their actions to the Common Benefit”. If this is true – that is, if anthropology shows that human nature is characterized by a conflict or, more simply,
competition with others – then one has to acknowledge that human societies cannot
exist without an agent that regulates them by force.
Abraham Lincoln rightly noted that it is impossible to govern someone without
their consent. Starting from this same concept, Hobbes bases his definition of the
State on the social contract and the people’s willingness to make such an agreement.
However, this concept is rather paradoxical: people must voluntarily agree to give
up their right to use force to a third subject. They must therefore submit themselves
voluntarily to this condition, permanently delegating their right to self-defence to
one or more individuals who, presumably, will make better use of it. Such a delegation is so radical that whoever is in charge of the alienated rights must be recognized
as acting on behalf of all those who gave up their right to self-defence.
This is more than consent, or concord; it is a real unity of them all, in one and the same
person, made by covenant of every man and with every man, in such a manner, as if every
man should say to every man, I authorize and give up my right of governing myself to this
man, or to this assembly of men, on this condition: that thou give up thy right to him, and
tiziana.andina@unito.it
94
T. Andina
authorize all his actions in like manner. This done, the multitude so united in one person is
called a COMMONWEALTH; in Latin CIVITAS (Hobbes and Shapiro, Leviathan part I
and II, Broadview Press, 2010, p. 158).
Human beings are weak and therefore need to make agreements that allow them
to avoid a permanent state of war. However, in order to do so they must agree once
and for all to give up their right to self-defence. This is the pars destruens of Hobbes’
model. I will now analyse the pars construens, which is even more interesting for
the purpose of this text because it defines the nature of the state. In this context, what
is a state for Hobbes? “It is a real unity of them all in one and the same person”.
Therefore, this is a veritable new metaphysical entity: a person, or at least something whose characteristics resemble those of a concrete person and yet is oddly
made up by the totality of wills – and perhaps consciences – of those who agreed to
found the State. This object reveals rather singular characteristics.
Of course, to argue that the state is roughly like a person has the advantage, from
Hobbes’ point of view, of emphasizing the synthesis of wills. In fact, this exact
synthesis – embodied in the sovereign or in the assemblies that represent the people – is entrusted with the exercise of power. Hobbes’ model, however, has some
fairly obvious weaknesses. On the one hand, it is based on the idea that the majority
gives a third subject both the authority and the delegated power to defence. On the
other hand, however, this subject’s features are far from trivial. What does Hobbes
mean when he says that the set of wills gives birth to a new person or subject? The
idea that the state is a person – that is, what in literature was defined as “organicist
paradigm” and spread during the eighteenth century2 – involves the State’s strict
dependence on the citizens who enable it by willingly delegating some of their
rights. It is not difficult to realise what this means on a concretely ontological level.
For example, let’s consider one of the many features that usually identify people,
that is, the fact that each individual is marked by individuality. Typically, one is
intuitively led to consider an organism as an individual, that is, as a being with precise spatial and temporal characteristics. In biology, some extensive and controversial researches have explored the concept of biological individual (Wilson 1999).
However, it is debatable whether a determination of this type can also be attributed
to the State in a non-metaphorical sense. If, for example, it is intuitively true that a
biological organism can generally bear a limited number of changes on its body
parts, one’s intuitions are different in the case of the state. Locke (Locke and
Phemister 2008: ch. XXVII) thought that memory was a good element of continuity
to determine an individual’s identity through time. Where there is continuity of
memory, there is also identity, that is, there is an organism and, in some cases, an
individual. On the other hand, to transfer an individual’s soul – devoid of any memory and psychological trait – to another individual’s body would not make the latter
identical to the former.
This means that, without consciousness and memory, the identity of the thinking
matter is not enough to make a person’s identity. In the case of the state, there seem
2
For a discussion on this, cf. (Mannheim 1953, pp. 165–182.)
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
95
to be a wider tolerance toward the changes of its parts. Also, it is much more difficult to say what parts the state is made up of. For example, it is quite clear that the
individual, as such, is not the necessary condition for the existence of the state:
individuals are born and die. This means that they enter and leave the state community without modifying the identity of the state. Furthermore, this also means that
the citizens who founded the State cannot be considered a necessary condition for
its existence, as it persists in time long after their death.
The state is indeed an entity that persists over time, that is, it lasts for a considerable period of time also because some of its elements are replaced. On closer inspection, the relative ease with which the individuals start and stop being part of a social
and political community is what actually creates the states. The relatively easy
adhesion and distancing from a social and political community, combined with the
fact that people perform actions that last considerably (as regards both the duration
of the action and the consequences implemented by them), presuppose a subject
guaranteeing the consequences that this metaphysical structure entails. The state,
therefore, exists; it is not a mere concept and it is not only – as the theoretical
hypothesis posits – a guardian of people’s security, but also a guarantor of the individuals’ actions (I will dwell more on this later). In other words, a significant and
important part of social actions would not be possible or normatively justifiable
without the state.
7.3.1
Ontology of the State
From an ontological perspective, I think it is theoretically appropriate to reject the
hypothesis that the State is a fictional entity, a mere concept, and to opt for a
Hegelian realism. However, compared to Hegel’s model (1991: § 269), which creates an analogy between the biological organism and the state, I propose to consider
the State as an object that depends on and emerges from the subjects’ wills – which,
as we have seen, vary constantly. In other words, the state is not a conventional term,
as some theorists have proposed,3 but an entity that exists and persists in time, while
its existence in space could even be optional. In these terms, the state is an entity
that can be included in our ontologies with full rights.
In order to exist in time, States must fit a precise ontological structure that basically implies two conditions. (1) First, the individuals’ will, characterized by intentionality; this will has led to the creation of the state-object at a certain time (the
state would not exist without a clear expression of some individuals’ will; it is therefore a necessary condition for its coming into being). (2) Secondly, it implies
“something” that redefines and preserves the structure of the will that led to the
formation of the state. Since the components of this will keep changing, it is clear
that both its constitution and its expression must be constantly redefined over time
3
For a deeper analysis, cf. (Abrams 1988).
tiziana.andina@unito.it
96
T. Andina
as well. Therefore, the will implies what I define a “vehicle of the institutional structure” – that is, one or more relationships that, whenever the individuals’ wills
change, guarantee to verify that both the general will and the mechanisms allowing
the will to express itself are still valid.
Between these two conditions, the latter concerns how the state persists over
time (de facto and de iure). Therefore, I will develop my analysis on two levels
concerning the state’s need to preserve itself over time. The former concerns factual
arguments (how can the State concretely preserve itself over time?). The latter is a
matter of law (what rights allow it to preserve itself over time?).
7.3.1.1
How States Can Preserve Themselves over Time: Matters of Fact
Edward Robinson (2014) rightly observed that in order to understand how an object
so peculiar as the state manages to preserve itself over time, one must first observe
its document structure.4 Robinson’s thesis is widely based on the theory of documentality and defines the states as objects that are “almost abstract” – that is, they
have a temporal, rather than spatial, connotation and their sovereignty is established,
maintained and managed by different kinds of documents (Robinson 2014: 461
et seq.). It is therefore a document – theoretically, a constitution – that brings a State
into being: that document is both the origin of the State and one of the tools, perhaps
the main one, that preserve it over time. Certain documents, for example, are the
archives of the wills that brought a State into being, contain some elements of validation (other elements are likely to be provided by the context and the information
offered by history), and entail the occurrence of some facts – some of these facts are
regulatory and institutional, others simply involve the formation and preservation of
collective memory. From this, one can also infer that states cannot be reduced to
documents neither from the point of view of the constitutive elements (documents
exist because they must convey contents that do not necessarily derive from other
documents), nor, as we shall see, from the point of view of the actions they perform.
In some circumstances, therefore, both normative and non-descriptive documents
produce actions. Some of these actions – and this is the most interesting theoretical
point – are only possible because the states exist.
In his metaphysical analysis, Robinson quite rightly points out the importance of
temporality. Unlike most political philosophers, he considers time much more
important than space.5 As we have seen, time and action are directly connected:
states perform enduring and persisting actions either directly or through elements
that make their agency possible (documents, people, institutions). Some of these
actions have a particular structure. I have identified them as actions of secondary
transgenerationality. Let’s now look at their characteristics.
4
5
The philosophers theoretically grounded documentality are (Ferraris 2013) and (Smith 2012).
Cf., for example, (Schmitt et al. 2015) e (Schmitt 2007)
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
7.3.1.2
97
How States Can Preserve Themselves Over Time: Matters of Law
States thus exists because of a normative bureaucracy in which people also play a
role. Now that I have explained how the state can exist, I shall address the second
question: why does it exist? The answer is that the state has to exist because it is the
only entity that can perform certain kinds of actions that otherwise would be neither
possible nor justifiable: transgenerational actions. Therefore, it is important to firstly
outline a taxonomy of collective actions and, secondly, to identify the features of the
transgenerational actions performed by States.
Collective Actions: A Taxonomy
Clearly, not all actions are individual – that is, concerning a single person. In fact,
there is another type of actions, performed by two or more people. The most frequent hypothesis is that they have a different structure compared to individual
actions and are typical of social reality. Thus, when creating a taxonomy of actions,
it is necessary to distinguish individual actions from collective actions. At the metaphysical level, instead, it is useful to focus on the features of a collective action. The
precondition for a collective action is, quite naturally, the fact that two or more
people somehow act together, which roughly means that they share something – the
purpose of the action. This can be shared in two different ways: 1. in one case, two
or more subjects can share the same goal in a way that is, so to speak, accidental
(when, hypothetically speaking, a fire breaks out in a movie theatre and the people
inside all act pretty much the same way, with the implicitly shared purpose to
escape); 2. or, and this is a different case, they can explicitly share the same goal: a
fire breaks out and a team of fire-fighters acts so as to maximize their efforts and
extinguish it. The latter case, for the purposes of this essay, is the most interesting
and better identifies collective action.
Let’s start with this case then. The basic question is: how can two or more people
act so as to accomplish the most appropriate set of actions to achieve their goal (to
extinguish the fire)? The social ontologies that have tried to answer these questions
have mainly resorted to the notion of “collective intentionality”. This allows one, at
least according to the theorists who support it,6 to suppose a sort of marked predisposition toward collective action. Searle’s version is probably the most challenging,
as the American philosopher understands collective intentionality as a primitive
that, as such, is prior to the human beings’ disposition to perform individual actions.
To be clear, the disposition to act collectively would not only be innate, but also
prior (Searle 1995: 23 ff.) to the disposition to act individually.
This means that, according to Searle, people are not only disposed to act collectively but they even share intentional states such as beliefs, desires and intentions.
6
Cf. in particular, (Searle 1995, 2010) For a weaker version of collective intentionality, which I
will refer to repeatedly throughout the article, (Tuomela 2002)
tiziana.andina@unito.it
98
T. Andina
Collective intentions must therefore be added to individual intentions. According to
Searle, a good example is that of those actions in which a person is doing something
as part of an action that has wider boundaries: think of the players of a football
team. Everyone performs their action, which certainly has a specific meaning (the
goalkeeper defends his goal), but whose full meaning is entirely given only in connection with the totality of the actions that make up the game from beginning to end.
The important fact in Searle’s thesis is that collective intentionality can neither be
reduced to individual intentionality nor be simply described as individual intentionality with some additional properties. Rather – this is Searle’s thesis – it is an entirely
different thing. I will define this the strong variant of the theory of collective
intentionality.
On the contrary, the Finnish philosopher Raimo Tuomela (2002: 19) supports a
weak variant. According to Tuomela, human beings obviously act by including
other human beings in their plans of action. This means that they somehow take
them and their responses into account. Tuomela’s position is more complex and
therefore better captures some facts of reality. It distinguishes between three different notions of collective intentionality that have a specific relationship with
their goals:
1. Objectives shared accidentally;
2. Objectives shared intentionally;
3. The objective of a collective.
The first one is obviously the weakest. This is the case, for example, of people at the
movie theater when a fire breaks out. Everyone will predictably try to reach the exit
as fast as possible. Therefore, everyone shares a goal in that precise moment.
However, they do not share it by choice, but rather as a result of a series of things
that determine their behaviour. In addition to sharing a specific goal (to do whatever
it takes to exit as fast as possible), the people involved in the fire situation are also
aware that to escape is, indeed, a shared goal. That is, they know that everyone who
is in that situation – unless they have individual and specific reasons – will be willing to quickly run away; they know that others will do the same and thus organize
their choices accordingly.
The second option is more challenging. It implies that those who share a certain
goal do so intentionally, but it also means that they have not shared a plan to achieve
the common objective. It is as if, once the objective is shared, the subjects had not
shared a plan to achieve it. The idea is that the goal is shared, but the actions and
plans of action designed to achieve such a goal are not shared because people could
not or did not want to. In this situation, the commitment toward the common goal is,
clearly, quite weak. There is only the subjects’ intention, expressed or suspected, but
there is no commitment as to how to realize this intention. This creates a significant
degree of uncertainty regarding the possibility to realistically achieve the common
goal. I think it is reasonable to ask whether this kind of intentional collective action
involves any degree of commitment, as Tuomela suggested (2002: 20). Indeed, a
commitment concerning the intentions already implies collective intentionality. And
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
99
this is true even if no action is performed in order to finalize the goal. I will return
to this later.
Lastly, Tuomela’s third form of collective action concerns those actions that do
not only imply the identification of a shared objective, but also the identification of
the actions necessary to achieve it. In this specific type of action, people work
closely together in order to achieve the goal that they jointly established. This type
of collective action can obviously be structured in many different ways. For example, the goal can be shared by few or many people, by people who are only gathered
because of the objective or, vice versa, by people who share other and more important goals, and so on. These actions are clear and distinctive because they imply
both the subjects’ voluntary stance and the embodiment of this stance in a number
of specific actions.
The theoretical precondition that allows Tuomela to speak in all three cases of
basic taxonomy of collective actions, as I have already mentioned, is the idea that:
(a) people do not only have beliefs; but (b) usually tend to share them and choose
the most advantageous option. If I am in the midst of a fire and decide to exit as fast
as I can, I expect whoever is in the same situation: (i) to have beliefs about the fire
and how to save herself; (ii) to plan actions and solutions similar to mine and, lastly,
(iii) to choose to implement these solutions. Now, in this example, some obvious
external reasons suggest that, indeed, things could go this way and that all subjects
would potentially act predictably, at least when choosing the objective (to save
themselves). As we know, living beings base their choices on the survival instinct,
that is, a primary biological instinct. These choices are therefore usually easy to
predict.
This presupposition is confirmed by reality as long as there are practical or normative constraints external to the subject that are quite strong and difficult to overcome. When this does not happen and the situation is like 1 or 2, it is not infrequent
that the shared objectives remain unfulfilled, causing one to even doubt the fact that
this was a collective action based on a collective intention. In other words, the interesting cases to test the idea of a collective or plural intentionality are those where
the outside world does not “force” the subjects to cooperate by applying constraints
of some kind – be they biological, normative or cultural. Obviously, these cases
exist and have been studied. The biologist Garrett Hardin (1968) proposed one of
the most interesting ones.
• Collective Actions and Commons
In seventeenth century England, “open” fields – i.e. fields available to public and
shared management – were widespread. Peasants, who lived on the edge of the poverty line, had at least the opportunity to work the land, thus gaining sustenance for
themselves and their families. Overall, the situation was far from prosperous,
because the overall wealth was very little. Survival was probably guaranteed, but
there was not much else to hope for. Between 1700 and 1810, the British Parliament
emanated a series of ‘enclosure acts’ that forced to enclose open fields and common
lands. This generated two main consequences: it determined a concentration of land
in the hands of the richest owners, namely those who could afford to bear the costs
tiziana.andina@unito.it
100
T. Andina
of the enclosures, and an increase in productivity. Interpretations of this dramatic
change have often been contrasting: on the one hand, those in favor of enclosures
claimed that this was the only way to increase the overall productivity of the state
and, therefore, to increase the wealth of the country. Conversely, detractors have
argued that enclosures marked the beginning of the institution of private property
and liberal policies.
In The Tragedy of The Commons Hardin engages with an issue that touches only
briefly on commons, and that is rather related to the problem of overpopulation of
the planet. Is there a way, a technical solution – Hardin wonders – so that overpopulation will not lead to the collapse of the earth? The answer is “no”, in the sense that
any solution we might imagine will be nothing more than a temporary solution.
Producing more food will result in an increase in population that will in turn oblige
us to produce more food, in an unstoppable crescendo.
To support his thesis, Hardin uses a number of targeted examples, all of which
have an underlying leitmotif: it is utopian to hope that common property will be
managed, by those who use them, with the same caution with which they would
manage their own private property. But what are commons and how do they work?
Hardin does not provide a definition, but he explains it through many examples,
extensively analyzing “small” commons.
Consider, for example, an unfenced field, or a stretch of sea where fishing is free.
Experience shows that the field or stretch of sea will be exploited until total depletion, which is dangerously irreversible. This is precisely what Hardin, with an effective formula, christens ‘the tragedy of the commons’: it occurs when individuals,
who act in independent and rational ways, squander a shared resource, despite
knowing that such behavior will go against their own interest. The reason for this is
simple: the fear felt by those who make this kind of seemingly counter-intuitive
choice, is that by doing otherwise they may suffer a double loss. If they acted differently, they might gain less than all the others, who are likely to use the field recklessly. In such situations, therefore, people do not seem to be able to coordinate in
order to achieve a collective goal and benefit. Now, whether they are unable to find
the salient and rational option or whether, despite having identified it, they decide to
act regardless of it, what matters is the result (Hardin 1968: 1246–1247): the pastures are depleted, the seas plundered of their fish, and the same fate awaits water
and oil resources. The moral of the story is very clear: while the individuals are
really inadequate to act in a cooperative way to preserve the richness of a common,
the only hope to this aim is that an entity including all parts involved in the actions
concerning the commons, without reducing to them, may be the actor having the
power of taking the necessary decisions for a proper management of the common.
That described by Hardin is a typical case of a transgenerational action. We have
individuals, who act in an independent and rational way, exploiting a shared
resource. In the framework proposed by Tuomela, these individuals are supposed to
share an intention (namely, a we-intention), which allows all people who share a
certain situation to take the right decisions in order to exploit the common at best.
Exactly as in the fire example, the people involved in the exploitation of – say – a
portion of the sea, are sharing the situation (all of them have access to the exploitation
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
101
of the resource), the objectives (to fish as much as is necessary to have a good life),
and the technical instruments to do so. Nevertheless, even though all the conditions
listed by Tuomela seem to be present in our imaginary case, very often people are
not collaborative and cooperative – at least, this is often the case in the real life. This
means that, even though the goals and the intentionality are often collective, the
actions in most of the cases remain largely based on individual choices. My view is
that the commons testify the main weakness of the hypothesis of a collective intention driving collective actions: there is no reason why rational objectives and shared
intentions should necessarily entail that people engage in common and cooperative
actions. Rather, the opposite is true. Common actions are just a possible choice
between many others.
It is now the time to add a third example. In the example we are imagining,
people involved in actions have achieved a good level of cooperation, after sharing
common activities. The third example is a classical one. People playing something –
say, a game or a piece of music – are sharing an objective (indeed, to play a game or
a piece of music) and are doing the proper actions in order to achieve those objectives (to win the match or to play a beautiful sonata). What are the differences
between these three cases? Or, to put it in other words, why is it that in one case
people are supposed to act jointly, while in the other case (that of the commons),
they are supposed to act individually? Let us pay attention to the differences.
• The differences are in the details.
It is now the time to ask ourselves why, even ifthe three cases are so similar, they
actually differ. To this aim, I would suggest two steps. Firstly, I would add another
case, very similar to the third example: another case of exploitation of a common.
Secondly, I would propose a comparison, trying to clarify the reasons why most
examples show cases in which the collective intention fails to obtain its objectives.
I will call this last case the good management of the commons.
In Norway, as is well known, oil is one of the most important national resources.
The “Government Petroleum Fund” is a sovereign fund set up by the Norwegian
government in 1990. The purpose of the fund was to invest part of the profit coming
from the extraction of oil. In 2006 it changed its name and status, becoming the
“Government Pension Fund Global.” It consists of a deposit in Norwegian kroner
run by the Bank of Norway on behalf of the Ministry of Finance, with the aim of
ensuring that “a reasonable portion of the country’s petroleum wealth benefits future
generations.”7
The reasoning behind this operation is very simple: the fund aims to be a sort of
piggy bank in which to set aside the surplus proceeds from the sale of oil. The bank,
in the intention of the legislature, maintains and produces new financial resources
that the state is committed to providing for future generations. Oil, unlike pastures
or fishing resources, is bound to run out. For this reason the state has decided to
7
In Ethical Guidelines for the Government Pension Fund-Global, 22 December 2005, on www.
regjeringen.no.
tiziana.andina@unito.it
102
T. Andina
make part of the wealth produced by the exploitation of that common good renewable, and thus accessible to future generations that will no longer have oil. This is an
exemplary case that seems to confirm Hardin’s thesis: the public institution not only
regulates the management of the common good, but it also finely programs a way to
reconstitute its value, although in a different form.
We are now facing a very simple question: why is it that Hardin’s example ends
up in disaster while Norway’s case is, in a way, a wonderful paradox? The case of
people facing a fire seems to show that, in a very particular way, people are able to
act establishing a kind of cooperation. This seems also true in the case of people
playing a game. So the point is: why do people seem able to act together when playing a game or escaping a fire, but apparently fail to exploit a common resource?
My view is that in all the positive cases the context is rather peculiar: first of all,
there is a very strong constraint, external to the will of the subjects (think of the fire
and Norway’s government). Moreover, in both good cases, there isa power (natural
or normative) that is external to the subjects and makes the difference. This means
that collective intentionality, supposing it really exists, in most cases has no real
influence on the choices of the subjects acting in a certain way. Subjects surely have
both the disposition and the ability to be cooperative, when needed. However, the
point is that this disposition is contrary and equivalent to the disposition to act individually. It is a matter of choice (and often of advantage) to choose to be individualists or not. At the end of the day, in fact, the only way to win a football match is to
think of oneself as a part of a team, which means thinking of a strategy involving all
players, rather than acting as a single player. The role of the others – as co-players
and as opponents – is impossible to bypass especially if one aims to win the game.
The question at this point is the following: are we sure that, in the case described
by Hardin, people are sharing a collective intention which is concretized in a collective aim? If this is the case, what is the aim that is shared? It is impossible to affirm
that it is the will to exploit the common natural resourcesin a sustainable way.
However, this is precisely a case in which cooperation is needed in order to find a
good balance between private and public interest. But people, at least in most circumstances, do not have the intention of exploiting the commons for public advantage. The case of the Norway’s oil shows a different end precisely because the
public good is managed not by individuals but by an institution, Norway’s government and, in the long run, the State. Those institutions may choose public over private advantage, considering the fact that their decisions as well as their acts will be
judged in the light of the chain of consequences they have over time.
At this point of the argument one may conclude as follows: it is a matter of fact
that people have the disposition to act and think together, but it is another matter of
fact that people, generally speaking, have the disposition to get a certain advantage
from the situation in which they find themselves. This means that, in most cases,
they simply do not intend to be involved in cooperative actions.
This is why normativity, declined in different forms, is not a choice, but the real
precondition of every large social community that aims to live together for a
long time.
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
103
• A final remark about the State
Concerned by the fate of future generations in the face of the vital challenges of the next
millennium, conscious that […] the very existence of human kind and his environment are
threatened, […] Determined to […] hand on a better world to future generations […] whose
fate depends to a great extent on decisions and actions taken today […] Convinced that
there is a moral obligation [whose fate ] depends to a great extent on decision and actors
taken today […] Convinced that there is a moral obligation to formulate behavioural guidelines for the present generations [so that] … the needs and interests of […] future generations are fully safeguarded […] Each generation inheriting the Earth temporarily should
[have the responsibility to bequeath it to future generations], take care to use natural
resources reasonably and ensure that life is not prejudiced by harmful modifications of the
ecosystems […] and should preserve […] the quality and integrity of the environment.
This is a Declaration on the Responsibility of the Present Generation towards Future
Generations adopted by UNESCO in 1997. This declaration is particularly important because it shows very well how institutions address the problem of the relationship between generations. At this stage I would like to make some final remarks on
the rule and function of the State as regards transgenerational actions. My view is
that every complex society, whose members aim at living together for a long time,
must reflection on this point. The case discussed by Hardin shows how the kind of
actions requiring cooperation between people involved may not be guided exclusively by the intentions of the people involved. This is why there is no guarantee that
people asked to act will decide for the best option, that is, for public utility.
A provisional analysis of transgenerational actions includes at least two main
types: 1. Those actions that cannot be completely accomplished by people who
chose them, but require other people, belonging to different generations, to be completed; 2. Those actions implying a regular and substantial diminution or alteration
of a common, that is, of a good whose propriety rests upon a society for a long
period of time.8 The actions of type 1 and 2 exhibit similar properties. They both
have a long duration over the time, and both involve a number of different agents
performing the action or a part of it, at some point in time. These two types of
actions imply transgenerationality in two different ways.
Type 1 requires transgenerationality because these actions imply the trust that
people who never decided for them will carry them out them anyway, assuming that
the decision is the right one. This trust is a necessary, but not sufficient, condition
for the existence of these actions. It is interesting to note that this trust is based upon
a prevision; namely, the prevision of a certain behaviour on the part of people that
do not yet exist. If the prevision does not have a good possibility to be realized, the
actions depending on that prevision would never possible, or would never have a
8
Commons were firstly conceived as a tertium genius between public and private property. It is
very interesting to look at the definition of commons proposed by the an Italian commission, the
Rodotà Commission, which received in 2008 the task of reshaping the discipline of the public
goods as stated by the Italian Civil Code, which dated back to 1942. The definition is the following:
“Commons produce utility that is functional to the exercise of fundamental rights and the free
development of individuals. Therefore, the law must guarantee in all cases that they are enjoyed
collectively, directly and by all, including future generations”.
tiziana.andina@unito.it
104
T. Andina
positive conclusion. As for the second type of actions (2), that requiring a regular
and substantial exploitation of the commons, transgenerationality is not a necessary
condition for the accomplishment of the action, but it is a criterion of the normativity accompanying these actions. The case made by Hardin paradigmatically
describes this group of actions.
To sum up: while in the first case (1) transgenerationality is a “condition” for the
action, in the second case (2), transgenerationality must be considered as the reference for the normativity accompanying some actions, as has been gradually recognised by the laws and constitutions of many states. In Germany, for example, with
the revision of the Federal Court in 1994, it was added that “the state, also in its
responsibility for future generations, protects natural resources” (article, 20 a).9 One
can also note that, in the first case, transgenerationality goes together with the trust
of people in the fact that transgenerationality itself will be effective over the time.
This point makes a great difference, which is very remarkable in the perspective of
metaphysics as well as in that of practical consequences.
As for the metaphysical implications, one should consider the subjects of transgenerational actions. What is a generation? How can it be past, present and future?
Who belongs to a given generation? Each of these questions constitutes a compelling metaphysical problem, which is ever more compelling in the perspective of law.
In the juridical framework, in fact, only where there is a subject is there a right. But
what kind of subject is a generation? Namely, if it is possible to define in some way
what a generation is and how it is composed, it is very clear that the adjective
“future” makes things quite complicated. How it is possible that a non-existing
object can be the subject of something, for example, of rights?10 My take is that it is
the action itself, that is, this particular type of action that brings into life a new subject: the future generation. This is also a new type of entity, whose nature needs to
be investigated. In a few words, the subject – that is, the “future generation” – is
something constructed by people and institutions referring to it through their
practices.
The most evident implication is that concerning the institutions’ ability to not
preserve transgenerationality as well as the set of rights connected to it. Most of the
present forms of protection of transgenerationality are based on the idea that the
attention for the future generation is a form of – we may say – over-generosity
toward still non-existing people. This is the reason why most of the references to
transgenerationality produce negative definitions. In fact, these definitions focus on
needs rather than aspirations, projects and wishes. They essentiallylimit themselves
to the notion that one should avoid dangerous excess that would significantly affect
the actions of future generations. However, quite evidently, this is just a half of the
story. The other half concerns the fact that, in our very complex societies, the present generations imply the fact that the future generations will carry on some of its
9
For an overview of the international laws regarding this matter cf. (Bailey et al. 2013).
A preliminary reflection on this can be found in M. Spanò, Who is the subject for future generations? An essay in genealogy, (Bailey et al. 2013, 45–59.).
10
tiziana.andina@unito.it
7
States and Transgenerational Actions
105
actions; this means that for some of our actions we take the will of future generations for granted. As far as I can see, the conclusion follows necessarily: if we
assume that transgenerationality is a necessary condition to define some of the
actions performed by individuals, institutions and states, then we have to conclude
that states, and institutions in general, must be necessarily guarantee that the consequences of transgenerationality (at least the foreseeable ones) must be carefully
considered along with the rights of future generations.
References
Abrams, P. (1988). Notes on the difficulty of studying the state (1977). Journal of Historical
Sociology, 1(1), 58–89. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6443.1988.tb00004.x.
Bailey, S., Farrell, G., & Mattei, U. (Eds.). (2013). Protecting future generations trought commons
(Trends in social coesion) (Vol. 26). Paris: Council of Europe.
Danto, A. C. (1965). Basic actions. American Philosophical Quarterly, 2(2), 141–148.
Danto, A. C. (1973). Analytical philosophy of action. Cambridge: University Press.
Ferraris, M. (2013). Documentality: Why it is necessary to leave traces. New York: Fordham
University Press.
Hardin, G. (1968). The tragedy of the commons. Science, 162(3859), 1243–1248.
Hegel, G. W. F., Wood, A. W., & Nisbet, H. B. (1991). Elements of the philosophy of right.
Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
Hobbes, T., & Shapiro, I. (2010). Leviathan, or, the matter, forme, & power of a common-wealth
ecclesiasticall and civill. New Haven: Yale University press.
Locke, J., & Phemister, P. (2008). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford/New York:
Oxford University Press.
Mannheim, K. (1953). Essays on sociology and social psychology. London: Routledge & Paul.
Moya, C. J. (1990). The philosophy of action: An introduction. Oxford: Polity Press.
Robinson, E. H. (2014). A documentary theory of states and their existence as quasi-abstract entities. Geopolitics, 19(3), 461–489.
Schmitt, C. (2007). The concept of the political. Expanded edition. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Schmitt, C., Russell, A. B., & Garrett Zeitlin, S. (2015). Land and sea: A world-historical meditation. Candor: Telos Press Publishing.
Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.
Searle, J. R. (2010). Making the social world: The structure of human civilization. Oxford/New
York: Oxford University Press.
Smith, B. (2012). How to do things with documents. Rivista di Estetica, 52(2), 179–198.
Tuomela, R. (2002). The philosophy of social practices: A collective acceptance view. Cambridge/
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, J. (1999). Biological individuality. The identity and persistence of living entities,
Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.
tiziana.andina@unito.it